Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    1/36

    arXiv:1312.3366v1

    [quant-ph]11Dec2013

    Quantum fluctuations from a local-causal information dynamics

    Agung Budiyono

    Jalan Emas 772 Growong Lor RT 04 RW 02 Juwana,

    Pati, 59185 Jawa Tengah, Indonesia

    (Dated: December 13, 2013)

    Abstract

    We shall show that the abstract and formal rules which govern the quantum kinematic and

    dynamics can be derived from a law of change of the information content or the degree of uncer-

    tainty that the system has a certain configuration in a microscopic time scale, which is singled

    out uniquely, up to a free parameter, by imposing the condition of Macroscopic Classicality and

    the principle of Locality. Unlike standard quantum mechanics, however, the system always has

    a definite configuration all the time as in classical mechanics, following a continuous trajectory

    fluctuating randomly in time. Moreover, we shall show that the average of the relevant physical

    quantities over the distribution of the configuration is equal to the quantum mechanical average of

    the corresponding quantum mechanical Hermitian operators over a quantum state.

    PACS numbers: 03.65.Ta; 03.65.Ud; 05.20.Gg

    Keywords: Reconstruction of quantum mechanics; Physical origin of quantum fluctuations; Informationdynamics; Principle of Locality; Macroscopic Classicality

    Electronic address: [email protected]

    1

    http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1http://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]://arxiv.org/abs/1312.3366v1
  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    2/36

    I. MOTIVATION

    The violation of Bell inequality by quantum mechanics is widely believed to lead to a

    bizarre conclusion that quantum mechanics allows the statistical results of a pair of mea-

    surement events spacelike separated from each other to have a stronger correlation than that

    is allowed by any local-causal theory [13]. The nonlocal correlation has been claimed to

    be verified in numerous experiments[416], in spite of the fact that no experiment hitherto

    conducted is free from loopholes[17,18]. Such a nonlocality prima facie contradicts the spirit

    of the special theory of relativity which presumes a finite maximum velocity of interaction

    given by the velocity of light in vacuum. Further careful investigation however showed that

    the quantum mechanical nonlocal correlation can not be exploited by one party to influence

    the statistical results of measurement performed by the other distantly separated party, thusprohibits signaling, in accord with the assertion of the special theory of relativity [1923].

    The co-existence of nonlocal correlation and no-signaling in quantum mechanics has in-

    spired some authors to ask if quantum mechanics can be derived from a certain balance

    between some kind of nonlocality and the principle of no-signaling [2428]. While it is

    shown that the constraints put by the nonlocal correlation and no-signaling are notsuffi-

    ciently strong to single out quantum mechanics [2628], it has renewed an interest in an

    approach to clarify the meaning of quantum mechanics by deriving its formal mathematical

    structures and numerous abstract postulates from a set of conceptually simple and phys-

    ically transparent axioms. In such a program, one attempts to directly answer the most

    tantalizing foundational question: why the quantum? [29]. One of the advantages of

    the program to reconstruct quantum mechanics is that it might provide physical insights for

    possible natural extensions of quantum mechanics either by modifying the axioms or varying

    the free parameters that are left unfixed by the axioms. Extension of quantum mechanics

    is not only necessary to set up precision tests against quantum mechanics, but might turn

    out to be the necessary step to solve some of the foundational problems of the latter.

    A lot of works along this line has been reported recently by regarding information as the

    basic ingredient of Natural phenomena[3047] : all things physical is information-theoretic

    in origin thus It from Bit [29]. In those works, one searches for a set of basic features of

    information processingwhich can be promoted as axioms to reconstruct quantum mechanics.

    Such an approach is partly motivated by the advancement of quantum information science

    2

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    3/36

    [48]: the fact that quantum mechanics allows information processing tasks that can not be

    performed at least as efficiently within classical mechanics suggests an intimate relationship

    between the the foundation of quantum mechanics and the basic features of information

    processing. This approach thus plays with information within operational-instrumentalist

    theoretical framework in which the notion of preparation and measurement play central

    role. Another different way to reconstruct quantum mechanics is to assume that quantum

    fluctuations is objectively real thus should be properly modeled by a stochastic processes.

    A lot of efforts have been made within this realist theoretical framework to derive the

    Schrodinger equation from a stochastic processes[4962]. The greatest challenge of such an

    approach is how to explain the nonlocal correlation predicted by quantum mechanics.

    In the present paper, we shall follow the above second point of view. We shall first

    propose a statistical model of stochastic deviation from classical mechanics in microscopic

    regime based on a stochastic fluctuations of infinitesimal stationary action. We shall then

    show that the abstract and strange [63] rules of quantization of classical systems can

    be derived from a specific law of infinitesimal change of the information content or the

    degree of uncertainty that the system hasa certain configuration along an infinitesimally

    short path, induced by the stochastic fluctuations of the infinitesimal stationary action.

    This law for the dynamics of information is shown to be singled out uniquely, up to a free

    parameter, by imposing the condition of Macroscopic Classicality and the principle of Local-Causality. Note that here, as will be detailed later, information is used to quantify an actual

    degree of of uncertainty referring directly to an event regardless of measurement. It is then

    imperative to ask: how to explain the violation of Bell inequality in experiments? Putting

    the problem aside, we will show that the local-causal statistical model thus developed leads

    to the derivation the linear Schrodinger equation with Borns statistical interpretation of

    wave function and quantum mechanical uncertainty relation, two of the cornerstones of

    standard quantum mechanics.

    We shall thus argue that quantization is physical and Planck constant acquires physical

    interpretation as a statistical average of the stochastic deviation from classical mechanics in

    a microscopic time scale. Two concrete examples of the application of the statistical model

    will be given. In the main text, we shall apply the model to quantize a system of particles

    subjected to external potentials and in the appendix we shall apply the model to quantize

    a classical mechanical model of measurement of physical quantities. Both reproduce the

    3

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    4/36

    prediction of the standard canonical quantization. Unlike the latter, however, the system

    always has a definite configuration all the time as in classical mechanics, fluctuating ran-

    domly with time. We shall also show that the average of the relevant physical quantities

    over the distribution of the configuration is equal to the quantum mechanical average of

    quantum mechanical Hermitian operators corresponding to the physical quantities over a

    wave function.

    II. A STATISTICAL MODEL OF MICROSCOPIC RANDOMNESS AND THE

    DYNAMICS OF UNCERTAINTY OBEYING THE PRINCIPLE OF LOCALITY

    A. A class of statistical models of microscopic stochastic deviation from classical

    mechanics

    There is a wealth of empirical evidences that phenomena in microscopic regime involve a

    universal stochastic element. Yet, unlike the Brownian motion, hitherto there is no consensus

    on the nature and origin of its randomness. Moreover, the prediction of quantum mechanics

    on the AB (Aharonov-Bohm) effect [64] and its experimental verification [65] suggest that

    the randomness in microscopic regime can not be adequately described by introducing some

    kinds of conventional random forces as in Brownian motion. The force has to act at a

    distance.

    To discuss the universal randomness in microscopic regime, let us consider the following

    class of statistical models. Letqdenotes the configuration of the system and tis time param-

    eterizing the evolution of the system. Let us assume that the Lagrangian is parameterized

    by a random variable fluctuating in a microscopic time scale dt, whose origin is not our

    present concern: L= L(q, q; ), where q .= dq/dt. Let us then consider two infinitesimally

    close spacetime points (q; t) and (q+ dq; t+ dt) such that is constant. Let us assume

    that fixing , the principle of stationary action is valid to select a path, denoted byJ(),that connects the two points. One must then solve a variational problem (Ldt) = 0 with

    fixed end points. This leads to the existence of a function, the Hamiltons principal function

    denoted byA(q; t, ), whose differential along the segment of trajectory is given by [66], for

    a fixed ,

    dA= Ldt = p dq Hdt, (1)

    4

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    5/36

    where p(q) = L/q is the classical momentum and H(q, p) .= p q(p) L(q, q(p)) is the

    classical Hamiltonian. The above relation implies the following Hamilton-Jacobi equation:

    p= qA,

    H(q, p) =tA. (2)

    Varying, the principle of stationary action will therefore pick up various different paths

    J(), all connecting the same two infinitesimally close spacetime points, each might havedifferent values of infinitesimal stationary actiondA(). dA() thus is randomly fluctuating

    due to the random fluctuations of. The system starting with a configuration qat time t

    may therefore take various different paths randomly to end up with a configuration q+dq

    at time t+dt. We have thus a stochastic processes driven by the random fluctuations of

    in a microscopic time scale. Hence a complete description of a single event is impossible.

    Instead, one has to rely on a statistical approach.

    One can see that the randomness enters into the dynamics in a microscopic time scale

    in a fundamentally different way from that of the Brownian motion. In the model, it is

    the infinitesimal stationary action that is randomly fluctuating in a microscopic time scale.

    By contrast, the randomness in the Brownian motion is induced by some random forces.

    We have thus assumed that the Lagrangian schema based on energies is more fundamental

    than the Newtonian schema based on forces. We expect that this will lead to a local-causal

    explanation of the AB effect. To see another implication of such a difference, let us consider

    a compound composed of two interacting subsystems. Within the formalism of Brownian

    motion, it is then possible to introduce a joint-probability for two random forces each act-

    ing locally to a subsystem. By contrast, since action is evaluated in configuration space

    rather than in ordinary space, then in the statistical model based on a random fluctua-

    tions of infinitesimal stationary action, one can notdefine a joint-probability density for the

    fluctuations of infinitesimal stationary action of each subsystem.We have thus a class of stochastic models which differ fundamentally from the conven-

    tional Brownian motion. In the following subsections, we shall select one of them by imposing

    the constraints that the statistical model has a smooth classical limit in macroscopic regime

    and respects the principle of Locality demanded by the theory of relativity.

    5

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    6/36

    B. The dynamics of information or uncertainty with a smooth Macroscopic

    Classicality

    To develop a statistical description of the stochastic processes, let us denote the joint-

    probability density that at time t the configuration of the system is qand a random value of

    is realized as (q, ; t). We would like to find an equation which describes how changes

    along an infinitesimally short trajectoryJ(). To do this, instead of working directly with, we shall below consider a quantity defined as

    I(q; t, ) .= ln(q, ; t). (3)

    This quantity is introduced by Shannon as a measure of information content or the degree

    of uncertainty of an event. Within the context of the stochastic model under study, fixing

    , it is the information content or the degree of uncertainty that the configuration of the

    system isqfor the following intuitive reasons: i) it is vanishing if the system definitely has

    a configuration qso that (q) = 1; ii) it is increasing monotonically as the probability that

    the system has a configuration qis decreasing and iii) it is additive for independent events.

    Let us first note that the information content or the degree of uncertainty defined above

    is objective referring directly to the configuration, thus the factual state, of the system. It

    isnot

    the information that one obtains by performing some measurements over the systemof interest. Hence, we shall in the present paper work with information within a realist

    rather than instrumentalist-operational theoretical model. The latter approach is however

    followed by most works in the reconstruction of quantum mechanics based on information

    theory, which is apparently motivated by the central role of measurement in the formalism

    of standard quantum mechanics. Moreover, let us note that the information quantified by

    I(q) refers to a single event that the system has a particular configuration q, rather than

    the whole possible events of the system distributed according to (q). The information with

    regard to the whole possible events is usually quantified by the average ofI(q) given by the

    Gibbs-Shannon entropy which is central in information theory[67].

    The interpretation of I(q) as the amount of information or degree of uncertainty that

    the system has a configuration qmay also be argued within the concept of microcanonical

    ensemble as follows. First, given the parameters of the system, let N denotes the total

    number of the microstates accessible by the system. Let us assume that the system may be in

    6

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    7/36

    one of the microstates equally probably. Let us then assume that qis a macroscopic coarse-

    grained variable of the microstates. LetNq denotes the number of microstates compatible

    with q. The probability that the system has a configuration q is thus given by =Nq/N.

    One therefore has ln N = I(q) + ln Nq. Interpreting ln Nas the amount of information or

    uncertainty that the system lies in one of theNpossible microstates, and ln Nqas the amount

    of information or uncertainty that the system lies in one of the Nq microstates compatible

    with q, then it is natural to interpret I(q) as the amount of information or uncertainty that

    the system has a configuration q.

    To avoid confusion, below we shall only use the term uncertainty to refer to information

    content or degree of uncertainty of an event. Let us proceed to again consider two infinites-

    imally close spacetime points (q; t) and (q+ dq; t+dt) such that is constant, connected

    by an infinitesimally short path J(). Let us then assume that as the configuration evolvesalong J(), the uncertainty that the system has a configuration qalso changes according tothe following balance equation:

    dI(q; t, ) = d ln(q, ; t) =(q; t, )dt, (4)

    where is a function ofq, and t. Our main goal in the present section is then to find a

    unique functional form ofand express it in terms of the physical properties of the system,

    by imposing a set of conceptually simple and physically transparent axioms.First, it is instructive to impose the condition of Macroscopic Classicality which demands

    that in a physical regime corresponding to macroscopic world, one should regain the clas-

    sical mechanics. Since the deviation from classical mechanics, as assumed in the previous

    subsection, is due to the fluctuations of infinitesimal stationary action induced by the fluc-

    tuations of, then in the classical limit of macroscopic regime, such fluctuations must be

    ignorable. In the macroscopic regime, one must therefore regain the dynamics of ensemble

    of classical trajectories driven by the deterministic flow of classical velocity field. The in-

    finitesimal change of the uncertainty must in this case solely be given by the flux due to the

    deterministic classical velocity field. Notice then that the uncertainty should increase if the

    velocity divergence along the infinitesimally short trajectory J() is positive and vice versa.On the other hand, since the system under consideration is closed, then probability has to

    be conserved. These two conditions combined suggest that in the macroscopic regime whose

    mathematical formulation will be clarified later, on the right hand side of Eq. (4) must

    7

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    8/36

    reduce to

    q vc= c, (5)

    where vc is the classical velocity field which is related to the classical Hamiltonian and

    the Hamiltons principal function via the kinematic part of the Hamilton equation and theHamilton-Jacobi equation of (2) as

    vc=H

    p

    p=qA

    . (6)

    Indeed, inserting Eq. (5) into Eq. (4), dividing both sides bydt and taking the limitdt 0,one obtains the continuity equation

    t +q

    vc

    = 0, (7)

    which guarantees the conservation of probability.

    Hence the demand of Macroscopic Classicality suggests that the right hand side of Eq.

    (4) should be given by the following terms:

    dI(q; t, ) = (q; t, )dt+(q; t, ),

    with .=q v, (8)

    where v is a velocity field which in the classical limit of macroscopic regime must approach

    vc

    v vc, (9)

    and is a function ofq,and t which must be vanishing in the classical limit

    (q; t, ) 0. (10)

    (q; t, ) may thus be regarded as the rate of production of uncertainty along the random

    pathJ() due to the fluctuations of in microscopic regime.From the discussion above, especially the demand thatmust be vanishing in the classical

    limit, it is then natural to assume that is a function of a quantity that measures the

    deviation from classical mechanics in microscopic regime due to the fluctuations of. To

    identify such a quantity, let us first assume that is the simplest random variable with two

    possible values, a binary random variable. Without losing generality let us assume that the

    two possible values ofdiffer from each other only by their signs, namely one is the opposite

    8

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    9/36

    of the other, =||. Suppose that both realizations of lead to the same path so thatdA() =dA(). Since the stationary action principle is valid for both values of, thensuch a model must recover the classical mechanics. Hence, the non-classical behavior must

    be measured by the difference ofdA() at

    |

    |,dA()

    dA(

    ).

    Now let us proceed to assume that may take continuous values. Let us assume that

    even in this case the difference of the values ofdA at,

    Z(q; t, ) .=dA(q; t, ) dA(q; t, ) = Z(q; t, ), (11)

    measures the non-classical behavior of the stochastic processes, namely the larger the dif-

    ference, the stronger is the deviation from classical mechanics. (q; t, ) should therefore be

    a function ofZ(q; t, ):

    = Z(q; t, ). (12)For later purpose, let us introduce a new stochastic quantity S(q; t, ) so that the differ-

    ential along the segment of pathJ() is given by

    dS(q; t, ) =dA(q; t, ) +dA(q; t, )

    2 =dS(q; t, ). (13)

    SubtractingdA(q; t, ) from both sides, one gets

    dS(q; t, ) dA(q; t, ) =dA(q; t,

    )

    dA(q; t, )

    2

    = Z(q; t, )/2. (14)

    of Eq. (12) may thus be written as a function ofdS() dA()

    =

    dS() dA(). (15)Note that the assumed universality of the law of physics demands that the functional form

    of must be independent from the details of the system of interest: the number of particles,

    masses, etc. It must only depend on dS dA.Let us then express the condition of macroscopic classicality of Eqs. (9) and (10) in term

    ofSdefined above. Let us first assume that the sign ofis fluctuating randomly in a time

    scaledt. Let us then denote the time scale for the fluctuations of|| as, and assume thatit is much larger than dt:

    dt. (16)

    9

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    10/36

    Within a time interval of length , the magnitude of is thus effectively constant while its

    sign fluctuates randomly. In order for the stochastic system to have a smooth classical limit

    for all time, then it is necessary that the classical mechanics is recovered in a time interval

    of length during which the magnitude of is effectively constant while its sign fluctuates

    randomly. As discussed above, for this binary random variable, the classicality is regained

    when dA() =dA(). In this case, one also has dS() =dA() by the virtue of Eq. (14),so that due to Eq. (1),Ssatisfies the Hamilton-Jacobi equation of (2). Taking into account

    this fact, first, the condition of Macroscopic Classicality of Eq. (10) should be rewritten as

    limdSdA

    (dS dA) = 0. (17)

    Moreover, the condition of Macroscopic Classicality of Eq. (9) is attained by assuming that

    v in Eq. (8) is related to Sas follows

    v=H

    p

    p=qS

    . (18)

    One can see that in the limit dS dAone hasqS qAso thatv vc as expected. Letus emphasize that the above condition is sufficient to recover the classical mechanics only

    within the time interval of length in which|| is constant. While it is also a necessarycondition to recover the classical dynamics for the whole time, it is not sufficient. One needs

    to have more conditions to recover classical mechanics for the whole time. This problem willbe discussed later.

    C. An infinitesimal change of uncertainty respecting the principle of Locality

    Let us then proceed to show that imposing the principle of Locality will pick up uniquely,

    up to a free parameter, the functional form of (dS dA). To do this, let us consider acompound of two subsystems, say two particles whose configuration are denoted respectively

    byq1 and q2. Let us assume that they are spacelike separated from each other so that due

    to the principle of Locality, there is no mechanical interaction between the two particles.

    The total Lagrangian is thus decomposable as L(q1, q2, q1, q2) = L1(q1, q1) + L2(q2, q2) and

    accordingly, dA(q1, q2) anddS(q1, q2) are also decomposable: dA(q1, q2) =dA1(q1) + dA2(q2)

    and dS(q1, q2) =dS1(q1) +dS2(q2). can thus be written as

    (dS dA) = (dS1 dA1) + (dS2 dA2). (19)10

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    11/36

    Further, in this case, the classical Hamiltonian is also decomposable H(q1, q2, p1, p2) =

    H1(q1, p1) +H2(q2, p2), where pi, i = 1, 2, is the momentum of iparticle. Putting thisinto Eq. (18) and recalling that dS is decomposable, then defined in Eq. (8) is also

    decomposable

    (q1, q2) = 1(q1) +2(q2). (20)

    The change of the uncertainty that the compound system has a configuration q = (q1, q2)

    moving along the pathJ() thus reads, by the virtue of Eq. (19) and (20),

    dI(q1, q2) =

    1+2

    dt+

    (dS1 dA1) + (dS2 dA2)

    . (21)

    On the other hand, since the two subsystems are spacelike separated from each other,

    the principle of Locality demands that the change of the uncertainty that the first (second)

    subsystem has a configurationq1 (q2), when the compound system moves along an infinitesi-

    mally short trajectory J(), must be independent from what happens with the second (first)subsystem. Otherwise, the uncertainty that one subsystem has a certain configuration can

    be influenced by the state of the other distantly separated subsystem by varying the control

    parameters of the latter despite of no interaction. Hence, the change of the uncertainty that

    each subsystem has a certain configuration must only depend on the corresponding single

    particle Lagrangian. One therefore has the following pair of decoupled relations:

    dI1(q1) = 1dt+(dS1 dA1),dI2(q2) =2dt+(dS2 dA2), (22)

    where dIi =d(lni), and i(qi), i= 1, 2, is the probability density for the configurationof the iparticle. dIi is thus the change of the uncertainty that the isubsystem has aconfiguration qi. Let us note again that the assumed universality of the law of physics

    demands that the functional form of for the whole compound system on the right hand

    side of Eq. (21) must be the same as those for each subsystem on the right hand side of Eq.

    (22).

    Let us first assume that the probability distribution of the configuration of the com-

    pound system is separable: (q1, q2) = 1(q1)2(q2). In this case, the total change of the

    uncertainty that the compound system has a configuration q = (q1, q2) as the configura-

    tion evolves alongJ() is then decomposable as dI(q1, q2) = dI1(q1) +dI2(q2). Now let us

    11

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    12/36

    consider a general case when the distribution of the configuration of the two spacelike sepa-

    rated subsystems are correlated. One thus has (q1, q2) = 12(q1|q2)2(q2), where 12(q1|q2)is the conditional probability that the configuration of the first subsystem is q1 when the

    configuration of the second subsystem is q2. As the configuration of the compound system

    evolves along an infinitesimally short pathJ(), the total change of the uncertainty thatthe compound system has a configurationq= (q1, q2) is then

    dI(q1, q2) =dI12(q1|q2) +dI2(q2), (23)

    where dI12= d ln 12 is the infinitesimal change of the uncertainty that the configurationof the first subsystem is q1 when the configuration of the second subsystem is q2. The

    principle of Locality however demands that, since the two subsystems are spacelike separated

    from each other, the infinitesimal change of the uncertainty that the first subsystem has aconfiguration q1 must be independent from the configuration of the second subsystem q2.

    One must thus have dI12(q1|q2) =dI1(q1). Inserting into Eq. (23), one therefore concludesthat in general the total infinitesimal change of the uncertainty that the two non-interacting

    subsystems have a configuration q= (q1, q2) is decomposable as

    dI(q1, q2) =dI1(q1) +dI2(q2). (24)

    Finally inserting Eqs. (21) and (22) into Eq. (24), in general(dSdA) must also satisfythe following decomposability condition:

    (dS1 dA1) + (dS2 dA2)

    = (dS1 dA1) +(dS2 dA2). (25)

    The above functional equation together with the necessary condition for Macroscopic Clas-

    sicality of Eq. (17) can then be solved to give the following linear solution:

    (dS dA) = (; t)(dS dA), (26)

    where is a real-valued function independent from dS dA, yet might depend on t and,hence is randomly fluctuating within a microscopic time scale. Let us emphasize that Eq.

    (26) now applies for general cases, not only for a compound of non-interacting subsystems.

    For the reason that will be clear later, let us introduce a new non-vanishing random vari-

    able(; t) = 2/. The change of the uncertainty that the system has a certain configuration

    along an infinitesimally short pathJ() of Eq. (4) is thus given by

    dI= d ln =dt +2

    (dS dA). (27)

    12

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    13/36

    Further, since is fixed during the time interval dt, one can expand all the differentials as

    dF =tF dt+qF dq to have the following pair of coupled partial differential equations:

    qln = 2

    qSp(q)

    ,

    tln = 2H(q, p) +tS +(S), (28)

    where we have made use of Eq. (1). The spatial and temporal changes of the uncertainty

    that the system has a certain configuration are thus related to the momentum and energy

    of the system, respectively. Let us emphasize that the above pair of equations are valid only

    for a time interval in which is constant.

    For later convenient let us write the pair of coupled equations of Eq. (28) as follows:

    p(q) = qS+ 2

    q

    ,

    H(q, p) = tS+ 2

    t

    +

    2(S), (29)

    where the momentum and energy are put on the left hand side. The above pair of relations

    must notbe interpreted that the momentum or velocity and energy of the system are deter-

    minedcausallyby the change of the uncertainty, which is physically absurd. Rather both the

    momentum and energy provide the source of change of the uncertainty that the system has

    a certain configuration along an infinitesimally short trajectory J() as shown explicitly byEq. (27). Further, it is evident that in the formal limit 0 whose physical meaning willbe clarified in the next subsection, Eq. (29) reduces back to the Hamilton-Jacobi equation

    of (2). In this sense, Eq. (29) can be regarded as a generalization of the Hamilton-Jacobi

    equation. Unlike the Hamilton-Jacobi equation in which we have a single unknown function

    A, however, to calculate the velocity or momentum and energy, one now needs a pair of

    unknown functions Sand .

    D. A stochastic processes with a transition probability given by an exponential

    distribution of deviation from infinitesimal stationary action

    We have started from a stochastic processes in which the system with a configuration

    qat time t can take one of many possible random pathsJ() selected by the principle ofstationary action with different random values of, to end up with a configurationq+ dqat

    13

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    14/36

    timet+dt. We then derived a law of infinitesimal change of the uncertainty of an event along

    an infinitesimally short path by imposing the condition of Macroscopic Classicality and the

    principle of Locality. It is then tempting to investigate if the law of change of uncertainty

    given by Eq. (27) completely determines the stochastic processes. To see this, fixing , let

    {(q+ dq; t+dt), (q; t)}J() denotes the conditional joint-probability density that theconfiguration of the system is q at time t, tracing the trajectoryJ() and end up with aconfiguration q+dqat time d+dt. Using this quantity, the change of probability density

    d due to the transport along the pathJ() is given by

    d(q, ; t) = {(q+dq; t+dt), (q; t)}J() (q, ; t). (30)

    Inserting into Eq. (27) one therefore has

    {(q+dq; t+dt), (q; t)}J()

    =

    1 (S)dt 2

    (dS dA)(q, ; t). (31)Let us then consider the case when |(dSdA)/| 1. Equation (31) can then be written

    approximately as

    {(q+dq; t+dt), (q; t)}

    J()

    e

    2(dS()dA())(S)dt

    (q, ; t). (32)

    The above relation can obviously be read within the conventional probability theory as

    follows: the joint-probability density that the system initially at (q; t) traces the segment

    of trajectoryJ() and end up at (q+dq; t+dt), {(q+dq; t+dt), (q; t)}J(), is equalto the probability that the configuration of the system is qat time t, (q, ; t), multiplied

    by a transition probability between the two infinitesimally close spacetime points via the

    segment of trajectoryJ() given by

    P((q+dq; t+dt)|{J(), (q; t)}) e 2 (dS()dA())/Z, (33)

    whereZ= exp((S)dt).Some notes are instructive. First, to guarantee the normalizability of the above transition

    probability, then the exponent (dS()dA())/() must be non-negative for any spacetimepoint (q, t). This demands that dS() dA() must always have the same sign as (). Onthe other hand, from Eq. (14), one can see thatdS() dA() changes its sign as flips its

    14

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    15/36

    sign. Hence, to guarantee the non-negativity of (dS() dA())/(), must also changeits sign as flips its sign. This allows us to assume that the sign of is always the same

    as that of. The time scale for the fluctuations of the sign of must therefore be the same

    as the time scale for the fluctuations of given by dt. Moreover, the second term on the

    right hand side of Eq. (27), , namely the rate of production of uncertainty due to the

    fluctuations of infinitesimal stationary action is always non-negative.

    It is also evident that for the distribution of Eq. (33) to make sense mathematically, the

    time scale for the fluctuations of||, denoted by , must be much larger than that of||.One thus has

    dt. (34)In other words,

    |

    |fluctuates much faster than

    |

    |, yet both and always have the same

    sign fluctuating randomly in the time scale dt. Hence, within a time interval of length

    during which|| is effectively constant, one may assume that dS() dA() is randomlyfluctuating due to the fluctuations of || distributed according to the exponential law of Eq.(33) characterized by||.

    Next, there is no a priori reason on how the sign of the values of dS dA should bedistributed. Following the principle of indifference (principle of insufficient reason) [68], it is

    then advisable to assume that the sign ofdS dA is distributed equally probably. Further,since the sign ofdS() dA() changes as flips its sign, then the sign ofmust also befluctuating randomly with equal probability so that the probability density of the value of

    at any given time, denoted below by PH(), must satisfy the following unbiased condition:

    PH() = PH(). (35)

    Since the sign of is always the same as that ofthen the probability distribution function

    of must also satisfy the same unbiased condition. Further, since PH() =

    dq(q, ; t),

    then Eq. (35) demands the following symmetry relation:

    (q, ; t) = (q, ; t). (36)

    One also has, from Eq. (13), the following symmetry relations for the spatiotemporal gra-

    dient ofS(q, ; t):

    qS(q; t, ) = qS(q; t, ),tS(q; t, ) = tS(q; t, ), (37)

    15

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    16/36

    which together with Eq. (36) will play important role later.

    Recall that the pair of relations in Eqs. (28) or (29) are valid when is fixed. However,

    since as discussed above, the second term on the right hand side of Eq. (27) is insensitive

    to the sign of which is always the same as the sign of , then the pair of equations in

    (29) are valid in a microscopic time interval of length during which the magnitude of

    is constant while its sign may change randomly. To have an evolution for a finite time

    interval t > , one can proceed along the following approximation. First one divides the

    time into a series of microscopic time intervals of length : t [(k 1), k),k = 1, 2, . . . ,and attributes to each interval a random value of (t) = k according to the probability

    distributionPHk(k) =PHk(k). Hence, during the interval [(k 1), k), the magnitudeof(t) =k is kept constant while its sign changes randomly in an infinitesimal time scale

    dt. One then applies the pair of relations in Eqs. (28) or (29) during each interval of time

    with fixed|(t)| = |k|, consecutively.SincedA is just the infinitesimal stationary action along the short pathJ(),|dS dA|

    may be regarded as the deviation from infinitesimal stationary action, the distribution of

    which is given by Eq. (33). Such an exponential distribution was firstly suggested heuristi-

    cally in Ref. [69] to model a microscopic stochastic deviation from classical mechanics. An

    application of the statistical model to model quantum measurement is given recently in Ref.

    [70]. For a fixed value of|| which is valid during a time interval of length , one can seefrom Eq. (33) that the average deviation from infinitesimal stationary action is given by

    |dS dA| = ||/2. (38)

    It is then evident that in the regime where the average deviation is much smaller than the

    infinitesimal stationary action itself, namely|dA/| 1, or formally in the limit|| 0,Eq. (33) reduces to

    (dS

    dA), (39)

    so that dS()dA(). Such a regime thus must be identified as the macroscopic regime.This fact suggests that || must have a very small microscopic value. In this regard, the pairof equations in (29) may be regarded as a generalization of the Hamilton-Jacobi equation of

    (2) due to the exponential distribution of deviation from infinitesimal stationary action of

    Eq. (33). Let us also note that since || in general may depend on time, then the transitionprobability is in general notstationary except when =Q all the time, whereQ is a

    16

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    17/36

    constant. We shall in the next section and appendix consider a stationary case of empirical

    interest whenQ = .One can also see that the decomposability of the infinitesimal change of the uncertainty

    for a pair of spacelike separated subsystems given by Eq. (24), which is demanded by the

    principle of Local-Causality, implies directly the separability of the transition probability of

    Eq. (33) for the non-interacting subsystems. Namely, for non-interacting two subsystems

    such that dA and dSare decomposable as dA(q1, q2) =dA1(q1) +dA2(q2) and dS(q1, q2) =

    dS1(q1) + dS2(q2), respectively, so that is also decomposable(q1, q2) =1(q1) + 2(q2), the

    transition probability of Eq. (33) is separable as

    PS(dS1+dS|dA1+dA2) =PS(dS1|dA1)PS(dS2|dA2). (40)

    Hence, the transition probability which determines the stochastic behavior of one subsystem

    is independent from that of the other subsystem as intuitively expected for spacelike sepa-

    rated non-interacting subsystems. Otherwise, the dynamics and statistics of one subsystem

    is influenced by the other subsystem, which contradicts the principle of Locality. See also

    Ref. [71] for a different approach to single out Eq. (33) by imposing the principle of Locality

    without directly employing the concept of information.

    III. QUANTIZATION

    A. The Schrodinger equation and Borns statistical interpretation of wave function

    Let us apply the above general formalism to stochastically modify a classical system of

    a single particle subjected to external potentials so that the classical Hamiltonian takes the

    following general form:

    H(q, p) =gij(q)

    2

    (pi

    ai)(pj

    aj) +V, (41)

    where ai(q), i = x, y, z and V(q) are vector and scalar potentials respectively, the metric

    gij(q) may depend on the position of the particle, and summation over repeated indices

    are assumed. The application to many particles system with different kind of classical

    Hamiltonians can be done in the same way by following exactly all the steps that we are

    going to take below. In the appendix we shall give another example of the application of the

    statistical model to a system of two interacting particles which is commonly used to model

    17

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    18/36

    the measurement of physical quantities, the detail elaboration of which is reported recently

    in Ref. [70].

    Let us first consider a time interval of length during which the magnitude of is

    effectively constant while its sign fluctuates randomly together with the random fluctuations

    of the sign of in a time scale dt. Let us then divide it into a series of microscopic time

    intervals of length , [(k 1), k), k = 1, 2, . . . and attribute to each interval a randomvalue of(t) =k according to the probability distribution PHk(k) = PHk(k). Hence, ineach interval, the magnitude of(t) = k is constant while its sign changes randomly and

    the pair of equations in (29) with fixed|k| apply.Let us first consider a microscopic time interval [(k 1), k). Within this interval of

    time, using Eq. (41) to express qin term ofp via the (kinematic part of the) usual Hamilton

    equation q= H/p, one has, by the virtue of the upper equation of (29)

    qi() =gij

    qjS() +

    2

    qj()

    () aj

    . (42)

    Assuming the conservation of probability one thus obtains the following continuity equation:

    0 =t +q (q)=t +qi

    gij(qjS aj)

    +

    2qi(g

    ijqj). (43)

    On the other hand, from Eq. (41),(S) defined in Eqs. (8) and (18) is given by

    (S) =qigij(qjS aj). (44)

    Using the above form of(S), the lower equation of (29) thus becomes

    H(q, p) = tS+ 2

    t

    +

    2qig

    ij(qjS aj). (45)

    Plugging the upper equation of (29) into the left hand side of Eq. (45) and using Eq. (41)

    one has, after arrangement

    tS+g ij

    2 (qiS ai)(qjS aj) +V

    2

    2

    gij

    qiqjR

    R +qig

    ijqjR

    R

    +

    2

    t +qi

    gij(qjS aj)

    +

    2qi(g

    ijqj)

    = 0, (46)

    where we have defined R .=

    and used the identity:

    1

    4

    qi

    qj

    =

    1

    2

    qiqj

    qiqjR

    R . (47)

    18

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    19/36

    Inserting Eq. (43), the last line of Eq. (46) vanishes to give

    tS+g ij

    2 (qiS ai)(qjS aj) +V

    2

    2 gij

    qiqjR

    R

    +qigij

    qjR

    R = 0. (48)We have thus a pair of coupled equations (43) and (48) which are parameterized by. Recall

    that the above pair of equations are valid in a microscopic time interval of length during

    which the magnitude ofis constant while its sign changes randomly with equal probability.

    Moreover, recall also that the sign of is always the same as the sign of. Keeping this in

    mind, averaging Eq. (43) for the cases, thus is also over, one has, by the virtue ofEqs. (36) and (37),

    t +qigij(qjS aj)= 0. (49)Similarly, averaging Eq. (48) over the cases will not change anything. We have thusfinally a pair of coupled equations (48) and (49) which are now parameterized by a constant

    ||, valid during a microscopic time interval of length characterized by a constant||.Next, since|| is non-vanishing, one can define the following complex-valued function:

    .=

    exp

    iS

    ||

    . (50)

    Using , recalling the assumption that|| is constant during the time interval of interestof length , the pair of Eqs. (48) and (49) can then be recast into the following modified

    Schrodinger equation:

    i||t =12

    (i||qi ai)gij(q)(i||qj aj) +V. (51)

    Notice that the above equation is valid only for a microscopic time interval [(n 1), n)during which the magnitude of=n is constant. For finite time interval t > , one must

    then apply Eq. (51) consecutively to each time intervals of length with different randomvalues of|n|,n = 1, 2, 3, . . . .

    Let us then consider a specific case when|| is given by the reduced Planck constant for all the time, namely = , so that the exponential distribution of the deviation frominfinitesimal stationary action of Eq. (33) is stationary and the average deviation is given

    by

    /2. (52)

    19

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    20/36

    Let us further assume that the fluctuations of|| around its average is sufficiently narrow.In this case, one may approximate (q, ||; t) and S(q; t, |n|) by the corresponding zerothorder terms of their Taylor expansion around the average of||, respectively denoted byQ(q; t) and SQ(q; t). The zeroth order approximation of Eq. (51) therefore reads

    itQ(q; t) = HQ(q; t),

    Q(q; t) .=

    Q(q; t)eiSQ(q;t), (53)

    where His just the quantum Hamiltonian given by

    H=1

    2(pi ai)gij(q)(pj aj) +V, (54)

    with pi.

    =iqi is the quantum mechanical Hermitian momentum operator. Unlike Eq.

    (51), Eq. (53) is now deterministic and is parameterized by . Moreover, from Eq. (53), onecan see that the Borns statistical interpretation of wave function is valid by construction

    Q(q; t) = |Q(q; t)|2. (55)

    Hence, for the specific type of classical Hamiltonian with a quadratic momentum given

    in Eq. (41), one regains the results of canonical quantization. The rules of canonical

    quantization thus effectively arise from a statistical modification of classical mechanics in

    microscopic regime based on a specific law of change of the uncertainty that the system has a

    certain configuration of Eq. (27) chosen uniquely by imposing the condition of Macroscopic

    Classicality and the principle of Local-Causality. Unlike the canonical quantization which is

    formal-mathematical with obscure physical meaning, the statistical model of quantization

    is thus physical. As shown above, Planck constant acquires a physical interpretation as

    the average deviation from classical mechanics in a microscopic time scale. Moreover, unlike

    canonical quantization which in general leads to an infinite number of possible quantum

    Hamiltonians if gij in Eq. (41) depends on q due to operators ordering ambiguity, the

    statistical model gives a unique quantum Hamiltonian with a specific ordering of operatorsof Eq. (54) where gij(q) is sandwiched by p a= iq a.

    B. Configuration as beable and quantum mechanical average

    Recall that in standard quantum mechanics, the state of the system is assumed to be de-

    termined completely by specifying the wave function. The wave function is thus regarded as

    20

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    21/36

    fundamental. Statements about position and momentum are then relegated operationallyto

    certain acts of measurement over the state of the system represented by the wave function.

    The canonical uncertainty relation between the statistical results of position and momentum

    measurement is usually mentioned to support the argumentation that it is in general impos-

    sible to attribute a pair of definite values of position and momentum to a system, nor such an

    attribution is useful. By contrast, in the statistical model of quantization developed in the

    present paper, one assumes the objective ontology of particles with a definite configuration

    for all the time as in classical mechanics. Hence, configuration of the system is regarded as

    the beable of the theory in Bells sense [72]. The wave function, on the other hand, is

    argued to be emergent artificial convenient mathematical tool to describe the dynamics and

    statistics of ensemble of trajectories. The objective ontology of the trajectories guarantees

    a conceptually smooth classical correspondence.

    For general types of classical Hamiltonian, the velocities of the particles are then obtained

    by first solving p(q) on the left hand side of the upper equation of (29) in term of qto have

    q() =H

    p

    p=qS()+

    ()2

    q()

    ()

    . (56)Hence, the velocities of the particles are fluctuating randomly due to the fluctuations of.

    The configuration of the system therefore follows a continuous and randomly fluctuating

    trajectory. Since, as argued in the previous section, in the limit || 0 which is interpretedphysically to correspond to classical regime, one has dS dA, then one can see that in thislimit, Eq. (56) reduces to the classical relation q= H

    p|p=qA. We have thus a formally and

    conceptually smooth classical correspondence.

    Note again that fixing ||, Eq. (56) is valid only within a time interval of length duringwhich the sign ofis fluctuating randomly. It is then natural to define an effective velocity

    as

    q(||) .=

    q() + q()2

    . (57)

    For the type of classical Hamiltonian given by Eq. (41), Eq. (56) reduces to Eq. (42). Let

    us now consider the case when the classical Hamiltonian is given by Eq. (41) withgij = 1/m

    and ai = 0, describing a particle of mass m subjected to an external scalar potential V(q).

    Let us again consider a specific case when = so that the average of the deviation frominfinitesimal stationary action distributed according to Eq. (33) is given by /2, and as

    shown in the previous subsection, one regains the prediction of canonical quantization. In

    21

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    22/36

    this case, the zeroth order approximation of Eq. (42) then reads

    q=qSQ

    m

    2m

    qQQ

    , (58)

    where the

    signs change randomly with equal probability. Moreover, calculating the

    effective velocity one gets, recalling that the sign of is the same as that of, and taking

    into account Eqs. (36) and (37),

    q= qSQ/m, (59)which, unlike Eqs. (42) and (58), is now deterministic due to the deterministic time evolution

    ofSQ given by the Schrodinger equation of (53). Hence, q in general fluctuates randomly

    around qSQ/m except when the particle happens to lie at the extremum points ofQ so

    that the second term of Eq. (58) vanishes and one has q= qSQ/m.

    One thus expects that the actual trajectory of the particle is in general fluctuating ran-

    domly around the integration over time of the effective velocityq=qSQ/m. The latter isjust the Bohmian trajectory of the particle in pilot-wave theory [73]. Hence, we have a physi-

    cal picture that the actual trajectory is fluctuating randomly around the Bohmian trajectory

    while the latter moves as if it is guided by the wave function evolving deterministically ac-

    cording to the Schrodinger equation. Yet, unlike the pilot-wave theory, the wave function

    in the statistical model is notphysically real but an artificial mathematical construct, and

    the Schrodinger equation and the guidance relation of Eqs. (53) and (59) are derived from

    first principle rather than ad-hoc-ly postulated as in pilot-wave theory. Recall that the fun-

    damental assumption in pilot-wave theory that the wave function is a physical field, living

    in configuration space rather than in ordinary space, is known to lead to a conceptual diffi-

    culty, and furthermore implies rigid nonlocality in direct conflict with the special theory of

    relativity. By contrast, the present statistical model is developed based on the principle of

    Locality. In this sense, the upper equation in (29) can not be regarded as a causal-dynamical

    guidance relation as in pilot-wave theory, but a kinematical relation. Moreover, unlike the

    pilot-wave theory which is deterministic and relegates the microscopic randomness to our

    ignorance of the initial condition, the statistical model is strictly stochastic.

    It is then imperative to calculate the statistical averages of the relevant physical quantities

    over all possible configuration distributed according to (q, ; t). It is natural to ask how

    such statistical averages are related to quantum mechanical averages. For this purpose, we

    22

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    23/36

    should again assume that = with equal probability in case of which the statisticalmodel reproduces the results of canonical quantization as the zeroth order approximation.

    First, the average of any function of the configuration O(q) at any time is given by

    O(q) .

    = dqdO(q) = dqdO(q)

    dqQO(q)Q.

    = Q|O(q)|Q, (60)

    where we have again counted only the zeroth order terms. Numerically, it is thus equal to

    the quantum mechanical average of a quantum mechanical observable O(q) =O(q) when

    the state of the system is given by the wave function Q. In particular, for the cases

    O(q) =qandO(q) = (qq)2, the left hand side of Eq. (60) are the average and standarddeviation of the fluctuations ofq, which are numerically equal to the quantum mechanical

    average of position operator and its standard deviation over the state Q given by the right

    hand side.

    Let us further calculate the average of the actual value of momentum p at a given time.

    One directly gets, from the upper equation in (29)

    p =

    dqd

    qS+

    2

    q

    =

    dqd(qS) =

    dqd(i||q)

    dqQ(iq)Q .= Q|p|Q, (61)where in the second equality we have used Eqs. (36) and (37) and taken into account the

    fact that the sign of is the same as that of, and in the last approximate equality we have

    imposed = and counted only the zeroth order terms. Again, it is numerically given bythe quantum mechanical average of momentum operator p= iq over the state Q.

    Let us proceed to calculate the average of a quantity which is a function of momentum

    up to second degree. Such a quantity can always be put into a quadratic form. It is thus

    sufficient to calculate the average of a quantity of the type O(q, p) =a(p f(q))2, where ais constant andf(q) is a vector-valued function. One directly gets

    O(q, p) =

    a

    qS+

    2

    q

    f(q)

    2=

    a2

    4

    q

    2+ a(qS f(q))2

    =

    dqda

    i||q f(q)2 Q|ap f(q)2|Q. (62)

    23

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    24/36

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    25/36

    over all possible configuration of the system are equal to the quantum mechanical average

    of the corresponding quantum observables represented by some Hermitian operators O over

    a wave function Q representing the corresponding quantum mechanical state:

    O .= dqdO(q, p) Q|O|Q, (67)where means that we have considered the case when= and counted only the zerothorder terms. It is then tempting to guess that the above conclusion applies for all quantities

    of a function of position and momentum O(q, p). One can however show that this is not

    the case. For example, averaging O = p3, regardless of its physical meaning and proceeding

    as before, one can check thatp3 =Q|p3|Q. Let us further emphasize however thatwhileQ|O|Q in the standard quantum mechanics refers to the average of the outcomesof measurement over an ensemble of identically prepared state represented by Q,Oin the statistical model refers to the objective properties of the ensemble independent of

    measurement.

    C. The principle of Locality, linearity of quantum dynamics and uncertainty re-

    lation

    Notice that as argued in the previous section, the unique form of the law of infinitesimalchange of the degree of uncertainty that the system has a certain configuration along a short

    path given by Eq. (27) is singled out by imposing the condition of Macroscopic Classicality

    and the principle of Locality. In particular, the principle of Locality is decisive in selecting

    the linear form of the second term on the right hand side of Eq. (27) which describes the

    production of information or uncertainty due to the fluctuation of infinitesimal stationary

    action. Since the stochastic processes based on such a change of the information leads to

    the derivation of the linearSchrodinger equation, one may thus argue that the principle of

    Locality expressed in Eq. (25) is a necessary condition for the linearity of the Schrodinger

    equation. To support this argumentation, let us mention that a nonlinear extension of

    quantum dynamics[74] may lead to signaling [75,76] thus violating the principle of Locality.

    The importance of the linearity of the Schrodinger equation can not be over emphasized.

    It gives the mathematical basis for the superposition principle which plays very crucial

    roles for the explanation of particle interference in double slits experiment, quantum entan-

    25

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    26/36

    glement, and also in quantum measurement. The linearity of the Schrodinger equation is

    also responsible for another important characteristic trait of quantum mechanics that it is

    impossible to copy an unknown quantum state, the no-cloning theory [7779].

    Let us proceed to show that the principle of Locality also plays a very important role in the

    derivation of the quantum mechanical uncertainty relation. First, as argued in the previous

    subsection, the actual trajectory of the system in configuration space is fluctuating randomly

    around the Bohmian trajectory. It is then imperative to ask how the fluctuations around the

    Bohmian trajectory is distributed. First, from the normalization of ,

    dqd(q, ) = 1,

    and the assumption that |q= 0 which is valid for arbitrary value of, one has

    1 =

    dqd =

    dqd(q q0)q

    = dqd{(q q0)}q, (68)where q0 is an arbitrary real number and the integration over spatial coordinate is taken

    fromq= toq= . Applying the Schwartz inequality one gets dqd(q q0)2

    dqd

    q

    2 1. (69)

    Substituting Eq. (42), considering the case when g ij = 1/mand ai= 0, one directly obtains

    dqd(q q0)2

    dqd(mq qS)2

    2

    4. (70)

    Let us again consider a specific case when =. The zeroth order approximation ofthe above inequality therefore reads [80]

    dq(q q0)2Q(q)

    dq(mq qSQ)2(q) 2

    4. (71)

    One then sees that the width of the fluctuations ofmqaroundqSQis bounded from below

    by the inverse of the width of the distribution ofqand vise-versa, in a similar fashion as the

    standard quantum mechanical uncertainty relation.

    On the other hand, from Eqs. (60) and (63), one has

    (q q)2(p p)2= Q|(q q)2|QQ|(p p)2|Q

    2

    4, (72)

    where the inequality is due to [q,p] = i. Hence, the width of the distribution of the

    actual momentum is bounded from below by the inverse of the width of the distribution of

    26

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    27/36

    the actual position in the ensemble, in exactly the same manner as the standard quantum

    mechanical uncertainty relation. Let us emphasize again that unlike the former which is

    objective referring to no measurement, the latter is referring to the statistical results of

    measurement of position and momentum over an ensemble of identically prepared system.

    The above uncertainty relation is related to the uncertainty relation of Eq. (71) via the

    fact that

    (p p)2

    2

    q

    2+ (qSQ qSQ)2

    2

    q

    2=

    (mq qSQ)2

    , (73)

    where in the first approximate equality we have used Eqs. (58) and (61) and taking into

    account Eqs. (36) and (37) and the fact that the sign ofis always the same as the sign of,

    and the last equality is due again to Eq. (58). Multiplying both sides with (qq0)2, takingq0 =q and imposing Eq. (71), one obtains Eq. (72). Hence, the quantum mechanicaluncertainty relation can be derived starting from the upper equation in Eq. (29). Since,

    as argued in the previous section, the pair of equations in (29) are derived by imposing

    the principle of Locality, then one may also conclude that the latter is necessary for the

    derivation of quantum mechanical uncertainty relation.

    IV. CONCLUSION AND REMARKS

    We first developed a stochastic processes for a microscopic stochastic deviation from

    classical mechanics in which the randomness is modeled by a stochastic fluctuations of the

    infinitesimal stationary action, thus is physically different from that of the Brownian motion

    based on random forces. Such a stochastic processes leads to a production of the uncertainty

    that the system has a certain configuration in a microscopic time scale, which is assumed

    to be vanishing in the classical limit of macroscopic regime. We then showed that imposingthe principle of Locality, which requires the infinitesimal change of the uncertainty that a

    subsystem has a certain configuration to be independent from the configuration of the other

    spacelike separated subsystem, will select a unique law of infinitesimal change of uncertainty,

    up to a free parameter. We then further showed that such a law of infinitesimal change of

    uncertainty determines a stochastic processes with a transition probability between two

    infinitesimally close spacetime points along a randomly chosen path that is given by an

    27

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    28/36

    exponential distribution of deviation from infinitesimal stationary action.

    Given a classical Hamiltonian, we showed that the statistical model leads to the deriva-

    tion of Schrodinger equation with Borns statistical interpretation of wave function and

    uncertainty relation, two of the cornerstones of standard quantum mechanics. Unlike the

    canonical quantization, however, in the statistical model, the system always has a definite

    configuration all the time as in classical mechanics, fluctuating randomly along a continuous

    trajectory. We have also shown, for a system of spin-less particles, that the average of the

    relevant physical quantities over the distribution of the configuration is numerically equal

    to the quantum mechanical average of the corresponding quantum mechanical Hermitian

    operators over a quantum state represented by a wave function. Since the principle of Lo-

    cality is derived from our conception of spacetime structure, then one may conclude that

    the dynamics and kinematics of quantum mechanics is intimately related to the former.

    Some problems are left for future study. It is first imperative to ask how such a local-

    causal statistical model would explain the violation of Bells inequalities predicted by the

    quantum mechanics and verified in numerous experiments which is widely believed to give

    strong evidences that Nature is nonlocal? This is a crucial problem needed an explanation

    within the statistical model. Recall that Bells inequalities are derived by assuming 1) the

    separability of probability of outcomes in a pair of spacelike joint-measurements (Bells lo-

    cality assumption) and 2) the so-called measurement independence or experimental free-will,that the distribution of the hidden variables underlying the measurement outcomes is inde-

    pendent from the setting parameters of the apparatus chosen freely by the observer [8184].

    It is tempting to guess that the objective locality of the statistical model implies the Bells

    locality assumption so that the model must somehow violate measurement independence. It

    is therefore instructive to study the above two fundamental hypothesis within the statistical

    model by first applying the model to develop quantum measurement in realistic physical

    systems and derive the Borns rule.

    Next, it is also tempting to ask why canonical quantization corresponds to a specific

    case when|| in Eq. (27), the free parameter of the statistical model, is given by sothat the average deviation from infinitesimal stationary action distributed according to the

    exponential law of Eq. (33) is given by /2. Is the relation|| = exact? Or whetherNature allows for a small fluctuations of|| around ? Recall also that the Schrodingerequation is derived as the zeroth order approximation of the statistical model. It is then

    28

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    29/36

    imperative to study the higher orders corrections. These last two cases may thus provide

    precision tests against quantum mechanics.

    Acknowledgments

    Appendix A: Quantization of classical mechanical model for the measurement of

    angular momentum

    To show the robustness of the statistical model, let us give an application of the model to a

    system of two interacting particles. Let us assume that the interaction classical Hamiltonian

    is given by

    HI=glz1p2, with lz1 =x1py1 y1px1. (A1)Here g is an interaction coupling, and lz1 is the zpart angular momentum of the firstparticle. Let us further assume that the interaction is impulsive (g is sufficiently strong) so

    that the single particle Hamiltonians, of the type given by Eq. (41), are ignorable.

    The interaction Hamiltonian above can be used as a classical mechanical model of mea-

    surement of the angular momentum lz1 of the first particle by regarding the position of the

    second particle as the pointer of the apparatus of measurement. To see this, first, in such

    a model lz1 is conserved: lz1 ={lz1, HI}= 0 where{, } is the usual Poisson bracket. The

    interaction Hamiltonian of Eq. (A1) thus correlates the value of lz1 with the momentum

    of the apparatus p2 while keeping the value oflz1 unchanged. On the other hand, one also

    has q2 ={q2, HI} = glz1, which, noting the fact that lz1 is a constant of motion, can beintegrated to give

    q2(tM) =q2(0) +glz1tM, (A2)

    where tM is the time span of the interaction. The value of lz1 prior to the interaction can

    thus in principle be inferred from the observation of the initial and final values ofq2. Inthis way, the measurement of the physical quantity lz1 of the first particle is reduced to the

    measurement of the position of the second particle q2. In the model, q2(t) therefore plays

    the role of the pointer of the apparatus of measurement.

    Now let us apply the statistical model discussed in the main text to stochastically modify

    the above classical mechanical model of measurement. We shall repeat all the steps and

    manipulations performed in the main text. What we need to do is to put the Hamiltonian

    29

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    30/36

    of Eq. (A1) in place of Eq. (41). Again, let us first consider a time interval of the scale

    in which the absolute value of is effectively constant while its sign fluctuates randomly

    together with the random fluctuations of the sign of. Let us then divide it into a series of

    microscopic time intervals of length , [(k

    1), k), k = 1, 2, . . . and attribute to each

    interval a random value of (t) = k according to the probability distribution PHk(k) =

    PHk(k) so that in each interval, the magnitude of is constant while its sign changesrandomly. During each time interval [(k 1), k), the pair of equations in Eq. (29), eachwith constant value of|k|, thus apply.

    Let us first consider a microscopic time interval [(k 1), k). Using the form of HIgiven by Eq. (A1) to express q in term ofp via q = H/p, the upper equation of (29)

    becomes

    x1= gy1

    q2S+

    2

    q2

    , y1= gx1

    q2S+

    2

    q2

    ,

    q2= g

    x1

    y1S+

    2

    y1

    y1

    x1S+

    2

    x1

    , (A3)

    and z1 = 0. Again, assuming that the probability is conserved, one gets, after a simple

    calculation, the following continuity equation:

    0 =t +q (q)

    =t gy1x1(q2S) +gx1y1(q2S) +gx1q2(y1S)gy1q2(x1S) g(y1x1q2 x1y1q2). (A4)

    On the other hand, from Eq. (A1),(S) defined in Eqs. (8) and (18) is given by

    (S) = 2g(x1q2y1S y1q2x1S). (A5)

    Substituting this into the lower equation of (29), one then obtains

    HI(q, p) = tS+ 2

    t

    +g(x1y1q2S y1x1q2S). (A6)

    Inserting the upper equation of (29) into the left hand side of the above equation, and using

    30

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    31/36

    Eq. (A1), one has, after arrangement

    tS+g

    x1y1S y1x1S

    q2S g2

    x1y1q2R

    R

    y1x1q2RR

    +

    2t gy1x1(q2S)

    +gx1y1(q2S) +gx1q2(y1S) gy1q2(x1S)g(y1x1q2 x1y1q2)

    = 0, (A7)

    where R =

    and we have again used the identity of Eq. (47). Substituting Eq. (A4), the

    last term of Eq. (A7) in the bracket vanishes to give

    tS+g

    x1y1S y1x1S

    q2S

    g2

    x1

    y1q2R

    R y1x1q2R

    R = 0. (A8)

    One thus has a pair of coupled equations (A4) and (A8) which are parameterized by .

    This pair of equations are valid in a microscopic time interval of length during which the

    magnitude ofis constant while its sign changes randomly with equal probability. Averaging

    Eq. (A4) over the cases, recalling that the sign of is the same as that of, one has, bythe virtue of Eqs. (36) and (37),

    t gy1x1(q2SQ) +gx1y1(q2SQ)

    +gx1q2(y1SQ) gy1q2(x1SQ) = 0. (A9)On the other hand, averaging Eq. (A8) over the cases does not change anything. Wefinally have a pair of Eqs. (A8) and (A9) which are now parameterized by|| valid for amicroscopic time interval of duration characterized by a constant||.

    Next, using defined in Eq. (50), and recalling that || is constant during the microscopictime interval of interest with length , the pair of Eqs. (A8) and (A9) can then be recast

    into the following compact form:

    i||t = 22

    HI. (A10)

    Here HIis a differential operator defined as

    HI.

    =glz1 p2, (A11)

    where pi =iqi , i= 1, 2, are the quantum mechanical momentum operator referring tothe iparticle and lz1 .= x1py1 y1px1 is the zpart of the quantum mechanical angular

    31

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    32/36

    momentum operator pertaining to the first particle; all are Hermitian. Recall that Eq.

    (A10) is valid only for a microscopic time interval [(k 1), k) during which|| =|k|is constant. For finite time interval, t > one must then apply Eq. (A10) to each time

    intervals, each is parameterized by a random value of

    |k

    |,k = 1, 2, . . . , consecutively.

    Let us again consider a specific case when || = . Moreover, let us further assumethat the fluctuations of|| around its average is sufficiently narrow so that (q, ||; t) andS(q; t, ||) can be approximated by the corresponding zeroth order terms, given respectivelybyQ(q; t) andSQ(q; t). In this case, Eq. (A10) can be approximated as

    itQ(q; t) = HIQ(q; t), (A12)

    where Qis defined as in Eq. (53). Unlike Eq. (A10), Eq. (A12) is now deterministic and is

    parameterized by the reduced Planck constant

    . Equation (A12) together with Eq. (A11)is just the Schrodinger equation for the von Neumann model of measurement of angular

    momentum operator lz1 of the first particle using the second particle as the apparatus.

    Without giving the detail, let us mention that the same results will be obtained for the

    measurement of position and linear momentum. In these cases, the interaction classical

    Hamiltonian will be given by

    HI=gO1(q1, p1)p2, (A13)

    where O1

    = q1

    and O1

    =p1, respectively. Proceeding as before, repeating all the steps and

    manipulations performed above, one will arrive at the Schrodinger equation with a quantum

    Hamiltonian given by

    HI=g O1p2, (A14)

    where O1= q1 = q1 and O1 = p1 = iq respectively for the measurement of position andmomentum. The measurement of energy should be reduced to the measurement of position,

    momentum and angular momentum.

    It is then instructive to discuss whether such a model of quantum measurement can

    reproduce the prediction of quantum mechanics. It is also interesting to ask how the model

    addresses the measurement problem. The above two problems are discussed in detail in Ref.

    [70].

    [1] J. S. Bell, Physics1, 195 (1964).

    32

  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    33/36

    [2] J. F. Clauser, M. A. Horne, A. Shimony, R. A. Holt, Phys. Rev. Lett. 23, 880 (1969).

    [3] J. S. Bell, Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics (Cambridge University Press,

    Cambridge, 1987).

    [4] J. Freedman and J. F. Clauser, Phys. Rev. Lett.28, 938 (1972).

    [5] A. Aspect, P. Grangier and G. Roger, Phys. Rev. Lett. 47, 460 (1981).

    [6] Z. Y. Ou and L. Mandel, Phys. Rev. Lett.61, 50 (1988).

    [7] Y. H. Shih and C. O. Alley, Phys. Rev. Lett. 61, 2921 (1988).

    [8] J. G. Rarity and P. R. Tapster, Phys. Rev. Lett. 64, 2495 (1990).

    [9] Z. Y. Ou, S. F. Pereira, H. J. Kimble and K. C. Peng, Phys. Rev. Lett. 68, 3663 (1992).

    [10] J. Brendel, E. Mohler and W. Martienssen, Europhys. Lett.20, 575 (1992).

    [11] P. G. Kwiat, K. Mattle, H. Weinfurter, A. Zeilinger, A. V. Sergienko and Y. H. Shih, Phys.

    Rev. Lett. 75, 4337 (1995)

    [12] G. Weihs, M. Reck, H. Weinfurter and A. Zeilinger, Phys. Rev. Lett.81, 5039 (1998).

    [13] W. Tittel, J. Brendel, H. Zbinden and N. Gisin, Phys. Rev. Lett. 81, 3563 (1998).

    [14] M. A. Rowe, D. Kielpinski, V. Meyer, C. A. Sackett, W. M. Itano, C. Monroe and D. J.

    Wineland, Nature 149, 791 (2001).

    [15] D. N. Matsukevich, P. Maunz, D. L. Moehring, S. Olmschenk and C. Monroe, Phys. Rev.

    Lett. 100, 150404 (2008).

    [16] D. Salart, A. Baas, C. Branciard, N. Gisin and H. Zbinden, Nature454, 861 (2008).

    [17] E. Santos, Found. Phys. 34, 1643 (2004).

    [18] N. Brunner, D. Cavalcanti, S. Pironio, V. Scarani, and S. Wehner,arXiv:1303.2849v1.

    [19] P. Eberhard, Nuovo Cimento B 46, 392 (1978).

    [20] G. C. Ghirardi, A. Rimini, T. Weber, Lett. Nuovo Cimento 27, 293 (1980).

    [21] D. Page, Phys. Rev. A91, 57 (1982).

    [22] J. Jarrett, Nous 18, 569 (1984).

    [23] A. Shimony in J. Ellis and D. Amati (eds.),Quantum Reflections(Cambridge University Press,

    Cambridge, 2000).

    [24] A. Shimony in Kamefuchi et al. (eds.), Foundations of Quantum Mechanics in Light of the

    New Technology(Tokyo, Japan Physical Society, 1983).

    [25] A. Shimony in R. Penrose and C. Isham (eds.),Quantum Concepts in Space and Time(Oxford,

    Claredon Press, 1986).

    33

    http://arxiv.org/abs/1303.2849http://arxiv.org/abs/1303.2849
  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    34/36

    [26] S. Popescu and D. Rohrlich, Found. Phys.24, 379 (1994).

    [27] J. Grunhaus, S. Popescu and D. Rohrlich, Phys. Rev. A,53, 3781 (1996).

    [28] S. Popescu and D. Rohrlich,arXiv:quant-ph/9709026v2.

    [29] J. A. Wheeler in W. H. Zurek (ed.), Complexity, information content and the physics of

    information(Westview Press, 1990).

    [30] C. Rovelli, Int. J. Theor. Phys.35, 1637 (1996).

    [31] A. Zeilinger, Found. Phys.29, 631 (1999).

    [32] L. Hardy, Quantum theory from five reasonable axioms,quant-ph/0101012.

    [33] C. Simon, V. Buzek and N. Gisin, Phys. Rev. Lett. 87, 170405 (2001).

    [34] R. Clifton, J. Bub and H. Halvorson, Found. Phys. 33, 1561 (2003).

    [35] W. van Dam, Thesis, Univ. Oxford (1999);quant-ph/0501159.

    [36] G. Brassard, H. Buhrman, N. Linden, A. A. Methot, A. Tapp and F. Unger, Phys. Rev. Lett.

    96, 250401 (2006).

    [37] P. Goyal, Phys. Rev. A 78, 052150 (2008).

    [38] M. Pawlowski, T. Paterek, D. Kaszlikowski, V. Scarani, A. Winter and M. Zukowski, Nature

    461, 1101 (2009).

    [39] J. Oppenheim and S Wehner, Science330, 1072 (2010).

    [40] H. Barnum, S. Beigi, S. Boixo, M. B. Elliott and S. Wehner, Phys. Rev. Lett. 104, 140401

    (2010).

    [41] M. Navascues and H. Wunderlich, Proc. R. Soc. A 466, 881 (2010).

    [42] D. Borivoje and C. Brukner in H. Halvorson (ed.), Deep beauty: understanding the quan-

    tum world through mathematical innovation(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011);

    (arXiv:0911.0695)

    [43] L. Masanes and M. P. Muller, New J. Phys. 13, 063001 (2011).

    [44] A. Caticha, J. Phys. A: Math. and Theor. 44, 225303 (2011).

    [45] G. Chiribella, G. M. DAriano and P. Perinotti, Phys. Rev. A 84, 012311 (2011).

    [46] G. de la Torre, L. Masanes, A. J. Short and M. P. Muller, Phys. Rev. Lett. 109, 090403

    (2012).

    [47] D. I. Fivel, Found. Phys.42, 291 (2012).

    [48] M. A. Nielsen and I. Chuang,Quantum Computation and Quantum Information(Cambridge

    University Press, Cambridge, 2000).

    34

    http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9709026http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0101012http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0501159http://arxiv.org/abs/0911.0695http://arxiv.org/abs/0911.0695http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0501159http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0101012http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9709026
  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    35/36

    [49] I. Fenyes, Z. Phys. 132, 81 (1952).

    [50] W. Weizel, Z. Phys.134, 264 (1953); 135, 270 (1953); 136, 582 (1954).

    [51] D. Kershaw, Phys. Rev. 136B, 1850 (1964).

    [52] E. Nelson, Phys. Rev. 150, 1079 (1966).

    [53] L. de la Pena-Auerbach, J. Math. Phys. 10, 1620 (1969).

    [54] M. Davidson, Lett. Math. Phys.3, 271 (1979).

    [55] L. de la Pena-Auerbach and A. M. Cetto, Found. Phys. 12, 1017 (1982).

    [56] Ph. Blanchard, Ph. Combe and W. Zeng, Lecture Notes Physics281, 1 (1987).

    [57] F. Guerra and L. M. Morato, Phys. Rev. D27, 1774 (1983).

    [58] P. Garbaczewski and J. -P. Vigier, Phys. Rev. A 46, 4634 (1992).

    [59] L. de la Pena-Auerbach and A. M. Cetto, The quantum dice: An introduction to stochastic

    electrodynamics(Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, 1996).

    [60] F. Markopoulou and L. Smolin, Phys. Rev. D70, 124029 (2004).

    [61] E. Santos, Phys. Lett. A 352, 49 (2006).

    [62] L. de la Pena-Auerbach, A. Valdes-Hernandes, A. M. Cetto, and H. M. Franca, Phys. Lett. A

    375, 1720 (2011).

    [63] D. Giulini, Lect. Notes Phys.631, 17 (2003); arXiv:quant-ph/0304202v1.

    [64] Y. Aharonov and D. Bohm, Phys. Rev.115, 485 (1959).

    [65] M. Peshkin and A. Tonomura, Lec. Notes. Phys.340 (Springer, Berlin, 1989).

    [66] H. Rund, The Hamilton-Jacobi theory in the calculus of variations: its role in mathematics

    and physics(Van Nostrand, London, 1966).

    [67] Iand its average given by the Gibbs-Shannon entropy also play important roles in optimal

    coding theory. See for example T. M. Cover and J. A. Thomas, Elements of Information

    Theory(John Wiley & Sons, New Jersey, 2006).

    [68] E. T. Jaynes,Probability theory: the logic of science(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,

    2003).

    [69] A. Budiyono, Physica A392, 307 (2013).

    [70] A. Budiyono, J. Stat. Mech.: Theory and Experiment P11007, 1 (2013).

    [71] A. Budiyono, Int. J. Theor. Phys. (2013), in press, DOI:10.1007/s10773-013-1925-4.

    [72] J. S. Bell, Epistemological Letter9, 11 (1976).

    [73] D. Bohm and B. Hiley, The undivided universe: an ontological interpretation of quantum

    35

    http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0304202http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0304202
  • 8/13/2019 Quantum Fluctuations From a Local-causal Information Dynamics - Agung Budiyono

    36/36

    theory (Routledge, London, 1993).

    [74] S. Weinberg, Phys. Rev. Lett. 62, 485 (1989).

    [75] N. Gisin, Phys. Lett. A 143, 1 (1990).

    [76] J. Polchinski, Phys. Ref. Lett.66, 397 (1991).

    [77] W. K. Wootters and W. H. Zurek, Nature299, 802 (1982).

    [78] D. Dieks, Phys. Lett. A92, (1982) 271.

    [79] P. W. Milonni and M. L. Hardies, Phys. Lett. A 92, 321 (1982).

    [80] A. Budiyono, Physica A392, 43 (2013).

    [81] J. S. Bell, Epistemol. Lett. 9, 11 (1976).

    [82] A. Shimony, M. A. Horne, J. S. Clauser, Epistemol. Lett. 13, 9 (1976).

    [83] B. d Espagnat, Phys. Rep. 110, 201 (1984).

    [84] M. J. W. Hall, Phys. Rev. Lett. 105, 250404 (2010).