21
Read about the evidence Aristotle (Aristot. Pol.). [ back to top ] Read about the evidence Aristotle (Aristot. Pol.). Read about the evidence Aristotle (Aristot. Pol.). Demos Home Summary. Introduction. Glossary. Instructions for reading passages. Passages: Defining the City State. Passages: Defining the Citizen. Passages: Defining the System of Government. Passages: Defining Democracy. Passages: Types of Democracy. Passages: Creating Democracy. Passages: Preserving Democracy. Passages: Destroying Democracy. Selective Bibliography. Index of Citations General Index Demos Home Dēmos Classical Athenian Democracy a Stoa Publication [ link colors: Demos | External Source | Citation to Evidence| Word Tools ] section view | home Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle Thomas R. Martin, with Neel Smith & Jennifer F.Stuart, edition of July 26, 2003 (Section 1 of 13) Summary Ancient Greek democracy has regularly aKracted the aKention of modern political scientists as part of the discussion of the theory and practice of democratic systems of government. By far the most important ancient text for this discussion is the Politics of Aristotle. Studying what Aristotle has to say about democracy in the Politics is challenging for several reasons. First of all, his remarks on the subject are spread widely throughout this extended work. The challenge is further increased by the discursive character of Aristotle’s arguments in the Politics, which for one thing mix discussions of theoretical principles for systems of government with observations about actual Greek states of Aristotle’s time (and before it). Finally, there is the strong possibility that the traditionally accepted order of the eight “Books” or chapters of the Politics is not the order in which Aristotle meant his arguments to be presented. (Section 2 of 13) Introduction The goal of this article is to provide one possible aid for those wishing to meet this challenge. It therefore offers a series of topical headings under which selected passages relevant to the study of democracy in the Politics are rearranged. That is, under each topic the passages are listed not in the order in which they occur in the Politics, but are instead arranged in an order that aKempts to suggest connections in thought between Aristotle’s various remarks on democracy. The passages are paraphrased rather than translated word for word, although the paraphrases of the shorter excerpts aKempt to stay as close to the Greek wording as is practical. Since the paraphrased passages are meant to serve as jumpingoff points for consideration of the full text of the Politics, each passage has an active link to the full text of the Politics.A glossary of Greek terms and a very selective bibliography of recommended print readings are also included. Since the approach adopted for this site rearranges the order of material on democracy from the Politics, it necessarily removes each passage from its context in order to suggest connections in thought that might not be easy to

Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

It's not clear what form of government he thought was ideal.

Citation preview

Page 1: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Read  about  the  evidence  Aristotle  (Aristot.  Pol.).

[  back  to  top  ]

Read  about  the  evidence  Aristotle  (Aristot.  Pol.).

Read  about  the  evidence  Aristotle  (Aristot.  Pol.).

Demos  HomeSummary.Introduction.Glossary.Instructions  for  readingpassages.Passages:  Defining  the  CityState.Passages:  Defining  theCitizen.Passages:  Defining  theSystem  of  Government.Passages:  DefiningDemocracy.Passages:  Types  ofDemocracy.Passages:  CreatingDemocracy.Passages:  PreservingDemocracy.Passages:  DestroyingDemocracy.Selective  Bibliography.—Index  of  CitationsGeneral  Index—Demos  Home

Dēmos  ·∙  Classical  Athenian  Democracy  ·∙  a  Stoa  Publication

[  link  colors:  Demos  |  External  Source  |  Citation  to  Evidence|  Word  Tools  ]

section  view    |    home

Democracy  in  the  Politics  of  Aristotle    Thomas  R.  Martin,  with  Neel  Smith  &  Jennifer  F.Stuart,  edition  of  July  26,  2003

(Section  1  of  13)

·∙  Summary  ·∙

Ancient  Greek  democracy  has  regularlyaKracted  the  aKention  of  modern  politicalscientists  as  part  of  the  discussion  of  the  theory  and  practice  ofdemocratic  systems  of  government.  By  far  the  most  important  ancienttext  for  this  discussion  is  the  Politics  of  Aristotle.  Studying  whatAristotle  has  to  say  about  democracy  in  the  Politics  is  challenging  forseveral  reasons.  First  of  all,  his  remarks  on  the  subject  are  spread  widelythroughout  this  extended  work.  The  challenge  is  further  increased  bythe  discursive  character  of  Aristotle’s  arguments  in  the  Politics,  whichfor  one  thing  mix  discussions  of  theoretical  principles  for  systems  ofgovernment  with  observations  about  actual  Greek  states  of  Aristotle’stime  (and  before  it).  Finally,  there  is  the  strong  possibility  that  thetraditionally  accepted  order  of  the  eight  “Books”  or  chapters  of  thePolitics  is  not  the  order  in  which  Aristotle  meant  his  arguments  to  bepresented.

(Section  2  of  13)

·∙  Introduction  ·∙

The  goal  of  this  article  is  to  provide  one  possible  aid  for  thosewishing  to  meet  this  challenge.  It  therefore  offers  a  series  of  topicalheadings  under  which  selected  passages  relevant  to  the  study  of  democracy  in  the  Politics  arerearranged.  That  is,  under  each  topic  the  passages  are  listed  not  in  the  order  in  which  theyoccur  in  the  Politics,  but  are  instead  arranged  in  an  order  that  aKempts  to  suggest  connectionsin  thought  between  Aristotle’s  various  remarks  on  democracy.  The  passages  are  paraphrasedrather  than  translated  word  for  word,  although  the  paraphrases  of  the  shorter  excerptsaKempt  to  stay  as  close  to  the  Greek  wording  as  is  practical.  Since  the  paraphrased  passagesare  meant  to  serve  as  jumping-­‐‑off  points  for  consideration  of  the  full  text  of  the  Politics,  eachpassage  has  an  active  link  to  the  full  text  of  the  Politics.  A  glossary  of  Greek  terms  and  a  veryselective  bibliography  of  recommended  print  readings  are  also  included.

Since  the  approach  adopted  for  this  site  rearranges  the  order  ofmaterial  on  democracy  from  the  Politics,  it  necessarily  removes  eachpassage  from  its  context  in  order  to  suggest  connections  in  thought  that  might  not  be  easy  to

Page 2: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

[  back  to  top  ]

Plot  on  a  Map  United  States.United  Kingdom.

grasp  when  the  text  is  read  serially  from  beginning  to  end.  This  displacement  of  the  passagessuggests  an  interpretation  of  the  connections  in  Aristotle’s  thought  on  democracy  in  thePolitics.  The  potential  danger  of  this  method,  of  course,  is  that  reading  excerpted  andparaphrased  passages  without  considering  their  full  context  can  be  seriously  misleading.  Itmust  be  strongly  emphasized,  therefore,  that  reading  the  Politics  thoroughly  from  beginningto  end  (and  more  than  once!)  is  the  only  way  to  try  to  understand  fully  its  complex  andinterwoven  arguments.  With  this  caution  firmly  in  mind,  users  can  consider  the  arrangementof  excerpted  passages  as  a  guide  to  further  study  of  Aristotle’s  reflections  on  ancient  Greekdemocracy.

In  the  environment  provided  by  electronic  publication,  all  readers  can  immediately  confrontour  implied  interpretation  with  the  underlying  evidence  and  offer  suggestions  forimprovement  by  electronic  response  to  the  author  and  contributors.  In  this  way  thecollaborative  work  that  produced  this  article  can  continue  as  a  scholarly  conversation  on  awide  scale.

(Section  3  of  13)

·∙  Glossary  ·∙

Every  aKempt  has  been  made  to  be  consistent  in  the  translation  of  crucial  Greek  terms,  suchas  polis,  but  the  flexibility  of  meaning  of  some  of  them  makes  absolute  consistency  impossible.The  following  translations  are  used  as  consistently  as  possible:

“Polity”  for  politeia  when  Aristotle  uses  the  word  in  its  particular  sense  to  indicate  rule  by  themany  in  what  he  defines  as  the  straight  or  correct  system  of  government  of  this  type.  (Bycontrast,  he  refers  to  rule  by  the  many  in  a  diverging  and  thus  “erroneous”  system  as“democracy.”)  (See  this  word  in  selections  from  Aristotle,  courtesy  of  the  Perseus  DigitalLibrary;  see  this  word  in  all  Perseus  texts.)

“System  of  government”  for  politeia  when  Aristotle  uses  the  wordin  its  generic  sense,  which  is  conventionally  translated  into  Englishas  “constitution.”  (This  departure  from  convention  is  to  avoid  thepotential  ambiguity  of  the  term  “constitution,”  which  as  a  familiar  term  in  the  United  Statestoday  is  usually  taken  to  mean  a  formal,  wriKen  document  prescribing  the  structure  ofgovernment.  The  “constitutions”  of  ancient  Greek  city-­‐‑states  were  often  not  wriKen  down,  atradition  found  today,  for  example,  in  the  United  Kingdom.)  (See  this  word  in  Perseusselections  from  Aristotle;  see  this  word  in  all  Perseus  texts.)

“Diverging  system  of  government”  for  parekbasis.  The  diverging  systems  are  tyranny,oligarchy,  and  democracy,  which  are  those  systems  that  “diverge”  (parekbaino)  from  the  three“straight  systems  of  government”  (orthai  politeiai),  which  are  kingship,  aristocracy,  and  polity.(See  parekbasis  in  Perseus  selections  from  Aristotle;  see  parekbasis  in  all  Perseus  texts.  Seeoccurences  of  orthos  within  five  words  of  politeia  in  Perseus  selections  from  Aristotle;  in  allPerseus  texts.)

“Excellence”  for  arete,  which  is  conventionally  translated  “virtue.”  Excellence  in  the  Greeksense  can  and  often  does  pertain  to  ethical  qualities  and  morality,  but  it  can  also  pertain  to,  forexample,  physical  strength  or  courage.  (See  this  word  in  Perseus  selections  from  Aristotle;  seethis  word  in  all  Perseus  texts.)

Page 3: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

[  back  to  top  ]

Read  about  the  evidence  Aristotle  (Aristot.  Pol.).  Plot  on  a  Map  Berlin.

“Partnership”  for  koinonia,  literally  “a  sharing  or  taking  part  in  a  thing  with  others.”  (See  thisword  in  Perseus  selections  from  Aristotle;  see  this  word  in  all  Perseus  texts.)

“Goal”  for  telos,  literally  “end,  purpose.”  (See  this  word  in  Perseus  selections  from  Aristotle;see  this  word  in  all  Perseus  texts.)

“Multitude”  for  plethos,  which  can  also  mean  “majority”  or,  by  extension,  “democracy.”  (Seethis  word  in  Perseus  selections  from  Aristotle;  see  this  word  in  all  Perseus  texts.)

“People”  for  demos,  which  can  also,  by  extension,  mean  “democracy.”  (See  this  word  inPerseus  selections  from  Aristotle;  see  this  word  in  all  Perseus  texts.)

(Section  4  of  13)

·∙  Instructions  for  reading  passages  ·∙

Important  information  on  links

The  links  from  each  passage  are  to  the  full  text  of  the  Politics  in  bothan  on-­‐‑line  Greek  text  and  an  accompanying  English  translationmaintained  by  the  Perseus  Digital  Library  at  Tufts  University.Passages  are  cited,  following  the  most  precise  standard  form  ofreference  to  the  Politics,  as  a  four-­‐‑digit  number  followed  by  the  leKer  “a”  or  “b”  (that  is,  1253a,1274b,  and  so  on)  to  indicate  a  particular  section  of  the  work.  The  precise  location  of  the  citedpassage  within  a  section  is  indicated  by  the  line  numbers  that  follow  the  citation  of  thesection.  (This  reference  system  is  derived  from  the  Greek  edition  of  the  Politics  published  byImmanuel  Bekker  in  Berlin  in  1831.)

Two  crucial  warnings

Each  section  (e.g.,  1253a,  1274b,  etc.)  is  presented  as  continuous  text.  The  line  numbersfollowing  the  section  designation  are  indicated  in  the  on-­‐‑line  Greek  text  in  multiples  of  five,while  the  corresponding  line  numbers  in  the  accompanying  English  translation  appear  everytwenty  lines  in  brackets,  but  the  line  divisions  as  represented  in  your  Web  browser  may  notcorrespond  exactly  to  this  numeration.

Since,  for  technical  reasons,  the  links  must  go  to  the  first  line  of  a  section  and  therefore  usuallynot  to  the  first  line  of  the  cited  reference  itself,  the  particular  lines  referred  to  may  appearrather  far  down  from  the  beginning  of  the  section.  In  some  cases,  the  particular  lines  may  befar  enough  from  the  beginning  of  the  section  that  they  will  not  be  on  the  screen  when  thesection  is  first  displayed,  and  it  will  then  be  necessary  to  scroll  until  they  appear.  Please  besure  to  note  the  precise  line  number  within  the  section  to  which  you  are  linking  beforefollowing  that  link  so  that  you  can  locate  that  line  by  scrolling.

Introduction  to  the  groups  of  excerpted  passages

The  first  three  groups  of  excerpted  passages  provide  context  for  the  remaining  groups.  Thefirst  of  the  three  concerns  elements  of  the  definition  of  the  ancient  Greek  city-­‐‑state  (polis)  in  thePolitics  because  Aristotle’s  discussion  of  democracy  pertains  to  this  type  of  political  state.  Thenext  group  concerns  the  definition  of  the  citizen  because  it  took  citizens  to  constitute  a  systemof  government  in  the  city-­‐‑state,  of  which  democracy  was  one.  The  third  concerns  the

Page 4: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

[  back  to  top  ]

definition  of  different  systems  of  government  in  the  city-­‐‑state,  especially  the  notion  thatdemocracy  is,  in  Aristotle’s  view,  a  “diverging”  system  of  government.  The  remaining  groupsof  passages  concern  democracy  itself.  In  the  paraphrases  of  the  passages,  square  brackets  [  ]indicate  editorial  additions  to  the  ancient  text.

The  text  of  the  Politics  is  conventionally  divided  into  eight  “Books,”  whose  proper  order  isdisputed.  These  book  divisions  do  not  appear  in  the  continuous  text  to  which  the  passages  arelinked.  For  those  who  wish  to  correlate  the  passages  cited  below  to  the  book  in  which  theyappear,  the  following  list  indicates  the  division  of  sections  in  the  books  as  traditionallynumbered.  Since  the  links  go  to  the  beginnings  of  sections,  they  will  not  go  to  the  part  of  thesection  at  which  a  particular  book  begins.  For  example,  Book  4  begins  at  1288b10,  but  the  linkgoes  to  the  beginning  of  1288b,  from  which  point  it  is  necessary  to  scroll  forward  to  reach  line10.

Book  1  =  1252a1  to  1260b24

Book  2  =  1260b27  to  1274b28

Book  3  =  1274b32  to  1288b6

Book  4  =  1288b10  to  1301a15

Book  5  =  1301a19  to  1316b27

Book  6  =  1316b31  to  1323a10

Book  7  =  1323a14  to  1337a7

Book  8  =  1337a11  to  1342b34

(Section  5  of  13)

·∙  Passages:  Defining  the  City  State  ·∙

1253a:  2-­‐‑3:  Human  beings  are,  by  nature,  creatures  who  live  in  a  city-­‐‑state  (polis).  [The  sameremark  occurs  at  1278b19.]  1274b:  33-­‐‑34:  It  is  a  disputed  question  what  exactly  the  city-­‐‑state  is.

1279a:  21:  A  city-­‐‑state  is  a  partnership  of  the  free.

1255b:  16-­‐‑20:  Rule  in  a  city-­‐‑state  is  the  rule  of  those  who  are  free  and  equal.  This  is  not  thesame  as  mastery,  where  one  is  a  slave  and  the  other  is  a  ruler.

1276b:  1-­‐‑2:  A  city-­‐‑state  is  a  partnership  of  citizens  in  a  system  of  government.

1252a:  1-­‐‑7:  Every  city-­‐‑state  is  a  kind  of  partnership,  and  every  partnership  is  created  for  thesake  of  something  good.  Political  partnership,  which  is  called  the  city-­‐‑state,  aims  at  the  mostauthoritative  good  of  all.

1275b:  17-­‐‑21:  Given  the  definition  of  a  citizen  in  1275a:  22-­‐‑23,  a  city-­‐‑state  is  a  multitude  of  suchpersons  large  enough  for  self-­‐‑sufficiency  of  life.

1252b:  29-­‐‑30:  The  city-­‐‑state  comes  into  being  for  the  sake  of  living,  but  it  exists  for  the  sake  ofliving  “well”  (to  eu  zen).  [This  phrase  implies  more  than  what  is  usually  meant  by  “livingwell”  in  English,  which  is  to  say  “being  prosperous.”  The  Greek  phrase  implies  above  all  a  lifelived  in  accordance  with  excellence  (arete).  Living  a  prosperous  life  is  not  necessarily  in

Page 5: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

[  back  to  top  ]

Plot  on  a  Map  

conflict  with  this  notion  but  is  certainly  not  the  principal  implication  of  living  “well”  in  Greek.See  the  next  passage.]

1280b:  29-­‐‑1281a8:  A  city-­‐‑state  is  clearly  not  just  living  together  in  a  shared  territory  for  mutualdefense  and  the  exchange  of  goods.  It  is  rather  a  partnership  among  households,  clans,  andvillages  for  living  “well,”  for  the  sake  of  a  fully  developed  and  self-­‐‑sufficient  life.  Those  whocontribute  most  to  a  partnership  of  this  sort  have  a  greater  part  in  the  city  than  those  who  areequal  or  greater  in  freedom  or  family,  but  unequal  in  political  excellence,  or  those  who  outdothem  in  wealth,  but  are  outdone  in  excellence.

1278b:  21-­‐‑25:  The  goal  or  purpose  (telos)  of  the  city-­‐‑state  certainly  encompasses  physicalexistence  and  survival,  but  it  is  also  more  than  that,  namely,  living  “finely”  (to  zen  kalos).

1280b:  6-­‐‑8:  The  city-­‐‑state  that  is  truly  a  city-­‐‑state  must  be  concerned  with  excellence  (arete).

1323b:  30-­‐‑34:  The  best  city-­‐‑state  is  happy  and  acts  finely.  It  is  impossible  for  those  who  do  notdo  fine  things  to  act  finely.  There  is  no  fine  action  of  man  or  city-­‐‑state  apart  from  excellenceand  thinking.

1253a:  37:  Justice  is  a  thing  of  the  city-­‐‑state.

1282b:  16-­‐‑18:  The  political  good  is  justice,  and  justice  is  the  common  advantage.

(Section  6  of  13)

·∙  Passages:  Defining  the  Citizen  ·∙

1275a:  22-­‐‑23:  A  citizen  defined  in  simple  terms  is  someone  who  can  participate  in  judging[that  is,  serve  as  a  juror  in  the  court  system]  and  in  governing  [that  is,  serve  in  public  office,which  here  means  not  just  magistracies  but  also  serving  in  the  assembly  and  on  the  council  insystems  of  government  that  have  these  institutions].

1275b:  5-­‐‑7:  The  definition  of  citizen  just  given  in  1275a:  22-­‐‑23  applies  especially  to  democracyand  possibly,  though  not  necessarily,  to  other  systems  of  government  because  differentdefinitions  would  apply  in  different  systems.

1275a:  2-­‐‑5:  Who  is  entitled  to  be  a  citizen?  No  agreement  exists;  someone  who  would  be  acitizen  in  a  democracy  would  often  not  be  a  citizen  in  an  oligarchy.

1278a:  8-­‐‑25:  In  the  best  city-­‐‑state,  craftsmen  (banausoi)  will  not  be  allowed  to  be  citizens,  sincethey  are  not  really  able  to  live  freely,  because  they  are  not  free  from  “necessary  tasks”  [that  is,they  have  to  do  physical  work  for  a  living]  and  therefore  do  not  have  the  time  to  devotethemselves  to  the  activities  in  which  excellence  is  manifested.  This  does  not  mean  that  theyare  poor;  craftsmen  in  fact  can  be  rich,  but  they  still  have  to  engage  in  making  things  withtheir  own  hands,  [an  activity  seen  as  demeaning  by  citizens  in  the  social  elite].

1278a:  26-­‐‑29:  In  many  systems  of  government,  citizens  are  legally  drawn  from  the  ranks  offoreigners  [that  is,  both  of  their  parents  do  not  have  to  be  citizens].  In  some  democracies,citizens  need  only  have  a  citizen  mother,  and  even  illegitimate  children  (nothoi)  can  be  citizensin  many  places.

1275b:  35-­‐‑37:  Cleisthenes  of  Athens  made  citizens  of  metics

Page 6: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Athens.

[  back  to  top  ]

Read  about  the  evidence  (Aristot.  Pol.).(Aristot.  Pol.).Aristotle  (Aristot.  Nic.  Eth.).Aristotle  (Aristot.  Nic.  Eth.).

[resident  foreigners],  who  had  been  foreigners  or  slaves,  followingthe  expulsion  of  the  tyrants  from  Athens  [near  the  end  of  the  sixth  century].

1283b:  42-­‐‑1284a4:  The  citizen  in  common  parlance  is  the  person  who  has  a  share  in  ruling  andbeing  ruled;  in  the  best  system  of  government  [namely,  a  polity,  on  which  see  under“Defining  Systems  of  Government”]  a  citizen  is  both  able  and  willing  to  rule  and  be  ruled  inaccordance  with  a  life  lived  with  excellence  as  its  aim.

1277a:  26-­‐‑27:  The  excellence  of  a  citizen  consists  of  being  able  to  rule  and  be  ruled  well.

1277b:  13-­‐‑18:  The  good  citizen  must  have  ability  and  knowledge  concerning  both  ruling  freemen  and  also  being  ruled.  A  good  citizen  must  possess  moderation  and  prudence  (sophrosyne)and  justice  (dikaiosyne)  with  respect  to  ruling.

1276b:  28-­‐‑29:  The  task  of  citizens  is  the  preservation  (soteria)  of  the  partnership  that  is  theirsystem  of  government.  [Also  under  “Preserving  Democracy”]

(Section  7  of  13)

·∙  Passages:  Defining  the  System  of  Government  ·∙

1323a:  14-­‐‑16:  To  seek  out  what  is  the  best  system  of  government,  it  is  first  necessary  to  definewhat  is  the  most  desirable  life.

1323b:  1-­‐‑4:  Living  happily,  whether  for  human  beings  it  comes  from  enjoyment  or  fromexcellence  or  from  both,  exists  for  those  persons  excessively  adorned  with  character  andpurpose  but  moderate  in  the  acquisition  of  external  goods.

1295a:  25-­‐‑1295b:  Like  the  best  life,  the  best  system  of  government  isconducted  in  accordance  with  excellence.  If  excellence  is  the  mean,as  argued  in  the  Nicomachean  Ethics  [for  example,  at  1101a:  14-­‐‑16],then  a  life  and  a  system  of  government  that  is  “in  the  middle”  isbest.  A  city-­‐‑state  has  three  elements  in  its  population:  the  rich,  the  poor,  and  those  in  themiddle.  The  political  partnership  that  is  constituted  from  those  in  the  middle  is  the  best.

1293a:  35-­‐‑42:  In  addition  to  the  four  systems  of  government  that  [other]  people  usually  bringup  in  discussing  systems  of  government  (namely,  monarchy,  oligarchy,  democracy,  andaristocracy),  there  is  a  fifth  one  called  polity  (politeia),  which  is  also  the  term  used  to  mean“system  of  government”  in  general  or  in  a  generic  sense.  This  fifth  system  of  government  issometimes  overlooked  in  discussions  of  the  types  of  systems  of  government  since  it  does  notcome  into  existence  very  often.

1289a:  26-­‐‑28:  As  was  established  previously  in  the  first  book  of  the  Politics,  there  are  three“straight”  or  “upright”  [and  therefore  correct  and  good]  systems  of  government  (orthaipoliteiai):  kingship,  aristocracy,  and  polity.

1265b:  26-­‐‑28:  The  system  of  government  called  polity  is  midway  between  democracy  andoligarchy.

1293b:  33-­‐‑37:  Polity  is,  to  put  it  simply,  a  mixture  of  oligarchy  and  democracy.  The  kinds  ofpolities  that  tend  towards  democracy  are  customarily  referred  to  by  the  name  of  polity,  while

Page 7: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

those  that  tend  towards  oligarchy  are  called  aristocracies.

1307a:  15-­‐‑16:  The  systems  of  government  inclining  more  toward  oligarchy  are  calledaristocracies,  while  those  inclining  more  toward  the  multitude  (plethos)  [which  can  also  mean“democracy”]  are  called  polities.

1297b:  22-­‐‑25:  As  city-­‐‑states  increased  in  size  and  grew  stronger  in  the  heavy-­‐‑infantry  [hoplite]section  of  the  citizen  body,  more  men  gained  a  share  in  the  system  of  government.  For  thisreason  what  are  now  called  polities  were  previously  called  democracies.

1279a:  37-­‐‑39:  When  the  multitude  governs  according  to  the  common  advantage,  then  thissystem  of  government  is  called  by  the  term  also  used  to  designate  systems  of  government  ingeneral,  namely,  polity.

1288a:  12-­‐‑15:  The  multitude  suitable  for  a  polity  is  one  capable  of  military  service  that  has  thenatural  ability  to  rule  and  be  ruled  in  accordance  with  law  that  distributes  offices  to  wealthiercitizens  on  the  basis  of  merit.

1307a:  5-­‐‑8:  Polities  and  aristocracies  are  undone  by  diverging  from  that  which  constitutesjustice  in  the  two  different  systems  of  government,  [which  is  not  necessarily  the  same  thing  ineach  system].  The  starting  point  in  a  polity  is  when  democracy  and  oligarchy  have  been  notmixed  appropriately  [literally,  “finely”].

1275b:  1-­‐‑3:  Diverging  and  erroneous  systems  of  government  are  necessarily  subsequent,  notprior  to  correct  [straight]  systems.

1279b:  4-­‐‑10:  There  are  three  systems  of  government  diverging  from  the  three  “straight”systems:  tyranny  diverging  from  kingship,  oligarchy  diverging  from  aristocracy,  anddemocracy  diverging  from  polity.  Each  diverging  system  (parekbasis)  is  structured  to  operateto  the  advantage  of  the  ruler(s);  for  example,  democracy  is  rule  to  the  advantage  of  the  poor.None  of  the  diverging  systems  aims  at  the  profit  of  every  type  of  citizen  in  common.

1289a:  28-­‐‑1289b5:  Of  these  three  diverging  systems  of  government,  tyranny  is  the  worst(which  is  to  say  the  furthest  from  polity),  oligarchy  the  next  worst,  and  democracy  the  mostmoderate.

1279a:  17-­‐‑21:  While  straight  systems  of  government  are  concerned  with  the  commonadvantage  according  to  what  is  quite  simply  just,  diverging  forms  of  government  are  thosethat  in  error  serve  the  interest  of  the  ruler(s).  Diverging  forms  of  government  tend  to  have  anelement  of  despotism,  because  a  city-­‐‑state  is  a  partnership  of  the  free.

1290a:  13-­‐‑29:  Some  people  claim  that,  just  as  there  are  two  main  kinds  of  wind  or  of  musicalharmonies,  and  the  other  winds  and  harmonies  are  regarded  as  divergences  from  these,  thereare  also  two  sorts  of  systems  of  government,  rule  by  the  people  and  oligarchy.  On  this  view,the,  polity  diverges  from  democracy  and  aristocracy  diverges  from  oligarchy.  But  it  is  beKerto  postulate  instead  that  there  are  “straight”  systems  of  government  and  systems  ofgovernment  diverging  from  them.

1259a:  39-­‐‑1259b10:  The  rule  that  a  husband  has  over  his  wife,  a  free  person,  is  the  same  sort  ofrule  that  exists  over  free  persons  in  a  polity.  Since  the  male  is  more  fit  to  rule  by  nature,  hewill  rule  continuously  in  the  household,  unless  he  is  somehow  unnatural.  In  contrast,  when

Page 8: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

[  back  to  top  ]

citizens  are  equals  and  do  not  differ,  then  the  roles  of  ruler  and  ruled  will  alternate.

1325b:  7-­‐‑8:  For  those  who  are  alike,  the  fine  and  the  just  is  [to  rule  and  be  ruled]  in  turn,  forthis  is  equal  and  alike.

1282b:  10-­‐‑13:  Since  laws  align  with  the  system  of  government,  the  laws  of  straight  systems  ofgovernment  are  necessarily  just,  but  those  of  diverging  systems  are  necessarily  not  just.

1309a:  36-­‐‑39:  Justice  and  the  excellence  associated  with  it  are  not  the  same  in  different  systemsof  government.

1309b:  19-­‐‑35:  Diverging  types  of  government  fail  to  pay  aKention  to  the  middle.  Institutionssuitable  to  a  certain  type  of  government  can  be  the  downfall  of  that  type  of  government  if  theybecome  too  extreme.  Just  as  a  nose  [on  a  statue]  can  still  be  appealing  to  look  at  if  it  divergesfrom  the  straightness  that  is  beautiful  but  can  become  not  even  a  nose  if  an  artist  pushes  it  toofar  in  the  direction  of  the  extremes,  so,  too,  a  system  of  government  such  as  democracy  thatdiverges  from  the  best  system  can  still  be  adequate  if  it  is  not  pushed  to  an  extreme.

1287b:  39-­‐‑41:  There  is  no  such  thing  as  a  person  being  naturally  fiKed  for  any  of  the  divergingsystems  of  governments,  for  they  have  come  into  being  contrary  to  nature  (physis).

(Section  8  of  13)

·∙  Passages:  Defining  Democracy  ·∙

1294a:  11:  Freedom  is  the  defining  principle  of  democracy.

1317a:  40-­‐‑1317b13:  The  underlying  principle  of  democracy  is  freedom,  and  it  is  customary  tosay  that  only  in  democracies  do  men  have  a  share  in  freedom,  for  that  is  what  everydemocracy  makes  its  aim.  There  are  two  main  aspects  of  freedom:  1)  being  ruled  and  ruling  inturn,  since  everyone  is  equal  according  to  number,  not  merit,  and  2)  to  be  able  to  live  as  onepleases.

1280a:  7-­‐‑11:  Justice  as  understood  in  democracy  is  equality,  but  this  considers  only  part  ofwhat  is  just;  the  same  is  true  of  the  notion  of  justice  in  oligarchy.

1330b:  19-­‐‑20:  A  level  location  is  suitable  for  a  democratic  city-­‐‑state,  an  acropolis  for  anoligarchy  or  a  monarchy.

1321a:  5-­‐‑14:  A  multitude  (plethos)  has  four  divisions:  farmers,  craftsmen,  merchants,  andlaborers.  There  are  four  [divisions  of  the  population]  useful  for  the  military:  those  who  ownhorses  [cavalrymen],  heavy-­‐‑armed  infantry  [hoplites],  light-­‐‑armed  infantry,  and  those  whorow  warships  in  the  navy.  Light-­‐‑armed  infantry  and  rowers  are  wholly  democratic  [sectionsof  the  citizen  body].

1278b:  8-­‐‑12:  The  system  of  government  of  a  city-­‐‑state  is  the  arrangement  of  its  variousinstitutions,  especially  those  having  authority.  In  a  democracy,  the  people  (demos)  haveauthority.

1281a:  40-­‐‑1281b6:  That  the  multitude  (plethos)  should  have  authority  rather  than  those  who  arebest  and  few  in  number  [is  a  defensible  position].  Even  though  none  of  the  many  isindividually  a  man  of  excellence,  nevertheless  they  can  be  beKer  when  they  are  all  together,

Page 9: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

just  as  a  dinner  to  which  many  people  contribute  can  be  beKer  than  one  furnished  from  asingle  source.  With  each  of  the  many  having  a  part  of  excellence  and  intelligence,  when  theyjoin  together  they  become  like  a  single  person.

1286a:  28-­‐‑37:  Any  one  man  [of  the  many]  may  be  inferior  [to  a  man  of  excellence],  but  the  city-­‐‑state  is  made  up  of  many  men.  Just  as  a  meal  done  by  many  is  beKer  than  a  single  and  simpleone,  for  this  reason  a  mass  (ochlos)  can  judge  many  things  beKer  than  any  one  man.  Inaddition,  that  which  is  many  is  less  likely  to  be  corrupted.  So,  although  an  individual’sjudgment  can  be  corrupted  when  he  is  overcome  by  anger  or  some  other  emotion,  it  isdifficult  for  all  to  become  angry  and  make  erroneous  judgments  simultaneously.  If  all  the  menare  good  men  and  good  citizens,  they  are  less  corruptible  than  one  man.  But  the  multitudemust  be  free  men  and  do  nothing  contrary  to  law,  except  in  cases  where  the  law  necessarilyfalls  short.

1281b:  23-­‐‑36:  What  authority  should  belong  to  the  multitude  (plethos)  of  free  citizens,  who  arenot  rich  and  have  not  a  single  claim  to  excellence?  They  should  not  have  a  share  in  the  highestoffices  because  their  injustice  and  imprudence  would  make  this  unsafe.  States  are  unstable,however,  that  are  filled  with  those  who  have  no  share  of  political  power  and  are  poor.Therefore,  it  is  left  for  them  to  share  in  the  deliberative  and  judicial  functions  of  government[namely,  the  assembly  and  the  courts].  For  when  they  have  all  come  together,  their  perception[of  political  issues]  is  sufficient,  and  when  they  are  mixed  with  the  “beKer”  citizens,  theybenefit  city-­‐‑states.

1282a:  25-­‐‑32:  In  some  systems  of  government,  authority  is  given  to  the  people  (demos)  overgreat  maKers,  such  as  overseeing  the  audits  of  the  conduct  and  accounts  of  magistrates  andchoosing  them,  for  this  power  is  given  to  the  assembly.  Thus,  citizens  of  whatever  age  andrequired  to  meet  only  a  low  financial  requirement  can  participate  in  the  assembly  anddeliberate  [on  political  issues]  and  serve  in  the  courts,  while  those  meeting  a  high  financialrequirement  serve  as  treasurers  and  generals  [the  chief  civic  magistrates]  and  in  the  highestmagistracies.

1279b:  18-­‐‑19:  Democracy  is  when  those  who  do  not  own  much  property,  but  are  poor,  haveauthority  in  the  system  of  government.

1279b:  20-­‐‑1280a6:  The  definitions  of  democracy  and  oligarchy  according  to  whether  the  manyor  the  few  have  authority  in  the  system  of  government  appear  problematic  if  one  supposesthat  it  might  happen  that  the  majority  in  a  state  were  wealthy  or  that  the  poor  would  be  fewin  number  but  still  have  authority.  In  fact,  it  is  only  a  contingent  factor  whether  the  few  or  themany  have  authority  in  a  state.  The  real  difference  between  democracy  and  oligarchy  isbetween  poverty  and  wealth.  Wherever  the  rulers,  whether  they  be  a  minority  or  a  majority,owe  their  power  to  wealth,  that  is  an  oligarchy.  Wherever  the  poor  rule,  that  is  a  democracy.Usually,  where  the  rulers  hold  power  by  wealth,  they  are  few,  but  where  the  poor  rule,  theyare  many,  because  few  men  are  rich  but  all  are  free  [if  they  are  citizens  in  a  city-­‐‑state],  andwealth  and  freedom  are  the  grounds  on  which  the  two  groups  lay  claim  to  government.

1290a:  30-­‐‑1290b2:  Democracy  is  not  necessarily  only  wherever  the  multitude  has  authority.Oligarchy  is  not  necessarily  wherever  a  minority  has  power  over  the  system  of  government.  Ifthe  majority  of  a  city-­‐‑state  were  wealthy  and  had  authority,  nobody  would  call  it  ademocracy,  just  as  if  a  small  group  of  poor  men  had  control  over  a  larger  rich  population,nobody  would  call  it  an  oligarchy.  Rather,  democracy  is  when  every  free  citizen  has  authority

Page 10: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

and  oligarchy  is  when  the  rich  have  it.

1290b:  17-­‐‑20:  Democracy  is  when  there  is  a  majority  of  free,  poor  men  who  have  authority  torule,  while  oligarchy  is  when  it  is  in  the  hands  of  the  wealthy  and  well-­‐‑born,  who  are  aminority.

1328b:  32-­‐‑33:  In  democracies,  everyone  has  a  share  in  everything.

1297b:  37-­‐‑1298a33:  There  are  three  parts  to  all  systems  of  government  for  which  a  good  lawmaker  must  try  to  find  the  best  arrangement:  deliberating  about  maKers  common  to  all,magistracies,  and  the  judicial  system.  It  is  democracy  when  all  the  citizens  can  deliberateabout  everything,  for  the  people  seek  this  kind  of  equality.  There  are  different  ways  of  doingthis.  One  way  is  by  taking  turns  rather  than  all  together.  Another  is  to  have  all  citizens  meettogether  but  only  for  the  election  of  magistrates,  law  making,  declarations  of  war  and  peace,and  audits  of  magistrates,  but  to  have  all  other  maKers  decided  by  magistrates  chosen  fromthe  entire  citizen  body  either  by  election  or  by  lot.  Another  is  just  like  this,  except  themagistrates  are  chosen  to  the  extent  possible  by  election  from  those  who  are  knowledgeable.A  fourth  way  is  when  all  citizens  meet  to  deliberate  on  all  maKers,  while  the  magistratesrender  only  preliminary  decisions,  not  final  ones.  The  so-­‐‑called  final  type  of  democracy  [onwhich  see  under  “Types  of  Democracy”],  the  type  of  democracy  that  is  analogous  to  dynasticoligarchy  and  tyrannical  monarchy  and  exists  now  [in  Aristotle’s  time],  is  arranged  in  thisfourth  way.

1317b:  17-­‐‑41:  The  following  arrangements  are  usually  considered  consistent  with  democracy:

1.   Election  to  all  offices  from  among  all  the  citizens.

2.   Rule  of  all  over  each  and  of  each  over  all  in  turn  filling  magistrates  by  lot,  or  at  leastthose  not  requiring  knowledge  and  technical  skill  not  having  a  financial  requirement  forholding  magistracies,  or  at  least  the  smallest  possible  requirement.

3.   The  same  person  not  repeating  the  same  magistracy,  or  only  rarely,  except  for  militaryoffices.

4.   Having  the  terms  of  magistracies  be  short,  wherever  possible.

5.   Choosing  jurors  from  all  citizens  to  adjudicate  all  maKers,  or  most  maKers,  especially  themost  important  ones.

6.   The  assembly  having  authority  over  all  maKers  or  the  most  important  maKers,  whilemagistrates  have  authority  over  none,  or  as  few  as  possible.

7.   Providing  pay  for  all  service  in  government,  or  for  all  functions  that  exercise  authority.

8.   Making  no  distinctions  according  to  a  citizen’s  birth,  poverty,  or  occupation  no  publicoffices  held  for  life.

1294b:  3-­‐‑4:  Democracy  allows  men  to  participate  in  the  assembly  with  either  no  propertyqualification  or  a  small  one.

1297a:  35-­‐‑38:  To  promote  democracy,  one  can  use  these  legislative  devices:  providingpayment  for  the  poor  for  aKending  the  assembly  and  for  jury  service  and  not  levying  fines  onthe  rich  for  not  participating.

Page 11: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Plot  on  a  Map  Sparta.

Plot  on  a  Map  Sparta  (in  text  as  “Spartan”).

Plot  on  a  Map  Sparta.

Plot  on  a  Map  Sparta  (in  text  as  “Spartan”).

1301a:  11-­‐‑12:  The  democratic  way  to  arrange  a  judicial  system  is  to  have  all  juries  drawn  fromall  the  citizens  and  hear  all  cases.

1294a:  39-­‐‑40:  In  a  democracy  the  poor  receive  pay  for  serving  on  juries  and  the  rich  are  notpenalized  for  failing  to  serve.

1323a:  6-­‐‑9:  Having  a  council  oversee  the  election  to  magistracies  that  carry  authority  isdemocratic.

1300a:  31-­‐‑34:  It  is  democratic  for  all  citizens  to  select  magistrates  from  all  citizens  by  electionor  by  lot  or  by  both  methods.

1299b:  24-­‐‑27:  In  a  democracy,  magistracies  are  filled  from  the  ranks  of  the  free,  while  in  anoligarchy  from  the  rich  and  in  an  aristocracy  from  the  educated.

1294b:  7-­‐‑10:  Democracy  fills  magistracies  by  lot  and  does  not  require  men  to  possess  aminimum  amount  of  wealth  to  be  eligible  to  serve.

1273b:  12-­‐‑13:  It  is  more  democratic—indeed  more  “polity-­‐‑like”—to  have  a  larger  number  ofpeople  hold  public  office  and  not  to  have  one  person  hold  multiple  magistraciessimultaneously,  if  the  city-­‐‑state  is  not  small.

1287a:  4-­‐‑5:  There  can  be  an  office  of  general  (strategia)  without  limit  of  time  in  all  systems  ofgovernment,  even  in  a  democracy.

1300a:  6-­‐‑7:  It  is  not  democratic,  but  aristocratic,  to  have  a  magistrate  to  oversee  children,  orone  to  oversee  women,  or  any  other  one  to  exercise  this  sort  of  oversight.  For  it  is  not  possible[as  practical  maKer]  to  prevent  the  wives  of  poor  men  from  going  out  of  their  homes  [becausethey  have  to  work  outside  the  home  to  earn  money  to  help  support  their  families].

1294b:  19-­‐‑39:  Many  try  to  talk  about  Sparta  as  a  democracy  becauseit  has  many  democratic  elements  in  the  arrangement  [of  its  systemof  government].  For  example,  the  children  of  rich  and  poor  are  raised  and  educated  in  thesame  way.  So,  too,  adults  eat  and  dress  the  same  way,  whether  rich  or  poor.  As  for  their  toptwo  offices,  one  is  elected  by  the  people  [that  is,  ordinary  citizens],  and  the  people  can  beelected  to  the  other.  Others  call  Sparta  an  oligarchy  because  it  has  oligarchic  elements  also.

1271a:  32-­‐‑37:  The  Spartan  common  messes  were  intended  to  be  ademocratic  institution,  but  they  did  not  work  out  that  way.Everyone  is  required  to  contribute  [to  the  shared  meals],  but  some  of  them  are  too  poor  to  doso.  The  very  poorest  cannot  easily  share  in  the  common  messes,  yet  this  is  the  ancestraldefining  principal  of  their  system  of  government.  Thus  the  very  poor  do  not  have  a  share  in  it.

1265b:  35-­‐‑1266a2:  Some  see  democratic  elements  in  the  system  ofgovernment  at  Sparta.  Some  of  these  think  the  board  of  overseers(ephors)  is  democratic  because  it  is  drawn  from  all  the  citizens.  Others,  however,  call  the  boardtyrannical  and  think  the  system  of  government  is  run  democratically  through  the  commonmesses  and  the  rest  of  the  everyday  way  of  life  at  Sparta.

1270b:  13-­‐‑17:  Since  the  Spartan  board  of  overseers  is  too  powerful,the  kings  must  aKempt  to  win  their  support.  This  has  done

Page 12: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

[  back  to  top  ]

additional  injury  to  the  system  of  government,  which  has  changed  from  aristocracy  todemocracy.

1284a:  3-­‐‑37:  A  man  who  is  clearly  superior  in  excellence  to  all  the  rest  of  the  city-­‐‑state  wouldbe  like  a  god  among  men.  Democratic  states  instituted  ostracism  to  banish  such  men  for  afixed  amount  of  time  to  prevent  them  from  taking  over  the  city-­‐‑state  because  they  werepreeminent  in  their  wealth,  their  large  number  of  supporters,  or  some  other  source  of  politicalstrength.

(Section  9  of  13)

·∙  Passages:  Types  of  Democracy  ·∙

1289a:  8-­‐‑10:  Multiple  types  of  democracy  happen  to  exist,  despite  some  people  saying  there  isonly  one  type.  [The  same  remark  occurs  at  1289a:  22-­‐‑25,  1291b:  15-­‐‑16,  and  1316b:  36.]

1317a:  22-­‐‑33:  There  are  two  reasons  why  there  are  several  different  types  of  democracy:  theirmajorities  or  “peoples”  are  of  different  kinds  (for  example,  farmers  as  opposed  to  craftsmenor  laborers),  and  they  can  have  different  combinations  of  the  institutions  that  make  themdemocratic.

1289a:  22-­‐‑23:  The  same  laws  cannot  be  advantageous  for  every  type  of  democracy.

1291b:  30-­‐‑1292a13:  [This  passage  appears  to  list  five  types  of  democracy,  but  the  next  twopassages  list  only  four.]

The  first  type  of  democracy  is  particularly  based  on  equality,where  neither  the  rich  nor  the  poor  has  pre-­‐‑eminent  authority,  but  both  are  similar  [intheir  authority].  Still,  since  the  majority  rules  and  the  “people”  will  be  in  the  majority,this  is  a  democracy.

Another  type  is  when  citizens  have  to  meet  a  financial  assessment  to  qualify  for  servicein  public  offices,  but  the  amount  is  low  and  any  citizen  possessing  the  required  amountcan  have  a  share.

Another  type  is  when  anyone  whose  citizenship  is  not  open  to  dispute  [because  they  aredescended  from  a  family  of  citizens  whose  citizenship  has  never  been  questioned?]  canhave  a  share,  and  the  law  rules.

Another  type  is  when  absolutely  everyone,  so  long  as  they  are  citizens  [and  even  if  theybecame  citizens  in  a  special  way,  such  as  being  made  citizens  in  political  revolution,  anddid  not  inherit  their  citizenship],  can  have  a  share  in  public  offices,  and  law  rules.

Another  type  is  the  same  in  the  other  ways  [as  in  type  no.  4?]  but  the  multitude  rules,  notlaw.  This  happens  when  decrees  [passed  by  the  multitude]  have  authority  rather  thanthe  law  having  authority.  Here  demagogues  arise,  and  the  multitude  becomes  amonarch.

1292b:  22-­‐‑1293a12:  [There  are  only  four  types  of  democracy  listed  in  this  passage.]

One  type  of  democracy  is  when  farmers  and  those  possessinga  moderate  amount  of  property  have  authority.  They  govern  themselves  in  accordancewith  law  because  their  work  leaves  them  liKle  leisure  time.  They  therefore  meet  in  the

Page 13: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Plot  on  a  Map  Aphytis  (in  text  as“Aphyteans”).

assembly  only  as  absolutely  necessary  [to  make  decisions  on  maKers  not  covered  by  thecode  of  law].  A  share  [in  the  system  of  government]  is  open  to  anyone  as  soon  as  theymeet  the  financial  assessment  set  by  law.  They  cannot  be  at  leisure  [for  public  service  ingoverning]  unless  there  is  public  revenue  [to  subsidize  their  participation].

A  second  type  is  when  anyone  whose  citizenship  is  beyond  question  by  his  descent  isentitled  to  have  a  share  but  only  those  with  leisure  [for  public  service  in  governing]actually  have  a  share.  The  laws  rule  because  there  is  no  public  revenue.

A  third  type  is  when  all  who  are  free  are  entitled  to  a  share  in  the  system  of  government,but  they  do  not  in  fact  take  part  for  the  reason  previously  stated.  Therefore,  lawnecessarily  rules.

A  fourth  type  is  the  last  type  to  arise  in  cities.  Since  cities  have  become  far  larger  thanbefore  and  have  public  revenue  from  which  to  pay  subsidies  for  public  service,  everyoneis  now  able  to  participate.  Even  the  poor  have  the  leisure  for  public  service  thanks  to  thepayments.  Their  private  business  and  affairs  are  not  an  impediment  for  their  publicservice,  but  such  things  are  an  impediment  for  the  rich,  who  therefore  frequently  avoidservice  in  the  assembly  or  the  courts.  In  this  way  the  multitude  of  the  poor  winsauthority  over  the  system  of  government,  not  the  laws.

1296b:  24-­‐‑31:  Where  the  quantity  of  the  multitude  of  the  poor  is  so  large  as  to  overbalance  thequality  of  the  rich,  according  to  the  formula  just  explained  [in  the  text  preceding  this  passage],there  democracy  springs  up  naturally.  What  type  of  democracy  it  is  will  depend  on  what  typeof  population  is  preeminent.  For  example,  if  it  is  a  multitude  of  farmers,  then  it  will  be  thefirst  type  of  democracy  it  is  the  first  kind.  If  it  is  a  multitude  of  craftsmen  and  wage-­‐‑earners,then  it  will  be  the  final  type,  and  so  on  with  the  types  in  between.

1318b:  6-­‐‑1319a3:  There  being  four  types  of  democracy,  the  best  is  the  first  in  the  arrangementpreviously  mentioned  [namely,  in  1292b22-­‐‑1293-­‐‑1293a12,  as  listed  above].  This  type  ofdemocracy  has  a  multitude  that  is  mostly  farmers  or  herders,  whose  work  keeps  them  toobusy  to  meet  frequently  in  the  assembly.  They  do  not  wish  to  serve  in  offices,  where  there  isno  great  profit  in  it.  Everyone  will  elect  magistrates  and  conduct  audits  of  them  and  serve  inthe  courts,  but  those  elected  to  office  will  meet  financial  assessments  or,  if  there  is  no  suchrequirement,  will  be  capable  people.

1319a:  4-­‐‑19:  This  is  the  best  democracy  because  of  what  sort  ofpeople  (demos)  it  has.  If  one  would  like  to  institute  a  farming  demos,one  should  look  to  the  law  of  the  Aphyteans,  who  divide  their  liKleamount  of  land  into  very  small  plots  so  that  everyone,  even  the  poor,  has  enough  land  to  meetthe  financial  requirement  for  sharing  in  citizenship.

1319a:  20-­‐‑38:  Next  best  to  having  a  multitude  consisting  of  farmers  is  to  have  a  herdingpeople.  The  herding  class  have  strong  bodies  and  dispositions  fit  for  military  service.  Theother  sorts  of  multitudes  from  which  democracies  are  constituted  are  far  worse.  Forcraftsmen,  merchants,  and  laborers  lead  lives  devoid  of  excellence,  and  they  are  always  in  themarketplace  and  in  the  city  and  thus  able  to  aKend  assemblies.  It  is  easier  to  create  a  gooddemocracy  in  a  place  where  the  fields  of  the  city-­‐‑state  are  located  at  some  distance  from  thecity  and  the  multitude  must  dwell  out  in  the  country  [to  work  in  the  fields  and  are  thus  noteasily  able  to  come  to  the  urban  center  to  aKend  meetings].  Even  where  there  is  a  crowd  ofmerchants,  assemblies  should  not  be  held  without  the  multitude  from  the  country.

Page 14: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Plot  on  a  Map  Athens.

Plot  on  a  Map  Leucas.

[  back  to  top  ]

1319b:  1-­‐‑32:  The  final  type  of  democracy,  in  which  everyone  is  inthe  partnership,  is  not  easy  for  every  city  to  maintain,  nor  is  it  easyfor  this  type  to  endure  because  its  laws  and  its  habits  are  not  well  composed.  Demagoguesexpand  its  citizen  body  by  allowing  in  those  of  illegitimate  birth  or  born  to  only  one  citizenparent.  If  the  rabble  grow  too  numerous,  they  create  disorder  and  can  provoke  the  notablemembers  of  the  population  to  resistance  against  the  democracy.  This  type  of  democracy  ismade  stronger  by  introducing  institutions  to  mix  everyone  up  together,  as  Cleisthenes  did  atAthens.  This  type  of  democracy  promotes  disorderly  living,  with  a  lack  of  control  overwomen,  children,  and  slaves,  and  a  toleration  for  everyone  living  as  he  pleases,  for  the  manyprefer  living  like  this  to  living  with  prudence  and  moderation.

1298b:  13-­‐‑19:  The  democracy  today  considered  the  most  democratic—namely,  the  type  inwhich  the  people  (demos)  has  authority  even  over  the  laws—arranges  things  to  serve  its  ownadvantage  in  the  deliberative  body:  they  pay  the  poor  to  aKend.

1305a:  28-­‐‑32:  A  change  from  ancestral  democracy  to  the  newest  democracy  can  occur.  If  thepeople  elect  the  magistrates  and  there  is  no  minimum  financial  requirement,  then  those  eagerfor  office  act  as  demagogues  to  accomplish  this  and  give  the  people  authority  over  the  laws.

1266b:  21-­‐‑24:  The  system  of  government  at  Leucas  became

excessively  democratic  when  offices  were  no  longer  filled  according  to  the  establishedminimum  property  requirement  based  on  “old  allotments”  of  land  [but  instead  therequirement  was  lowered].

1312b:  4-­‐‑6:  The  final  type  of  democracy  is  a  tyranny.

1313b:  32-­‐‑41  The  final  form  of  democracy  has  characteristics  of  tyranny:  women  dominate  inthe  household  so  that  they  can  denounce  their  husbands,  slaves  lack  discipline,  and  flaKerers—demagogues—are  held  in  honor.  The  people  wish  to  be  a  monarch.

1295b:  39-­‐‑1296a5:  It  is  best  for  citizens  in  a  city-­‐‑state  to  possess  a  moderate  amount  of  wealthbecause  where  some  have  a  lot  and  some  have  none  the  result  is  the  ultimate  democracy  orunmixed  oligarchy.  Tyranny  can  result  from  both  these  extremes.  It  is  much  less  likely  tospring  from  moderate  systems  of  government.

1311a:  15-­‐‑16:  Taking  after  democracy,  tyranny  makes  war  on  the  notables  in  the  citizen  body.

1276a:  12-­‐‑14:  Some  democracies,  like  tyrannies,  rest  on  force  and  are  not  directed  toward  thecommon  advantage.

1277b:  1-­‐‑3:  In  some  places  in  the  old  days,  before  the  development  of  “ultimate”  democracy,craftsmen  were  barred  from  office.

1312b:  35-­‐‑38:  Ultimate  democracy,  like  unmixed  and  final  oligarchy,  is  really  a  tyrannydivided  [among  a  multitude  of  persons].

(Section  10  of  13)

·∙  Passages:  Creating  Democracy  ·∙

1286b:  11-­‐‑22:  When  there  came  to  be  many  men  alike  in  their  excellence,  they  ceased  to  put  up

Page 15: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Plot  on  a  Map  Istros.

Plot  on  a  Map  Tarentum.Argos.Athens.

Plot  on  a  Map  Athens.Persia.

Plot  on  a  Map  Persia.Salamis.Athens.Syracuse.Chalcis.Ambracia.

[  back  to  top  ]

with  kingship  and  instead,  seeking  something  shared,  established  a  polity.  As  they  became[morally]  worse  and  began  to  make  a  profit  from  common  affairs  [or  “resources”],  oligarchiesarose,  for  they  made  wealth  something  honorable.  Then  these  oligarchies  changed  first  intotyrannies,  and  from  tyrannies  into  democracies.  For  by  always  bringing  power  to  ever  fewerpeople  in  search  of  base  profit,  they  made  the  multitude  stronger,  which  aKacked  [theruler(s)],  and  democracies  arose.  Now  that  city-­‐‑states  have  become  even  larger  than  before,  itis  not  very  easy  for  any  system  of  government  but  a  democracy  to  come  into  existence.

1301a:  28-­‐‑31:  [Rule  by  the]  people  developed  because  those  who  are  equal  in  whatever  waysuppose  that  they  are  quite  simply  equal  [in  all  ways].  Since  they  are  all  free  in  like  manner,they  think  they  are  quite  simply  equal.

1292b:  11-­‐‑14:  It  happens  that  a  system  of  government  may  not  be  democratic  in  terms  of  itslaws  but  is  still  governed  democratically  on  account  of  the  habit  and  upbringing  of  thecitizens.

1296a:  22-­‐‑36:  When  there  is  factional  strife  between  rich  and  poor  because  there  is  not  a  strong“middle”  [in  the  citizen  body],  the  conflict  leads  to  either  democracy  or  oligarchy,  dependingon  who  wins.  Once  the  fight  is  decided,  the  victors  do  not  establish  a  shared  or  equal  systemof  government;  rather,  they  establish  one  to  their  own  advantage.

1305a:  37-­‐‑1305b11:  Mistreating  the  people  can  lead  to  the  overthrowof  oligarchy  and  the  establishment  of  [the  rule  of]  the  people,  as  atIstros.

1303a:  1-­‐‑10:  A  system  of  government  can  be  changed  into  ademocracy  when  the  size  of  the  multitude  of  the  poor  increases,  asoccurred  at  Tarentum,  Argos,  and  Athens.

1273b:  35-­‐‑1274a15:  Some  people  say  that  Solon  did  away  with  anexcessively  unmixed  oligarchy  [at  Athens]  and  ended  theenslavement  of  the  people  (demos),  thus  founding  the  ancestraldemocracy,  which  had  a  mixture  of  oligarchic,  aristocratic,  and  democratic  elements.  In  fact,what  he  did  was  to  create  [the  rule  of  the]  people  by  founding  courts  whose  juries  weredrawn  from  the  entire  citizen  body.  Later  leaders  continued  [to  increase  the  power  of  thepeople],  leading  to  the  present  [more  democratic]  democracy.  It  really  was  not  Solon’sintention  for  this  to  happen.  But  because  the  people  were  the  source  of  Athenian  navalstrength  in  the  wars  against  Persia,  they  began  to  have  high  aspirations  [for  political  power]and  to  choose  unworthy  demagogues  as  leaders  when  socially  more  respectable  citizensopposed  this  development.

1304a:  17-­‐‑34:  Changes  towards  democracy  (or  another  type  ofgovernment)  can  come  about  when  a  magistracy  or  some  part  ofthe  city-­‐‑state  grows  in  power.  This  led  to  greater  democracy  atAthens  after  the  war  with  Persia,  when  those  who  rowed  in  the  fleetbecame  the  cause  of  the  victory  at  Salamis  and  of  the  leadership[over  its  Greek  allies]  that  Athens  earned  from  its  naval  strength.So,  too,  at  Syracuse,  Chalcis,  and  Ambracia  the  people  set  up  democracies  after  theirparticipation  in  baKle  was  the  crucial  element  enabling  their  city-­‐‑state  to  be  victorious  in  war.

(Section  11  of  13)

Page 16: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

·∙  Passages:  Preserving  Democracy  ·∙

1276b:  28-­‐‑29:  The  task  of  citizens  is  the  preservation  (soteria)  of  the  partnership  that  is  theirsystem  of  government.  [Also  under  “Defining  the  Citizen”]

1309b:  35-­‐‑37:  The  lawmaker  and  the  political  man  must  know  what  kind  of  democraticinstitutions  preserve  and  what  kinds  destroy  democracy.

1308a:  11-­‐‑16:  The  equality  that  supporters  of  democracy  seek  is  just  and  advantageous  forpeople  who  are  alike.  Where  there  are  many  people  in  government,  legal  rules  of  a  democraticcast  are  advantageous,  such  as  limiting  term  in  office  to  six  months  so  that  everyone  who  isalike  can  have  a  share  in  filling  public  posts.

1321a:  1-­‐‑2:  Democracies  are  generally  preserved  by  having  a  large  citizen  body.

1326b:  2-­‐‑7:  A  city-­‐‑state  must  be  populous  enough  to  be  self-­‐‑sufficient,  but  too  large  a  statecannot  be  a  city-­‐‑state  because  it  is  not  easy  to  have  a  system  of  government  in  it.  It  is  too  largeto  be  effectively  managed  militarily,  and  no  herald  can  shout  loud  enough  [to  conduct  theassembly  meetings  of  a  large  population].

1296a:  13-­‐‑16:  Democracies  are  more  secure  than  oligarchies  and  more  enduring  since  theyhave  more  “middle”  people  with  a  greater  share  in  [political]  prerogatives.

1309b:  37-­‐‑1310a6:  To  endure,  a  democracy,  like  an  oligarchy,  needs  both  the  rich  and  the  poor.A  democracy  that  destroys  the  well-­‐‑off  becomes  unstable.  Where  the  people  have  authorityover  the  laws,  demagogues  tear  the  city  in  two  by  fighting  with  the  rich.  Instead,  they  shoulddo  the  opposite  and  appear  to  speak  on  the  behalf  of  the  rich.

1309a:  1-­‐‑9:  It  is  democratic  for  all  to  be  eligible  to  hold  public  office.  The  policy  of  not  allowingoffice  holders  to  profit  from  their  office  will  mean  that  the  poor  will  not  desire  to  hold  office,but  rather  they  will  prefer  to  tend  to  their  own  affairs.  Thus,  they  will  become  moreprosperous  by  working,  while  the  notable  and  wealthy  members  of  the  citizen  body  will  holdoffice  because  they  have  no  need  to  earn  money  from  public  service.  In  this  way  the  notableswill  not  be  governed  by  just  anyone.  Both  groups  will  then  have  what  they  want  [andtherefore  the  state  will  be  stable].

1299b:  32-­‐‑34:  A  council  (boule)  with  a  large  number  of  members  is  supportive  of  democracybecause  it  does  preliminary  deliberation  for  the  people  so  that  they  can  have  time  for  theiroccupations.

1309a:  27-­‐‑31:  In  democracy,  as  in  oligarchy,  it  is  advantageous  to  give  equality  or  precedencein  all  aspects  of  the  government  except  the  highest  offices  to  that  group  which  has  the  leastshare  in  the  system  of  government.  In  a  democracy,  that  group  would  be  the  rich.

1319b:  33-­‐‑1320b17:  To  preserve  a  democracy,  one  should  strive  not  for  measures  that  willmake  it  absolutely  as  democratic  as  possible  but  rather  that  will  preserve  it  for  the  longesttime.  The  following  measures  are  recommended:  any  confiscations  of  property  imposed  aspunishment  in  a  legal  judgment  should  become  property  of  the  gods,  not  of  the  public,  toprevent  corrupt  court  judgments  meant  to  secure  a  distribution  to  the  population  from  theconfiscated  property;  large  penalties  should  be  imposed  for  frivolous  prosecutions  to  prevent

Page 17: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Plot  on  a  Map  Sparta  (in  text  as  “Spartans”).

harassment  of  the  rich;  if  there  are  no  [additional]  sources  of  public  revenues  besides  taxes  [onindividuals],  confiscations,  and  corrupt  court  judgments  to  pay  subsidies  to  the  multitude  foraKending  the  assembly,  then  only  infrequent  assembly  meetings  and  brief  court  sessionsshould  be  held  [to  minimize  the  need  to  take  money  from  the  rich  to  pay  the  subsidies];  ifthere  are  [additional]  public  revenues,  no  surplus  from  them  should  be  distributed  to  thepoor,  for  this  practice  stimulates  more  demand  for  this  sort  of  distribution;  at  the  same  time,the  multitude  should  be  kept  from  becoming  overly  poor,  since  this  development  createswretched  [and  thus  excess]  democracy;  money  should  be  provided  from  public  revenues  tothe  poor  so  that  they  can  acquire  land  for  farming  or  learn  a  craft  and  become  beKer  off  overtime;  the  rich  should  be  taxed  to  provide  pay  [to  ordinary  citizens  to  enable  them  to  aKend]necessary  meetings,  but  the  rich  should  be  released  from  unnecessary  public  service;  the  richshould  divide  the  poor  citizens  among  themselves  and  then  give  them  enough  money  [fornecessary  tools,  etc.]  so  that  they  can  start  to  work;  magistracies  should  be  chosen  some  byelection  and  some  by  lot.

1309a:  14-­‐‑20:  In  democracies,  the  rich  should  be  spared  and  not  have  their  property  or  theirincomes  redivided  [for  distribution  to  the  poor].  They  should  also  be  prohibited  fromspending  money  on  expensive  but  useless  sponsorships  of  public  occasions  (liturgies)  such  asleading  choral  groups  for  musical  and  dramatic  festivals  or  officiating  at  torch  races,  even  ifthey  want  to  pay  for  such  sponsorships.

1308b:  10-­‐‑19:  In  all  systems  of  government  no  one  is  allowed  to  become  overly  great  [so  as  tothreaten  the  stability  of  the  state].  Acquiring  great  prerogatives  quickly  tends  to  corruptpeople,  for  not  everyone  can  stand  good  fortune.  Above  all,  the  laws  should  prevent  anyonefrom  becoming  especially  preeminent  in  the  power  derived  from  his  supporters  or  his  wealth;if  the  laws  cannot  prevent  this,  then  such  persons  should  be  sent  to  spend  time  abroad.

1308b:  31-­‐‑33:  It  is  of  the  greatest  importance  in  all  systems  of  government  to  have  laws  and  therest  of  governmental  administration  so  arranged  that  magistrates  cannot  profit  financiallyfrom  their  offices.

1310a:  12-­‐‑36:  The  greatest  thing  of  everything  that  has  been  mentioned  for  preserving  asystem  of  government,  although  this  is  the  thing  everyone  slights,  is  providing  education  inaccordance  with  the  system  of  government.  For  even  the  most  beneficial  and  widely  approvedlaws  bring  no  benefit  if  they  are  not  going  to  be  inculcated  through  education  and  the  habitsof  the  citizens.  Education  appropriate  for  a  democratic  system  of  government  is  not  to  beguided  by  what  brings  enjoyment  to  the  partisans  of  democracy  but  rather  by  what  makes  itpossible  to  run  a  system  of  government  democratically.  In  the  democracies  that  seem  to  be  themost  democratic,  they  do  what  is  not  advantageous  because  they  define  freedom  badly.  Fordemocracy  is  thought  to  be  defined  by  two  things:  by  the  majority  having  authority  and  byfreedom.  Justice  is  then  thought  of  as  equality,  and  equality  as  that  whatever  the  multitudedecides  is  what  is  authoritative.  Freedom  and  equality  are  doing  whatever  one  wishes.  So  inthis  sort  of  democracy  everybody  lives  as  he  wants  and  for  whatever  goal  he  craves.  This  is  acontemptible  thing.  Living  according  to  one’s  system  of  government  should  not  be  thought  ofas  slavery,  but  rather  as  preservation.

1337a:  11-­‐‑1337b3:  Everyone  would  agree  that  law  makers  shouldmake  the  education  of  the  young  a  special  priority.  City-­‐‑states  thatfail  to  do  this  injure  their  systems  of  government.  The  education  must  suit  the  system  ofgovernment,  for  this  preserves  it.  Since  a  city-­‐‑state  has  a  single  goal  (telos),  education  must,  of

Page 18: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

[  back  to  top  ]

Plot  on  a  Map  Cos.Rhodes.Heracleia.Megara.Cyme.

necessity,  be  the  same  and  be  given  to  everyone.  Its  oversight  should  be  a  public  maKer,  notas  it  is  now,  with  everyone  overseeing  his  own  children’s  education  privately  and  havingthem  taught  what  he  believes  best.  Training  for  things  that  are  shared  should  be  a  sharedactivity  done  in  common.  The  Spartans  might  well  deserve  praise  on  this  score,  since  they,more  than  anyone,  devote  effort  to  their  children,  and  as  a  shared  task.

1260b:  15-­‐‑20:  It  is  necessary  to  educate  women  and  children  with  an  eye  to  the  system  ofgovernment,  if  the  state  is  to  be  worthy.  For  women  make  up  half  of  the  free  population,  andfrom  the  children  will  come  the  partners  in  the  system  of  government.

1342b:  34:  There  are  three  defining  principles  for  education:  the  middle,  the  possible,  and  theappropriate.

1266b:  29-­‐‑31:  There  is  a  greater  need  to  level  people’s  desires  rather  than  their  property  (bylegislation  redividing  property  holdings  or  limiting  them),  and  this  can  be  done  only  whenpeople  are  sufficiently  educated  by  the  laws.

1313a:  41-­‐‑1313b6:  Education,  debate,  and  social  groups  dedicated  to  inquiry  and  discussionare  enemies  of  tyranny,  since  they  encourage  intelligent  thought  and  trust  [among  citizens].

1263b:  36-­‐‑37:  Since  a  city-­‐‑state  is  a  multitude,  it  is  necessary  to  use  education  to  make  it  into  apartnership  and  a  unity.

(Section  12  of  13)

·∙  Passages:  Destroying  Democracy  ·∙

1304b:  20-­‐‑1305a7:  The  main  cause  of  the  overthrow  of  democraciesis  the  outrageous  behavior  of  demagogues.  By  aKacking  [rich]property  owners  they  motivate  them  to  band  together  out  of  fear,and  they  also  spur  on  the  people  [to  try  to  bleed  the  rich].  In  thisway  democracy  has  been  overthrown  at  numerous  places:  Cos,  Rhodes,  Heracleia,  Megara,Cyme.  This  is  more  or  less  the  way  democracies  are  destroyed.  To  win  popular  support,demagogues  propose  unjust  treatment  for  the  notables  and  thus  force  them  to  band  together,by  making  them  give  up  their  property  for  redivision,  or  by  having  them  expend  theirresources  on  public  service,  or  by  slandering  them  to  force  confiscations  of  their  property.

1311a:  22-­‐‑26:  The  same  beginnings  lead  to  the  overthrow  of  polities  and  monarchies  alike.  Forthose  who  are  ruled  aKack  monarchies  on  account  of  injustice,  fear,  and  contempt.

1301b:  26-­‐‑29:  Factional  conflict  (stasis)  erupts  everywhere  on  account  of  inequality,  or  at  leastit  does  if  no  proportion  exists  between  those  who  are  unequal.  In  general,  people  engage  infactional  conflict  seeking  equality.

1303b:  6-­‐‑7:  In  democracies,  the  notables  cause  factional  conflict  because  they  have  [only]  anequal  share  in  things  even  though  [in  their  own  eyes]  they  are  not  equal  [to  everybody  elsebut  feel  superior  and  therefore  feel  they  should  possess  more  political  power,  etc.  than  thosewhom  they  see  as  their  inferiors].

1302a:  31-­‐‑34:  Factional  conflict  is  the  result  of  fighting  to  gain  profit  and  honor  and  to  avoidtheir  opposites,  dishonor  and  penalties.

Page 19: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Plot  on  a  Map  Rhodes.

Plot  on  a  Map  Thebes.Megara.Rhodes.

Plot  on  a  Map  Athens.Piraeus.

[  back  to  top  ]

Plot  on  a  Map  Istanbul.

1302b:  21-­‐‑24:  Fear  causes  factional  conflict,  both  when  men  fearpunishment  for  injustice  they  have  commiKed  and  also  when  theyfear  being  treated  unjustly.  At  Rhodes,  for  example,  the  notables  rebelled  against  the  peopleon  account  of  legal  prosecutions  that  were  being  brought  against  them.

1302b:  27-­‐‑33:  Factional  conflict  occurs  in  democracies  when  the  richfeel  contempt  for  the  disorder  and  anarchy  [of  the  government],  asat  Thebes  and  Megara  following  defeats  in  baKle  and  on  Rhodespreceding  the  rebellion  [of  the  notables].

1302b:  15-­‐‑18:  Factional  conflict  can  arise  when  there  is  a  person  or  a  group  whose  powerexceeds  that  of  the  city-­‐‑state  or  its  government.  The  institution  of  ostracism  came  into  being  toprevent  this.

1308b:  20-­‐‑22:  Since  men’s  private  lives  can  lead  them  to  seek  the  overthrow  of  the  system  ofgovernment,  a  magistracy  is  needed  to  oversee  those  living  against  the  common  advantage  ofthe  city-­‐‑state,  for  example,  in  a  democracy  those  living  lives  disadvantageous  for  democracy.

1303b:  7-­‐‑12:  City-­‐‑states  sometimes  fall  into  factions  on  account  oftheir  topography.  At  Athens,  for  example,  the  citizens  ones  living  inthe  Piraeus  [the  harbor  district]  are  more  democratic  than  those  inthe  urban  center.

1302a:  8-­‐‑13:  Democracy  is  more  stable  and  less  prone  to  factional  conflict  than  oligarchy.  In  anoligarchy  there  are  two  types  of  possible  conflict,  namely,  conflict  between  the  oligarchsthemselves  and  conflict  between  the  oligarchs  and  the  people.  In  a  democracy,  however,  thereis  only  conflict  between  citizens  favoring  democracy  and  citizens  favoring  oligarchy,  as  noserious  factional  conflict  arises  in  the  people  [that  is,  those  favoring  democracy]  againstthemselves.

(Section  13  of  13)

·∙  Selective  Bibliography  ·∙

Translation  and  Commentary

Aristotle,  The  Politics.  Translated  with  an  introduction  by  Carnes  Lord.  (Chicago,  1984).  Anadmirable  translation,  remarkably  close  to  the  Greek  but  still  very  readable.

W.  L.  Newman,  The  Politics  of  Aristotle,  4  vols.  (Oxford,  1887-­‐‑1902).  A  massive  criticalcommentary  that  has  never  been  equaled.  See  especially  his  discussion  of  Aristotle  and  Greekdemocracy  in  vol.  4,  pages  xxxvi-­‐‑lxi.

Interpretative  Studies

Pierre  Aubenque,  “Aristote  et  la  démocratie,”  in  Individu  et  société.L’influence  d’Aristote  dans  le  monde  méditerranéen.  Actes  du  Colloqued’Istanbul  Palais  de  France,  5-­‐‑9  Janvier  1986.  ed.  Thierry  Zarcone  (Istanbul,  1988  =  Varia  TurcicaX),  pp.  31-­‐‑38.

Jonathan  Barnes,  “Aristotle  and  Political  Liberty,”  in  Aristoteles’  Politik.  Akten  des  XI.

Page 20: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

Symposium  Aristotelicum.  Friedrichshafen/Bodensee  25.8-­‐‑3.9.1987,  ed.  G.  Pavig  (GöKingen,  1990),pages  249-­‐‑263,  with  comments  by  R.  Sorabji,  pages  264-­‐‑76.

Mortimer  Chambers,  “Aristotle’s  ‘Forms  of  Democracy,’”  Transactions  of  the  AmericanPhilological  Association  vol.  92  (1961),  pages  20-­‐‑36.

Abraham  Edel,  Aristotle  and  his  Philosophy  (Chapel  Hill,  1982),  pages  325-­‐‑328.

Christoph  Eucken,  “Der  aristotelische  Demokratiebegriff  und  sein  historisches  Umfeld,”  inAristoteles'ʹ  Politik.  Akten  des  XI.  Symposium  Aristotelicum.  Friedrichshafen/Bodensee  25.8-­‐‑3.9.1987,ed.  G.  Pavig  (GöKingen,  1990),  pages  277-­‐‑291,  with  comments  by  T.  H.  Irwin,  pages  292-­‐‑95.

Robert  A.  Goldberg,  Democracy  and  Justice  in  Aristotle’s  Politics,  University  of  Torontodissertation,  1990;  summary  in  Dissertation  Abstracts  51  (1990-­‐‑91)  1369A.

Andrew  LintoK,  “Aristotle  and  Democracy,”  Classical  Quarterly  42  (1992),  pages  114-­‐‑128.

Claude  Mossé,  “égalité  democratique  et  inégalité  sociales.  Le  Débat  à  Athènes  au  IVèmeSiècle,”  Metis  2  (1987),  pages  165-­‐‑176,  195-­‐‑206  (esp.  pages  201-­‐‑206  on  the  Politics).

R.  G.  Mulgan,  Aristotle’s  Political  Theory.  An  Introduction  for  Students  of  Political  Theory  (Oxford,1977),  pages  73-­‐‑75,  and  “Aristotle’s  analysis  of  democracy  and  oligarchy,”  in  A  Companion  toAristotle’s  Politics,  ed.  David  Keyt  and  Fred  D,  Miller,  Jr.  (Blackwell,  Oxford,  1991),  pages  307-­‐‑322.

Oswyn  Murray,  “Polis  and  Politeia  in  Aristotle,”  in  The  Ancient  Greek  City  State,  edited  MogensHerman  Hansen  (Copenhagen,  1993),  pages  197-­‐‑210.

Martha  Nussbaum,  “Aristotelian  Social  Democracy,”  in  Liberalism  and  the  Good,  edited  R.Bruce  Douglas  (New  York,  1990),  pages  203-­‐‑252.

Josiah  Ober,  “Aristotle’s  Political  Sociology:  Class,  Status,  and  Order  in  the  Politics,”  in  Essayson  the  Foundations  of  Aristotelian  Political  Science,  edited  Carnes  Lord  and  David  K.  O'ʹConnor(Berkeley  and  Los  Angeles,  1991),  pages  112-­‐‑135.

Demetris  Papadis,  “Il  conceKo  di  democrazia  in  Aristotele,”  Discorsi  9  (1989),  pages  326-­‐‑340.

C.  I.  Papageorgiou,  “Four  or  five  types  of  democracy  in  Aristotle?,”  History  of  Political  Thoughtvol.  11  (1990),  pages  1-­‐‑8.

David  Ross,  Aristotle,  5th  edition  (London,  1949),  pages  250-­‐‑263.

Arlene  W.  Saxenhouse,  Fear  of  Diversity.  The  Birth  of  Political  Science  in  Ancient  Greek  Thought(Chicago,  1992),  pages  189-­‐‑232  (“Aristotle:  Diversity  and  the  Birth  of  Political  Science”).

Paul  Schollmeier,  “The  democracy  most  in  accordance  with  equality,”  History  of  PoliticalThought  9  (1988),  pages  205-­‐‑209.

Barry  S.  Strauss,  “On  Aristotle'ʹs  Critique  of  Athenian  Democracy,”  in  Essays  on  the  Foundationsof  Aristotelian  Political  Science,  ed.  Carnes  Lord  and  David  K.  O'ʹConnor  (Berkeley  and  LosAngeles,  1991),  pages  212-­‐‑233.

Page 21: Democracy in the Politics of Aristotle

[  back  to  top  ]

J.  Touloumakos,  Die  theoretische  Begründung  der  Demokratie  in  der  klassischen  Zeit  Griechenlands(Die  demokratische  Argumentation  in  der  “Politik”  des  Aristoteles)  (Athens,  1985).

section  view    |    home

When  using  this  article  as  a  resource,  cite  it  thus:

Thomas  R.  Martin,  with  Neel  Smith  &  Jennifer  F.Stuart,  “Democracy  in  the  Politics  of  Aristotle  ,”  in  C.W.  Blackwell,  ed.,Dēmos:  Classical  Athenian  Democracy  (A.  Mahoney  and  R.  Scaife,  edd.,  The  Stoa:  a  consortium  for  electronic  publication  in  the

humanities  [www.stoa.org])  edition  of  July  26,  2003.  Contact:  [email protected].

©  July  26,  2003,  Thomas  R.  Martin,  with  Neel  Smith  &  Jennifer  F.Stuart.  This  work  is  licensed  under  a  Creative  CommonsLicense.

Dēmos  ·∙  Classical  Athenian  Democracy  ·∙  a  Stoa  Publication