24
1 Conceptual Analysis and Natural Kinds: The Case of Knowledge Joachim Horvath University of Cologne April 29, 2015 Final Version * Abstract: There is a line of reasoning in metaepistemology that is congenial to naturalism and hard to resist, yet ultimately misguided: that knowledge might be a natural kind, and that this would undermine the use of conceptual analysis in the theory of knowledge. In this paper, I first bring out various problems with Hilary Kornblith’s argument from the causalexplanatory indispensability of knowledge to the natural kindhood of knowledge. I then criticize the argument from the natural kindhood of knowledge against the method of conceptual analysis in the theory of knowledge. A natural motivation for this argument is the following seemingly plausible principle: if knowledge is a natural kind, then the concept of knowledge is a natural kind concept. Since this principle lacks adequate support, the crucial semantic claim that the concept of knowledge is a natural kind concept must be defended in some more direct way. However, there are two striking epistemic disanalogies between the concept of knowledge and paradigmatic natural kind concepts that militate against this semantic claim. Conceptual analyses of knowledge are not affected by total error, and the proponents of such analyses are not subject to a priori conceptual obliviousness. I conclude that the argument from natural kindhood does not succeed in undermining the use of conceptual analysis in the theory of knowledge. * The final publication is available at Springer via http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0751-z.

Conceptual analysis and natural kinds: The case of knowledge

  • Upload
    rub

  • View
    1

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  1  

Conceptual  Analysis  and  Natural  Kinds:  

The  Case  of  Knowledge    

Joachim  Horvath  

University  of  Cologne  

April  29,  2015  

 

Final  Version*  

 

 

Abstract:   There  is  a  line  of  reasoning  in  metaepistemology  that  is  congenial  to  

naturalism  and  hard  to  resist,  yet  ultimately  misguided:  that  knowledge  might  be  a  

natural  kind,  and  that  this  would  undermine  the  use  of  conceptual  analysis  in  the  theory  

of  knowledge.  In  this  paper,  I  first  bring  out  various  problems  with  Hilary  Kornblith’s  

argument  from  the  causal-­‐explanatory  indispensability  of  knowledge  to  the  natural  

kindhood  of  knowledge.  I  then  criticize  the  argument  from  the  natural  kindhood  of  

knowledge  against  the  method  of  conceptual  analysis  in  the  theory  of  knowledge.  A  

natural  motivation  for  this  argument  is  the  following  seemingly  plausible  principle:  if  

knowledge  is  a  natural  kind,  then  the  concept  of  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind  concept.  

Since  this  principle  lacks  adequate  support,  the  crucial  semantic  claim  that  the  concept  

of  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind  concept  must  be  defended  in  some  more  direct  way.  

However,  there  are  two  striking  epistemic  disanalogies  between  the  concept  of  

knowledge  and  paradigmatic  natural  kind  concepts  that  militate  against  this  semantic  

claim.  Conceptual  analyses  of  knowledge  are  not  affected  by  total  error,  and  the  

proponents  of  such  analyses  are  not  subject  to  a  priori  conceptual  obliviousness.  I  

conclude  that  the  argument  from  natural  kindhood  does  not  succeed  in  undermining  the  

use  of  conceptual  analysis  in  the  theory  of  knowledge.  

 

                                                                                                               * The final publication is available at Springer via http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0751-z.

  2  

1.  Introduction  

 

There  is  a  certain  temptation  in  metaepistemology  that  is  congenial  to  naturalism  and  

hard  to  resist,  even  though  it  is  ultimately  misguided.  This  temptation  can  be  brought  

out  as  follows.  Suppose  you  are  an  epistemologist  working  on  the  theory  of  knowledge  

and  God  tells  you  one  day  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind.  Your  reaction  to  this  divine  

revelation  might  be  the  following:  “All  these  years  of  hard  armchair  work  on  the  analysis  

of  knowledge,  all  this  wrestling  with  tricky  cases  and  counterexamples,  all  these  

countless  refinements  and  improvements  of  my  analysis  of  knowledge:  it  was  all  a  giant  

waste  of  time!  I  should  have  gotten  out  of  the  armchair  a  long  time  ago  and  studied  

knowledge  just  like  any  other  empirical  phenomenon.”  Even  though  it  would  be  

tempting  to  react  in  this  way  (see,  e.g.,  Heller  1996,  335;  Kornblith  2007,  47;  Kumar  

2014,  442;  Ludwig  2013,  232),  this  temptation  should  nevertheless  be  resisted,  as  I  will  

argue  in  this  paper.  

  The  philosopher  who  has  given  in  to  this  temptation  more  than  any  other  

philosopher  is  Hilary  Kornblith  (cf.  Kornblith  1999,  2002,  2007).  The  main  point  of  his  

book  Knowledge  and  Its  Place  in  Nature  (2002)  is  to  argue  for  the  radical  

metaepistemological  claim  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind.  According  to  Kornblith,  

knowledge  should  therefore  be  investigated  with  the  methods  of  empirical  science,  and  

not  by  means  of  armchair  conceptual  analysis  or  intuitions.  Even  though  Kornblith  also  

advances  other  objections  to  conceptual  analysis  in  epistemology  (cf.  Kornblith  2007,  

2013),  the  argument  from  the  natural  kindhood  of  knowledge  arguably  takes  center  

stage  in  his  particular  brand  of  naturalized  epistemology.  He  summarizes  the  argument  

as  follows  in  the  final  chapter  of  Knowledge  and  Its  Place  in  Nature:  

 

I  have  been  urging  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind  and  thus  that  a  proper  understanding  

of  the  nature  of  knowledge  requires  a  certain  sort  of  empirical  investigation.  It  is  a  mistake  

to  investigate  our  intuitions  about  knowledge  or  our  concept  of  knowledge  because  

these  may  be  importantly  incomplete  or  importantly  mistaken  or  both.  (Kornblith  2002,  

163;  my  emphasis)2  

 

                                                                                                               2 Other proponents of naturalized epistemology tend to concur. For example, Victor Kumar claims: “If knowledge is a natural kind, then the satisfaction conditions for ‘knowledge’ cannot be discovered through armchair reflection of the sort that is characteristic of traditional conceptual analysis.” (Kumar 2014, 442).

  3  

As  it  stands,  the  argument  challenges  any  kind  of  apriorism  in  the  theory  of  knowledge,  

and  not  just  the  use  of  conceptual  analysis  or  intuitions,  because  Kornblith  draws  the  

very  general  conclusion  that  the  natural  kindhood  of  knowledge  “requires  a  certain  sort  

of  empirical  investigation”.  In  this  paper,  I  want  to  address  the  more  specific  question  

whether  the  natural  kindhood  of  knowledge  undermines  the  use  of  conceptual  analysis  

in  the  theory  of  knowledge.  I  will  conclude  that  the  metaphysical  claim  that  knowledge  

is  a  natural  kind  does  not  by  itself  undermine  the  methodological  claim  that  conceptual  

analysis  is  an  adequate  method  for  analyzing  knowledge.  To  challenge  the  latter  claim,  

one  must  focus  on  the  concept  of  knowledge  instead,  and  argue  that  it  is  a  natural  kind  

concept  like  WATER  or  GOLD.3  However,  the  prospects  for  such  an  argument  are  dim,  

because  KNOWLEDGE  behaves  very  unlike  paradigmatic  natural  kind  concepts.  

 

 

2.  The  Argument  from  the  Natural  Kindhood  of  Knowledge  

 

The  standard  view  in  the  theory  of  knowledge  is  that  conceptual  analysis  aims  at  an  

analysis  of  knowledge  in  terms  of  an  illuminating4  set  of  individually  necessary  and  

jointly  sufficient  conditions  for  knowledge,5  of  the  kind  that  potentially6  reveals  the  

essence  or  nature7  of  the  property  or  kind  knowledge.8  Proposed  analyses  of  knowledge  

are  standardly  expressed  by  (metaphysically)  necessary  biconditionals,  such  as  

‘necessarily,  something  is  knowledge  if  and  only  if  it  is  a  justified  true  belief’  (cf.  

                                                                                                               3 I follow the usual convention of indicating reference to concepts with SMALL CAPS. 4 This qualification is supposed to rule out circular or irrelevant necessary conditions, such as the condition of being self-identical or being such that 2 + 2 = 4. In fact, I think that an adequate account of philosophical analysis requires a more substantial and specific condition than the fairly vague requirement of being illuminating (cf. Horvath ms). But for our present purposes, this condition should work reasonably well. 5 For example, in his An Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology Matthias Steup writes: “For an analysis to be correct, the analysans must specify conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for the analysandum. […] For an analysis to be successful, it must be illuminating […].” (Steup 1996, 27–28) 6 Why this hedged formulation? Because the connection between a philosophical analysis and the essence of the relevant property or kind is less straightforward than is commonly assumed (cf. Horvath ms). In particular, the nature of this link depends on one’s general metaphysical commitments concerning the metaphysics of properties and essences. For example, if one takes properties to be mere sets of possibilia (cf. Lewis 1986, chap. 1.5), then all necessarily co-instantiated properties will be identical, and thus a necessary biconditional that states necessary and sufficient conditions for X will effectively just tell us that a certain property X—which can be expressed in at least two different ways—is necessarily self-co-instantiated. However, such general truths about properties arguably do not belong to the essence of any particular property, and thus the necessary biconditional in question would not reveal the specific nature of the property of being X (cf. Fine 1995). In this case, an analysis of X would be more like an informative identity claim, such as ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’, than like a claim about the essence of being X—because being the set of all possible Xs might already exhaust the latter. 7 I use the terms ‘essence’ and ‘nature’ interchangeably in this paper. 8 I indicate reference to properties or kinds with italics, and I will mostly gloss over the difference, if any, between properties and kinds (unless explicitly noted otherwise).

  4  

Williamson  2007;  Malmgren  2011).  If  successful,  the  argument  from  natural  kindhood  

would  undermine  the  status  of  conceptual  analysis  as  a  proper  method  for  seeking  an  

analysis  of  knowledge  in  this  sense.    

Let  us  now  make  this  argument  more  explicit:  

 

    (1)   Knowledge  is  a  natural  kind.  

(2)   If  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind,  then  illuminating  necessary  and  

sufficient  conditions  for  knowledge  can  only  be  figured  out  with  

empirical  methods.  

(3)   Conceptual  analysis  is  not  an  empirical  method.  

(C)   Illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  knowledge  

cannot  be  figured  out  with  conceptual  analysis.  

 

Since  the  argument  is  clearly  valid,  let  us  therefore  consider  its  premises.  The  least  

controversial  premise  should  be  (3),  that  conceptual  analysis  is  not  an  empirical  

method.  Indeed,  the  method  of  conceptual  analysis  is  typically  seen  as  a  paradigm  of  an  

a  priori  method,  and  given  that  a  priori  methods  are  standardly  understood  as  non-­‐

empirical  methods,  premise  (3)  simply  follows  from  these  widely  held  assumptions.  

Even  though  there  are  a  few  dissenting  voices  (cf.  Miščević  2000,  2005;  Schwitzgebel  

2008),  I  will  simply  take  premise  (3)  for  granted  in  the  following.  

 

 

3.  Knowledge  as  a  Natural  Kind?  

 

What  can  be  said  in  favor  of  premise  (1)  of  the  argument  from  natural  kindhood,  i.e.,  the  

claim  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind?  Let  us  consider  how  Kornblith  (2002,  ch.  2)  

argues  for  this  seemingly  radical  thesis.    

Kornblith’s  key  move  is  to  point  out  that  knowledge  plays  a  robust  explanatory  

role  in  cognitive  ethology,  which  is  a  branch  of  behavioral  biology.  On  the  basis  of  

behavioral  evidence  about  animals  such  as  ravens  or  chimpanzees,  Kornblith  argues—

following  many  cognitive  ethologists—that  the  ascription  of  knowledge,  instead  of  mere  

true  belief,  is  often  indispensable  for  explaining  sophisticated  forms  of  animal  behavior,  

for  example,  co-­‐operative  hunting  behavior  in  ravens  (cf.  Kornblith  2002,  31).  The  key  

  5  

idea  is  that  the  animals  in  question  could  not  behave  in  the  way  they  do  unless  certain  

knowledge-­‐states  were  among  the  causally  relevant  antecedents  of  their  behavior.    

How  do  these  considerations  from  cognitive  ethology  support  the  claim  that  

knowledge  is  a  natural  kind?  On  Kornblith’s  preferred  account  of  natural  kinds,  

something  is  a  natural  kind  just  in  case  it  is  a  homeostatic  cluster  of  properties,9  i.e.,  a  

cluster  of  properties  that  is  “mutually  supporting  and  reinforcing  in  the  face  of  external  

change”  (Kornblith  2002,  61).  Such  homeostatic  clusters  of  properties  display  a  degree  

of  causal  stability  that  is  “not  found  in  just  any  random  collection”  of  properties  (ibid.).  

Therefore,  homeostatic  clusters  are  able  to  support  various  inductive  inferences  or  

natural  (causal)  laws.  They  also  explain  the  characteristic  surface-­‐properties  of  natural  

kinds,  such  as  the  liquidity  of  water,  which  is  explained  by  the  homeostatic  character  of  

H2O  molecules  and  their  causal  interactions  with  other  H2O  molecules  under  ordinary  

conditions  of  pressure  and  temperature.  Natural  kinds  are  thus  understood  as  

particularly  stable  nodes  in  the  causal  network  of  the  world,  i.e.,  they  are  individuated  in  

causal-­‐explanatory  terms.  Given  that  Kornblith  subscribes  to  a  causal  view  of  natural  

kinds,  it  makes  sense  to  identify  natural  kinds  and  their  essential  features  by  the  role  

they  play  in  our  best  causal  explanations.  And  given  that  knowledge  seems  to  play  an  

indispensable  role  in  the  causal  explanation  of  sophisticated  animal  behavior,  it  thus  

makes  sense  to  conclude  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind.  

Kornblith’s  key  empirical  claim  that  knowledge  is  an  indispensable  factor  in  

causal  explanations  is  open  to  various  objections  (see,  e.g.,  Pernu  2009),  but  I  do  not  

want  to  take  issue  with  this  part  of  his  argument  here.  For  the  sake  of  the  argument,  I  

will  assume  that  he  is  completely  right  about  that.  What  seems  more  committal  from  a  

philosophical  point  of  view  is  the  crucial  inference  from  ‘playing  an  indispensable  

causal-­‐explanatory  role’  to  ‘being  a  natural  kind’.  The  main  justification  for  this  move  is  

the  assumption,  adopted  via  Boyd’s  (1988,  1991)  homeostatic  cluster  account  of  natural  

kinds,  that  natural  kinds  are  individuated  in  causal  terms.    

However,  the  homeostatic  cluster  view  has  a  striking  feature  that  makes  it  

especially  problematic  in  the  context  of  a  methodological  argument  against  conceptual  

analysis.  On  the  homeostatic  cluster  view,  natural  kinds  are  causally  stable  clusters  of  

properties.  Since  causal  stability  is  a  matter  of  degree,  it  can  be  more  or  less  perfect.  As  a  

result,  there  will  be  instances  of  natural  kinds  that  lack  some  of  the  properties  in  the  

                                                                                                               9 The account is mainly developed in Kornblith (1993), and it is basically a version of Richard Boyd’s account of natural kinds (cf. Boyd 1988, 1991).

  6  

relevant  cluster,  e.g.,  borderline  instances  of  biological  species.  The  consequence  is  that  

the  properties  in  a  homeostatic  cluster  do  not  specify  necessary  and  sufficient  

conditions  for  membership  in  the  relevant  kind.  Here  is  how  Boyd  sums  up  this  point:  

 

The  natural  definition  of  one  of  these  homeostatic  property  cluster  kinds  is  determined  

by  the  members  of  a  cluster  of  often  co-­‐occurring  properties  and  by  the  (“homeostatic”)  

mechanisms  that  bring  about  their  co-­‐occurrence.  […]  In  cases  of  imperfect  homeostasis  

in  which  some  of  the  properties  in  the  cluster  are  absent  or  some  of  the  mechanisms  

inoperative  it  will  sometimes  happen  that  neither  theoretical  nor  methodological  

considerations  assign  the  object  being  classified  determinately  to  the  kind  or  to  its  

complement,  with  the  result  that  the  homeostatic  property-­‐cluster  definition  fails  to  

specify  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  kind  membership.  (Boyd  1991,  141–142)  

 

Recall  that  the  standard  goal  of  conceptual  analysis  is  to  come  up  with  an  analysis  in  

terms  of  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions.  Someone  who  relies  on  a  

homeostatic  cluster  view  of  natural  kinds,  like  Kornblith,  would  thus  be  unable  to  

contribute  to  that  goal,  for  reasons  that  have  nothing  specifically  to  do  with  the  rejection  

of  a  priori  methods.  For,  if  knowledge  were  a  homeostatic  cluster  kind,  then  no  method  

could  possibly  deliver  a  set  of  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  

knowledge,  simply  because  knowledge  would  not  be  the  sort  of  thing  that  has  

illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions.  Therefore,  it  seems  that  Kornblith  

would  have  to  reject  conceptual  analysis  not  primarily  because  of  its  a  priori  character,  

but  rather  by  (implicitly)  rejecting  its  very  goal  of  specifying  illuminating  necessary  and  

sufficient  conditions.10  However,  this  is  not  how  Kornblith  actually  argues  in  the  passage  

quoted  above,  where  he  seems  to  hold  on  to  the  standard  goal  of  conceptual  analysis  

and  merely  objects  to  its  non-­‐empirical  character.  To  reject  both  the  standard  goal  

(illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions)  and  method  (conceptual  analysis,  

intuition)  of  analyzing  knowledge  would  make  Kornblith’s  naturalism  even  more  radical  

than  it  already  is.  

                                                                                                               10 One might object that conceptual analysis could also pursue the weaker goal of providing a cluster analysis, e.g., in the sense of Searle (1969, chap. 7), which would seem to be compatible with the homeostatic cluster account of natural kinds (thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue). The basic idea is that something only needs to satisfy sufficiently many (but not all) of the analyzing features that a cluster analysis of some category K specifies in order to qualify as an instance of K. From a methodological point of view, however, this can only be seen as a highly revisionary proposal, at least with respect to the category of knowledge—it certainly does not reflect how most epistemologists conceive of their own attempts at analyzing knowledge.

  7  

Given  Kornblith’s  own  emphasis  on  the  rejection  of  conceptual  analysis  qua  a  

priori  method,  it  would  thus  seem  fitting  to  adopt  the  more  orthodox  conception  of  

natural  kinds  by  Putnam  (1975)  and  Kripke  (1980).  This  conception  allows  for  the  

discovery  of  a  posteriori  identities,  such  as  ‘water  is  H2O’  or  ‘gold  is  the  element  with  

atomic  number  79’,  that  specify  the  underlying  microstructure  of  the  natural  kinds  in  

question.11  Since  a  posteriori  identities  of  this  sort  entail  illuminating  necessary  

biconditionals  such  as  ‘necessarily,  something  is  water  iff  it  is  H2O’,  they  do  allow  for  

pursuing  the  traditional  goal  of  conceptual  analysis,  i.e.,  to  provide  illuminating  

necessary  and  sufficient  conditions,  with  empirical  means—unlike  the  homeostatic  

cluster  view.  In  other  words,  the  Putnam-­‐Kripke  conception  of  natural  kinds  would  

enable  Kornblith  to  only  reject  conceptual  analysis  as  an  appropriate  method  for  

theorizing  about  knowledge,  while  holding  on  to  the  standard  goal  of  providing  

illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  knowledge  (although  on  a  scientific  

basis  and  not  through  some  form  of  armchair  analysis).  

Adopting  the  Putnam-­‐Kripke  conception  would,  however,  threaten  to  undermine  

Kornblith’s  argument  for  the  claim  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind,  because  this  

argument  crucially  depends  on  the  inference  from  ‘playing  an  indispensable  causal-­‐

explanatory  role’  to  ‘being  a  natural  kind’.  Since  the  Putnam-­‐Kripke  conception  is  not  

committed  to  a  causal  individuation  of  natural  kinds,  it  does  not  by  itself  support  the  key  

inference  from  ‘having  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile’  to  ‘being  a  natural  kind’.  On  

this  conception,  something  that  clearly  is  a  natural  kind,  like  water  or  gold,  might  be  

causally  inert  in  some  other  possible  world,  e.g.,  in  a  world  with  very  different  laws  of  

nature,  while  something  that  has  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile  in  the  actual  world,  

like  knowledge  (if  Kornblith  is  right),  might  nevertheless  fail  to  be  a  natural  kind.  

But  maybe  Kornblith’s  argument  for  the  natural  kindhood  of  knowledge  does  not  

require  such  a  tight  connection  between  the  causal-­‐explanatory  role  of  knowledge  and  

the  causal  individuation  of  natural  kinds.  Maybe  the  fact  that  a  given  kind  K  has  a  robust  

causal-­‐explanatory  profile  should  rather  be  seen  as  a  fallible  criterion  for  the  natural  

kindhood  of  K.  Understood  in  this  way,  Kornblith’s  argument  would  merely  require  that  

the  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile  of  knowledge  makes  the  natural  kindhood  of  

knowledge  sufficiently  likely,  without  actually  entailing  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind.  

                                                                                                               11 In fact, Kornblith explicitly endorses the basic contours of the Putnam-Kripke conception of natural kinds and natural kind concepts (Kornblith 2002, 12–13, fn. 17 & 18).

  8  

Yet  given  the  orthodox  Putnam-­‐Kripke  conception,  which  does  not  claim  any  

constitutive  link  between  causal  efficacy  and  natural  kindhood,  it  seems  difficult  to  

motivate  even  a  merely  probabilistic  relation  between  ‘having  a  robust  causal-­‐

explanatory  profile’  and  ‘being  a  natural  kind’.  For  this  would  apparently  require  that  

most  of  the  categories  that  have  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile  also  happen  to  be  

natural  kinds.  Since  the  total  number  of  categories  that  have  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  

profile  is  vast,  maybe  even  infinite,  such  a  claim  is  difficult  to  evaluate.  But  on  the  face  of  

it,  many  categories  that  have  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile  are  not  happily  

classified  as  natural  kinds.  Think,  for  example,  about  the  many  causal-­‐explanatory  

categories  from  the  social  realm,  such  as  money,  power,  citizenship,  or  military  force,  or  

about  the  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile  of  many  artifactual  kinds,  such  as  key,  

hammer,  screwdriver,  or  lawnmower.  In  fact,  even  some  mathematical  categories,  which  

typically  do  not  figure  on  anyone’s  list  of  natural  kinds,  have  a  robust-­‐causal  explanatory  

profile,  as  I  will  argue  in  the  following  section  for  the  case  of  primeness.  So  arguably,  

there  is  a  large  number  of  prima  facie  counterexamples  to  the  inference  from  ‘having  a  

robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile’  to  ‘being  a  natural  kind’,  and  this  challenges  the  claim  

that  most  of  the  categories  that  have  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile  are  natural  

kinds.  For  this  reason,  the  idea  that  having  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile  is  a  valid  

probabilistic  criterion  for  natural  kindhood  does  not  seem  very  promising  either.  

In  sum,  it  is  hard  to  see  how  Kornblith’s  argument  from  the  indispensable  causal-­‐

explanatory  role  of  knowledge  in  cognitive  ethology  to  the  natural  kindhood  of  

knowledge  can  be  supported  in  the  intended  way.  On  the  one  hand,  the  argument  from  

the  causal-­‐explanatory  role  of  knowledge  to  the  natural  kindhood  of  knowledge  crucially  

relies  on  the  homeostatic  cluster  view  of  natural  kinds.  Yet  this  view  undermines  the  

standard  goal  of  analyzing  knowledge  in  terms  of  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  

conditions,  and  so  the  argument  aims  too  broadly.  Opting  for  the  orthodox  Putnam-­‐

Kripke  conception  of  natural  kinds  would  help  to  avoid  the  latter  problem,  but  this  

conception  fails  to  provide  a  metaphysical  link  between  causal-­‐explanatory  

indispensability  and  natural  kindhood.  Absent  such  a  link,  however,  it  seems  difficult  to  

support  the  crucial  inference  from  ‘having  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile’  to  ‘being  

a  natural  kind’.  

 

 

 

  9  

4.  Natural  Kindhood  and  Conceptual  Analysis  

 

How  should  we  assess  premise  (2)  of  the  argument  from  natural  kindhood?  That  is,  how  

should  we  assess  the  conditional  ‘if  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind,  then  illuminating  

necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  knowledge  can  only  be  figured  out  with  empirical  

methods’?  

  Here  is  an  initial  reason  to  be  skeptical  about  premise  (2).  The  claim  that  

knowledge  is  a  natural  kind  is  a  metaphysical  claim  about  knowledge,  and  not  a  claim  

about  our  epistemic  relation  to  knowledge,  and  also  not  a  claim  about  our  concept  of  

knowledge.  And  why  should  a  particular  view  about  the  metaphysics  of  knowledge  have  

any  specific  implications  for  the  epistemology  or  semantics  of  knowledge—in  this  case:  

negative  implications  for  conceptual  analysis?  The  metaphysical  status  of  individual  

objects,  for  example,  does  not  have  any  specific  implications  for  the  analysis  of  proper  

names,  and  the  metaphysics  of  spacetime  does  not  suggest  any  particular  view  about  the  

meaning  of  indexicals  like  ‘here’  or  ‘now’.  Why  should  this  be  otherwise  in  case  of  the  

metaphysics  of  knowledge  and  the  meaning  of  the  word  ‘knowledge’,  or  the  content  of  

the  concept  KNOWLEDGE?  

One  suggestive  answer  might  be:  if  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind,  then  KNOWLEDGE  

must  be  a  natural  kind  concept,  and  natural  kind  concepts  are  not  a  priori  analyzable  in  

terms  of  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions.12  According  to  the  standard  

view,  natural  kind  concepts  are  nondescriptive  concepts13  that  are  not  constitutively  

                                                                                                               12 Note that the converse argument from ‘KNOWLEDGE is a natural kind concept’ to ‘knowledge is a natural kind’ clearly fails, because a natural kind concept may fail to pick out any kind at all, as in the case of PHLOGISTON, or it may pick out a disjunctive, non-natural kind, as in the case of JADE. One might object that it is not clear what exactly makes PHLOGISTON or JADE a natural kind concept in the first place, given that they actually fail to pick out a natural kind (thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue). First, of course, what makes them natural kind concepts is the fact that they are equally nondescriptive as paradigmatic natural kind concepts, such as MASS or GOLD. But since nondescriptiveness is not sufficient for being a natural kind concept—given that one can even refer to a non-natural kind like bachelorhood with a nondescriptive concept (see below in the main text)—there must be some further reason why it is legitimate to regard PHLOGISTON and JADE as natural kind concepts. A plausible suggestion would be that the way the concepts PHLOGISTON and JADE were introduced is completely analogous to the way certain paradigmatic natural kind concepts were introduced, and this, together with their nondescriptiveness, suffices to regard them as natural kind concepts. With some amount of idealization, we can say that, for example, the concept PHLOGISTON was introduced to refer to a certain natural phenomenon that was (incorrectly) thought to play a particular theoretical role in chemistry – just like the concept MASS was introduced to refer to a certain natural phenomenon that was (correctly) thought to play a particular theoretical role in physics. And again with some amount of idealization, we can say that the concept JADE was introduced by ostension to particular instances of jade, with the (unsuccessful) intention of referring to that kind of stuff or natural kind (depending on the conceptual sophistication of those who introduced the concept)—just like the concept GOLD was introduced by ostension to particular instances of gold, with the (successful) intention of referring to that kind of stuff or natural kind (see also Soames 2007). 13 According to some accounts of natural kind concepts, they must at least have a minimal descriptive core in order to solve the so-called ‘qua-problem’ (see, e.g., Devitt and Sterelny 1999). For example, one might try to fix

  10  

associated  with  any  descriptive  features  or  inferential  relations  (cf.  Kripke  1980;  

Putnam  1970,  1975;  Soames  2002).14  Therefore,  we  need  not  have  any  explicit  or  

implicit  representations  of  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  in  order  to  

possess  a  natural  kind  concept.  And  the  representations  that  we  have  can  be  highly  

misleading  with  respect  to  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  kind  membership.  

Even  subjects  who  competently  possess  a  natural  kind  concept,  such  as  WATER  or  GOLD,  

are  therefore  prone  to  all  kinds  of  ignorance  and  error  concerning  necessary  and  

sufficient  conditions  for  membership  in  the  relevant  kind.  Apparently,  this  is  what  

Kornblith  has  in  mind  when  he  suggests  that  “our  concept  of  knowledge  […]  may  be  

importantly  incomplete  or  importantly  mistaken  or  both”  (see  quote  above).  

However,  it  does  not  follow  from  the  fact  that  a  kind  K  is  a  natural  kind  that  any  

concept  of  K  must  be  a  natural  kind  concept.  Gold  is  a  natural  kind,  but  THE  ELEMENT  WITH  

ATOMIC  NUMBER  79  is  a  descriptive  concept  of  gold  (see  also  Ludwig  2013,  233).  Of  course,  

analyzing  the  concept  THE  ELEMENT  WITH  ATOMIC  NUMBER  79  only  provides  us  with  the  

rather  trivial  necessary  biconditional  ‘something  is  the  element  with  atomic  number  79  

iff  it  is  the  only  thing  that  is  an  element  and  has  atomic  number  79’.    

But  the  apparent  difference  between  a  concept  like  THE  ELEMENT  WITH  ATOMIC  

NUMBER  79  and  the  concept  KNOWLEDGE  can  be  understood  in  purely  epistemic  terms.  

While  the  descriptive  content  of  the  concept  THE  ELEMENT  WITH  ATOMIC  NUMBER  79  is  

cognitively  transparent,  such  that  coming  to  know  that  content  requires  only  minimal  

reflection,  the  descriptive  content  of  the  concept  KNOWLEDGE  is  not  cognitively  

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         the reference of the concept TIGER to the natural kind tiger by ostension to actual tigers, which is one important way to fix the reference of natural kind concepts. But then it may still be indeterminate whether TIGER refers to tigers, animals, living beings, or material objects. For this reason, natural kind concepts may need a certain minimum of descriptive features in their content, such as being an animal. As a consequence, one may come to know certain trivial facts about tigers merely on the basis of analyzing the concept TIGER, e.g., that tigers are animals. This is still a far cry from illuminating necessary and sufficient conditions for being a tiger, however. 14 Natural kind concepts are also standardly regarded as rigid designators (cf. Kripke 1980), i.e., as concepts that have the same referent in all possible worlds (where they have a referent at all). However, it is an open question whether the notion of rigidity—which was primarily developed for singular terms—can also be extended to general terms or general concepts, like WATER, GOLD, or BACHELOR (cf. Besson 2010; Schwartz 1980, 2002; Soames 2002, chap. 9). For example, if one identifies the reference of general concepts with their extension, then the reference of most natural kind concepts will clearly not be the same in all relevant possible worlds. There surely could have been, e.g., more or less water or gold than there actually is, so the extension of WATER and GOLD changes across possible worlds. What if one identifies the reference of general concepts with the relevant property or kind instead, e.g., with the property of being gold in case of the concept GOLD? This assigns a reference to GOLD that does indeed remain constant across all relevant possible worlds. But the same holds for general concepts that are clearly not natural kind concepts. For example, if the concept BACHELOR has the property of being a bachelor as its referent, then it surely refers to that property in all possible worlds where it has a referent at all—for, which other property should it refer to if not to the property being a bachelor? For these reasons, I put the issue of rigidity aside in this paper. The whole work in an argument against conceptual analysis is done by the nondescriptiveness of natural kind concepts anyway.

  11  

transparent  in  this  way,  and  coming  to  know  it  apparently  requires  a  substantial  amount  

of  a  priori  reflection.    

The  dissociation  between  the  epistemic  properties  of  a  concept  and  the  

metaphysical  status  of  its  referent  is  further  substantiated  by  the  fact  that  we  can  also  

use  nondescriptive  concepts  in  order  to  refer  to  paradigmatic  non-­‐natural  kinds.  For  

example,  we  could  introduce  a  nondescriptive  concept  of  bachelorhood  by  using  the  

merely  reference-­‐fixing  description  ‘men  with  that  marital  status’,  while  

demonstratively  referring  to  a  group  of  bachelors  (cf.  Kripke  1980,  57–58  on  merely  

reference-­‐fixing  descriptions).  

Therefore,  even  if  knowledge  is  indeed  a  natural  kind,  it  does  not  follow  that  

every  concept  of  knowledge  is  also  a  natural  kind  concept.  One  might  object  that  we  are  

not  considering  arbitrary  concepts  of  knowledge  here,  such  as  ERNEST  SOSA’S  FAVORITE  

PHILOSOPHICAL  SUBJECT  MATTER  or  THE  MAIN  TOPIC  OF  KNOWLEDGE  AND  ITS  PLACE  IN  NATURE.  

Rather,  we  are  concerned  with  the  pre-­‐theoretical  lexicalized  concept  KNOWLEDGE  that  

we  standardly  express  with  the  ordinary  English  word  ‘knowledge’.  Even  if  it  does  not  

strictly  follow  from  the  natural  kindhood  of  K  that  our  lexicalized  concept  of  K  is  a  

natural  kind  concept,  one  might  nevertheless  argue  that  this  inference  enjoys  strong  

inductive  support.  For,  in  case  of  paradigmatic  natural  kinds,  such  as  water,  gold,  tiger,  

or  aluminum,  the  relevant  lexicalized  concepts  are  indeed  natural  kind  concepts.  So  

given  the  assumption  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind,  isn’t  it  at  least  highly  probable  

that  KNOWLEDGE  is  a  natural  kind  concept?    

The  answer  is:  only  if  the  characteristic  features  of  paradigmatic  natural  kinds  

are  projectible  to  the  case  of  knowledge,  and  this  seems  highly  questionable.  For  on  the  

face  of  it,  the  kind  knowledge  is  very  unlike  paradigmatic  natural  kinds.  In  case  of  

paradigmatic  natural  kinds,  like  water  or  gold,  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  

conditions  for  kind  membership  are  identified  at  the  level  of  underlying  microstructure.  

For  example,  the  underlying  microstructure  of  water  is  identified  at  the  molecular  level,  

as  being  composed  of  H2O  molecules,  the  underlying  microstructure  of  gold  is  identified  

at  the  atomic  level,  as  being  the  element  with  atomic  number  79,  and  the  underlying  

microstructure  of  tiger  is  presumably  identified  at  the  biochemical  level,  as  being  a  

species  with  a  certain  genetic  make-­‐up.15  The  various  instances  of  knowledge  do  not  

share  this  paradigmatic  feature  of  being  unified  by  their  underlying  microstructure.    

                                                                                                               15 It should be noted, however, that the natural kindhood of biological species is a highly controversial issue in contemporary philosophy of biology (cf. Bird and Tobin 2015, sec. 2.1). In particular, it is not clear whether the

  12  

One  reason  for  this  important  dissimilarity  might  be  that  cognitive  kinds,  like  

knowledge,  belief  or  intention,  are  multiply  realizable  at  the  underlying  neurological  or  

biochemical  level,  which  is  a  widely  held  view  in  the  metaphysics  of  mind  (cf.  Putnam  

1967;  Fodor  1974;  Bickle  2013).16  Accordingly,  it  makes  sense,  at  least  in  principle,  to  

ascribe  such  cognitive  states  to  a  wide  range  of  different  creatures—from  humans  to  

ravens,  chimpanzees,  octopuses,  or  even  aliens.  For  this  reason,  we  cannot  expect  that  

the  instances  of  these  cognitive  states  have  anything  interesting  in  common  in  terms  of  

their  underlying  microstructure  (see  also  Bird  and  Tobin  2015,  sec.  2.3).    

In  addition  to  that,  no  one  has  ever  made  a  plausible  suggestion  concerning  the  

“underlying  microstructure”  of  the  kind  knowledge.  Kornblith’s  own  supposedly  

empirical  identification  of  knowledge  with  reliably  produced  true  belief  (cf.  Kornblith  

2002,  62–63)  is  clearly  not  a  proposal  in  terms  of  microstructure,  nor  does  it  have  the  

flavor  of  a  new  or  surprising  scientific  discovery  that  one  finds  in  the  case  of  

paradigmatic  natural  kinds—in  fact,  the  very  same  proposal  was  already  made  many  

years  before  on  the  basis  of  armchair  conceptual  analysis  (cf.  Goldman  1986).    

So  if  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind,  then  it  is  at  best  a  rather  atypical  natural  kind,  

one  whose  nature  is  not  “hidden”  at  some  underlying  micro-­‐level  that  calls  for  sustained  

empirical  investigation.  For  this  reason,  one  should  be  wary  of  projecting  features  of  

paradigmatic  natural  kinds,  such  as  the  existence  of  lexicalized  natural  kind  concepts,  

onto  atypical  cases  like  knowledge.  Moreover,  as  I  will  argue  in  the  following  section,  

there  are  strong  direct  considerations  against  the  claim  that  KNOWLEDGE  is  a  natural  kind  

concept—considerations  that  would  trump  any  inductive  considerations  of  the  sort  just  

considered.  In  sum,  there  is  no  good  reason  for  accepting  the  inference  from  ‘knowledge  

is  a  natural  kind’  to  ‘KNOWLEDGE  is  a  natural  kind  concept’.  

What  is  more,  premise  (2)  of  the  argument  from  natural  kindhood  derives  its  

prima  facie  plausibility  from  the  more  general  claim  that  if  some  category  K  is  a  natural  

kind,  then  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  K  can  only  be  figured  out  

with  empirical  methods.  However,  if  we  accept  causal-­‐explanatory  indispensability  as  a  

good  criterion  of  natural  kindhood,  as  Kornblith  suggests,  then  this  more  general  claim  

becomes  subject  to  a  number  of  counterexamples.  For  there  are  cases  where  a  kind                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                            nature of biological species can be understood in terms of their intrinsic, microstructural properties—or whether it must instead be understood in extrinsic, relational terms (cf. Okasha 2002; LaPorte 2004). 16 For the multiple realizability of knowledge it does not matter whether knowledge is a composite state that consists of a belief that satisfies various further conditions, such as justification or truth—which is the orthodox view in epistemology (cf. Nagel 2013)—, or whether knowledge is a distinctive mental state in its own right (cf. Williamson 1995, 2000; Nagel 2013).

  13  

figures  indispensably  in  causal  explanations,  and  should  thus  be  regarded  as  a  natural  

kind  according  to  the  present  criterion,  but  where  an  a  priori  analysis  of  the  relevant  

lexicalized  concept  might  still  yield  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions.  

These  cases  undermine  the  crucial  transition  from  ‘K  is  a  natural  kind’  to  ‘illuminating  

necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  K  can  only  be  figured  out  with  empirical  

methods’.  Let  us  consider  some  of  these  cases.  

A  first  case  might  be  analytic  functionalism  in  the  philosophy  of  mind  (cf.  

Armstrong  1968;  Lewis  1972;  Shoemaker  1981;  Braddon-­‐Mitchell  and  Jackson  2007),  

which  is  a  live  theoretical  option  for  at  least  some  mental  states.  The  basic  idea  is  that  a  

mental  state  M  is  individuated  by  its  functional  role,  that  is,  by  its  typical  causes  and  

effects,  and  that  this  functional  role  is  a  priori  accessible  on  the  basis  of  reflection  on  our  

concept  of  M.  For  illustration,  let  us  assume  that  analytic  functionalism  is  true  of  pain.  

The  mental  state  of  pain  would  then  be  individuated  by  the  typical  causes  and  effects  of  

being  in  pain,  such  as  grimacing-­‐,  wincing-­‐  and  moaning-­‐behavior.  This  complex  cluster  

of  typical  causes  and  effects,  which  is  considered  to  be  a  priori  accessible  on  the  basis  of  

analyzing  our  concept  PAIN,  would  then  provide  the  materials  for  a  functional  analysis  of  

pain.  Since  the  case  for  the  causal-­‐explanatory  indispensability  of  mental  kinds  like  pain  

is  at  least  as  strong  as  the  corresponding  case  for  knowledge,  such  mental  kinds  would  

qualify  as  natural  kinds  in  light  of  the  causal-­‐explanatory  criterion.  But  in  that  case,  the  

relevant  mental  kinds  would  be  natural  kinds  that  are  amenable  to  a  priori  analysis.  

Analytic  functionalism  is  a  controversial  view,  of  course,  but  there  are  also  less  

controversial  cases.  Consider  dispositional  kinds  like  poison  or  fragility.  These  kinds  

often  play  an  indispensable  causal-­‐explanatory  role,  at  least  no  less  than  knowledge  

does,  and  should  thus  be  regarded  as  natural  kinds  according  to  the  causal-­‐explanatory  

criterion.  The  fragility  of  glass  explains,  for  example,  why  glass  cannot  be  handled  and  

transported  like  other  materials,  such  as  metal  or  wood.  It  seems  plausible,  however,  

that  we  can  figure  out  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  fragility  solely  

on  the  basis  of  our  grasp  of  the  concept  FRAGILITY,  e.g.,  as  a  rough  approximation,  that  

fragile  objects  tend  to  break  when  they  collide  with  hard  objects.17    

Mathematical  properties  play  an  indispensable  role  in  many  causal  explanations  

as  well.18  For  example,  primeness  plays  a  crucial  role  in  the  explanation  of  the  highly  

                                                                                                               17 The apparent analyzability of fragility should not be confused with the seemingly more problematic idea of providing illuminating necessary and sufficient conditions for the dispositionality of fragility (cf. Bird 2007; Ellis 2001; Mumford 2004). 18 Thanks to Brendan Balcerak Jackson for discussion.

  14  

unusual  13-­‐year  and  17-­‐year  life  cycles  of  the  cicada  genus  Magicicada.  According  to  one  

of  the  leading  hypotheses,  “the  cycle  length  is  a  prime  number  in  order  to  optimally  

escape  predators”  (Goles,  Schulz,  and  Markus  2001,  33).19  As  Goles  et  al.  elaborate,  “a  

prey  with  a  12-­‐year  cycle  will  meet—every  time  it  appears—properly  synchronized  

predators  appearing  every  1,  2,  3,  4,  6  or  12  years,  whereas  a  mutant  with  a  13-­‐year  

period  has  the  advantage  of  being  subject  to  fewer  predators.”  In  other  words,  

Magicicada  have  their  unusual  13-­‐year  and  17-­‐year  life  cycles  because  the  primeness  of  

these  life  cycles  increases  their  survival  rate  and  thus  enhances  their  evolutionary  

fitness.  Therefore,  the  primeness  of  the  Magicicada  life  cycles  is  an  indispensable  part  of  

the  causal  explanation  of  these  life  cycles  in  evolutionary  terms.20  In  light  of  the  causal-­‐

explanatory  criterion  for  natural  kindhood,  primeness  should  thus  be  considered  as  a  

natural  kind.  However,  an  a  priori  analysis  of  the  concept  PRIMENESS  clearly  yields  

illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  primeness,  i.e.,  that  something  is  

prime  if  and  only  if  it  is  only  divisible  by  one  and  itself.  The  fact  that  even  certain  

mathematical  properties  qualify  as  natural  kinds  according  to  the  causal-­‐explanatory  

criterion  of  natural  kindhood  further  undermines  the  crucial  transition  from  ‘K  is  a  

natural  kind’  to  ‘illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  K  can  only  be  

figured  out  with  empirical  methods’.  

One  might  object  that  if  it  were  indeed  established  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  

kind,  then  there  would  be  no  reason  to  be  interested  in  the  concept  of  knowledge  

anymore.  Instead,  one  should  investigate  the  natural  kind  knowledge  itself,  just  as  

Kornblith  urges  on  the  first  page  of  Knowledge  and  Its  Place  in  Nature.21  However,  if  it  

were  also  established  that  the  concept  KNOWLEDGE  is  a  descriptive  concept,  and  not  a  

nondescriptive  natural  kind  concept,  then  we  might  actually  learn  something  about  

knowledge  itself  by  means  of  conceptual  analysis,  just  as  we  learn  something  about  

primeness  itself  by  doing  conceptual  analysis.  For  in  that  case,  conceptual  analysis  would  

arguably  have  the  power  to  reveal  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  

knowledge,  and  it  seems  hard  to  deny  that  this  would  be  of  philosophical  interest.  

 

 

                                                                                                               19 According to a competing hypothesis, the prime life cycles of Magicicada are adaptations that prevent hybridization in small and isolated populations (cf. Cox and Carlton 1988; Yoshimura 1997). 20 We are only considering a special science explanation here, of course, just as Kornblith does in the case of knowledge and cognitive ethology. 21 Thanks to Kirk Michaelian for pressing this point.

  15  

5.  KNOWLEDGE  as  a  Natural  Kind  Concept?  

 

What  emerges  from  the  preceding  discussion  is  that  Kornblith’s  rejection  of  conceptual  

analysis  with  respect  to  knowledge  hinges  primarily  on  the  semantic  claim  that  

KNOWLEDGE  is  a  natural  kind  concept,  and  only  secondarily  on  the  metaphysical  claim  

that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind.  Therefore,  concluding  that  conceptual  analysis  fails  to  

yield  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  knowledge  on  the  basis  of  the  

metaphysical  claim  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind  actually  turns  things  upside  down.  

A  more  straightforward  way  to  argue  for  this  conclusion  would  be  to  employ  familiar  

considerations  from  the  discussion  about  natural  kind  terms  and  semantic  externalism  

(cf.  Kripke  1980;  Putnam  1970,  1975).  If  one  had  shown,  in  this  way,  that  KNOWLEDGE  is  a  

natural  kind  concept,  then  one  could  follow  the  standard  procedure  for  establishing  that  

knowledge  is  a  natural  kind,  namely,  by  investigating  whether  paradigmatic  instances  of  

knowledge  share  some  underlying  feature—just  as  paradigmatic  instances  of  water,  

tiger,  or  gold  (cf.  Kornblith  2002,  10–11;  Kripke  1980;  Putnam  1975).  A  systematic  

discussion  of  the  claim  that  KNOWLEDGE  is  a  natural  kind  concept  would  thus  need  to  

examine  the  standard  arguments  that  semantic  externalists  have  advanced  for  this  sort  

of  conclusion.  At  a  minimum,  this  would  involve  a  discussion  of  Putnam’s  (1975)  Twin  

Earth  thought  experiment,  Kripke’s  (1980)  epistemic  and  modal  arguments,  and  Burge’s  

(1979)  related  arguments  for  social  externalism.  In  my  view,  these  arguments  do  not  

apply  very  well  to  the  concept  of  knowledge  (pace,  e.g.,  Cappelen  and  Winblad  1999;  

Kumar  2014).  Since  a  defense  of  this  claim  would  require  another  paper  or  chapter  (cf.  

Horvath  2011),  my  aim  in  this  section  will  be  more  limited,  namely,  to  highlight  two  

epistemic  features  of  the  concept  of  knowledge  that  make  for  a  striking  disanalogy  

between  this  concept  and  paradigmatic  natural  kind  concepts.  

  It  is  characteristic  of  natural  kind  concepts,  like  WATER  or  GOLD,  that  a  priori  

conceptual  analysis  does  not  reveal  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  

membership  in  the  relevant  kinds.  On  the  one  hand,  this  comes  down  to  the  familiar  

observation  that  we  are  subject  to  all  kinds  of  ignorance  and  error  when  we  try  to  

determine  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for,  e.g.,  water  or  gold  on  the  

basis  of  a  priori  conceptual  analysis  (cf.  Kripke  1980;  Putnam  1975).  On  the  other  hand,  

there  is  the  less  familiar  observation  that  the  proposed  conceptual  analyses  of  water  or  

gold  did  not  come  anywhere  near  identifying  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  

conditions.  

  16  

First,  a  priori  analyses  of  gold  as,  e.g.,  being  a  yellow  metal  (cf.  Kant  1977,  10:  

267),  or  of  water  as,  e.g.,  being  a  clear  drinkable  liquid,  did  not  hit  upon  any  of  the  

conditions  that  figure  in  the  correct  scientific  analysis  of  these  kinds,  which  is  being  the  

element  with  atomic  number  79  in  case  of  gold,  and  being  composed  of  H2O  molecules  in  

case  of  water  (cf.  Kripke  1980;  Putnam  1975).  Therefore,  these  a  priori  analyses  are  not  

just  partly  wrong,  or  subject  to  some  degree  of  ignorance,  but  they  are  defective  in  the  

more  radical  sense  of  being  affected  by  total  error.22    

Second,  prior  to  empirical  research  in  modern  chemistry  nobody  even  had  the  

concepts  that  are  required  for  grasping  the  correct  scientific  analysis  of,  e.g.,  water  in  

terms  of  H2O,  such  as  HYDROGEN  or  OXYGEN.  And  this  is  anything  but  an  isolated  case.  Just  

consider  concepts  like  PROTON,  ELECTROMAGNETISM,  or  CHROMOSOME  that  are  required  for  

grasping  the  correct  scientific  analysis  of  various  other  natural  kinds.  However,  

proponents  of  a  priori  analyses  of  natural  kinds  did  not  only  fail  to  possess  the  concepts  

that  are  needed  for  grasping  their  correct  scientific  analysis,  but  there  was  also  no  

recognizable  way  of  acquiring  these  concepts  solely  through  further  a  priori  theorizing.  

Thus,  a  priori  analyses  of  natural  kinds  were  not  only  affected  by  total  error,  but  the  

proponents  of  these  analyses  were  also  subject  to  a  priori  conceptual  obliviousness  with  

respect  to  the  correct  scientific  analysis  of  the  natural  kinds  in  question.23  

We  can  summarize  these  two  observations  as  follows:  

 

(O1)   A  priori  analyses  of  natural  kinds  are  affected  by  total  error.  

 

(O2)     Proponents  of  a  priori  analyses  of  natural  kinds  are  subject  to  a  priori  

conceptual  obliviousness.  

 

I  will  now  argue  that  neither  (O1)  nor  (O2)  applies  to  a  priori  conceptual  analyses  of  

knowledge,  which  is  a  powerful  reason  to  conclude  that  KNOWLEDGE  is  not  a  natural  kind  

concept.  

Why  does  (O1)  not  apply  to  a  priori  conceptual  analyses  of  knowledge?  There  is  

no  indication  that  conceptual  analyses  of  knowledge  are  subject  to  anything  like  the  

                                                                                                               22 A proposed analysis Ap of K is subject to total error iff none of the analyzing features that figure in Ap also figure in the correct analysis Ac of K. 23 A thinker T is subject to a priori conceptual obliviousness with respect to the correct analysis Ac of K iff T possesses none (or almost none) of the concepts C1, …, Cn that are needed for grasping the analyzing features that figure in Ac, and there is no realistic way for T to acquire C1, …, Cn solely through further a priori theorizing.

  17  

total  error  that  affects  a  priori  analyses  of,  e.g.,  water  or  gold.  It  is  true,  of  course,  that  

many  a  priori  analyses  of  knowledge  are  subject  to  partial  ignorance  or  error.  This  can  

be  seen,  for  example,  from  the  failure  of  the  standard  analysis  of  knowledge  as  justified  

true  belief  (cf.  Gettier  1963),  and—more  generally—from  the  failure  of  most  suggested  

analyses  of  knowledge,  and  also  from  the  fact  that  epistemologists  endorse  a  variety  of  

different  analyses  of  knowledge  that  are  mutually  incompatible  (cf.  Shope  1983,  2002).  

The  majority  of  contemporary  epistemologists  agree,  however,  that  knowledge  implies  

true  belief  (cf.  Ichikawa  and  Steup  2012),  or  that  the  truth  of  a  knowledge-­‐constituting  

belief  must  not  be  an  accident  (cf.  Unger  1968;  Zagzebski  1994;  Pritchard  2005).  So  

these  largely  uncontroversial  necessary  features  of  knowledge  do  not  seem  to  be  

affected  by  any  ignorance  or  error,  as  far  as  we  can  tell  from  our  present  perspective  

(and  this  is  the  only  perspective  that  we  can  reasonably  take  on  this  issue).  Even  

Kornblith’s  own  allegedly  scientific  analysis  of  knowledge  on  the  basis  of  considerations  

from  cognitive  ethology  includes  these  widely  accepted  necessary  features,  since  he  

identifies  knowledge  with  reliably  produced  true  belief  (cf.  Kornblith  2002,  58).  In  fact,  

this  is  the  same  result  that  Goldman,  according  to  his  methodological  self-­‐understanding  

(cf.  Goldman  2007),  had  obtained  many  years  before  on  the  basis  of  a  priori  conceptual  

analysis  (cf.  Goldman  1986).  These  observations  about  contemporary  epistemology—

including  naturalized  epistemology—suggest  that  (O1)  does  not  apply  to  a  priori  

conceptual  analyses  of  knowledge,  for  there  is  presently  no  indication  that  they  are  

affected  by  total  error.  

Why  does  (O2)  not  apply  to  a  priori  analyses  of  knowledge?  Since  some  of  the  

necessary  features  of  knowledge  that  are  widely  accepted  on  the  basis  of  conceptual  

analysis  are  apparently  not  subject  to  ignorance  or  error,  it  follows  that  philosophers  

possess  at  least  some  of  the  concepts  that  are  required  for  grasping  the  correct  analysis  

of  knowledge,  such  as  TRUTH  or  BELIEF.  Moreover,  since  TRUTH  and  BELIEF  are  

pretheoretical  concepts,  it  follows  that  even  lay  people  possess  some  of  the  concepts  

that  are  required  for  grasping  some  of  the  necessary  features  of  knowledge.  And  even  if  

EPISTEMIC  JUSTIFICATION  should  be  a  pretheoretical  concept  as  well,  which  seems  doubtful  

(cf.  Senor  2013),  there  is  still  reason  to  think  that  philosophers  did  not  always  possess  

all  of  the  concepts  that  are  required  for  grasping  the  analyzing  features  of  knowledge.  

For  as  a  result  of  Gettier’s  (1963)  refutation  of  the  standard  analysis  of  knowledge  as  

justified  true  belief,  the  justification  condition  will  either  have  to  be  supplemented  or  

replaced  by  some  additional  or  alternative  condition  X.  Some  of  the  candidate  features  

  18  

for  X  that  epistemologists  have  suggested  are:  indefeasibility  (cf.  Lehrer  and  Paxson  

1969),  reliability  (cf.  Goldman  1979),  sensitivity  (cf.  Nozick  1981),  safety  (cf.  Sosa  1999),  

or  aptness  (cf.  Sosa  2007).  It  seems  clear  that  the  relevant  concepts  of  indefeasibility,  

reliability,  sensitivity,  etc.  are  not  pretheoretical  concepts,  and  that  even  most  

epistemologists  only  acquired  them  post-­‐Gettier.  So  before  Gettier,  even  most  

philosophers  failed  to  possess  some  of  the  concepts  that  are  needed  for  grasping  some  

of  the  analyzing  features  of  knowledge.  Yet  isn’t  this  simply  a  form  of  a  priori  conceptual  

obliviousness  with  respect  to  the  analyzing  features  of  knowledge,  and  thus  evidence  

that  KNOWLEDGE  might  be  a  natural  kind  concept  after  all?    

It  seems  plausible  that,  pre-­‐Gettier,  even  most  epistemologists  were  subject  to  a  

limited,  partial  from  of  conceptual  obliviousness  vis-­‐à-­‐vis  the  correct  analysis  of  

knowledge  (whatever  exactly  it  may  be).  But  given  that  epistemologists  did  already  

possess  crucial  concepts  like  TRUTH  or  BELIEF,  this  was  very  different  from  the  complete  

conceptual  obliviousness  that  is  characteristic  of  proponents  of  a  priori  analyses  of  

natural  kinds.  More  importantly,  however,  there  is  no  indication  that  philosophers  were  

ever  subject  to  a  priori  conceptual  obliviousness  concerning  the  analyzing  features  of  

knowledge.  Unlike  concepts  like  HYDROGEN  or  ATOMIC  NUMBER  that  were  only  shaped  and  

acquired  through  a  sustained  process  of  empirical  theorizing,  the  acquisition  of  technical  

concepts  in  the  theory  of  knowledge,  like  INDEEFEASIBILITY,  SENSITIVITY,  or  APTNESS,  does  

not  seem  to  depend  on  empirical  information  or  theorizing  in  any  substantial  sense.  

Rather,  these  concepts  were  shaped  and  acquired  within  the  very  process  of  a  priori  

reflection  on  the  analyzing  features  of  knowledge  that  is  so  characteristic  of  the  method  

of  conceptual  analysis.  Therefore,  proponents  of  conceptual  analyses  of  knowledge  were  

never  subject  to  anything  like  the  a  priori  conceptual  obliviousness  that  we  find  in  

proponents  of  a  priori  analyses  of  natural  kinds.  At  most,  epistemologists  were  (and  

probably  still  are)  subject  to  a  limited  form  of  conceptual  obliviousness  that  can  be  

cured  by  further  a  priori  theorizing.  These  considerations  suggest  that  (O2)  does  not  

apply  to  proponents  of  a  priori  conceptual  analyses  of  knowledge,  which  is  another  

disanalogy  between  the  concept  KNOWLEDGE  and  paradigmatic  natural  kind  concepts.  

To  conclude,  the  concept  of  knowledge  lacks  two  epistemic  features  that  are  

characteristic  of  paradigmatic  natural  kind  concepts.  The  first  of  these  features  is  that  a  

priori  analyses  of  paradigmatic  natural  kinds  are  affected  by  total  error.  The  second  

feature  is  that  proponents  of  a  priori  analyses  of  natural  kinds  are  subject  to  a  priori  

conceptual  obliviousness.  These  two  features  constitute  a  striking  disanalogy  between  

  19  

KNOWLEDGE  and  paradigmatic  natural  kind  concepts,  like  WATER  or  GOLD,  that  makes  it  

quite  unlikely  that  they  all  belong  to  the  same  semantic  category.  

 

 

6.  Conclusion  

 

The  metaepistemological  temptation  that  I  described  at  the  beginning  of  this  paper  

should  be  resisted:  there  is  no  convincing  argument  against  conceptual  analysis  in  the  

theory  of  knowledge  from  the  claim  that  knowledge  is  a  natural  kind.  

First,  the  argument  from  the  indispensable  causal-­‐explanatory  role  of  knowledge  

to  the  natural  kindhood  of  knowledge  is  problematic  in  several  ways.  The  argument  

either  proves  too  much  by  ruling  out  illuminating  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions  for  

knowledge  on  metaphysical  grounds  alone  (insofar  as  it  relies  on  the  homeostatic  

cluster  account  of  natural  kinds),  or  the  argument  loses  the  metaphysical  connection  

between  causal-­‐explanatory  indispensability  and  natural  kindhood  (when  it  resorts  to  a  

non-­‐causal  theory  of  natural  kinds).  Absent  such  a  connection,  the  inference  from  

‘having  a  robust  causal-­‐explanatory  profile’  to  ‘being  a  natural  kind’  remains  

unsupported.  

But  what  if  knowledge  were  indeed  a  natural  kind?  Wouldn’t  this  tell  strongly  

against  conceptual  analysis  in  the  theory  of  knowledge?  To  support  this  worry,  one  

might  appeal  to  the  following  seemingly  plausible  principle:  if  K  is  a  natural  kind,  then  

the  concept  of  K  is  a  natural  kind  concept.  And  as  we  learnt  from  Putnam  and  Kripke,  

natural  kind  concepts  like  WATER  or  GOLD  are  not  amenable  to  a  priori  conceptual  

analysis.  This  principle  fails,  however,  because  one  can  even  refer  to  paradigmatic  

natural  kinds  with  purely  descriptive  concepts,  such  as  THE  ELEMENT  WITH  ATOMIC  NUMBER  

79  in  the  case  of  gold.  It  is  true  that  lexicalized  concepts  of  paradigmatic  natural  kinds  

are  typically  natural  kind  concepts,  but  one  cannot  simply  draw  any  inductive  

conclusions  about  the  concept  of  knowledge  from  that  fact,  because  even  if  knowledge  is  

indeed  a  natural  kind,  it  is  a  rather  atypical  natural  kind.  Moreover,  the  criterion  of  

causal-­‐explanatory  indispensability  allows  for  various  counterexamples  to  the  transition  

from  ‘K  is  a  natural  kind’  to  ‘K  is  not  amenable  to  conceptual  analysis’,  e.g.,  in  the  case  of  

dispositional  or  mathematical  categories.  In  order  to  assess  the  viability  of  conceptual  

analysis  in  the  theory  of  knowledge,  one  should  therefore  focus  directly  on  the  semantic  

question  whether  KNOWLEDGE  is  a  natural  kind  concept  or  not.  

  20  

However,  there  are  two  striking  epistemic  disanalogies  between  the  concept  

KNOWLEDGE  and  paradigmatic  natural  kind  concepts  that  make  it  quite  unlikely  that  

KNOWLEDGE  belongs  to  the  same  semantic  category.  First,  in  contrast  to  proposed  a  priori  

analyses  of  natural  kinds,  a  priori  conceptual  analyses  of  knowledge  are  not  affected  by  

total  error.  And  second,  proponents  of  conceptual  analyses  of  knowledge  are  not  subject  

to  a  priori  conceptual  obliviousness  with  respect  to  the  analyzing  features  of  knowledge.  

We  should  thus  resist  the  temptation  to  draw  negative  conclusions  about  

conceptual  analysis  from  the  natural  kindhood  of  knowledge,  for  this  kind  of  inference  is  

fraught  with  difficulties  and  problems.  This  point  presumably  applies  to  other  important  

philosophical  categories  as  well,  such  as  free  will,  justice,  action  or  truth.  At  any  rate,  one  

should  expect  that  at  least  some  of  the  considerations  that  are  relevant  to  the  case  of  

knowledge  also  apply  to  those  other  cases.  With  respect  to  the  case  of  knowledge,  I  

conclude  that  conceptual  analysis  remains  unshaken  by  Kornblith’s  argument  from  the  

natural  kindhood  of  knowledge.  Conceptual  analysis  continues  to  be  a  viable  method  in  

the  theory  of  knowledge,  irrespective  of  the  largely  orthogonal  question  of  whether  

knowledge  is  a  natural  kind  or  not.  

 Acknowledgments:     I  would  like  to  thank  Brendan  Balcerak  Jackson,  Thomas  Grundmann,  Frank  

Hofmann,  Jonathan  Jenkins  Ichikawa,  Stan  Husi,  Jens  Kipper,  Hilary  Kornblith,  Kirk  Michaelian,  Wolfgang  

Schwarz,  Anand  Vaidya,  and  various  anonymous  reviewers  for  numerous  helpful  comments  on  this  paper  

and  its  non-­‐identical  predecessors.  The  paper  originated  from  a  critical  comment  on  Hilary  Kornblith’s  

work  at  the  2nd  Cologne  Summer  School  in  Philosophy  in  August  2007  at  the  University  of  Cologne.  Special  

thanks  to  Hilary  for  extensive  discussion  and  plenty  of  encouragement.  I  also  want  to  thank  the  

participants  of  Hilary’s  doctoral  colloquium  at  the  University  of  Massachusetts  Amherst  in  March  2008—

Kristoffer  Ahlstrom-­‐Vij,  Jeremy  Cushing,  Jeff  Dunn,  Meghan  Masto,  Alex  Sarch,  Kirk  Michaelian,  Indrani  

Bhattacharjee,  and  Hilary  Kornblith—for  their  generous  engagement  with  my  paper  and  very  valuable  

comments.  Thanks  also  to  Brendan  Balcerak  Jackson,  Magdalena  Balcerak  Jackson,  Alma  Barner  and  

Wolfgang  Schwarz  for  their  very  helpful  comments  in  a  reading  group  session  of  the  Emmy  Noether  

Independent  Junior  Research  Group  Understanding  and  the  A  Priori  in  June  2009,  which  was  kindly  hosted  

by  the  University  of  Cologne  and  generously  supported  by  the  Deutsche  Forschungsgemeinschaft  DFG  

(German  Research  Foundation).  Additional  thanks  to  the  DFG  for  supporting  my  research  on  this  paper  as  

part  of  the  project  Eine  Verteidigung  der  Begriffsanalyse  gegen  die  Herausforderungen  des  Naturalismus  (A  

Defense  of  Conceptual  Analysis  against  the  Challenges  from  Naturalism),  which  was  kindly  hosted  by  the  

University  of  Cologne  from  2007  to  2010  (under  the  auspices  of  Thomas  Grundmann).  

 

 

 

  21  

References:  

 

Armstrong,  David.  1968.  A  Materialist  Theory  of  the  Mind.  London:  Routledge  &  K.  Paul.  

Besson,  Corine.  2010.  “Rigidity,  Natural  Kind  Terms  and  Metasemantics.”  In  The  

Semantics  and  Metaphysics  of  Natural  Kind  Terms,  eds.  Helen  Beebee  and  Nigel  

Sabbarton-­‐Leary.  New  York:  Routledge.  

Bickle,  John.  2013.  “Multiple  Realizability.”  In  The  Stanford  Encyclopedia  of  Philosophy,  

ed.  Edward  N.  Zalta.  

http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/multiple-­‐realizability/  

(March  5,  2015).  

Bird,  Alexander.  2007.  Nature’s  Metaphysics:  Laws  and  Properties.  Oxford:  Clarendon  

Press.    

Bird,  Alexander,  and  Emma  Tobin.  2015.  “Natural  Kinds.”  In  The  Stanford  Encyclopedia  of  

Philosophy,  ed.  Edward  N.  Zalta.  

http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/natural-­‐kinds/  (February  

27,  2015).  

Boyd,  Richard.  1988.  “How  to  Be  a  Moral  Realist.”  In  Essays  on  Moral  Realism,  ed.  

Geoffrey  Sayre  McCord.  Ithaca,  N.Y.:  Cornell  University  Press.  

———.  1991.  “Realism,  Anti-­‐Foundationalism  and  the  Enthusiasm  for  Natural  Kinds.”  

Philosophical  Studies  61(1):  127–48.  

Braddon-­‐Mitchell,  David,  and  Frank  Jackson.  2007.  The  Philosophy  of  Mind  and  Cognition:  

An  Introduction.  Oxford:  Blackwell.  

Burge,  Tyler.  1979.  “Individualism  and  the  Mental.”  Midwest  Studies  in  Philosophy  4:  73–

121.  

Cappelen,  Herman,  and  Douglas  Winblad.  1999.  “Intuitions.”  Facta  Philosophica  1:  197–

216.  

Cox,  Randel  Tom,  and  C.  E.  Carlton.  1988.  “Paleoclimatic  Influences  in  the  Evolution  of  

Periodical  Cicadas  (Insecta:  Homoptera:  Cicadidae:  Magicicada  Spp.).”  American  

Midland  Naturalist  120(1):  183–93.  

Devitt,  Michael,  and  Kim  Sterelny.  1999.  Language  and  Reality:  An  Introduction  to  the  

Philosophy  of  Language.  Cambridge,  Mass.:  MIT  Press.  

Ellis,  Brian.  2001.  Scientific  Essentialism.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.  

Fine,  Kit.  1995.  “Senses  of  Essence.”  In  Modality,  Morality  and  Belief:  Essays  in  Honour  of  

Ruth  Barcan  Marcus,  eds.  Ruth  Barcan  Marcus,  Walter  Sinnott-­‐Armstrong,  Diana  

  22  

Raffman,  and  Nicholas  Asher.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  53–73.  

Fodor,  Jerry  1974.  “Special  Sciences  (Or:  The  Disunity  of  Science  as  a  Working  

Hypothesis).”  Synthese  28(2):  97–115.  

Gettier,  Edmund.  1963.  “Is  Justified  True  Belief  Knowledge?”  Analysis  23(6):  121–23.  

Goldman,  Alvin.  1979.  “What  Is  Justified  Belief?”  In  Justification  and  Knowledge,  ed.  

George  Pappas.  Dordrecht:  D.  Reidel,  1–23.  

———.  1986.  Epistemology  and  Cognition.  Cambridge,  Mass.:  Harvard  University  Press.  

———.  2007.  “Philosophical  Intuitions:  Their  Target,  Their  Source,  and  Their  Epistemic  

Status.”  Grazer  Philosophische  Studien  74:  1–26.  

Goles,  Eric,  Oliver  Schulz,  and  Mario  Markus.  2001.  “Prime  Number  Selection  of  Cycles  in  

a  Predator-­‐Prey  Model.”  Complexity  6(4):  33–38.  

Heller,  Mark.  1996.  “The  Mad  Scientist  Meets  the  Robot  Cats:  Compatibilism,  Kinds,  and  

Counterexamples.”  Philosophy  and  Phenomenological  Research  56(2):  333–37.  

Horvath,  Joachim.  2011.  In  Defense  of  Conceptual  Analysis.  Dissertation.  University  of  

Cologne.  

———.  ms.  “Philosophical  Analysis:  The  Concept  Grounding  View.”  

Ichikawa,  Jonathan  Jenkins,  and  Matthias  Steup.  2012.  “The  Analysis  of  Knowledge.”  In  

The  Stanford  Encyclopedia  of  Philosophy,  ed.  Edward  N.  Zalta.  

http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/knowledge-­‐analysis/  

(April  9,  2013).  

Kant,  Immanuel.  1977.  Prolegomena  to  Any  Future  Metaphysics.  ed.  James  W  Ellington.  

Indianapolis:  Hackett  Publishing.  

Kornblith,  Hilary.  1993.  Inductive  Inference  and  Its  Natural  Ground:  An  Essay  in  

Naturalistic  Epistemology.  Cambridge,  Mass.:  MIT  Press.  

———.  1999.  “Knowledge  in  Humans  and  Other  Animals.”  Philosophical  Perspectives  13:  

327–46.  

———.  2002.  Knowledge  and  Its  Place  in  Nature.  Oxford:  Clarendon  Press.  

———.  2007.  “Naturalism  and  Intuitions.”  Grazer  Philosophische  Studien  74:  27–49.  

———.  2013.  “Is  There  Room  for  Armchair  Theorizing  in  Epistemology?”  In  

Philosophical  Methodology:  The  Armchair  or  the  Laboratory?,  ed.  Matthew  Haug.  

London:  Routledge,  195–216.  

Kripke,  Saul.  1980.  Naming  and  Necessity.  Cambridge,  Mass.:  Harvard  University  Press.  

Kumar,  Victor.  2014.  “‘Knowledge’  as  a  Natural  Kind  Term.”  Synthese  191(3):  439–57.  

LaPorte,  Joseph.  2004.  Natural  Kinds  and  Conceptual  Change.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  

  23  

University  Press.  

Lehrer,  Keith,  and  Thomas  Paxson.  1969.  “Knowledge:  Undefeated  Justified  True  Belief.”  

Journal  of  Philosophy  66(8):  225–37.  

Lewis,  David.  1972.  “Psychophysical  and  Theoretical  Identifications.”  Australasian  

Journal  of  Philosophy  50(3):  249–58.  

———.  1986.  On  the  Plurality  of  Worlds.  Oxford:  Blackwell.  

Ludwig,  Kirk.  2013.  “Methods  in  Analytic  Epistemology.”  In  Philosophical  Methodology:  

The  Armchair  or  the  Laboratory?,  ed.  Matthew  Haug.  London:  Routledge,  217–39.  

Malmgren,  Anna-­‐Sara.  2011.  “Rationalism  and  the  Content  of  Intuitive  Judgements.”  

Mind  120(478):  263–327.  

Miščević,  Nenad.  2000.  “Deep  and  Superficial  A  Priori.”  Acta  Analytica:  Philosophy  and  

Psychology  15:  89–112.  

———.  2005.  “Empirical  Concepts  and  A  Priori  Truth.”  Croatian  Journal  of  Philosophy  5:  

289–315.  

Mumford,  Stephen.  2004.  Laws  in  Nature.  London:  Routledge.  

Nagel,  Jennifer.  2013.  “Knowledge  as  a  Mental  State.”  In  Oxford  Studies  in  Epistemology  

Volume  4,  eds.  Tamar  Szabó  Gendler  and  John  Hawthorne.  Oxford:  Oxford  

University  Press,  272–308.  

Nozick,  Robert.  1981.  Philosophical  Explanations.  Cambridge,  Mass.:  Harvard  University  

Press.  

Okasha,  Samir.  2002.  “Darwinian  Metaphysics:  Species  And  The  Question  Of  

Essentialism.”  Synthese  131(2):  191–213.  

Pernu,  Tuomas  K.  2009.  “Is  Knowledge  a  Natural  Kind?”  Philosophical  Studies  142(3):  

371–86.  

Pritchard,  Duncan.  2005.  Epistemic  Luck.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Putnam,  Hilary.  1967.  “Psychological  Predicates.”  In  Art,  Mind,  and  Religion,  eds.  W.  H.  

Capitan  and  D.  D.  Merrill.  Pittsburgh:  University  of  Pittsburgh  Press,  37–48.  

———.  1970.  “Is  Semantics  Possible?”  In  Mind,  Language  and  Reality :  Philosophical  

Papers  Vol.  2,  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  139–52.  

———.  1975.  “The  Meaning  of  ‘Meaning.’”  In  Mind,  Language  and  Reality :  Philosophical  

Papers  Vol.  2,  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  215–71.  

Schwartz,  Stephen.  1980.  “Formal  Semantics  and  Natural  Kind  Terms.”  Philosophical  

Studies  38(2):  189–98.  

———.  2002.  “Kinds,  General  Terms,  and  Rigidity:  A  Reply  to  Laporte.”  Philosophical  

  24  

Studies  109(3):  265–77.  

Schwitzgebel,  Eric.  2008.  “Against  Metaphysics,  Especially  the  Metaphysics  of  

Consciousness.”  The  Splintered  Mind.  

http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com/2008/07/against-­‐metaphysics-­‐

especially.html.  

Searle,  John  R.  1969.  Speech  Acts:  An  Essay  in  the  Philosophy  of  Language.  London:  

Cambridge  University  Press.  

Senor,  Thomas  D.  2013.  “Justified  Belief  and  Demon  Worlds.”  Res  Philosophica  90(2):  

203–14.  

Shoemaker,  Sydney.  1981.  “Some  Varieties  of  Functionalism.”  Philosophical  Topics  12(1):  

93–119.  

Shope,  Robert.  1983.  The  Analysis  of  Knowing:  A  Decade  of  Research.  Princeton  

University  Press.  

———.  2002.  “Conditions  and  Analyses  of  Knowledge.”  In  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  

Epistemology,  ed.  Paul  Moser.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  25–71.  

Soames,  Scott.  2002.  Beyond  Rigidity:  The  Unfinished  Semantic  Agenda  of  Naming  and  

Necessity.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

———.  2007.  “What  Are  Natural  Kinds?”  Philosophical  Topics  35(1):  329–42.  

Sosa,  Ernest.  1999.  “How  to  Defeat  Opposition  to  Moore.”  Noûs  33:  141–53.  

———.  2007.  A  Virtue  Epistemology:  Apt  Belief  and  Reflective  Knowledge.  Oxford:  Oxford  

University  Press.  

Steup,  Matthias.  1996.  An  Introduction  to  Contemporary  Epistemology.  Upper  Saddle  

River,  N.J.:  Prentice  Hall.  

Unger,  Peter.  1968.  “An  Analysis  of  Factual  Knowledge.”  The  Journal  of  Philosophy  65(6):  

157–70.  

Williamson,  Timothy.  1995.  “Is  Knowing  a  State  of  Mind?”  Mind  104(415):  533–65.  

———.  2000.  Knowledge  and  Its  Limits.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

———.  2007.  The  Philosophy  of  Philosophy.  Malden,  Mass.:  Blackwell.  

Yoshimura,  Jin.  1997.  “The  Evolutionary  Origins  of  Periodical  Cicadas  During  Ice  Ages.”  

The  American  Naturalist  149(1):  112–24.  

Zagzebski,  Linda.  1994.  “The  Inescapability  of  Gettier  Problems.”  Philosophical  Quarterly  

44(174):  65–73.