Transcript

The Tuskegee Syphilis Study: What It Means To Conduct Unethical Research On Human

Beings

Dr. Joseph Costa, D.H.Sc., PA-C

Health Policy and Management

MPH 525

Diana Pinney

April 2013

Table of Contents

Chapter Page

1. Introduction: The Tuskegee Syphilis Study……………...………………...…...………3

2. How to Study Humans and Current Policies..……...…………………………….…….5

The Nuremburg Code……………………………….………………………….....5

The Belmont Report…………………...………………………………………......6

Respect for Persons and Individual Autonomy………….……………………......6

Beneficence……………………………….…………………………………........7

Justice……….…………………………………………………………….….…...8

Informed Consent……………………………..…………………………..….......9

3. The Tuskegee Study from and Ethical Perspective…………….……………….…….10

Why did the Medical Profession Pursue this Study?…….………………………10

What Went Wrong?...............................................................................................11

Scenarios in Which Informed Consent is Not Needed..........................................13

Waiving Consent for Some Areas of Clinical Investigation……..........................14

4. Summary.………………………………………………………………………..…….17

Recommendations……………………………………………..…………………17

References………………………………………………………………………………..20

2

Chapter 1

Introduction: The Tuskegee Syphilis Study

The Tuskegee Syphilis Study is named after the town and institution in Macon

County, Alabama in which this United States Public Health Service (USPHS) research

took place (Tuskegee University, 2013). The actual name given the study when it began

in 1932 was the “Tuskegee Study of Untreated Syphilis in the Negro Male” (Centers for

Disease Control [CDC], 2011). Six hundred African American men enrolled in the study.

Of the 600, 399 had syphilis, and 201 controls did not (CDC, 2011).

Syphilis, the disease this study was designed to observe, is a sexually transmitted

infection that is passed from contact with sores the bacterial infection causes (US

Department of Health and Human Services [HHS] 2013). Syphilis is easily cured with a

dose of penicillin, an antibiotic that was not in use when this study started (Tuskegee

University, 2013).

Alexander Fleming discovered the antibacterial agents of the penicillin mold in

1928 (PBS, 1998). It would not be until 1938 that Fleming would publish his findings

(PBS, 1998). Having seen the effects of bacterial infections during his experience in

World War I, it was Fleming’s goal to allay this danger for the young men on the fronts

of World War II (PBS, 1998). United States chemical manufacturers started the mass

production and distribution of penicillin in 1943 (PBS, 1998). Penicillin was discovered

to be a curative agent for the disease in 1948 (Tuskegee University, 2013).

Perhaps the most egregious aspect of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study is the fact that

it continued until November of 1972. The participants were not informed of the benefits

of penicillin, nor were they offered the opportunity to leave the study (Tuskegee

3

University, 2013). Jean Heller, a reporter for the Associated Press released a story about a

“study” on African American males in Alabama that was not treating their syphilis, but

instead letting them languish with the symptoms and continue to sexually transmit it

(Tuskegee University, 2013). The backlash was great. Six months later and after a federal

interagency review, the Tuskegee Syphilis Study was declared “ethically unjustified” and

was shut down by Assistant Secretary for Health and Scientific Affairs (Tuskegee

University, 2013).

This perpetration of human rights violations by academic researchers continued

without internal censure until it was forcibly ended by the federal government and only

after being revealed by the press.

4

Chapter 2

How To Study Humans and Current Policies

There are very specific designs for the use of humans as research participants.

These designs are intended to protect individual rights, and preserve the ethics of science

(National Institutes of Health [NIH], 2011). The overarching idea that encompasses the

policies surrounding the use of people as research participants is that humans shall never

be used “as means to an end” (NIH, 2011).

This form of study and its governing policies are necessary because human

subjects are essential for the progress of science, medicine, and our health. It is for this

reason that the relationship between researchers and their participants “should be based

on honesty, trust, and respect” (NIH, 2011, p. 3). It is also for this reason that conventions

have been put in place governing studies using human subjects.

Two of the most significant and predominant collections of ethics pertaining to

biomedical research are the Nuremberg Code and the Belmont Report.

The Nuremberg Code

The unfortunate need for the creation of the Nuremberg Code was instigated by

countless human rights violations perpetrated upon individuals residing in Nazi

concentration camps during World War II (NIH, 2011). The War Crimes Tribunal at

Nuremberg of December 1946 found that, “‘medical experiments’ were performed on

thousands of concentration camp prisoners and included deadly studies and tortures such

as injecting people with gasoline and live viruses, immersing people in ice water, and

forcing people to ingest poisons” (NIH, 2011, p. 4).

5

The judges of this trial wrote the verdict in August of 1947. In a section of their

decision called “permissible medical experiments” they created 10 “directives for human

experimentation.” These directives are collectively called the Nuremberg Code (NIH,

2011). The Nuremberg Code represents “the basic principles that must be observed in

order to satisfy moral, ethical, and legal concepts in the conduct of human subject

research” (NIH, 2011, p. 5). It is still used today as a model for numerous institutions,

projects, and as an internationally shared foundation. The Nuremberg Code also

influenced the United States’ first federal policy regarding testing human subjects created

at the Clinical Center of the National Institutes of Health (NIH, 2011).

The Belmont Report

The Belmont Report is the HHS’s form of ethics relating to human subjects

compiled in the tenuous time following the end of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study (NIH,

2011). In 1974, the National Research Act established the National Commission for the

Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research (HHS, 2013). This

commission was given the task of highlighting ethical ideals that would form a standard

of behavior surrounding human research subjects (HHS, 2013). This compilation of

bioethics would come to be known as the Belmont Report and officially included in

HHS’s policy.

The Belmont report made official and commonplace the bioethical ideas of respect for

persons, beneficence, and justice. The final report also references the importance of

informed consent and assessment of risks and benefits (HHS, 2013).

Respect For Persons and Individual Autonomy

According to the Belmont Report, there are two aspects of ethics involved when

6

considering respect of persons. These are “first, that individuals should be treated as

autonomous agents, and second, that persons with diminished autonomy are entitled to

protection” (HHS, 2013).

The concept of individual autonomy was born of Enlightenment humanism and

has highly influenced contemporary liberal political philosophy (Stanford Encyclopedia

of Philosophy, 2009). In our modern, western tradition, individual autonomy is the basis

of ethical considerations. “To be autonomous is to be one's own person, to be directed by

considerations, desires, conditions, and characteristics that are not simply imposed

externally upon one, but are part of what can somehow be considered one's authentic

self” (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2009).

Not all people are able to grasp the concept of individual autonomy. Some

individuals may experience “diminished autonomy” depending on one’s cognitive,

emotional, physical, or mental state (HHS, 2013). It is for this reason that, out of respect

for persons, individuals with diminished autonomy are “in need of extensive protection”

which may mean discounting them from research involving human subjects (HHS, 2013).

A necessary component of ethical human subject research is that participation is informed

and voluntary, because of the requirement for respect and autonomy. Researchers must

confirm the subjects understand the risks and benefits of the study while not influencing

their decision to participate in any way (NIH, 2011).

Essentially, the basis of the Belmont Report’s ethical ideal regarding respect for

persons is not based simply on the presence of individual autonomy, but also on the

absence of oppression.

Beneficence

7

The root word of beneficence, benefit, assists in its definition because beneficent

behavior is displayed with the intent to benefit others (Stanford Encyclopedia of

Philosophy, 2008). This definition links beneficent behavior to understanding the

potential risks and benefits to a set of planned actions (NIH, 2011). Principles of

beneficence codified by many philosophers can potentially provide a basis for decisions

made on what is right, or what is wrong (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2008).

The Belmont Report conveys two ways in which beneficence shall be utilized in

scientific studies. The first is “do not harm,” and the second, “maximize possible benefits

and minimize possible harms” (NIH, 2011, p. 19).

Beneficence comes into play during the construction of a therapeutic study as

members of the scientific community consider what they hope to learn, how they hope to

learn it, and how it will potentially benefit their subjects’ health and the health of the

greater population. This must all be considered with the great responsibility of upholding

individual rights and avoiding unnecessary risks.

Justice

The concept of justice in its application to biomedical research addresses the

requirement for participants to “be treated fairly and equitably in terms of bearing the

burdens and receiving the benefits of research” (NIH, 2011, p. 19).

It is important for investigators to take a step back and attempt to, as objectively

as they can, consider why a certain group is being sought out for participation in a study.

The principle of justice is employed when considering if a cohort is aptly suited for the

matter of the research or if they are being considered because of proximity, or are poor,

or a member of a vulnerable population (NIH, 2011). Research subjects’ participation

8

cannot be coerced or taken advantage of and the potential benefits of the research must be

accordingly shared among them.

Informed Consent

Informed consent is not a principle of the Belmont Code, but is an exceedingly

important facet of respect for persons, beneficence and justice. Correct procedure of

gaining informed consent from a research participant involves information,

comprehension, and voluntariness (HHS, 2013).

Information must be provided to the subjects regarding how the study will be

undertaken and for what purpose. The subject is provided with the knowledge they may

ask any questions or decide to abstain at anytime from the study (HHS, 2013).

The subject (or their third party representative) must also comprehend all of these

stipulations in order to act for their own concern (HHS, 2013).

Informed consent also does not end once a participant agrees to be part of a study.

Informed consent is a progression that investigators and participants experience together

throughout the course of the study (NIH, 2011).

Informed consent must be documented with a signed form. There are also extra

considerations taken into account when considering pregnant women, children, those

with diminished autonomy, and incarcerated individuals (NIH, 2011).

9

Chapter 3

The Tuskegee Syphilis Study From an Ethical Perspective

Why did the Medical Profession Pursue This Study?

During the era that saw the inception of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study, Darwin’s

theories of evolution had been transcribed to the human race and termed “Social

Darwinism” (Brandt, 2013). African Americans were seen to be increasingly subject to

crime, disease, poverty, and therefore to be devolving into primitive ways that would

eventually lead to their extinction (Brandt, 2013). There are writings by doctors of this

time that predicted tuberculosis and syphilis “will be the end of the negro problem”

Brandt, 2013, p. 3). These attitudes within the medical and anthropological fields were

incredibly pervasive and “scientifically” linked to the physicality of African Americans,

their religious beliefs (i.e. lack of morality), and their social organization (Brandt, 2013).

These attitudes combined with the high prevalence of syphilis among the African

American population of Macon County, Alabama created an ideal cohort for a study on

the possibility of “mass treatment” (Brandt, 2013). It was not necessarily the effects of

treatment these scientists desired to understand, though. The late stages of syphilis are

often symptomatically quiet. This fact, combined with the opinion of the time that

African Americans would not actually respond to treatment made this cohort perfect for

observing the long term effects of untreated syphilis (Brandt, 2013).

The Tuskegee Syphilis Study was also shaped by the “premise that blacks,

promiscuous and lustful, would not seek or continue treatment” and that the high

prevalence of syphilis in African American males was proof of general immorality and

10

expected apathy in regards to treatment (Brandt, 2013, p. 6). It was also thought that the

progression of the disease was different between races and once determined latent,

syphilis required less, if any, vigorous treatment (Brandt, 2013). One of the hopes of this

study’s findings was that syphilis, once “in remission” did not require any treatment at all

and illegitimate, hopeless members of a lesser race were the perfect subjects to watch

suffer.

The United States Public Health Service (USPHS) pursued this study design

because there was no medical consensus on the need for the treatment of latent syphilis,

for which no proven therapy had been found. Syphilis was endemic in many populations

and easily transmitted, therefore a major public health issue of the day. The population of

Macon County, Alabama intersected perfectly a potential study’s needs because of the

convenient social theories relating to its inherent worth coupled with its high prevalence

of syphilis.

It should be noted that while syphilis treatments using arsenic and mercury had

their own toxic dangers and were largely ineffective, previous studies (namely, the Oslo

Study) had already proven that up to 30% of untreated syphilis cases suffer dire

consequences (Brandt, 2013). At the same time the Tuskegee study was started, the

USPHS supported and published research by “syphilis experts that strongly argued for

treating latent syphilis” (Brandt, 2013, p. 5).

What Went Wrong?

The driving hypothesis of the study (that African Americans were apathetic to

treatment) was immediately contradicted by the large amounts of people who showed up

for treatment, worrying the investigators of the financial solvency of their undertaking

11

and forcing them to pretend as if this study was meant to be therapeutic (Brandt, 2013).

Potential enrollees were either sent away without treatment or provided almost

ineffectual creams to keep their interest because free care was so highly desired (Brandt,

2013). This was never really a scientific foray into the treatment of syphilis, but more of a

“study in nature” (Brandt 2013, p. 4).

The design of this study is the first thing that went wrong. Collecting ill

participants under the guise of receiving care they were never going to obtain is just one

of countless ethical missteps that defines the Tuskegee Syphilis Study. The idea that

people are never to be used as means to an end was shattered by the form and goals of

The Tuskegee Syphilis Study.

The enrollees were also lied to about what they were being “treated” for. The

opinion may have existed among the investigators that participants would not understand

anyway, but investigators used local colloquialisms such as ‘bad blood’ to define their

malady (CDC, 2011). The participants were not even told what was actually being

studied. Even though this study intended to document the effects of syphilis on an

untreated individual, it is unclear exactly how many perished from the horrific symptoms

of late-stage syphilis. The number is estimated to be between 28 and 100 men, although

the effect of the continued transmission of syphilis to sexual partners and to unborn

children will never be known (University of Virginia Health System, 1996).

The participants were also targeted for this study because of popular opinion of

the state of their cognition and morality. They were essentially taken advantage of. While

such international standards such as the Nuremberg Code and the Belmont Report had

not yet been compiled, it is still significant that not one aspect of the Tuskegee Syphilis

12

Study complied with the currently accepted ways to treat human subjects.

“Coercion through excessive compensation” is currently prohibited as a part of the

Belmont Code. (NIH, 2011, p. 19) These participants were subtly coerced because they

desperately needed what they got in exchange, which were free meals, medical exams,

and burial insurance (CDC, 2011).

The idea of beneficence says that all test subjects must know the risks. Not only

were these test subjects not treated and continuing to sexually transmit syphilis, but they

were also subjected to debilitating tests, such as spinal taps (Brandt, 2013). There was not

even a control group until one year into the study. By 1936 this control group helped the

investigators to the conclusion that the life expectancy of people with syphilis is 20% less

than those without (Brandt, 2013). The participants were also prevented from seeking

treatment elsewhere, especially when penicillin became a simple and commonplace

treatment for syphilis (Brandt, 2013).

What went wrong is that every aspect of beneficence, informed consent, and

justice was obliterated in order to observe how an untreated disease behaves in an

undervalued population.

Seemingly everything about this study should be changed; studying the effects of

untreated disease is inherently unethical. The policy of informed consent would naturally

lead a participant to desire treatment and most likely not voluntarily forgo it. The only

way this study could have been conducted in an ethical manner was if the investigators

ignorantly studied differences between how each race physically responds to treatment or

socially reacts to it.

Scenarios in Which Informed Consent Is Not Needed

13

In 1996, the federal government waived the need for documented informed

consent in emergency situations. When “a strictly limited class of research” related to

emergency therapy is required and no legal consent can be completed, an Institutional

Review Board (IRB) may approve research (HHS, 1996). This emergency stipulation is

not applicable to pregnant women, children, or prisoners (HHS, 1996). The case,

Canterbury v Spence, created a precedent that informed consent may be waived for

“cases in which it is reasonably believed that disclosure to the patient would pose a

serious threat to the patient’s well being” (Hartman and Lang, 1999, p. 53).

Other situations in which informed consent is not required is when research is

done in a school setting to test the efficacy of curricula, teaching methods, or testing for

achievement (HHS 2009). Food tasting tests or the evaluation of public services also does

not require documented informed consent (HHS, 1996).

In general, besides emergency studies, no informed consent is required if a study

using humans does not directly affect or augment their current physical state.

Waiving Consent For Some Areas of Clinical Investigation

Though there are many regulations overseeing medical experiments that are based

on morality with respect to human beings, unethical studies still take place today. For

example, researchers at the University of California, Davis were punished recently not for

failing to obtain informed consent, but for conducting their study without the oversight of

an IRB (Smith, 2012). Even the Tuskegee Syphilis Study was “widely reported for forty

years without evoking any significant protest within the medical community” (Brandt,

2013, p. 13).

Kottow (2003) argues that there still exists “a limited form of paternalism” in

14

clinical research settings that eat away at patients’ autonomy. This is a foreseeable

problem. There is a broadly held view that, for participants that are already sick, a doctor

knows best (Kottow, 2003). Vulnerable populations are still abused by the medical

profession as “unacceptable conditions are offered to destitute populations on the

presumption that poverty and lack of education entail the inability to exercise autonomy

and make decisions” (Kottow, 2003, p. 565). It is also argued that the use of placebos as a

control erases individual autonomy because the potential benefits of participating in the

trial are removed (Kottow, 2003).

Foreseeable problems definitely lead to vulnerable populations being taken

advantage of especially because of the current shift of investigations being spearheaded

by for-profit entities instead of universities (Kottow, 2003). While wanting to trust in the

experience and ethical growth of the medical field, it is the author’s opinion that further

curtailing of informed consent will only lead to ethical missteps within our borders and

outside of them as the oversight of IRBs is diminished.

Something concerning about the idea of waiving consent for some areas of

clinical investigation is the ambition of the medical community to research and publish.

The Nuremberg Code did not influence the single-minded and goal-oriented investigators

of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study. Why would it influence today a team of US-based

biomedical investigators conducting studies in developing nations where population

health and health outcomes are poor anyway?

It does not matter that beneficence, informed consent, or justice had not yet been

officially defined when the Tuskegee Syphilis Study took place. Basic human decency

did not exist in this situation and the pervasive idea that some people are lesser than

15

others still exists today. This is why it is more pragmatic to put one’s trust in a set of

morals and ethics than the sometimes flawed and ambitious nature of human conduct. For

this reason, it is not ethically acceptable to further erode any aspect of informed consent,

even if this process slows down the forward progress of medicine and curative

possibilities.

16

Chapter 4

Summary

The Tuskegee Syphilis ‘Study’ was a wholly unethical observation of untreated

syphilis in African American males. Participation was coerced and proved detrimental to

their health and the surrounding population’s. Backlash from the media outing of this 40-

year study incited the creation of the Belmont Code of bioethics, which the study at

Tuskegee violates every aspect of.

One of the main stipulations of the Belmont Code is that of informed consent.

This provision is under pressure to be relaxed by paternalistic ideals still present in the

scientific community. Because of past and present erosions of individual autonomy

relating to informed consent, and because utmost trust can only be placed in ethics and

not the actions of humans, it is the author’s opinion that the present regulations regarding

consent and autonomy remain.

Recommendations

When considering recommendations for the future of therapeutic clinical testing

using human subjects, the first concept that comes to mind is that of paternalism.

From the Latin, pater, or father, paternalism means to act like a father or treat

another as if they were a child. These are two distinct ideas. One represents the idea that

“father knows best,” or know better than you. The other idea, to treat another like a child

is, “benevolent, but its means coercive” (Gray, 1999). The overarching idea is that

paternalism protects people from their own “harmful” choices.

The concept and presence of paternalism (especially in medicine) is nothing new.

17

What is new is the era of modern medicine, modern diseases, and with them a negative

paternalistic influence on the autonomy of individuals.

Individuals are not absolved of the reason for the presence of paternalism. The

way in which many treat their bodies (abuse them and then check them in for a medical

tune-up) exacerbates the demand for paternalistic oversight. There may be little need for

philosophical discussions surrounding autonomy or informed consent free of paternalistic

coercion if every individual was an active advocate for their own health and well-being.

If only.

Official apologies have already been made for the crimes of the Tuskegee

Syphilis Study and retributions paid to survivors and their affected relations. What

recommendations are there to make? Recommendations aimed at preventing such human

rights violations from being perpetrated upon clinical study participants again.

Recommendations in this vein beg for broad, systemic change and not a policy band-aid.

Suppose our national discourse was augmented. What if “patients” became

“consumers?” The era of engaging in an intimate and advisory relationship with one’s

physician is over. We are sitting and eating ourselves to death and thusly the individual

has made a seat at the table for paternalistic oversight. If individuals saw themselves as

consumers, they would find it more appropriate to advocate for proper treatment, ask

questions, become informed, and not be taken advantage of.

The author is not necessarily suggesting that patients as consumers will make

everyone healthy and reduce the need for paternalism. The suggestion is that scientific

travesties large and small will not occur if the individual is unable to be coerced or

misinformed.

18

It is recommended that vulnerable populations and the population as a whole

transform the national discourse from “patients in need of help,” to “consumers in need

of information.” With continued oversight by Institutional Review Boards and federal

policies, the prevention of the breakdown of individual rights in clinical studies would be

more effective.

19

References

Brandt, A. M. (2013). Racism and research: the case of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study.

The Navy Bureau of Medicine and Surgery. Retrieved from

http://www.med.navy.mil/bumed/Documents/Healthcare%20Ethics/Racism-And-

Research.pdf

Centers for Disease Control. (2011). The Tuskegee Timeline. Retrieved from

http://www.cdc.gov/tuskegee/timeline.htm

Kottow, M. (2003). The battering of informed consent. Journal of Medical Ethics. (30):

565-569. doi: 10.1136/jme.2003.002949

National Institutes of Health. (2011). Protecting human research participants. Retrieved

from http://phrp.nihtrain ing.com/users/PHRP.pdf

PBS. (1998). Fleming discovers penicillin. Retrieved from

http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/aso/databank/entries/dm28pe.html

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (2009). Autonomy in moral and political

philosophy. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/autonomy-

moral/#ConAut

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (2008). The principle of beneficence in applied

ethics. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/principle-

beneficence/#ConBenBen

Smith, W. J. (2012, July 24). UC Davis punishes professors for unethical medical

20

experiments. The National Review. Retrieved from

http://www.nationalreview.com/human-exceptionalism/328110/uc-davis-

punishes-professors-unethical-medical-experiments

Suber, P. (1999). Philosophy of law: an encyclopedia. Illinois: Garland Pub. Co.

Retrieved from http://legacy.earlham.edu/~peters/writing/paternal.htm

University of Virginia Health System. (1996, May 20). Final report of the Tuskegee

Syphilis Study Legacy Committee. Retrieved from

http://www.hsl.virginia.edu/historical/medical_history/bad_blood/report.cfm

US Department of Health and Human Services. (2013). The Belmont report. Retrieved

from http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/humansubjects/guidance/belmont.html

US Department of Health and Human Services. (2013). Syphilis fact sheet. Retrieved

from http://www.hhs.gov/opa/reproductive-health/stis/syphilis/

US Department of Health and Human Services. (2009). Code of federal regulations.

Retrieved from

http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/humansubjects/guidance/45cfr46.html#46.101

US Department of Health and Human Services. (1996). Informed consent requirements

in emergency research. Retrieved from http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/policy/hsdc97-

01.html

Tuskegee University. (2013). About the USPHS Syphilis Study. Retrieved from

http://www.tuskegee.edu/about_us/centers_of_excellence/bioethics_center/about_

the_usphs_syphilis_study.aspx

21

22