54
Peter J. Boettke WHERE DID ECONOMICS GO WRONG? MODERN ECONOMICS AS A FLIGHT FROM REALITY ABSTRACT: F.A. Hayek’s realistic economic theory has been replaced by the formalistic use of equlibrium models that bear little resemblance to real- ity.These models are as serviceable to the right as to the left: they allow the economist either to condemn capitalism for failing to measure up to the model of perfect competition, or to praise capitalism as a utopia of perfect knowledge and rational expectations. Hayek, by contrast, used equilibrium to show that while capitalism is not perfect, it contains error-correcting insti- tutions that bring it closer to perfection than is intuitively apparent. On March , ,F. A. Hayek delivered his inaugural lecture at the London School of Economics and Political Science. Hayek, re- cently appointed to the Thomas Tooke Chair in Economic Science and Statistics at the LSE, sought to explain the trend in public opinion toward economic interventionism, embodied in the para- Critical Review , no. (Winter ). ISSN Critical Review Foundation. Peter J. Boettke, Department of Economics, New York University, Mercer Street, New York, NY , telephone () -, e-mail [email protected], the au- thor of The Political Economy of Soviet Socialism (Kluwer, ) and Why Perestroika Failed (Routledge, ), thanks Tyler Cowen, Jeffrey Friedman, Steven Horwitz, Israel Kirzner, Daniel Klein, David Prychitko, Mario Rizzo, and Edward Weick for their comments and sug- gestions, and gratefully acknowledges financial assistance from the National Fellows Program of the Hoover Institution on War, Revolution, and Peace, and from the Sarah Scaife Founda- tion in support of the Austrian Economics Program at NYU. Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the History of Economic Society meetings at the University of Notre Dame, June ; the Austrian Economics Colloquium at New York University, March ; and Central European University, Prague, January .

Peter J.Boettke - The Dissident

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    5

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Peter J. Boettke

WHERE DID ECONOMICS GO WRONG?

MODERN ECONOMICS AS A

FLIGHT FROM REALITY

ABSTRACT: F. A. Hayek’s realistic economic theory has been replaced bythe formalistic use of equlibrium models that bear little resemblance to real-ity.These models are as serviceable to the right as to the left: they allow theeconomist either to condemn capitalism for failing to measure up to themodel of perfect competition, or to praise capitalism as a utopia of perfectknowledge and rational expectations. Hayek, by contrast, used equilibriumto show that while capitalism is not perfect, it contains error-correcting insti-tutions that bring it closer to perfection than is intuitively apparent.

On March , , F. A. Hayek delivered his inaugural lecture at theLondon School of Economics and Political Science. Hayek, re-cently appointed to the Thomas Tooke Chair in Economic Scienceand Statistics at the LSE, sought to explain the trend in publicopinion toward economic interventionism, embodied in the para-

Critical Review , no. (Winter ). ISSN ‒. © Critical Review Foundation.

Peter J. Boettke, Department of Economics, New York University, Mercer Street, NewYork, NY , telephone () -, e-mail [email protected], the au-thor of The Political Economy of Soviet Socialism (Kluwer, ) and Why Perestroika Failed(Routledge, ), thanks Tyler Cowen, Jeffrey Friedman, Steven Horwitz, Israel Kirzner,Daniel Klein, David Prychitko, Mario Rizzo, and Edward Weick for their comments and sug-gestions, and gratefully acknowledges financial assistance from the National Fellows Programof the Hoover Institution on War, Revolution, and Peace, and from the Sarah Scaife Founda-tion in support of the Austrian Economics Program at NYU. Earlier versions of this paperwere presented at the History of Economic Society meetings at the University of NotreDame, June ; the Austrian Economics Colloquium at New York University, March ;and Central European University, Prague, January .

dox that questions about economic matters were asked more fre-quently than questions related to any other academic discipline,even while the answers economists gave were largely disregarded bya skeptical public.

The cause of this paradox, according to Hayek, was twofold.First, the teachings of economics are counterintuitive. (Who wouldintuit that a law to raise wages might instead cause unemploy-ment?) Second, these teachings expose as utopian many common-sensical solutions to concrete problems. “The existence of a body ofreasoning which prevented people from following their first impul-sive reactions, and which compelled them to balance indirect ef-fects, which could be seen only by exercising the intellect, againstintense feeling caused by the direct observation of concrete suffer-ing, then as now, occasioned resentment” (Hayek , ).

This resentment, Hayek argued, coupled with recent re-examina-tions of the analytical foundations of classical economics, had pro-vided fertile ground for the German Historical school to rise toprominence among economists. The German school, along withAmerican Institutionalism, offered a method for the practical-minded economist that did not possess the frustrating features ofclassical analytical economics. A body of thought that justifiedtreating economic problems as unique—and their solutions as un-bound by economic principles—was welcome relief for the would-be economic reformer.

The full effect of this trend, Hayek argued, was only being feltwithin the second generation of economists subject to its influence.The first generation, while rejecting the analytical method of classi-cal economics, was nevertheless trained in it. Although they triedto shake off the rigorous logic of the classical school, economiststrained in that way of thinking could not fully escape its influence.The second generation, however, not trained in the classicalmethod, lacked the mental tools necessary to interpret economicphenomena in a theoretically coherent manner.

Hayek’s argument can cut two ways, as I will try to demonstratethroughout this essay. On the one hand, Hayek was certainly rightto suggest that the attempt to reject economic theory in the nameof “realism” was inimical to satisfactory economics. We have nochoice but to think in terms of models and simplifying assump-tions. The world would be too complex to understand otherwise.But, on the other hand, the proposition that all thought is framed

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

by theoretical concepts (whether consciously or unconsciouslyadopted) and, as a result, that all facts are theory-laden, does not li-cense the adoption of any and every theory. Some theories are bet-ter than others. Hayek left this side of the argument unexamined.For his purposes, it was enough to contrast theory with Historicismand maintain that theory is essential for proper economic analysisand public policy application.

Internal coherence is one way of adjudicating among theories,but so is correspondence to everyday life. Too much realism maykill analysis, but too little realism is unscientific. If theoretical co-herence alone were all that mattered, then the only constraint ontheoretical exercises would be the human imagination. Interestingpuzzles would replace pragmatic solutions to problems encounteredin the world—arguably, an accurate characterization of most con-temporary economic theory. Economists must steer a course be-tween (allegedly) pure description and the mere recording ofevents, on the one side, and self-indulgent mental gymnastics onthe other. In , Hayek addressed himself only to the problemsassociated with putatively unvarnished historical description.

The task of the economist, according to Hayek, was to constructfrom familiar elements, gleaned from our everyday experience inthe world, a mental model aimed at reproducing the workings ofthe economic system. This task was misunderstood by economistsof his day, he argued, because the self-organizing principles of themarket economy were no longer understood. These principles werethe great contributions of classical economics. But by the time neo-classical economists responded to the Historicist challenge by de-veloping marginal analysis, it had been too late. The generation ofeconomists now entrusted with designing public policy had lost anunderstanding of the basic properties of the market system. As a re-sult, the trend in economic thinking was biased toward governmentplanning of the economy. This trend was not only reflected in thegrowing interest in socialism, but could also be detected in the re-emergence of arguments for protectionism in international tradeand for regulation of the domestic economy.

I. WHERE HAYEK WENT WRONG

Hayek’s lecture is of interest to us today mainly for its early state-ment of themes that later came to dominate his research program.

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

As Bruce Caldwell puts it, Hayek’s lecture, although entitled “TheTrend of Economic Thinking,” “is probably best viewed as a suit-able point of departure for explicating the trend of Hayek’s think-ing” (Caldwell , ). Hayek was prescient about the policy di-rection that would increasingly dominate economic thought, but heblamed the wrong forces for this trend. Historicism and Institution-alism, along with Hayek’s own Austrian school of economics, wereto be completely displaced by formalism within the decade follow-ing Hayek’s address. Interventionism and planning would be justi-fied not on Historicist grounds, but on the basis of the most ad-vanced refinements of economic theory and technique thatneoclassical economics—the very brand of economics Hayek tried todefend—had to offer.

The Austrians’ theoretical arguments, however, soon came to beexcluded from the canon of neoclassical “theory” by mathematicalformalists, even while the empirical investigations of the AmericanInstitutionalists and the German Historicists were not considered“empirical” after the parallel development of modern statisticaltechniques by econometricians (Caldwell ). The discipline ofeconomics rejected both the Austrian and the Historicist/Institu-tionalist traditions of economic thought, yet reached nearly thesame interventionist conclusions that the Historical and Institution-alist schools favored.

This was hardly the trend that Hayek detected in his inauguraladdress at the LSE. Nor was Hayek the only member of the Aus-trian school about to be blindsided by the direction of economics.Ludwig von Mises wrote in that there were no substantive dif-ferences between the various schools of modern neoclassical eco-nomics (Mises , ). He viewed Austr ian economics assquarely within the mainstream of neoclassical thought, the tradi-tion identified by Hayek as yielding propositions that flew in theface of the simplistic intuitive appeal of government interventionand planning. For Mises, much as for Hayek, the enemies of mod-ern economic science were Marxism, Historicism, and Institution-alism. Subtle differences in theory and the mode of its presentationamong mainstream neoclassical economic theorists did not mattermuch, not when compared to this major division. Neoclassical eco-nomics—classical economics grounded in marginal utility theory—was scientific; other approaches were pseudoscientific.

Hayek’s and Mises’s myopia notwithstanding, among neoclassical

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

economists the Austrians were indeed different. The Vienneseeconomist Carl Menger and those following in his footsteps em-phasized, in addition to subjectivism and marginal utility analysis,the role of knowledge and ignorance, time and uncertainty, changeand disequilibrium in understanding economic processes. Austrianand Swedish economists (and a few Americans and Britons, such asFrank Fetter and Philip Wicksteed) aside, neoclassical economistsignored these matters in their theorizing. But because Austrianeconomists agreed with the mainstream about the value of subjec-tive utility and marginal analysis, they were viewed by the others,and more importantly by themselves, as indistinguishable frommainstream economists who overlooked market “imperfections”such as time and ignorance.1

Hayek and Mises failed to see what was coming because the ten-sion between neoclassical and Austrian economics only becameacute during two economic debates that had not yet begun: onewith John Maynard Keynes over macroeconomic theory and policy,and the other with Oskar Lange over the feasibility and desirabilityof socialism. Even the debate with Keynes was not, alone, enoughto disturb the Austrians’ vision of their school’s “mainstream” status.In reality this debate revolved around fundamental issues in moneyand capital theory, but on the surface it was about more superficialquestions of public policy. This was obscured, on both sides, by thefact that Hayek’s brand of Continental capital and monetary theorywas little understood and appreciated in England and America.John Hicks pointed out that while Hayek wrote in English, it wasnot English economics (Hicks ). As a result, many of the ana-lytical issues at stake were never adequately addressed.

Keynes, for example, never successfully responded to Hayek’s cri-tique of his Treatise on Money, in which Hayek questioned Keynes’stendency to treat real economic factors as aggregates, and criticizedKeynes’s failure to provide a theory of capital. The debate was acase study in mutual misunderstanding. Since Hayek shared the ba-sically laissez-faire policy conclusions of many classical Britisheconomists, Keynes associated Hayek, incorrectly, with the Britishanti-interventionists’ theoretical apparatus—which Hayek had (al-beit unwittingly) jettisoned, at least in part. In this manner, Hayekwas lumped by Keynes with the “classical” school that was to beoverturned by The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money.By the same token, according to the Austrians all that was needed

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

to demonstrate the fundamental problems with Keynes was classicaleconomics; for Keynes’s General Theory was interpreted by Misesand Hayek as a return to the inflationist fallacies of the past (whicheven crude versions of the quantity theory of money had displaced)and to an economics of abundance, which denied that capital re-sources were scarce. But here the Austrians were mistaken.2 Cer-tainly Keynes made fundamental errors in economic reasoning, butin many other respects, he had penetrated classical British econom-ics deeply and had left it in tatters. Appeals to economic orthodoxywere not enough, either rhetorically or substantively, to forestall therush to embrace Keynesian economics and policy.3

The Great Depression not only led to the embrace of Keynesianeconomics, it also lent new prestige to socialism. Capitalism, criticsargued, was both unjust and chaotic. Business cycles were seen asmanifestations of the inherent contradictions of capitalism. Thismessage possessed a very practical appeal during the crisis, for obvi-ous reasons.

Nothing in the popular version of this socialism would haveshaken the self-image of Austrian economists as members of theeconomics mainstream. As early as the s, Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk had used neoclassical economic theory to rebut Marx’s un-derstanding of the operation of capitalism. In , Mises did thesame thing for the idea of socialist economic planning, demonstrat-ing that without private ownership in the means of production, so-cialist planners could not rationally calculate the alternative uses ofscarce resources (Mises and ). But in the s, OskarLange used neoclassical equilibrium analysis to demonstrate thatMises’s criticism was not valid—if one assumed that perfect knowl-edge was available to the planners. For in that case, they could cal-culate the alternative use of resources just as the competitive marketsupposedly does, through a process of trial and error. Socialist plan-ners would draw on knowledge of supply and demand conditionsin the same manner that economic agents within a market econ-omy were pictured as doing in the neoclassical model of the per-fectly competitive economy in equilibrium. If this model was theo-retically coherent, then Lange’s model of market socialism wasequally coherent.

Lange’s defense of socialism on neoclassical grounds took theAustrians by surprise, as did its acceptance by mainstream econo-mists. Such established figures as Frank Knight and Joseph Schum-

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

peter concurred with Lange’s assessment of the analytical issue, andyounger economists, such as Abba Lerner, began to develop Lange’sargument further. In response, both Mises and Hayek started to ar-ticulate more clearly and precisely what differentiated Austrianeconomics from the neoclassical orthodoxy. But by this time theywere already too far outside of the mainstream to command its at-tention any longer. Mises and Hayek came increasingly to beviewed as politically motivated pundits of the right, not as seriouseconomists. By at the latest, the Austrian school of economicswas forced underground—to the extent that, by now, it is question-able whether it should be considered part of the discipline of eco-nomics any more. By mid-century Hayek’s prediction had cametrue: interventionism, even socialism, came to dominate economics.But the source of this trend was not antitheoretical Historicism. Itwas neoclassical theory itself.

II. THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION

In the eyes of professional economists, Austrian economics wassoundly defeated by both Keynesianism and neoclassical socialism.Whereas Keynesianism challenged the macroeconomic stability ofcapitalism, neoclassical socialism challenged its microeconomic effi-ciency. Lange and Lerner’s argument could be interpreted asdemonstrating that ideal market socialism could perform as well asideal capitalism. A stronger interpretation, however, was that in theface of allegedly widespread monopoly power in real-world capital-ism, real-world market socialism would be even more efficient.

What made the neoclassical mainstream receptive to these ideaswas its failure to take seriously such factors as the use of (and im-perfections in) economic knowledge, the presence of ignorance anduncertainty, the passage of time, and changes in economic condi-tions. All of this was assumed away in mainstream equilibriummodels. Meanwhile, Austrians continued to uphold the counterin-tuitive policy conclusions of earlier economic theory because, ifone did take these factors seriously, new forms of interventionismpremised upon perfect knowledge in a timeless, changeless equilib-rium seemed utterly fantastic, hence irrelevant.

Austrians, for example, argued that monetary inflation worked itsway through the economic system by means of a ragged process ofrelative price adjustment. Thus, the nominally unimportant effect

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

of inflation on money prices could have very real effects on the un-derlying distribution of resources: relative price signals could be-come distorted, misleading investors. The injection of money intoone sector of the economy could create the illusion of increasedreal demand there, leading to unneeded new investment. Moreover,investment required resources that, far from being an undifferenti-ated aggregate, “capital,” were both heterogeneous and specific tocertain projects. The capital needed to build a house is differentfrom that needed to build a car. Distortions in investment causedby monetary disturbances in the price system could therefore havesevere consequences. Blinded by its maintenance of a stable supplyof “capital,” the government could overstimulate the supply of, forinstance, houses at the expense of what consumers actually wanted,such as cars. Mainstream neoclassical economics, however, over-looked these problems either by rejecting the quantity theory ofmoney altogether, as Keynesians did; or else by accepting the Mon-etarists’ crudely mechanical version of it, which took evenly pro-portionate adjustments in the general price level to be the mainconsequence of increases in the money supply. The theoretical andmethodological work of Mises and Hayek, which emphasizedprocesses of adjustment to real-world changes in the “data” that themainstream saw as given and unproblematic, appeared anachronisticto economists whose attention was focused on an imaginary stateof equilibrium, whether perfect or imperfect (i.e., marred by un-employment).

In , the gap between the Austrians and the mainstream ofneoclassical economics was widened by the publication of PaulSamuelson’s Foundations of Economic Analysis.4 Samuelson pioneereda synthesis of neoclassical and Keynesian economics, as well as en-dorsing the Lange-Lerner argument for market socialism.5 Samuel-son also furthered the neoclassical case against the free market inthe s, with his development of the theory of market failure.

Previously, the model of a perfectly competitive market was pri-marily used in thought experiments designed to be contrasted withreal-world market institutions. Such counterfactual thought experi-ments illuminated the positive function of those institutions (e.g.,Knight ). In a world of complete information, for example,neither firms nor profits would logically exist. Therefore, the con-strast of this imaginary world against the real world of firms and

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

profits showed that such institutions may have some functional sig-nificance in coping with imperfect and incomplete information.

This counterfactual use of the theory of perfect competition wasreversed by the formalist revolution in economics.6 The departuresof reality from the model of perfect competition were now thoughtto highlight interventions in the market economy that would benecessary to approximate equilibrium. Competitive equilibriumand the maximizing behavior that would ideally produce it repre-sented the hard core of the research program of economists from on. As this happened, economics as a discipline was trans-formed.7

The central role the model came to play was independent ofwhether it was employed by the minority who thought the marketeconomy approximated the model, or the majority who thoughtthat capitalism deviated significantly enough from the model that agreat deal of government intervention was justified. In both cases,formalism led to utopianism. Either (in the minority view) realitywas idealized, so that it approximated the model; or (in the majorityview) reality became a dystopia, devoid of dynamic adjustmentproperties, and utopian properties were inadvertently attributed tointerventions designed to make reality match the model. Absentfrom both types of formalism was recognition of any possibilityother than all or nothing. Either the real world exemplified staticequilibrium, or it could not approach that state without a pushfrom the state. The intermediate possibilities represented by real-world institutions of adjustment to disequilibrium became invisiblebecause the model contained only equilibrium.

Competitive equilibrium required: () perfect information, ()large numbers of buyers and sellers, and () costless mobility of re-sources. Under this set of restrictions, the logic of the model deter-mined () that each market participant would treat prices as given,and () that prices would equal the marginal costs of production.As a result, firms would produce at minimum average cost and earnzero economic profits. In the s and s, mainstream theoryproduced two fundamental welfare theorems that followed fromproofs of the (mathematical) existence and stability of this competi-tive equilibrium. The first welfare theorem stated that an economyin competitive general equilibrium was Pareto efficient. The secondtheorem stated that any desired Pareto-efficient economy could beachieved through the decentralized market mechanism. Together,

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

these two welfare theorems prove that if the appropriate conditionshold, the market mechanism yields the best possible economy.

That, however, is a big if. Without perfect futures markets, for ex-ample, intertemporal allocations could not be assumed to be opti-mal. Unless the strict conditions required for general competitiveequilibrium were met, the economic theorist could not with anyconfidence make pronouncements about the efficiency of marketallocations. In fact, she could be confident that the market wouldyield suboptimal results that demanded corrective government action.

The new role played by competitive equilibrium was fostered bySamuelson’s methodological innovations. Samuelson sought torewrite economics into the language of mathematics so as to elimi-nate the vague assumptions that underlay debates among “literaryeconomists” of previous generations. Restating economics in theaxiomatic language of mathematics, Samuelson argued, would forceeconomists to make explicit assumptions that they had previouslyheld implicitly. But the techniques of mathematics available toSamuelson required well-behaved and linear functions; otherwise,results would be indeterminate and the promised precision wouldnot be achieved. In order to fit economic behavior into mathemati-cal language, the real world had to be drained of its complexity.The problem situation of economic actors had to be simplifieddrastically so as to yield the precise formulations Samuelson sought.

Samuelson’s research program eliminated the conscious compo-nent from the economic choices facing individuals in a world ofuncertainty. Choice was reduced to a simple determinate exercisewithin a given ends-means framework, something an automatoncould master. The task of discovering not only appropriate means,but also which ends to pursue, was left out of the equation. More-over, it was forgotten that market institutions and practices arise inlarge part precisely because of deviations from the perfect-marketmodel. Just as the friction between the soles of our shoes and thesidewalk enables us to walk, the imperfections of the real worldgive rise to the essential institutions and practices that make eco-nomic life possible. The complexity of both institutions and indi-viduals is impossible to model precisely, so it was pushed aside bysimplifying assumptions.

The huge gap between the older view preserved in Austrianeconomics and the new use of equilibrium models can be illus-

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

trated by considering the reception of Ronald Coase’s work ontransaction costs. Viewed as a practitioner of counterfactual thoughtexperiments, what Coase was focusing on (in both his paperon the theory of the firm and his paper on the problem of so-cial costs) was the origin of actual market and legal institutions asmechanisms for coping with real-world positive transaction costs(see Coase ). Without transaction costs, Coase argued in ,there would be no need for firms. Transactions in spot marketswould be all that would be necessary to coordinate production. Inaddition, without transaction costs, Coase argued in , therewould be no need for property law. Voluntary negotiations betweeneconomic actors would resolve all conflicts over property rights.The actual existence of firms and the law can be seen, therefore, asevidence of the ubiquity and intractability of transaction costs.

Coase’s project, however, has been largely misunderstood by for-malist neoclassical economics. Instead of highlighting the functionalsignificance of real-world institutions in a world of positive transac-tion costs, Coase’s work has been interpreted as describing the wel-fare implications of a zero-transaction-cost world. The “Coase The-orem” has been taken to hold that in a world of zero transactioncosts, the initial distribution of property rights does not matter; foras long as individuals are free to transact, resources will be chan-nelled toward their most highly valued use.8

Coase’s theoretical insights into the role of institutions of prop-erty and contract, however, were not all that was buried by the for-malist revolution. Historical work on the complex web of institu-tions that undergird capitalist dynamics produced by the earliergeneration of neoclassical scholars, such as Knut Wicksell, FrankKnight, and Jacob Viner, as well as Mises and Hayek, was sweptaside in the rush toward formal theorizing. The real problem withthe trend in economic thinking in the s and s was neitherthe critique of theory carried on by Historicism and Institutional-ism, nor the war against classical liberalism launched by Keynesiansand socialists. The antitheoretical stance of Historicism and Institu-tionalism was self-defeating, and Keynesianism and socialism wouldrise and fall with the tides of politics. The real problem for eco-nomics was that the medium was becoming the message, as thestrictures of formalism denied scientific status to realistic theory.

Ideas that defied the techniques of formal analysis came to beconsidered unworthy of serious consideration. Even when an idea

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

was thought to be interesting, if it could not be translated into anappropriate model, there was not much that could be done withit.9 The substance of economics was displaced by mathematicaltechnique, and fundamental economic knowledge was set back—despite the obvious progress made in the precision with whicheconomists could say what was left to say.10

The first casualty of the formalist revolution was the historicallyand institutionally rich tradition of economics still evident in thes. Case studies of particular industries, for example, had beencommon. After the development of econometrics, however, thecase-study approach was discarded in favor of large-sample dataanalysis. The second casualty of the formalist revolution was whatmight be called “the economist’s way of thinking,” the definingcharacteristic of the discipline in both its classical and early neoclas-sical renditions. The best of the earlier economics combined an ap-preciation for the particularities of institutional context with theorygrounded in the generalities of choice under conditions of scarcity.Individuals always face tradeoffs, in this view, but the manner inwhich they weight their choices is contingent upon the particularcontext of choice.

Samuelson drained economic theory of institutional context, andthe econometric approach to empirical economics eliminated historical detail. Parsimony won out over thoroughness. Economicsmoved at this time from one side of the cultural divide (the liberalarts) to the other side (the sciences)—or at least that was the self-image of economists, who equated science more with precisionthan accuracy. The physicist does not allow the impossiblity of making accurate predictions in many real-world contexts (suchas meteorology) interfere with her pursuit of the precise formallaws that govern them. By myopically pursuing only the formal as-pects of the discipline, economics was reduced to its present state,in which we continually know more and more about less andless.11

III. EQUILIBRIUM: DESCRIPTION OF REALITY,NORMATIVE CRITIQUE, OR IDEAL TYPE?

In light of the formalist revolution in economic theory, we can use-fully distinguish the older use of the equilibrium model as an idealtype from its use by free-market Chicago-school economists as a

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

description of reality, as well as its use by interventionist Neo-Key-nesians as a critical standard with which reality could be indictedwhen it failed to measure up. In the latter two uses of equilibrium,it constitutes a static ideal, and the question is whether reality doesor does not match it. In the ideal-type use, by contrast, the questionis how departures from the ideal type—denied by the Chicagoschool; equated with market “failure” by Neo-Keynesians—mayconstitute forms of incomplete success. An ideal type is neither in-tended to describe reality nor to indict it. It is instead a theoreticalconstruct intended to illuminate certain things that might occur inreality; empirical investigation determines whether these phenom-ena are actually present and how they came to be there.13 In thisview, disequilibrium is not necessarily a market failure; somethingless than perfection may yet be better than any attainable alterna-tive.

Deployed as an ideal type, equilibrium analysis allowed econo-mists to describe what the world would be like in the absence ofimperfections such as uncertainty and change. The descriptive valueof the model lay precisely in its departure from observed reality, forthis underscored the function of real-world institutions in dealingwith imperfect knowledge, uncertainty, and so forth. Equilibrium wasused as an ideal type by such Austrian economists as Mises andHayek; early Chicago-school theorists, such as Frank Knight; LSEtheorists, such as Coase; and Swedish-school theorists, such as KnutWicksell. By contrast, economic formalism was, at first, virtuallydefined by the use of equilibrium as a standard for criticizing realitythat, on the one hand, ignored its dynamic elements and, on theother, assumed that static perfection must (somehow) be attainable.Samuelson, Kenneth Arrow, Frank Hahn, and more recently JosephStiglitz are the major theorists who have employed equilibriummodels in this manner.

Almost simultaneously with the emergence of equilibrium as anindictment of reality, University of Chicago economists such as Mil-ton Friedman, George Stigler, Gary Becker, and Robert Lucasbegan to use it as a description of reality. In their view, real marketscome breathtakingly close to approximating the efficiency proper-ties of general competitive equilibrium. And even if a real-worldmarket deviates from the ideal, the predictions of the model ap-proximate behavior in the real world better than alternative modelsdo. Real-world markets, in other words, act “as if ” they were in

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

competitive equilibr ium. In fact, Becker and Lucas treat the existence of equilibrium as an explicit core assumption of theiranalysis of economic phenomena. By collapsing the gap betweenthe model and reality, the Chicago school in its purest form doesaway with the need for intervention of the sort advocated bySamuelson et al. Hence the current reputation of laissez faire as awildly unrealistic economist’s dogma. In comparison with the im-plausible assumptions of Chicago-school laissez faire, governmentregulation has come to be seen not as a utopian outgrowth ofcrude, “intutive” economic thought, but as a form of hard-headedrealism.

From the perspective of those who see equilibrium as an idealtype, both its empirical idealization and its use as an indictment of astatic reality appear deficient. The Chicago school’s use of equilib-rium to describe reality conflates the mental and empirical worlds.And while those who use equilibrium to indict reality recognizethat the world is not perfect, their ignorance of the ways imperfectinstitutions do produce a semblance of economic order gives theman unduly pessimistic view of the market, and an unrealistically op-timistic tendency to rely on legal fiat to bring reality up to par. Inboth cases, the heuristic value of equilibrium is sacrificed. By ignoring thedynamics of disequilibrium, both traditions obscure the possibilitythat real-world market institutions may have coordinative propertieseven in the presence of dispersed knowledge, pervasive ignorance, theirreversibility of time, and changing conditions.14 While the de-scriptive use of equilibrium readily leads to an endorsement ofmarket transactions, it does so on an unrealistic basis. The proof isthat the Chicago school lacks a theory explaining how marketsachieve whatever degree of success they do; all the important work,as critics never tire of pointing out, is done by the model’s assump-tions. Similarly, the use of equilibrium as an indictment of realityfails to allow that existing imperfections may, in a dynamic world,be a source of motivation and learning that leads to the correctionof market errors.

Both predictive and normative uses of equilibrium portray mar-kets as essentially static. This constitutes an unwitting rejection ofthe heart of Hayek’s contribution, despite the lip-service often paidby formalist economists to his seminal essays on “Economics andKnowledge” () and “The Use of Knowledge in Society”().15

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

IV. “INFORMATION” AS A BRIDGE TO REALITY

The central concern of economics, Hayek suggested, is to explain“how the spontaneous interaction of a number of people, each pos-sessing only bits of knowledge, brings about a state of affairs inwhich prices correspond to costs, etc., and which could be broughtabout by deliberate direction only by somebody who possessed thecombined knowledge of all those individuals.” Economic theory, inother words, should explain observed reality. The empirical obser-vation that prices do tend to correspond to costs is the starting pointof economic science. But formal neoclassical theory, instead of dis-cerning how diffuse information is processed and used by imperfecteconomic actors, falls “back on the assumption that everybodyknows everything” and so evades “any real solution of the problem”(Hayek [] , –).

Hayek went further, arguing that the kind of knowledge that isdispersed among market participants is “knowledge of the kindwhich by its nature cannot enter into statistics” (Hayek [] ,). The content of market prices is not the sort of informationthat can be treated as a commodity. It is not, therefore, the costlinessof information that is essential to Hayek’s story, but rather its disper-sal. Its dispersal makes economic knowledge inaccessible exceptunder special, institutionally fragile, circumstances. The relevanteconomic knowledge, as Hayek put, is knowledge of “particulartime and place” (ibid., ). It can only be used and discovered inparticular institutional contexts—contexts that are abstracted awayin the timeless, placeless formalism of equilibrium modelling.Hence the irrelevance of contemporary economics for comparingthe effects of alternative real-world institutional arrangments on ac-tual economic performance.16

The fundamental purpose of economic analysis, once Hayek’sview of economic knowledge is accepted, is to determine how adynamic system of production utilizes dispersed knowledge of timeand place in a manner that aligns production plans with consump-tion demands. The money-price system, within an institutional en-vironment of well-defined and enforced private property rights,serves this aligning function in at least three ways. First, ex ante,prices transmit knowledge about the relative scarcities of goods tovarious market participants so they may adjust their behavior ac-cordingly. If the price of a good goes up, this informs economic ac-

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

tors that the good has become relatively more scarce and that theyshould economize on its use. For this reason, participants in themarket have an incentive to include the knowledge contained inprices in their actions over time. Second, the price system serves theex post function of revealing the ultimate profitability or unprof-itability of economic actions. Prescient entrepreneurship (in thebroad sense of the term) is rewarded with profits; errors are penal-ized by losses. Market prices, therefore, not only motivate futuredecisions by conveying information about changing market condi-tions, but also help market participants evaluate the appropriatenessof past market decisions and correct erroneous ones.

Seen in this light, the market process is a matter of dynamic adjust-ment. What is it adjustment to? It is, in effect, adjustment to the gapsbetween a static equilibrium of universal satisfaction and the manydepartures from this model that are present in the real world. Eachof these gaps between the counterfactual and the factual represent aprofit opportunity. Price information is also motivation for profitablereal-world adjustment, over time, to the profit opportunities of aparticular place.17

Formal equilibrium theory contains only a distorted, static imageof these aspects of the price system. As they came to recognize thisdeficiency in mainstream neoclassical economics, Hayek and othersin the Austrian tradition sought to explain how the price systemworks in real-world disequilibrium.18 The Austrian critique of thestandard model is that it has no place for the multifaceted role thatdisequilibrium prices serve within the market process.

The very idea of an economic theory of the market process standsin contrast to the static nature of equilibrium analysis. Since onlyan array of disequilibrium prices sets in motion the competitiveprocess characterizing real-world markets, the formalist orthodoxy,by its very nature, must ignore this process. As Mises wrote:

The activities of the entrepreneur or of any other actor on the eco-nomic scene are not guided by considerations of any such thing asequilibrium prices and the evenly rotating economy. The entrepre-neurs take into account anticipated future prices, not final prices orequilibrium prices. They discover discrepancies between the heightof the prices of the complementary factors of production and theanticipated future prices of the products, and they are intent upontaking advantage of such discrepancies. (, )

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

Prices serve as the basis of economic calculation only in the con-text of a process of competition brought into being by what for-malism assumes a way: disequilibrium. Real-world market prices donot perfectly contain all of the relevant information required forcompetitive equilibrium; if such information were known already,there would be no need for economic activity in the first place.Under disequilibrium conditions, however, the active bidding up ofprices when demand exceeds supply, and their bidding down whensupply exceeds demand, generates the incentives and informationnecessary to coordinate economic decisions. The discrepancy be-tween the current array of prices and the anticipated future array ofprices provides the incentive for entrepreneurs to discover hitherto-unknown opportunities for economic profit. Of course, in thisprocess of perceiving the future, entrepreneurs may (and do) makeerrors, but these errors can, by creating further discovery opportu-nities, generate further activity aimed at allocating or reallocatingresources in a more effective manner to obtain the ends soughtafter. “The market process,” Israel Kirzner writes, “emerges as thenecessary implication of the circumstances that people act, and thatin their actions they err, discover their errors, and tend to revisetheir actions in a direction likely to be less erroneous than before”(, ). While the assumption of perfect knowledge was essentialfor modelling the state of competitive equilibrium, it precluded anexamination of the path by which adjustment toward equilibriumcould be achieved. If the system were not already in equilibrium,one could not explain how it would get there. Omniscience logi-cally results in non-action. A profit opportunity that is known to allcan be realized by none. Thus, if it is to be realistic, the model’s as-sumptions have to be relaxed, but then it becomes overly complexand loses its formal elegance.

This dilemma has dogged a significant strand within the main-stream of economic thought that, since about , has tried totake up Hayek’s challenge and examine the informational aspect ofmarkets. This research program is of vital importance in evaluatingthe current state of economics not only because it is the rising or-thodoxy at the moment, but because it attempts to grapple with themain feature of reality that, in the Austrian view, is obscured byeconomic formalism. But because the new economics of informa-tion is itself formalist in its use of equilibrium models, it has been

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

fated to oscillate between utopianism about the informationalproperties of real markets and utopianism about the alternatives.

Classical economics had focused exclusively upon the incentiveto purchase more or less of a particular good that prices provided.The new economists of information recognize that prices serve acommunicative function as well. They see that prices transmit vitalknowledge about (for instance) relative scarcities, enabling eco-nomic participants to coordinate their decisions. Chicago’s GeorgeStigler is usually credited with being the first economist to developan informational model consistent with standard neoclassical pricetheory. Stigler () argued that individuals will optimally searchfor the information necessary to accomplish their goals in the mar-ket, but unlike Hayek, he assumed that they will do so in an opti-mal manner by comparing the marginal cost of information withthe marginal benefit of continuing to search for it. In other words,Stigler joined the informational content of markets with the as-sumption that equilibrium models should be seen as describing ac-tual behavior. In Stigler’s view, there was economic ignorance inthe real world, but it was the optimal level of ignorance. The at-tempt to eliminate the remaining ignorance would entail searchesfor information that were more costly than the benefits they couldproduce.

Following Stigler, economists such as Armen Alchian and JackHirshleifer developed information-search models in which variousaspects of the economic system such as advertising, middlemen, un-employment, queues, and rationing take on a new meaning andfunctional significance.19 At the same time, economists who treatedequilibrium as a critical norm rather than a reality, such as KennethArrow, Leonid Hurwicz, and Roy Radner, also sought to developmodels that accounted for informational imperfections.20 WhereStigler’s approach extended the assumption of maximizing behaviorto the information-search process, predicting that markets wouldsee various practices emerge to economize on the search processand generate an optimal flow of information, the Arrow/Hur-wicz/Radner approach argued that in the face of incomplete infor-mation, maximizing agents would be unable to coordinate their be-havior with others in an optimal manner unless an appropriatemechanism could be designed anterior to the market.21 The firstapproach presupposed the efficiency of market allocations, the sec-ond their inefficiency and the prevalence of market failure. Neither

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

approach adequately dealt with disequilibrium or the multi-infor-mational components of market processes that help economic ac-tors adjust to and learn from disequilibrium.

Among contemporary economists, Joseph Stiglitz and SanfordGrossman have elaborated the second approach more systematicallythan anyone else. Their research on the informational role of priceshas led to a fundamental recasting of many basic questions in or-thodox economic theory.22 Grossman and Stiglitz understandHayek to be arguing that prices are “sufficient statistics” for eco-nomic coordination, and they conclude that this argument isflawed. In situations where private information is important, theycontend, market prices will be informationally inefficient, for themarket will not provide the appropriate incentives for informationacquisition; thus, the case for economic decentralization is not astheoretically strong as Hayek suggests.

Grossman and Stiglitz’s reasoning, however, begs the questionagainst Hayek by starting from the unrealistic assumption of ratio-nal-expectations equilibrium. Given this assumption, they maintain,prices will reveal information so efficiently that no one could gainfrom the revelation of privately held information.23 Individualagents can simply look at prices and obtain free what would becostly to acquire privately. This free riding leads to an underpro-duction of information by the market. Prices, as a result, will neces-sarily fail to reflect all the available information. Grossman (,) states the supposed paradox as follows:

In an economy with complete markets, the price system does act insuch a way that individuals, observing only prices, and acting in selfinterest, generate allocations which are efficient. However, sucheconomies need not be stable because prices are revealing so muchinformation that incentives for the collection of information are re-moved. The price system can be maintained only when it is noisyenough so that traders who collect information can hide that infor-mation from other traders.

This paradox does challenge Stigler’s model of informationsearching, as well as the traditional welfare theorems of generalcompetitive equilibrium when they are viewed as describing thedecentralized price system. But long before Grossman and Stiglitz,Hayek recognized that the first and second welfare theorems pro-vided neither an accurate descr iption of how actual market

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

processes coordinate economic plans, nor of how the institutionalenvironment of the decentralized market generates desirable conse-quences. Hayek suggested that economists redirect their researchprogram to emphasize the use of dispersed knowledge and the im-pact of alternative insitutional arrangements on learning. Hayek’stheoretical criticisms of standard welfare economics, though, arelargely obscured by Grossman and Stiglitz’s analysis because it trans-lates Hayek’s view of dispersed knowledge into the language ofmodern formal information theory. This leaves out questions of thecontext and the tacit dimension of knowledge.

The economic problem, Hayek emphatically stated, was not thatposed by standard welfare economics, namely the allocation ofscarce resources among competing ends.24 This way of stating theproblem—which leads the neoclassical mainstream to regard gen-eral equilibrium as a solution—“habitually disregards” essential ele-ments of the phenomena under investigation, according to Hayek,by ignoring “the unavoidable imperfection of man’s knowledge andthe consequent need for a process by which knowledge is con-stantly communicated and acquired.” Equilibrium theorizing is notto be rejected, according to Hayek, but its real purpose must beconstantly kept in mind. Formal modeling can be a very good ser-vant, but a poor master; unless we remember that the situation themodel describes has little direct relevance for the solution of practi-cal problems, it can lead to mistaken judgement. Hayek constantlyreiterated that the equilibrium model “does not deal with the socialprocess at all and that it is no more than a useful preliminary for thestudy of the main problem” ( [], , ).

The essence of the coordinative property of the price system liesnot in its ability to convey perfectly correct information about re-source scarcity and technological possibilities, but in “its ability tocommunicate information concerning its own faulty information-communication properties” (Kirzner , ). Disequilibrium rel-ative prices, imperfect as they are, nevertheless provide someguidence in error correction and avoidance. This dynamic processof error detection and correction is absent from formal models ofeconomic “information” premised on static equilibrium.

The informational role of prices goes to the heart not only ofHayek’s challenge to economic orthodoxy, but of the particularissue that led Hayek to launch this challenge: the debate over so-cialism.25

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

V. SOCIALISM REVISITED

Mises began the debate by pointing out that unlike socialism, capi-talism could rely on the information and incentives of the privateproperty order that are manifested in the practice of “economiccalculation” based on market prices. Eventually the debate ledHayek to realize that the neoclassical mainstream, as embodied inthe socialist economists, was treating economic knowledge asgiven—not in need of discovery by entrepreneurs. This error is re-vived by the new information economics, in the sense that it doesnot recognize the possibility of genuine ignorance. Both the laissez-faire Stigler and the interventionist Stiglitz (et al.) treat knowledge“as if ” it exists on a bookshelf, so that the only question is whetherit is in one’s interest to pull it off the shelf or communicate it accu-rately to others. Searching for existing, already discovered informa-tion is important, but it is not the activity captured in economiccalculation. Since Grossman and Stiglitz confuse the “informa-tional” role of prices discussed by Hayek with the pregiven infor-mation assumed by static equilibrium models, they misconstrue thesocialist calculation debate as pitting capitalism, in which prices al-locate resources based upon an imperfect arbitrage process, againstsocialism, in which the allocation of resources is performed by cen-tral administrators but will be imperfect because of the cost ofmonitoring them.

Once Grossman and Stiglitz questioned the informational effi-ciency of the price system, then some alternative theoretical frame-work for assessing economic systems was required. Raaj Sah andStiglitz (Sah and Stiglitz and ) went on to develop an al-ternative framework for comparing economic systems, continuingthe program laid out by Grossman and Stiglitz for examining thecomparative costs of different systems of economic coordination.“Informational” questions continue to be at the center of the re-search agenda, although the focus of comparative assessment is notlimited to the informational efficiency of monetary prices.26

Armed with their putatively realistic—yet, in fact, static—under-standing of economic information, Sah and Stiglitz propose thateconomists turn to the “quality of decision making” within differ-ent organizational structures as the standard of comparison. “Howindividuals are arranged together affects the nature of the errorsmade by the economic system,” they write (, ). In address-

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

ing this issue, Sah and Stiglitz begin by postulating that in a marketsystem, if one entrepreneur fails to pursue a profitable opportunity,it is likely that some other entrepreneur will remedy this failure. Ina planned economy, though, the decision by the planning board notto pursue a production project rules out its adoption by anyoneelse. What impact, then, do market and planned economies have onthe ability to choose good over bad production projects?

Suppose we have an urn filled with ping-pong balls, each ballcorresponding to a production project. In polyarchical economies(markets) we would expect more of both good and bad projects tobe chosen. Hierarchical (planned) economies, on the other hand,will choose fewer good projects, but also fewer bad ones. There-fore, according to Sah and Stiglitz, “the incidence of Type I error isrelatively higher in a hierarchy, whereas the incidence of Type IIerror is relatively higher in a polyarchy” (, ). Type I errormeans the rejection of a project that should have been accepted,while Type II error is the acceptance of a project that should havebeen rejected.

While this exercise is theoretically interesting, it does little to ex-plain the way economic systems actually work. In the real world,Type I and Type II errors are linked and omnipresent. Rejecting aproject that should have been accepted allows someone to use theresources freed up by this rejection to pursue a project that shouldhave been rejected. The question, then, is what systemic mecha-nisms can detect errors of both kinds and can provide informationand incentives to correct them.27 “An appraisal of the efficiency ofthe market process,” as Kirzner puts it, “involves an appraisal of theway the market process disseminates [the] missing links of informa-tion necessary for the discovery of superior opportunities for theallocation of resources” (, –). In making such an ap-praisal, production projects cannot be treated as essentially knownand given. They must be discovered by real-world entrepreneursoperating in specific institutional contexts. The Sah-Stiglitz frame-work brushes aside any context in which innovation and the dis-covery of economic information affect economic performance. Byviewing economic projects as items in a metaphorical urn, theytreat economic information as if it were on the shelf already, suchthat the only question is how to give people sufficient incentives toget them to pull it off the shelf and use it. This is to ignore the fun-

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

damental question raised by Mises and Hayek: how informationgets onto the shelf in the first place.

Hayek’s insight—supposedly the starting-point of Stiglitz’s con-cern with information (see Stiglitz , , –)—is that themarket process allows us to exploit, utilize, and discover knowledgethat had hitherto been unknown to market participants. Entrepre-neurs do not choose the optimal production project from an arrayof known projects; they must discover opportunities for profitableventures. They must be alert to as-yet overlooked opportunities andexercise good judgment in pursuing them. As Don Lavoie puts it,“the key point of the calculation argument is that the requiredknowledge of objective production possibilities would be unavail-able without the competitive market process” (, ).

The Sah-Stiglitz framework, by ignoring both the necessary ig-norance of economic actors and the corresponding problem ofknowledge discovery, directs attention from the questions real-world comparative-systems analysis must ask. The problem is notthe establishment of the optimal conditions of competitive equilib-rium, but rather the detection of errors—deviations, as it were,from equilibrium. To find such an error is to produce economic in-formation that is useful in a world that does not approximate equi-librium; to use this information in order to make a profit is tomove that world a little closer to the normative ideal. A compari-son of capitalism and socialism that ignores their systemic ability (orinability) to engage in such error detection and correction is butanother exercise in the use of equilibrium to indict reality while ig-noring its positive dimension.

Similar difficulties afflict the work of Pranab Bardhan and JohnRoemer (), who argue that the revolutions of have un-justly discredited the socialist model. The system that failed in, they point out, was characterized by public ownership of themeans of production; noncompetitive, undemocratic politics; andcentral command over resource allocation. Bardhan and Roemeroffer instead a model of socialism that jettisons central commandsand noncompetitive and undemocratic politics, but public owner-ship remains intact. They interpret public ownership broadly tomean that the political process is in charge of distributing the prof-its of firms in order to achieve an egalitarian distribution of theeconomy’s surplus. They claim that while a competitive marketeconomy is necessary to achieve the efficient allocation of re-

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

sources, private ownership is not a prerequisite for competitivemarkets.

In Bardhan and Roemer’s view, unbridled capitalism generatesnegative externalities, not the least of which are political. The highdegree of ownership concentration under capitalism perversely af-fects the political process through the influence of the wealthy, theyallege. Thus, the efficiency gains of capitalism are offset by the sub-version of democracy. Separating economics from politics, and viceversa, is essential to the establishment of a socially harmonious andjust system.

The traditional problem with public ownership was the inabilityto separate political from economic criteria in resource-allocationdecisions. Bardhan and Roemer try to avoid this problem by givingfirms, not government, the power to allocate resources. But inorder to prevent the unequal distribution of wealth, Bardhan andRoemer postulate a model of competition between firms in whichproperty nonetheless remains collectively owned. The real issue,they argue, is competitiveness, not property ownership. The marketmust be constrained by egalitarian ownership: democracy in distri-bution, but competition in provision. Concretely, this means thedistribution of equal entitlements to firms’ profits in the form ofshares that can be traded openly, but not cashed in. Shares can onlybe traded for other shares, not for money. Such a market, accordingto Bardhan and Roemer, would provide the necessary signals that acapitalist market provides, yet would prevent the concentration ofcapital.

To Bardhan and Roemer, the key question their model must an-swer is how to motivate the managers of public firms to act effi-ciently. They contend that modern research in industrial organiza-tion has demonstrated that the owner-entrepreneur model is nolonger applicable to capitalist economies. The modern corporationcan, however, be disciplined through the capital market and themanagerial labor market, so Bardhan and Roemer proceed to repli-cate them through incentives schemes that tie a manager’s reputa-tion and salary to performance and to the distribution of unsaleableshares in their firms. Monitoring has been achieved on the eco-nomic front, and political control over the distribution of wealthhas been maintained.

The perspective undergirding this model is the Stiglitzian pro-gram for recasting economic theory along “informational” lines. If

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

one desires a society of change and mobility, then one shouldchoose capitalism. But if stability and security are desired, then oneshould opt for socialism. Once incomplete and imperfect informa-tion are introduced, Chicago-school defenders of the market systemcannot sustain descriptive claims of the Pareto efficiency of the realworld. Thus, Stiglitz’s use of rational-expectations equilibrium as-sumptions to achieve a more realistic understanding of capitalismthan is usual among rational-expectations theorists leads, paradoxi-cally, to the conclusion that capitalism deviates from the model in away that justifies state action—socialism—as a remedy.28

One might well prefer even more realism, however—if one iswilling to return to the days when accuracy was more importantthan mathematical virtuosity. While Stiglitz, Grossman, and Sah ad-mirably introduce realistic elements into the equilibrium frame-work, that framework remains primary, preventing them from ad-dressing the central issues of the socialist calculation debate. Humanfallibility is introduced, but our capacity to adapt to changing con-ditions and to learn from false starts and ill-fated projects is not.Human imperfection is introduced into the analysis, but only to becondemned by contrast with the equilibrium ideal. Still missingfrom the analysis is an examination of how imperfect human beingsattempt to cope in a real world of ignorance and uncertainty. As aresult, we get the bifurcation of the world into a private sector thatobeys rational expectations postulates while being unable to doanything to cope with the slightest departure from general equilib-rium, and a public sector that, being the creation of the normativeequilibrium theorists’ imagination, is able to rectify the resultingproblems “as if by an invisible hand.” As in the earlier Neo-Keyne-sian synthesis of Paul Samuelson, the gap between norm and realityis closed by the omniscient state.

In Mises and Hayek’s analysis, on the other hand, the complexweb of institutions and habits that come into existense because ofdisequilibrium are the object of study. According to Mises andHayek, legally secured property rights aid social learning in an im-perfect real world by encouraging investment, motivating responsi-ble decision making, allowing economic experimentation aimed aterror correction, and providing the basis for economic calculationby expanding the context within which price and profit/loss signalscan reasonably guide resource use. Formal models of competitiveequilibrium, such as Lange’s model of socialism, were not able to

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

deal with such institutional questions; formal models modified tobe superficially realistic, such as Stiglitz’s new economics, areequally inadequate.29

In the Austrian argument the concrete context within which de-cisions are made conveys vital information. It is not just that infor-mation is costly to obtain, but that it is different information if it isstimulated by a context of rivalrous, private-property exchange.The knowledge actors rely on to make decisions is not universaland abstract, as it must be if it is to be replicated through either bu-reaucratic planning or political deliberation.

Moreover, in Bardhan and Roemer’s model there is no realism,even of a superficial sort, concerning the workings of democracy. Inthe real world of mass democracies, principal/agent problems (cf.the “state theory” discussed in Evans et al. ) are just as real asthose facing modern corporations, not to mention problems ofpreference falsification (Kuran ) and pervasive ignorance (e.g.,Converse ; see Friedman ). Bardhan and Roemer equatepolitical failure with the inequality of influence brought about bythe power of money. (This equation is more assumed than proved.)Absent inequalities of wealth, they imagine that effective interestgroups could not be formed, so the democratic process would enactthe “will of the people.” This leaves unexamined the question ofthe quality of democratic decision making even in the absence ofinterest groups, and it ignores the possibility that such factors asideology, personal influence, identity politics, xenophobia, and dif-ferential ignorance (e.g., Neuman ; Zaller ) can be thesource of unequal power as easily as money can.

VI. FROM POLITICAL TO ECONOMIC UTOPIANISM AND BACK AGAIN

Samuelson’s synthesis created a rather strange mix of general equi-librium microeconomics with Keynesian macroeconomics. AsRobert Lucas repeatedly pointed out in the early s, graduatestudents were taught one thing during their Monday/Wednesdaymicroeconomic theory courses, and another thing on Tuesdays andThursdays in their macroeconomic theory courses. The link be-tween microeconomics and macroeconomics was supposed to befound in the labor market. But if the labor market was in competi-

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

tive equilibrium, this implied that the full-employment output levelhad been achieved, i.e., that there was no macroeconomic problem.

The circle was squared in Samuelson’s Neo-Keynesian model bymeans of “wage stickiness” and the “money illusion.” Unemploy-ment, according to classical economists, was due to wage rigiditycaused by labor union or government restrictions on wage adjust-ments. When there were no such rigidities, then wage cuts couldserve to clear the labor market, and widespread, persistent unem-ployment could not occur. Keynesian economics, however, raisedthe possibility that unemployment could emerge endogenously infree markets because, first, discoordination between savings and in-vestments in the capital market could produce an effective demandfailure that would reinforce pessimistic expectations (see Keynes, -); and, second, because of workers’ psychological resis-tance to nominal pay cuts, and their inability to distinguish nominalfrom real wages. The second of these problems has, like neoclassicalsocialism, been taken up by both descriptive and normative equilib-rium theorists; indeed, the attack on this aspect of Keynesianismwas central in the rise of the Chicago school—and, in turn, to itscurrent displacement by the New Keynesianism.

In the Keynesian system as modeled by Samuelson, workers careabout their relative nominal wage rather than their real wage. Inbad times, then, workers will resist downward adjustments in rela-tive nominal wages that might bring the labor market into equilib-rium. This “stickiness” in wage adjustment makes possible theemergence of an unemployment equilibrium.30 Only the tools ofmonetary and fiscal policy can shift the economy away from such acondition and toward full employment. Workers will be less aggres-sive in resisting the gradual and indirect downward adjustment oftheir real wages through inflation than they will in resisting directdownward adjustments of their nominal wages by their employers.Public-policy prescriptions guided by Samuelson’s Neo-Keynesiansynthesis, then, were predicated on the ability of the government tointervene so as to avoid the excesses of boom and bust and promoteeconomic growth. The interventionist consensus came to be em-bodied in the idea that there existed a stable tradeoff between infla-tion and unemployment, and that it was the job of policy makers tonegotiate this tradeoff.

The major difficulty with this model was that it relied on an as-sumption of worker irrationality that was every bit as implausible as

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

the hyperrationalistic assumptions with which the Chicago schoolwould soon replace it.

Samuelson’s assumption that workers were systematically and re-peatedly fooled by the money illusion was less a real synthesis ofequilibrium modeling with Keynesian economics than an ad hoc, apriori amendment to the neoclassical microeconomic model of ra-tionally self-interested behavior. As such, it was vulnerable fromtwo directions: either from an Institutionalist attempt to preserve itsad hoc, “empirical” elements at the expense of neoclassical theory(Post Keynesianism; see Davidson and Prychitko ), orfrom a hyperformalist attempt to purify the synthesis by purging itof its Keynesian contaminants. The second route, needless to say, isthe one that had the most appeal to a discipline now wedded toformal technique. This explains the astonishing success the Chicagoschool’s “New Classical” economics would have in the s in al-tering the policy agenda of a discipline that had been resolutely in-terventionist since the Great Depression.

The first shot in the Chicago counterrevolution was MiltonFriedman’s analysis of adaptive expectations. Next, the Neo-Keyne-sian synthesis was thoroughly discredited by the development of ra-tional expectations theory.31 Samuelson’s reconciliation of the mi-croeconomic ideal type with involuntary unemployment wasrepudiated, along with Keynesian prescriptions, in favor of the viewthat there could be no involuntary unemployment, hence that gov-ernment action was unnecessary. The result was a doctrinaire de-rivation of the laissez-faire conclusions that had been overturned bythe formalist revolution; economics was now cleansed of Keynesianimpurities that had been introduced in the interest of realism.Equilibrium theory was now used not to indict the market econ-omy, but to insist that it was perpetually in a state of rest. Pressed bythe Chicago school for a coherent—formalistic—theory of how re-ality deviated from equilibrium theory, the Neo-Keynesian synthe-sis imploded.

Since formalist economics could not model the real-worldprocesses of capitalist adjustment to disequilibrium, economists nowhad to choose between an irrational world of disequilibrium (origi-nal Keynesianism), a rational but unrealistic world of equilibrium(New Classical economics), and an untenable mixture of the two(Neo-Keynesianism). Neo-Keynesian economists, committed toformalism, had tried to fit Keynes’s speculations about the failure of

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

capitalist economies to maintain full employment into the programof general equilibrium theory. By the s, their model had cometo represent the intellectual standard of argument to which alleconomists who wanted to receive a serious professional hearinghad to adhere. But Keynes’s economics raised questions that wereoutside the scope of the model.32

The Chicago school resolved the tension between Neo-Keyne-sian theory and reality by insisting that reality must approximate(equilibrium) theory. But since the Chicago school was as commit-ted to formalist methods as the Neo-Keynesians were, it could pro-vide no more of a theoretical explanation of how real-world mar-ket economies could approximate full-employment equilibriumthan Samuelson could plausibly explain how an unemploymentequilibrium came into being. Perfect markets were a presumption,not a conclusion of New Classical economics, just as rigid unem-ployment was a presumption of Neo-Keynesianism.

The techniques of rational expectations and the development ofNew Classical economics came to dominate economic thinking inthe s and s.33 The assumption of perfect knowledge al-lowed the New Classicists to interpret all actual ignorance as opti-mal. Involuntary unemployment could not exist in this model be-cause once search costs were included, the labor market was foreverin equilibrium. Disequilibrium was considered incompatible witheconomic theory.34 If someone was unemployed, it must be be-cause she preferred to continue her search for a new job rather thanaccept work at the prevailing wage.

New Classical economists also sought to place the theory of thebusiness cycle on firm equilibrium foundations.35 Robert Lucas’stheory of the business cycle presumed that noise in price signalsprevented economic actors from distinguishing between changes inrelative prices caused by market conditions and changes in the gen-eral price level caused by inflation. Increases in the money supplythat translated into a change in the general price level should haveno effect on the level of output, but if a change in the general pricelevel were misinterpreted by economic actors as a change in relativeprices, then the level of output could be distorted by the confusion.In this, the simplest version of Lucas’s story, distortions must becaused by unanticipated changes in the money supply. The Chicagoschool’s later “real”—as opposed to monetary—business cycle the-ory emphasized exogenous factors such as technological change

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

and random shocks to explain fluctuations in the aggregate level ofoutput.

The New Classical economics demanded too much. Economicagents were modeled to continually and optimally update theirknowledge about the state of the world. In addition, economicagents were assumed to share the monetarist understanding of theeffect of monetary policy on the price level. These assumptionsgave economic actors the ability to checkmate policy makers. Sys-tematic, rational government intervention was therefore useless.Only unanticipated government policy could affect the aggregatelevel of output. Despite the flawless precision of this model, it pro-duced a view of the world that was obviously contrary to reality. Itis not controversial to insist that real involuntary unemployment,for example, existed during the s. Yet the Keynesian explana-tion of how this phenomenon occurred assumed economic agentswithout adaptive qualities.36 Constrained by the methodologicaldemands of formalism, economists had no way to explain imperfectadaptation to changing economic conditions, so they opted to ex-plain away such imperfections rather than accept them, à la Neo-Keynesianism, as brute facts.

The perfect-market assumption and the extreme policy implica-tions of New Classical economics led, in reaction, to the develop-ment of the New Keynesian economics and a resurrection of theanalytical importance of involuntary unemployment (see Gordon and Summers ). The New Keynesians sought to providerational-choice microeconomic foundations for wage and pricestickiness.37 The first New Keynesian models emphasized nominalrigidities in the price system. In contrast to the New Classicalmodel, which assumed that prices were perfectly flexible, the NewKeynesians emphasized that prices are often quite inflexible for avariety of reasons. Real-world labor markets, New Keynesians con-tended, are often characterized by inflexibility due to the preva-lence of long-term contracts, so even if agents have rational expec-tations, nominal rigidities prevent perfect adjustment and create theneed for Keynesian interventionist policies.

However, the early New Keynesian models were criticized byNew Classical theorists for lacking a rational-choice foundation forthe long-term labor contracts to which they attributed marketrigidity. Why would profit-maximizing firms repeatedly lock them-selves into long-term contracts that would prove suboptimal at

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

some later date? The next generation of New Keynesian modelsemphasized real rigidities in market adjustment, while retaining thebehavioral assumption of rational expectations (or near rationality)throughout the structure of the model. In a world of imperfect in-formation and imperfect market structure, New Keynesian econo-mists such as Stiglitz were able to demonstrate that a non-market-clearing equilibrium could emerge. Thus, real r igidities werecapable of generating involuntary unemployment in long-run equi-librium. Furthermore, New Keynesian models were immune fromthe criticisms leveled against Keynes and the Neo-Keynesians forassuming persistent worker irrationality and misperception of theprice level. The New Keynesian models are populated by maximiz-ing agents who suffer no informational disequilibrium, yet who ex-perience involuntary unemployment. This was an intuitively pleas-ing development because, as Robert Gordon points out, it isevident that unemployed workers and firms are unhappy abouttheir condition. “Workers and firms do not act as if they were mak-ing a voluntary choice to cut production and hours worked.”39

Paul Krugman writes that “the new Keynesian idea serves a criti-cally important purpose. During the s conservative macroeco-nomics had Keynesianism on the run with its assertion that it was alogically flawed theory—that it could not be right. The new Keynes-ian theory showed, on the contrary, that the idea that recessionsrepresent a market failure that can be corrected by government ac-tion can indeed be right. This is useful, because in reality Keynes-ianism is basically right, so it’s nice to have a theory that lets usadmit it” (Krugman , ).

New Keynesianism is able to achieve this result by means of theefficiency wage theorem. If workers’ productivity depends on theirwages, it may be rational for employers to offer a wage rate that ex-ceeds the market-clearing level.40 They may refuse to lower wagesto the market-clearing level, fearful that the productivity of theirexisting workforce will fall. A higher-than-market-clearing wagemay therefore be rational, since workers, realizing that the wage issignificantly higher than wages they could obtain by working else-where, will work harder, shirk less, quit less often, and be loyal anddiligent.41 The downside of the higher-than-equilibrium wage,however, is that both unemployed workers and firms face difficultiesin bidding down the price of labor.42 Too-high wages, and thus in-voluntary unemployment, are structurally embedded in capitalism.

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

This model is, however, as formalistic as its Neo-Keynesian andNew Classical predecessors. The New Keynesians raise many inter-esting questions about market frictions, but since the model of gen-eral competitive equilibrium remains the benchmark, the efficiencywage simply replaces the money illusion as an ad hoc, empiricallyungrounded dogma purporting to explain why, in an otherwiseperfect world that approximates the equilibrium model, inconve-niences such as unemployment seem to occur. To be sure, NewKeynesianism is an improvement upon the New Classical assump-tion of the instantanous adjustment of all markets, including theone for labor; the New Keynesians at least take notice of the exis-tence of involuntary unemployment. But their explanation of thisphenomenon is inconsistent with even the most cursory examina-tion of the way real-world firms tend to set wages. Everyday expe-rience suggests that high wages are often caused by, rather thanbeing the cause of, talents that are in great demand; and that whendemand for a worker’s talents slackens, her wages are cut. Such ob-servations reopen the door to explanations of involuntary unem-ployment in which some exogenous factor renders labor unable toaccept wage cuts in order to avoid unemployment, since it wouldseem that if there is systemic unemployment, something must bedisrupting the market’s profit-and-loss error-correction mechanism.At this point economics will have parted decisively with New Key-nesianism, since the latter view presupposes that the market containsendogenous sources of mass unemployment.43

It is entirely possible, of course, that in some firms, industries, oreven entire economies, the New Keynesian story will turn out tohold good. But surely the burden is on the spinners of this tale todemonstrate how often it is anything more than speculation; andthey have no more discharged this obligation than their New Clas-sical opponents have demonstrated the existence of perfect markets.Instead, the New Keynesians appear to be satisfied with having putrational-choice foundations under Keynes’s conviction that marketadjustments alone cannot solve unemployment. Like rational-expec-tations theorists who developed elaborate “proofs” of how the(Neo-)Keynesian picture could not be true, the New Keynesiansstart with the assumption that it (or something very much like it)must be true, and then try to explain how this “reality,” as Krugmanputs it, might have come to be. In the end, then, the New Keyne-sians are as ideological as the Chicago school. In the hands of both,

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

economics is reduced to a game in which preconceived notionsabout the goodness or badness of markets are decked out in spec-tacular theory. In neither case do economists fulfil the fundamentalscientific responsibility of testing the veracity of their explanations.

To make such a serious charge against the two dominant schoolsof contemporary economics, however, is to do little more than no-tice the logical implication of their use of the equilibrium model aseither a representation of reality or an indictment of it. And thisbrings us back to the marginalization of the old style of neoclassicaleconomics that took place shortly after Hayek’s speech of . Itwas, after all, an ideological impulse—the desire of left-wing econ-omists to justify Keynesian interventionism and socialism—that ledto the initial triumph of formalism. These economists needed nopersuading that the market had little capacity for self-correctionand adjustment to disequilibrium; thus, they treated the state as adeus ex machina that could close the gap between theory and reality.The Chicago school’s reaction against this view was equally ideo-logical, for all its scientism; but here the deus ex machina was themarket itself. Even while Hayek was seen as ideological because ofhis inability to make his case in the language of “scientific” formal-ism, the introduction of this language actually had the effect of li-censing any ideological predisposition that could be translated intoits terminology.

Both the Chicago school’s utopian view of reality and its oppo-nents’ dystopian view were given life by the assumption that equi-librium was necessarily intended to be a description of the market.The Chicago school simply affirmed this intention by praising the“magic of the market.” The Keynesians, Neo-Keynesians, and NewKeynesians also affirmed the intention, but they denied that the re-sulting description was accurate. They were led, in consequence, toview the model as an ideal that is attainable only by governmentaction; they replaced the magic of the market with the magic of thestate. Neither the Keynesians nor the Chicagoans explain how im-perfection can be institutionally remedied, rather than circumventedby either market or political actors with heroic capacities.

What both schools overlooked was the fact that equilibrium is astatic construction that could not possibly represent a dynamicworld of time, ignorance, and uncertainty; but that the divergencebetween ideal and reality can highlight the ways reality may haveinstitutionalized error-correcting properties that can, in fact, be seen

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

as propelling the world in a direction reminiscent of general equi-librium. But like any ideal type, equilibrium is a postulate that is notnecessarily effected in the real world.44 The main task of any science isto investigate the degree of correspondence between various idealtypes and empirical reality; but this means that science is primarily amatter of experimentation or, in social science, historical research—not model-building but model-testing (i.e., testing of the applicabil-ity of intelligible models to given situations). Still, the “falsification”of an ideal type in a given instance does not require that it be dis-carded as useless. It may aid the scientist in constructing ever morerealistic models of the circumstances of that particular time andplace. This procedure once allowed economics to be somethingquite different from an exercise in the provision of rationales forpredetermined conclusions.

VII. WHAT WENT WRONG

I do not claim that economists who followed the ideal-type proce-dure, such as Hayek, were immune from ideology themselves. Butin principle, treating models as ideal types allows one, or one’s col-leagues, to root out one’s ideological prejudices by subjecting one’smodels to the empirical test of applicability as well as the philo-sophical test of intelligibility.

This view of ideal-typical science is itself, of course, an idealtype; it will apply more to some scientists or disciplines in someeras, and less to others. Unfortunately, since the trend of West-ern economic thinking has been to turn this ideal type—and thisideal—into nothing but a pious hope. Despite economists’ officialadherence to Milton Friedman’s methodological positivism, thetesting of theories against reality has become less and less central totheir activity; instead, the generation of formal models has becomean end in itself.45 This was virtually inevitable, since the tenets offormalism require that economic argument must be placed in a cer-tain language if it is to be considered scientifically legitimate.46

As a result, none of the main centers of economic educationconvey a theoretical understanding of real-world market institutions.That is not viewed as their educational purpose. D. N. McCloskey(, ) has pointed out that “economics in American universitieshas become a mathematical game. The science has been drainedout of economics, replaced by a Nintendo game of assumptions . . .

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

with as much practical payoff as chess or lotto.” Instead of produc-ing economists who seek to understand the working properties ofeconomic forces in real historical time, “the graduate schools ineconomics have been producing scientific illiterates.” These aresharp criticisms, but they are more or less on target. Arjo Klamerand David Colander’s study, The Making of an Economist (), de-tails how the formalist revolution substituted mathematical skill forsensitivity to historical and institutional details, and how studentshave responded predictably to the internal reward system set up byformalist economics.

The devolution of thought that Hayek perceived at the time hewrote “The Trend of Economic Thinking” provides a useful pointof comparison with the present situation. Just as Hayek saw the realdanger as residing in the second generation of anti-theoreticaleconomists, the first generation of formalists, having been taught byolder economists, still possessed a sense of historical and institu-tional realism that was absent in the next and subsequent genera-tions. Equilibrium models still had to meet some standard of real-ism, even if these standards no longer had official methodologicallegitimacy. Thereafter, however, it was the model, and not theworld, that became the dominant source of intellectual excitement.Technique has trumped substance ever since.

As a result of this natural progression of the formalist revolution, anew form of theoretical relativism has emerged. Hayek saw Histori-cism as providing a relativistic challenge to the analytical claims ofclassical and neoclassical economics, especially when applied to pub-lic policy. Arguments for laissez faire were rejected by Historicists onthe grounds that they were based either on faulty assumptions abouthuman nature, or on analysis that may have been true for one periodof history, but was irrelevant in another period. But this apparentlyfact-based, scientific approach did not actually provide empirical evi-dence that, say, the “laws” of supply and demand were “repealed” incertain historical epochs. To do this, Historicism would have had toexplain what motivated observed economic relationships in the ab-sence of such “laws.” But, for the most part, no such alternative ex-planations were forthcoming. Instead, Historicists typically pointedto some phenomenon that seemed on the surface to contradict eco-nomic “laws,” and then reached the sweeping conclusion that in theface of such phenomena, one should abandon theorizing about themin favor of data collection and policy ad-hocery. This naive empiri-

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

cism had the effect of substituting confused, sub rosa theorizing forthe careful, refutable theorizing embodied in classical economics andcanonized in Weber’s method of ideal types. In the guise of repudi-ating the classical economic assumption that instrumentally rationalbehavior is an ideal type that is universally instantiated in the realworld, Historicism proposed an equally a priori, unscientific theoret-ical scheme—a scheme of historically determined motivational pluralism unfounded on any rigorous investigation of behavioral evidence—but one that could not even be debated intelligently,since the theoretical claims about a given era were implicit and incoherent.

The formalist revolution generated a similar disregard for empiri-cally meaningful and rigorous theorizing. Ideal-type theorizing hadbeen designed to establish whether real-world processes might ex-plain the movement of disequilibrium phenomena toward an ever-elusive hypothetical equilibrium. But to render the equilibriummodel in mathematical terms, formalists had to view it as a staticcondition against which disequilibria could only be comparedtimelessly—or banished as an illusion.

Different formal models generate different conclusions, and sinceeach model is, in principle, equally unable to explain real-worlddisequilibria, there is no way to choose between them in any ab-solute sense. Economic arguments against interventionism based onNew Classical assumptions could just as easily be false as argumentsfor intervention based on New Keynesian assumptions could betrue. All we have is a succession of logically consistent and very el-egant models that say little or nothing about the world—exceptthat anything is possible.

What is true of contemporary macroeconomics is also true formicroeconomics. Consider the situation in industrial organization.As Franklin Fisher () pointed out in a review essay on theHandbook of Industrial Organization, the main organizing principleof modern industrial organization is that there are no organizingprinciples. Modern theory simply demonstrates that anything canhappen, given different assumptions. All of the models are admit-tedly unrealistic and do not illuminate real situations in the econ-omy. This is viewed as a pragmatic weakness, but not a “theoretical”weakness, since theory has been divorced from reality. The unrealis-tic simplicity of the models is designed to allow theorists to docomplicated mathematics, not to allow testing against reality. Con-

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

versely, the empirical analysis that does occur is rarely informed bytheory. And any policy preference can be backed up in some vagueway by one model or another.

Ironically, the interventionism this allows is a product of themethodology of the arch-laissez faire Chicago school. Samuelsonwas responsible for transforming economic theory into a branch ofapplied mathematics, but Milton Friedman must share some of theresponsibility for transforming the psychology of economists bymeans of his seminal Essays on Positive Economics—one of thestaples of graduate economic education over the last four decades,along with Samuelson’s bible of technical economics.

Friedman argued that an assumption’s realism mattered little aslong as it could produce positive predictions. Part of what wentwrong with economics, it might be argued, is that this testing is theexception rather than the rule (see, e.g., Rosenberg ). But theproblem goes deeper. Even in the wake of formalism, theorists hadbeen constrained by an historical and institutional sensitivity thatprevented them from introducing blatantly false assumptions.47

Friedman himself, for example, had attacked Abba Lerner’s TheEconomics of Control () for failing to address many of the institu-tional questions that would arise from using the price system in theabsence of private-property ownership. The Economics of Control waseconomics in a vacuum, according to Friedman, and was not “com-bined with a realistic appraisal of the administrative problems ofeconomic institutions or of their social and political implications”(, ). But just such an appraisal is undermined by Friedman’smethodology. All Lerner had done (like Lange before him), afterall, was replicate for socialism the unrealistic model assumed to belegitimate for capitalism—the model of perfectly competitive gen-eral equilibrium—that Friedman had placed at the foundation ofthe Chicago school’s understanding of economic reality. Change afew assumptions here and there, and it follows that general equilib-rium socialism can achieve the same efficiency properties as generalequilibrium capitalism. Since real-world capitalism deviates consid-erably from competitive equilibrium (and is more likely to corre-spond to monopolistic rather than competitive equilibrium), real-world social ism built on the Lange-Lerner model wouldoutperform capitalism. Yet in his role as comparative systems econ-omist rather than methodologist, Friedman implies that only a seri-

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

ous case of confusing mental constructs with empirical realitycould result in this judgment.

By the same token, Friedman’s famous advocacy of economiclaissez faire, unlike that of such later Chicagoans as Gary Becker, isin most cases unconnected to the general equilibrium model.Rather, Friedman’s policy outlook is deeply shaped by Hayek’sanalysis of the informational difficulties of government planningand Hayek’s understanding of spontaneous order, combined withJames Buchanan’s work in public choice theory and constitutionalpolitical economy (see, e.g., Milton Friedman ). Later econo-mists, however, took Friedman’s methodology more seriously thanhe himself seems to have done. His pragmatic concerns were sweptaway in favor of elegant formal modelling. The economic world isno longer an object of study; the formal model of an abstract econ-omy is what is of concern to economic scientists.48 Thus, GaryBecker (, ) defines the economic approach as the relentlessand unflinching use of the postulates of maximizing behavior, mar-ket equilibrium, and stable preferences. His efficiency claims aboutthe market are predicated on the assumption that these postulatesare descriptively accurate, even though they are propositions incomparative statics while the real world is evidently dynamic.

Faced with the kind of criticisms of this view that have beenraised by Arrow, Stiglitz, and other market-failure theor ists,Chicago economists typically respond by insisting that the realworld is in equilibrium when all the appropriate costs are included in theanalysis. In other words, the market-failure theorists have made anillegitimate comparison between an ideal state and the imperfectworld. Demsetz’s attack on the “nirvana fallacy” is an example ofthis style of Chicago response to suggested market failures. Demsetzargues that Arrow’s market failure theory results from an illegiti-mate chain of reasoning that begins with a deduced discrepancybetween the ideal situation and the real situation, which is thentransformed into a demand for perfection by the use of an unexam-ined alternative arrangement. This call for perfection by incantationis guilty of the fallacy of the free lunch, i.e., the belief that the al-ternative arrangement could be established costlessly (Demsetz).

This response, while making an important analytical point aboutcomparative institutional analysis, nevertheless contains a bias infavor of the status quo that Demsetz fails to justify. He implies that

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

whatever exists must be efficient; otherwise, change for the betterwould have already occured. But if the economy were as efficient asDemsetz assumes, many of the phenomena Chicago economistsstudy—including money, firms, and law—would not exist.49 Suchinstitutions enable economic processes in the real world to achievewhatever degree of self-correction and economic coordination theformal model of competitive equilibrium was supposed to capturein the first place; yet these institutions come into being only to theextent that equilibrium is not a description of reality, but an idealtype that does not describe reality.

The New Classical economics that emerged in the s ands displayed the same complacency about the status quo, dis-missing involuntary unemployment as theoretically incoherent andempirically void. For involuntary unemployment to be a myth, theNew Classical economists posited economic actors who adjustedtheir behavior so quickly (for all practical purposes, instantly) thatequilibrium would be achieved at all points. Compared to this, theNew Keynesian efficiency-wage theorem appears the model ofsober realism.50

New Keynesianism interventionism is nourished by leaks in thesupposedly watertight equilibrium theory of the Chicago school.But the arguments for the new interventionism are simply varia-tions on the bad habits that gave rise to the Chicago school. Imper-fect market theory, like perfect market theory, is addressed to amodel, not to the world the model is supposed to illuminate.

* * *

Alan Coddington has pointed out that “instead of asking how rea-son can be applied to the knowledge that men can or do have oftheir economic circumstances,” modern economic theory “askshow reason can be applied to circumstances which are perfectlyknown.” The troublesome problems of “what can be known, andhow it can come to be known—problems of ignorance, uncer-tainty, risk, deception, delusion, perception, conjecture, adaptationand learning—are then tackled as a complication and refinementon the theory” (Coddington , ). Modern theorists’ staticconception of reason is in direct conflict with the passage of realtime (O’Driscoll and Rizzo , –). The postulates of rationalchoice theory can only generate formal proofs if the future (withits novelty, uncertainty, and ignorance) is excluded. Modeling that

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

excludes this component of reality not just for counterfactual pur-poses, but as part of realistic attempts to describe or condemn themarket, are bound to be insufficient.51

This is not, as I have tried to demonstrate throughout this essay,simply a methodological complaint. It has a host of serious implica-tions. The temporal structure of production, for example, with itsemployment of heterogeneous components to form the variouscombinations that make up the unique capital structure of a giveneconomy, are excluded from modern analysis. As a result, the waymarket signals constantly reorganize capital combinations remainsinvisible to the modern economist. Nor is the impact of monetaryprice adjustments on the pattern of exchange and production fullyincorporated into economic theory: either prices are assumed torepresent the underlying information perfectly (competitive equi-librium), or they are assumed to reflect that information so imper-fectly that they constitute market failure. In both instances, the in-formational content of the price system is misrepresented. Asshould be obvious, this has profound implications for understandingvarious economic systems and paths of economic development.

The precision of equilibrium modeling is gained at the expenseof correspondence with the imprecise world the model was oncesupposed to help us understand. Paradoxically, the careful expres-sion of imprecise concepts and processes in natural language sup-plies us with a more accurate picture of the economic world thanthe most rigorous mathematical modelling. Careful thought re-quires coherence; relevant thought requires correspondence to real-ity. Good economics requires both coherence and correspondence.

The often-stated argument that mathematical modeling elimi-nates ambiguity in thought by forcing theorists to state assumptionsexplicitly is based on a conflation of the concepts of syntactic and se-mantic clarity. Mathematical reasoning ensures that modeling is dis-ciplined by syntactic clarity, but semantic ambiguity is the result(see Coddington , ). The abandonment of mathematicalreasoning using equilibrium models would herald a return to se-mantically rigorous standards of argument about the economicworld “out there.”

The twentieth century’s oscillation between perfect market the-ory and market failure theory, both of which take as the terms ofdebate the formal model of general competitive equilibrium, willinevitably be won by theorists of market failure. It is obvious that

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

the economic world is not perfectly competitive (or even near thatstate of affairs). Hence the triumph of the interventionism Hayekforecast—not because economic theory has been rejected, but be-cause it has been misconceived. While Stiglitz and other contem-porary market-failure theorists intend to rebut Hayek’s analysis ofthe benefits of the private-property, competitive-price system, inreality their response to Hayek constitutes a non sequitur.52 SinceHayek’s argument did not depend on the achievement of staticequilibrium, the deviations of real markets from the model do notconstitute rebuttals to him. Indeed, deviations from the model wereHayek’s starting point.

To address Hayek’s argument seriously, economists would have todrop the false precision of equilibrium models and engage in care-ful reasoning about imprecise phenomena, such as the passage oftime, the limits of our knowledge, the uncertainty of the future, andthe discovery of opportunities.53 Perhaps Hayek’s argument cannotbe sustained when confronted in this manner, but this we will notknow until seven decades’ worth of disastrous formalization is aban-doned and the realities of economic life are re-engaged.

NOTES

. Of course, the Austrians were involved in major debates of this era amongmainstream economists, notably the capital theory debate (with J. B.Clark) and the value and price theory debate (with Alfred Marshall).These were, however, viewed as intramural analytical, not programmatic,debates. Marginalists were thought to be analytically united, despite differ-ences over subsidary assumptions or even broader issues of pre-analyticalvision.

. Henry Hazlitt’s critique of the Keynesian system, presented in The Failureof the “New Economics”: An Analysis of the Keynesian Fallacies (), arguesthat many of the fallacies within Keynesianism are the consequence ofmisunderstanding orthodox doctrine. See also Hazlitt .

. See Skidelsky for an intellectual biography of Keynes during thetime of the writing of The General Theory.

. Samuelson’s hold over economists can be explained on two levels. First,economists suffer from physics envy; Samuelson’s mathematization of eco-nomics promised to complete the transformation of economics into socialphysics that was started by Leon Walras. Second, Samuelson was not onlysmart, but strategic. Shortly after his Foundations became the major text-book in graduate education, Samuelson’s Economics became the leading un-

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

dergraduate text. Samuelson influenced students on their way in and ontheir way out. Within a decade, Samuelson became synonymous with eco-nomics, and his hold over the style—if no longer the substance—of eco-nomic reasoning has not waned since.

. See Samuelson , –, where he discusses welfare economics andthe implications of the competitive model. Also see Samuelson ,– and –, for his undergraduate textbook’s treatment of the is-sues related to socialist planning.

. One of the best examples of this reversal is to consider the interpretivedifference between Samuelson and Hayek on the implications of the equi-librium pricing theories of Pareto () and Barone () for collectivistplanning. Hayek included a translation of Barone’s essay in his CollectivistEconomic Planning () precisely because he thought it was clear thatBarone demonstrated the practical inability of the collectivist planning sys-tem to replicate what is achieved in the competitive market economy.Similarly, Pareto is explicit that the collectivist planner would confront aninsurmountable task even in a simple economy, whereas the capitalist sys-tem solves the problem of economic calculation every day through theimpersonal market process. Both Barone and Pareto, however, demon-strated that in order to achieve economic efficiency in production, collec-tivism would have to solve the same set of equations as competitive capi-talism. In other words, there was a formal similarity in the economicproblem in both capitalism and socialism. The recognition of this formalsimilarity was preliminary to the analysis of the problems that collectivistplanning would confront, not their solution. Yet since Samuelson con-tended that Mises’s critique of socialism was refuted in advance by thework of Barone and Pareto, he contended that the collectivist planningsystem could simply replicate the trial-and-error process explicated byBarone and Pareto. The fact that both Barone and Pareto explicitly deniedthat such a replication was possible in practice is brushed aside by Samuel-son.

. Besides Samuelson, the most important figures in this transformation ofeconomics were Kenneth Arrow, Gerald Debreu, and Frank Hahn. It is nocoincidence that each of these individuals made major contributions tomarket failure theory in addition to their development of the model ofgeneral competitive equilibrium.

. In perhaps the best intellectual biography of Coase to date, StevenMedema () argues that Coase was concerned with examining theconsequences of alternative legal arrangements on economic performancerather than in using economic techniques to examine the law. This differ-ence in emphasis explains Coase’s lack of interest in Posnerian law andeconomics, a movement more concerned with the use of economic tech-niques to examine the efficiency of various legal arrangements. Coase notonly suggested an alternative comparative institutional program of re-search, but thoroughly questioned the logical coherence of mainstream

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

neoclassical economics. Part of the equilibrium exercise that Coase en-gaged in was to show that pursuing the logic of maximizing within an en-vironment of zero transaction costs led to conclusions different from thosesuggested by Pigouvian welfare economics. If transaction costs were zero,then economic actors would negotiate away the conflict; if transactioncosts (including informational costs) were positive, then how would au-thorities know what the right level of tax or subsidy should be to correctthe situation? Coase’s research program entailed both a critique of prevail-ing practice and a positive alternative program that is now emerging in theNew Institutional Economics, of which Coase is still the leading represen-tative.

. Krugman admits that the development theory of Albert O.Hirschman and Gunnar Myrdal was essentially correct in its emphasis onstrategic complementarity in investment, and in using coordination failuresto explain why some countries are rich while others remain poor. Butthese ideas were ignored by economists in the s and s becausethey were not properly modeled—which Krugman defends, because onlya properly modeled idea deserves serious attention by the profession.Avinash Dixit () makes a simliar argument with respect to the eco-nomic theory of politics. It is this attitude among the second and thirdgeneration of economists after Samuelson that has come to dominatemainstream economics.

. I have addressed this evolution in economic thought in Boettke a. Cf.Heilbroner and Milberg .

. Nothing I have said in this paragraph is original to me: See Hirschman and Sen . Hirschman has proposed that we complicate economicdiscourse by recognizing the incredible complexity of human nature, whileSen suggests that we recapture moral philosophy in economic discourse.

. Various scholars often blend the different uses. Frank Knight, for example,used equilibrium as an ideal type in his classic Risk, Uncertainty and Profit(), but in The Ethics of Competition () he used it as a critical nor-mative standard. Alfred Marshall is remembered as the pioneer of partialequilibrium analysis (which assumes an overall equilibrium in the econ-omy, but focuses on a particular market), often assumed to be the hallmarkof the Chicago-school approach, but we can also read Marshall as an ideal-type theorist when he states that equilibrium analysis is preliminary to an“advanced study” that would be more evolutionary in nature (Marshall, ). Nevertheless, even in these cases one can easily distinguish be-tween the various deployments of the equilibrium construct.

. See Jeffrey Friedman for this version of Weber’s methodology of idealtypes. Cf. Weber [] , –. Machlup , – discusses theideal-type methodology as applied to economics in general. Cf. Weber[] , , on “the ‘imaginary experiment’ which consists in thinkingaway certain elements of a chain of motivation and working out thecourse of action which would then probably ensue, thus arriving at a

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

causal judgment.” Mises (, –) describes this approach as “themethod of imaginary construction.” Cf. Hayek , –.

. Those inclined toward the descriptive use of equilibrium basically denythat these seemingly complex problems exist in the world. Philosophically,the argument relates back to the ancient assertion that change is an illu-sion. On the other hand, those who use equilibrium as an indictment ofreality view the existence of a problem as, by definition, evidence that theideal solution of competitive equilibrium is obtainable somehow. If themarket does not attain perfection, then the state must be capable of it.

. The relevant papers by Hayek are collected in Hayek [] .. In “Economics and Knowledge,” Hayek argues that the pure logic of

choice is a necessary, though not sufficient, component of an explanationof systematic economic coordination. An understanding of economic co-ordination requires an empirical understanding of learning. Hayek’s re-search program for economics would have shifted it from the determina-tion of optimal resource use under given conditions to the exploration ofthe impact of alternative institutional environments on learning.

. Picking up a theme first raised by Oskar Morgenstern, Hayek emphasizedthat perfect foresight was a defining characteristic of equilibrium but not aprecondition that must be present for equilibrium to be obtained. Logi-cally, in fact, what Morgenstern had demonstrated was that if economicagents possessed perfect foresight, then a determinate equilibrium solutionwould evade them. As Joan Robinson also emphasized, the only way toacheive an equilibrium would be to already be in equilibrium—no processtoward equilibrium could be articulated on the basis of a theory of perfectforesight. The implication for Hayek of this theoretical conundrum wasthat economists should focus attention not on the state of equilibrium, buton dynamic adjustment and learning through time. “A theory which startsout by assuming that adjustments have proceeded to the point where nofurther changes are required,” Hayek stated, “is without relevance to ourproblems. What we need is a theory which helps us to explain the interre-lations between the actions of different members of the community duringthe period (which is the only period of practical importance) before thematerial structure of productive equipment has been brought to a statewhich will make an unchanging, self-repeating process possible” (,–).

. Kirzner is an examination of how the theory of entrepreneuriallearning fits into this research program and contrasts with standard pricetheory. Fisher is a discussion by a leading equilibrium theorist of thenecessity of disequilibrium foundations for equilibrium economics. A the-ory of convergence to equilibrium, according to Fisher, has to be devel-oped, not assumed.

. On the theory of search, in contrast to the Austrian view of the marketprocess, see High , – and –.

. This line of literature explored information/communication and motiva-

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

tional questions associated with the structure of incentives. The main con-clusion was that decentralization was less important than incentives. Butthe version of decentralization explored in these models was far differentfrom Hayek’s hypothesis about the use of knowledge in society, eventhough Hayek was supposed to be the starting point of this literature.

. Information economics led economists to investigate agency costs, infor-mational asymmetries, strategic interaction, and organizational design.These are all important problems, but the models developed to explorethem arguably fail to capture how real-world adjustment processes dealwith them.

. For overviews of this work in information-theoretic research in economicssee Stiglitz and Grossman . A textbook-style treatment of infor-mation-theoretic economics in general can be found in Campbell .An Austrian critique of the Stiglitz-Grossman program can be found inThomsen . For critical discussion of Stiglitz see Boettke band Prychitko .

. The strong assumption of rational expectations had become by the mid-s common in all models.

. Buchanan [] , –, also forcefully argues that economists shouldconcentrate their efforts on exchange relationships and the various institu-tional arrangements that result from these relationships, rather than equi-librium states, placing Buchanan alongside Mises and Hayek and earlierthinkers such as Richard Whateley. Also see Kirzner , –.

. There has been some debate over the relative importance of Mises’s calcu-lation argument and Hayek’s knowledge problem. But they seem to me tobe two sides of the same coin. Calculation without knowledge is oxy-moronic, and knowledge without the ability to do economic calculation isunimportant. Private property and monetary calculation are the means bywhich the knowledge problem can be solved in complex economies. Thatis the argument Mises’s and Hayek’s critiques of socialism shared, despitetheir differences of emphasis. As Mises points out in Liberalism, the “deci-sive objection that economics raises against the possibility of a socialist so-ciety [is that] it must forgo the intellectual division of labor that consists inthe cooperation of all entrepreneurs, landowners, and workers as producersand consumers in the formation of market prices” (Mises [] , ).See Boettke c for further discussion.

. The informational content of a multitude of market practices, not justmonetary prices, is recognized by Hayek and others in the Austrian tradi-tion, such as Fritz Machlup. Stiglitz’s attempt to remedy the unrealistic na-ture of descriptive equilibrium by paying attention to information isdoomed to failure because information is dynamic, yet formalism rendersit inherently static.

. See Boettke , –.. Stiglitz does demonstrate the sensitivity of general equilibrium results to

initial assumptions. Even rational expectations models do not yield

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

Chicago-type efficiency conclusions once slight changes in the initial as-sumptions are made as (half-hearted) concessions to realism.

. Lange, for example, accused Mises of “institutionalism” for suggesting thatthe ability to engage in rational economic calculation was related to a spe-cific institutional context, namely private property in the means of pro-duction. See Lange , n . Stiglitz , –, also doubts the im-portance of private property in influencing economic performance.

. Equilibrium here is defined in its classical sense: a state of affairs wherethere are no endogenous forces that will change the existing state of af-fairs. Defining the equilibrium state was fundamental to the Keynesianproject. As Franklin Fisher writes: “The central question which Keynessought to answer in The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Moneywas that of whether (and how) an economy could get stuck at an under-employment equilibrium. To show this, it is not enough to show that suchan equilibrium exists, we must also show that it has at least local stabilityproperties so that an economy that gets close enough to such a point willnot escape from it without an exogenous change in circumstances” (Fisher, ).

. Friedman’s theory of adaptive expectations was actually his last in a longline of criticisms of the Keynesian analytical and public policy system. Hiswork on consumption theory had questioned the behavioral premise ofthe Keynesian theory of consumption, his work on the quantity theory ofmoney challenged Keynesian monetary theory, and his work on rules ver-sus discretion raised doubt about Keynesian fine-tuning.

. Keynes’s theory of the failure of modern capitalism relied on cultural andpsychological factors as much as economic ones. The emergence of themuch-vaunted “casino” character of the stock market was, according toKeynes, a result of a change in the culture (and the population pool) oftrading. In the nineteenth century, more civilized and cultured tradersguarded against wide swings due to animal spirits. In the twentieth cen-tury, however, old habits evaporated and with them breaks against the wildtides of optimism and pessimism. The interventionist policies Keynes ad-vocated to correct for market breakdown were predicated on the assump-tion that those in government would be in a better position to assess theefficiency of capital investment (especially in the long term) than thosetrapped in the hustle and bustle of current market behavior.

. For a collection of the main papers see Lucas and Sargent . Also seeSnowdon,Vane, and Wynarczyk , –; and Hoover .

. See, for example, Lucas’s interview in Klamer . This dismissal of dise-quilibr ium theory aborted not only the development of traditional Keynesian analysis, but also the work of Clower and Leijonhufvud, PostKeynesian analysis of the sort done by Paul Davidson, as well as Austrianeconomics. Fisher has characterized Lucas’s position “always-clearing mar-kets.” When one takes this position, equilibrium analysis does not need anyjustification. Movements of actual market prices are to be analyzed as a se-

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

quence of temporary equilibria. Price offers are instantly adjusted to theshort-run equilibrium point. See Fisher , –.

. When Lucas first articulated an equilibrium theory of the business cyclehe would often cite Hayek (a recent Nobel Laurate at the time) as a pre-cursor of his approach. Hayek did, in fact, insist that Keynesians had com-mitted an error by not developing an equilibrium theory of the businesscycle. But what Hayek meant was that one cannot offer an explanation ofunemployment unless one begins in a state of full employment and ex-plains why the unemployment resulted in the first place. In the system ar-ticulated by Keynes and his early followers, full employment was denied atthe start of analysis—one began with unemployment (idle resources).Hayek used the equilibrium state of full employment only as a preliminaryto the real analysis, which was to explain how unemployment may emerge.Hayek’s position, then, was in direct opposition to both Keynes and Lucas.Keynes assumes what needs to be explained, and Lucas treats equilibriumnot only as the beginning, but also the end, of his analysis.

. One of the problems with the Keynesian system was the lack of symmetryin the motives and behavior attributed to economic agents, as opposed tothe economist-experts who would fine-tune the economy. Economicagents were assumed to be irrational and self-interested, whereas govern-ment policy-makers were presumed to be completely rational and publicspirited. Like all ideal types, this one might be found to represent reality ina given time and place; but this needs to be proved, not assumed. Other-wise the theorist can simply predetermine policy conclusions by manipu-lating assumptions.

. For a collection of the main papers in New Keynesian thought seeMankiw and Romer . Also see Snowdon, Vane, and Wynarczyk ,–; and Keenan . One of the crucial differences between NewClassical and New Keynesian models can be found in the assumption ofprice taking behavior within the New Classical models and price making mo-nopolistic behavior within the New Keynesian models.

. As Samuelson emerged as the central figure in the formalist revolution,Stiglitz is emerging as the central figure in contemporary economics. Notonly does Stiglitz’s work, like Samuelson’s, dominate the graduate curricu-lum, but he has published an introductory-level textbook, Economics(), summarizing the extent of his vast contributions to economics fora new generation of students. Just as Samuelsonianism defined economicsfrom the s through the s, Stiglitzian economics is likely to domi-nate economic thinking and education from now until well into thetwenty-first century. Stiglitz’s influence has also been more direct, as he hasserved as the chief economist in the President’s Council of Economic Ad-visors and the World Bank. Many Stiglitz-inspired arguments have beendeployed in policy debates over intervention in the health-care industry(adverse selection), banking (adverse selection and moral hazard), and an-titrust (imperfect competition).

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

The effect of Stigliz’s influence is to make economics even more pre-sumptively interventionist than Samuelson preferred. Samuelson treatedmarket failure as the exception to the general rule of efficient markets.But the Greenwald-Stiglitz theorem posits market failure as the norm, es-tablishing “that government could potentially almost always improve uponthe market’s resource allocation.” And the Sappington-Stiglitz theorem“establishes that an ideal government could do better running an enter-prise itself than it could through privatization” (Stiglitz , )

. As quoted in Snowdon,Vane, and Wynarczyk , .. In other words, the causation implied in the marginal productivity theory

of wages is reversed in the efficiency wage theorem. Rather than workersbeing paid according to their marginal productivity, they are productiveaccording to what they are paid.

. Potential employees are assumed to know more about their work skills andpersonal qualities than employers. Since the costs of hiring and firing arenot trivial, firms are concerned about hiring people they will have toeventually let go because of low productivity. In this situation, the NewKeynesian model suggests that applicants who offer to work for less thanthe efficiency wage will send a signal that they are low-productivity work-ers. This is a version of adverse selection.

. Unemployed workers are seen as unable to bid wages down for a varietyof reasons that have been summarized as the advantages of insiders (in-cumbent workers) over outsiders (unemployed workers). The cost of re-placing insiders with outsiders is often quite high, including fitting theoutsiders into the insiders’ work environment if the insiders perceive thethreat of wage cuts from the outsiders.

. Cf. Bellante .. In this paragraph I follow Jeffrey Friedman a, ff, which elaborates a

Weberian, particularistic methodology; but I disagree with ibid., , whichblames preformalist economics for assuming, rather than investigating, thecorrespondence of its ideal types with reality.

. Cf. Jeffrey Friedman a, –; Mayer .. After the s, as Robert Solow puts it, “judicious discussion is no longer

the way serious economics is carried out” (, ). Model-building hasbecome the standard intellectual exercise.

. Unless, of course, the purpose of the introduction of such assumptions wasto engage in a counterfactual mental experiment.

. In the new interventionism, one set of assumptions (optimal search, perfectcompetition, etc.) is replaced by another (asymmetric information, imper-fect competition, etc.) and the logical results are derived. The model, notthe economy, is the subject under investigation.

. This, for example, is why Coase is to be contrasted with Stigler or Beckeror Posner. The starting point of Coase’s analysis was that in general equi-librium the phenomena he sought to illuminate would be absent. Thecauses of the phenomena must therefore be found in deviations from equi-

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

librium—in Coase’s case, positive transaction costs. In Mises , thismethod of contrast is employed throughout to illustrate the functional sig-nificance of various market insititutions in a non-equilibrium world ofchange. By exploring the logic of a world free of change, one can by wayof contrast explore the world of change, which would be too complex toexamine directly without the help of this mental tool.

. The same can be said of the direction in which research on market social-ism is going. At the moment these models are not as well worked-out asthe New Keynesian models. But in the work of Roemer the key issue isone of mechanism design and determining the appropriate monitoring/contractual relationship to align incentives. In short, Roemer is trying touse the rational choice equilibrium framework to solve the problems asso-ciated with market socialism. As New Keynesian models increasingly ques-tion the efficiency of financial and labor markets under capitalism, theneed for Roemerian solutions appears to grow, just as in the s ands the socialist models had a parasitic relationship to Keynesianism.

. A great deal of contemporary economics refines traditional theory by in-corporating more realistic situations, such as increasing returns, multipleequilibria, and findings from experimental economics. In a recent surveyof modern economic theory, David Kreps () contends that these de-velopments (especially experimental economics) have the potential ofmaking economics relevant to reality. But, like market failure theory, thepoint of much of this work is to demonstrate how real-world behavior de-viates from the standard equilibrium model. The standard model remainsthe point of reference, so the passage of time, the generation of newknowledge, and changing conditions have yet to be incorporated.

. See, for example, Stiglitz , – and –. Also see John Roemer’s essay review of Stiglitz’s book, which he refers to as “An Anti-Hayekian Manifesto.”

. As Karen Vaughn (, ) concludes in her book on the migration ofthe Austrian school to America, “It seems indisputable that scientific un-derstanding would be much improved if at some point in the future wecould genuinely and intelligently say, along with Milton Friedman, there isno such thing as Austrian economics, only good economics and bad eco-nomics. But this time we would mean that good economics was an eco-nomics not only of preferences and constraints, but also an economics oftime and ignorance.”

REFERENCES

Bardhan, Pranab, and John Roemer. . “Market Socialism: A Case for Re-juvenation.” Journal of Economic Perspectives (Summer).

Bardhan, Pranab, and John Roemer, eds. . Market Socialism:The Current De-bate. New York: Oxford University Press.

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

Barone, Enrico. . “The Ministry of Production in the Collectivist State.”In Hayek .

Becker, Gary. . The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago: Uni-versity of Chicago Press.

Bellante, Don. . “Sticky Wages, Efficiency Wages, and Market Processes.”Review of Austrian Economics .

Boettke, Peter J. . “Analysis and Vision in Economic Discourse.” Journal ofthe History of Economic Thought (Spring).

Boettke, Peter J. . Why Perestroika Failed:The Politics and Economics of Social-ist Transformation. New York: Routledge.

Boettke, Peter J. . “Hayek’s The Road to Serfdom Revisited: GovernmentFailure in the Argument against Socialism.” Eastern Economic Journal

(Winter).Boettke, Peter J. a. “What Is Wrong with Neoclassical Economics (And

What Is Still Wrong with Austrian Economics).” In Fred Foldvary, ed.,Beyond Neoclassical Economics. Aldershot, England: Edward Elgar.

Boettke, Peter J. b. Review of Joseph Stiglitz, Whither Socialism. Journal ofEconomic Literature (March).

Boettke, Peter J. c. “Economic Calculation: The Austrian Contribution toPolitical Economy.” Mimeo.

Boettke, Peter J., ed. . The Elgar Companion to Austrian Economics. Alder-shot, England: Edward Elgar.

Boettke, Peter J., and David L. Prychitko, eds. . The Market Process: Essaysin Contemporary Austrian Economics. Aldershot, England: Edward Elgar.

Buchanan, James M. [] . “What Should Economists Do?” In idem,What Should Economists Do? Indianapolis: Liberty Press.

Caldwell, Bruce. . “Hayek’s ‘The Trend of Economic Thinking.’” Review ofAustrian Economics .

Caldwell, Bruce. . “Austrians and Institutionalists: The Historical Originsof their Shared Characteristics.” Research in the History of EconomicThought and Methodology .

Campbell, Donald. . Incentives: Motivation and the Economics of Information.New York: Cambridge University Press.

Coase, Ronald. . The Firm, the Market and the Law. Chicago: University ofChicago Press.

Coddington, Alan. . “Creaking Semaphore and Beyond: A Considerationof Shackle’s ‘Epistemics and Economics.’” British Journal of the Philosophyof Science .

Converse, Philip E. . “The Nature of Belief Systems in Mass Publics.” InDavid E. Apter, ed., Ideology and Discontent. New York: Free Press.

Davidson, Paul. . “The Economics of Ignorance or Ignorance of Econom-ics?” Critical Review (–): –.

Demsetz, Harold. . “Information and Efficiency.” Journal of Law and Eco-nomics (March).

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

Dixit, Avinash. . The Making of Economic Policy: A Transaction-Cost PoliticsPerspective. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Evans, Peter B., Dietrich Rueschmeyer, and Theda Skocpol, eds. . Bringingthe State Back In. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Fisher, Franklin. . Disequilibrium Foundations of Equilibrium Economics. NewYork: Cambridge University Press.

Fisher, Franklin. . “Organizing Industrial Organization: Reflections on theHandbook of Industrial Organization.” Brookings Papers: Microeconomics.

Friedman, Jeffrey. . “Economic Approaches to Politics.” Critical Review

(–): –.Friedman, Jeffrey. a. “Introduction: Economic Approaches to Politics.” In

idem ed., The Rational Choice Controversy: Economic Models of Politics Re-considered. New Haven: Yale University Press. Adapted from Friedman.

Friedman, Jeffrey. b. “Public Opinion and Democracy.” Critical Review

(): i–xii.Friedman, Milton. . Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of

Chicago Press.Friedman, Milton. . Free to Choose. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.Garrison, Roger. . “Time and Money.” Journal of Macroeconomics (Spring).Gordon, Robert. . “What is New-Keynesian Economics?” Journal of Eco-

nomic Literature (September).Grossman, Sanford. . “On the Efficiency of Competitive Stock Markets

Where Traders Have Diverse Information.” Journal of Finance (May).Grossman, Sanford. . The Informational Role of Prices. Cambridge, Mass.:

MIT Press.Grossman, Sanford, and Joseph Stiglitz. . “Information and Competitive

Price Systems.” American Economic Review (May).Grossman, Sanford, and Joseph Stiglitz. . “On the Impossibility of Infor-

mationally Efficient Markets.” American Economic Review (June).Hayek, F. A. . “The Trend of Economic Thinking.” In Hayek .Hayek, F. A., ed., . Collectivist Economic Planning. London: Routledge.Hayek, F. A. . “Economics and Knowledge.” In Hayek .Hayek, F. A. . The Road to Serfdom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Hayek, F. A. . “The Use of Knowledge in Society.” In Hayek .Hayek, F. A. . Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of

Chicago Press.Hayek, F. A. . Law, Legislation and Liberty, vol. : Rules and Order. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press.Hayek, F. A. . The Collected Works of F.A. Hayek, vol. : The Trend of Eco-

nomic Thinking. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Hazlitt, Henry. . Economics in One Lesson. New York: Harper & Brothers.Hazlitt, Henry. . The Failure of the “New Economics.” Princeton: Van Nos-

trand.

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

Hazlitt, Henry, ed. . The Critics of Keynesian Economics. Princeton: VanNostrand.

Heilbroner, Robert, and William Milberg. . The Crisis of Vision in ModernEconomic Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Hicks, John. . “The Hayek Story.” In idem, Critical Essays in Monetary The-ory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

High, Jack. . Maximizing, Action, and Market Adjustment: An Inquiry into theTheory of Economic Organization. Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

Hirschman, Albert O. . “Against Parsimony: Three Easy Ways of Compli-cating Some Categories of Economic Discourse.” In idem, Rival Views ofMarket Society. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Hoover, Kevin. . “New Classical Economics.” In Boettke .Keenan, Sean. . “New Keynesian Economics.” In Boettke .Keynes, John Maynard. [] . The General Theory of Employment, Interest,

and Money. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.Kirzner, Israel M. . Market Theory and the Price System. Princeton:Van Nos-

trand.Kirzner, Israel M. . Competition and Entrepreneurship. Chicago: University of

Chicago Press.Kirzner, Israel M. . Perception, Opportunity and Profit. Chicago: University

of Chicago Press.Kirzner, Israel M. . “Economic Planning and the Knowledge Problem.”

Cato Journal (Fall).Kirzner, Israel M. . “Prices, the Communication of Knowledge, and the

Discovery Process.” In Kurt Leube and Albert Zlabinger, eds., The Politi-cal Economy of Freedom: Essays in Honor of F. A. Hayek . Munich:Philosophia Verlag.

Kirzner, Israel M. . “The Economic Calculation Debate: Lessons for Aus-trians.” Review of Austrian Economics .

Kirzner, Israel M. . The Meaning of Market Process. New York: Routledge.Kirzner, Israel M. . “Entrepreneurial Discovery and the Competitive Mar-

ket Process: An Austrian Approach.” Journal of Economic Literature

(March).Klamer, Arjo. . Conversations with Economists. New York: Rowman and Lit-

tlefield.Klamer, Arjo, and Colander, David. . The Making of an Economist. Boulder:

Westview.Knight, Frank. [] . Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. Chicago: University of

Chicago Press.Knight, Frank. [] . The Ethics of Competition. New York: Augustus M.

Kelley.Kreps, David. . “Economics—The Current Position.” Daedalus (Winter).Krugman, Paul. a. The Age of Diminished Expectations: U.S. Economic Policy

in the s. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Krugman, Paul. b. Peddling Prosperity. New York: Norton.

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1

Krugman, Paul. . Development, Geography, and Economic Theory. Cambridge,Mass.: MIT Press.

Kuran, Timur. . Private Truths, Public Lies. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Uni-versity Press.

Lange, Oskar. [] . “On the Economic Theory of Socialism.” In Ben-jamin Lippincott, ed., On the Economic Theory of Socialism. New York:Augustus M. Kelley.

Lavoie, Don. . Rivalry and Central Planning. New York: Cambridge Univer-sity Press.

Lerner, Abba. . The Economics of Control. London: Macmillan.Lucas, Robert, and Thomas Sargent, eds. . Rational Expectations and Econo-

metric Practice. vols. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Machlup, Fritz. . Methodology of Economics and Other Social Sciences. New

York: Academic Press.Mahovec, Frank. . Perfect Competition and the Transformation of Economics.

New York: Routledge.Mankiw, Gregory, and David Romer, eds. . New Keynesian Economics.

vols. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Marshall, Alfred. . Principles of Economics. Philadelphia: Porcupine Press.Mayer, Thomas. . Truth versus Precision in Economics. Aldershot, England:

Edward Elgar.McCloskey, D. N. . “The Arrogance of Economic Theorists.” Swiss Review

of World Affairs (October).McCloskey, D. N. . The Vices of Economists, The Virtues of the Bourgeoisie.

Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.Medema, Steven. . Ronald H. Coase. New York: St. Martin’s Press.Mises, Ludwig. [] . The Theory of Money and Credit. Indianapolis: Lib-

erty Classics.Mises, Ludwig. . “Economic Calculation in the Socialist Commonwealth.”

In Hayek .Mises, Ludwig. [] . Socialism: An Economic and Sociological Analysis. In-

dianapolis: Liberty Classics.Mises, Ludwig. [] . Liberalism. Irvington-on-Hudson, N.Y.: Founda-

tion for Economic Education.Mises, Ludwig. [] . Epistemological Problems of Economics. New York:

New York University Press.Mises, Ludwig. . Omnipotent Government. New Haven: Yale University

Press.Mises, Ludwig. [] . Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, rd rev. ed.

Chicago: Henry Regnery.Neuman, W. Russell. . The Paradox of Mass Politics: Knowledge and Opinion

in the American Electorate. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.O’Driscoll, Gerald P., and Mario J. Rizzo. . The Economics of Time and Ig-

norance. New York: Basil Blackwell.

Boettke • What Went Wrong with Economics?

Pareto, Vilfredo. [] . Manual of Political Economy. New York: AugustusM. Kelley.

Prychitko, David L. . “After Davidson, Who Needs the Austrians? Replyto Davidson.” Critical Review (–): –.

Prychitko, David L. . Review of Joseph Stiglitz, Whither Socialism? CatoJournal (Fall).

Roemer, John. . A Future for Socialism. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univer-sity Press.

Roemer, John. . “An Anti-Hayekian Manifesto.” New Left Review(May/June).

Rosenberg, Alexander. . Economics—Mathematical Politics or Science of Di-minishing Returns? Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Rothbard, Murray. . Man, Economy and State. vols. Princeton: Van Nos-trand.

Sah, R. K., and Joseph Stiglitz. . “Human Fallibility and Economic Orga-nization.” American Economic Review (May).

Sah, R. K., and Joseph Stiglitz. . “The Architecture of Economic Systems.”American Economic Review (September).

Samuelson, Paul. . Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cambridge, Mass.: Har-vard University Press.

Samuelson, Paul. . Economics. New York: McGraw-Hill.Sen, Amartya. . On Ethics and Economics. Oxford: Blackwell.Skidelsky, Robert. . John Maynard Keynes: The Economist as Savior,

–. New York: Penguin.Smith, Adam. [] . An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of

Nations. New York: Modern Library.Snowdon, Brian, Howard Vane, and Peter Wynarczyk. . A Modern Guide to

Macroeconomics: An Introduction to Competing Schools of Thought. Aldershot,England: Edward Elgar.

Solow, Robert. . “How Did Economics Get That Way and What Way Didit Get?” Daedalus (Winter).

Stigler, George. . “The Economics of Information.” Journal of Political Econ-omy (June).

Stiglitz, Joseph. . Economics. New York: Norton.Stiglitz, Joseph. . Whither Socialism? Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Summers, Lawrence. . Understanding Unemployment. Cambridge, Mass.:

MIT Press.Thomsen, Esteban. . Prices and Knowledge:A Market-Process Perspective. New

York: Routledge.Vaughn, Karen. . Austrian Economics in America:The Migration of a Tradition.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Weber, Max. [] . Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociol-

ogy, vol. 1. Ed. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich. Berkeley: Universityof California Press.

Zaller, John. . The Nature and Origins of Mass Opinion. Cambridge: Cam-bridge University Press.

Critical Review Vol. 11, No. 1