26
Royal Institute of Philosophy The Epistemological Foundations of Natural Philosophy Author(s): G. J. Whitrow Source: Philosophy, Vol. 21, No. 78 (Apr., 1946), pp. 5-28 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of Royal Institute of Philosophy Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3748301 . Accessed: 24/06/2011 11:00 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup . . Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Cambridge University Press and Royal Institute of Philosophy are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org

Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 1/25

Page 2: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 2/25

THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL FOUNDATIONSOF NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

G. J..WHITROW, M.A.

THEhistory of Natural Philosophy is dominated by a paradox;broadly speaking, a vast increasein its range of applicationto theexternal world has been

accompanied bya

sweeping simplificationin its basic assumptions. -From the standpoint of Empiricismthisdual development appears utterly mysterious. On the other hand,Rationalism,which seeks to demonstrate the metaphysicalnecessityof naturallaw, and hencemight throwlight on this development,hasbeen generallydiscredited,particularlyby men of science. It is not

surprising, therefore, that philosophical discussion of scientificmethod has become a Babel of confusingtongues.

I

SCIENTIFICMETHOD

What is meant by scientificlaw? Norman CampbellIhas shownthat a law usually implies some kind of "invariableassociation";for

example,laws of cause and effectare concernedwith invariable asso-ciations in time. Natural science has been described by Campbellzas the study of those judgments concerningwhich "universal"agree-

ment can be obtained,at least in principle. Accordingto this view,scientific method is the interpretationof phenomenaby a principleof "uniformity"and "communicability."

It may be objected that this concept of scientific method is too

amorphous, including, inter alia, logic and pure mathematics. It is

true that one reasonwhy men took so long to find a fruitful method

of scientific enquiry was because they were slow to separate the

"physical" from the "biological," etc. In particular, the Pytha-

goreans were led to logical paradoxes by identifying physical and

mathematical situations uncritically. Nevertheless, the oppositepolicy, to regardthe mathematicalas wholly abstract and the physi-cal as completely concrete,results in epistemologicalonfusion.

The principal problem examined in this essay is the epistemo-

logical one of how a consistent system of elementarynatural philo-

sophy is possible, rather than the equally important psychological

I Norman Campbell: Physics: the Elements (I920), p. 2I.

2 Ibid., p. 39.

5

Page 3: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 3/25

PHILOSOPHY

one of how to analyse our primitive sense data. Although strictlybiological and psychological considerations do not lie within my

scope, the point of view I adopt is similar to Campbell's,synopticrather than artificially specialized.Hence my policy is to associate

logic, epistemology,mathematics and physics, as far as possible.All concepts of scientific method, wide or narrow, involve some

notion of "uniformity."Here the cloven hoof appears: is this uni-

formity inherent in Nature or imposed by the Mind? In practice,most investigators are sustained by the belief that Nature is not

capricious and that an Order of Nature can be discovered, irre-

spective of its origin. Nevertheless, the philosophically minded

cannot remain content with this uncritical optimism. As CharlesPeirceIremarked,"Uniformities are precisely the sort of facts thatneed to be accounted for. . . . Law is par excellence the thing that

wants a reason."

By consideringthe similaritiesand uniformitiesapparent in the

world,the ancientlogicianswere led to the constructionof concepts.In Aristotelianlogic it was assumedthat the Mindcould select fromthe multiplicity of existing objects the features common to some ofthem. To be fruitful this method

necessarilyinvolved a

pre-logicalselection principle. For example, "if we group cherriesand meat

together underthe attributesred, juicy and edible,we do not obtaina conceptof any value."2Thus,in practiceclassical ogic presupposeda theory of being. In the backgroundof ancient thought lay theworldof universals,an absoluteunchangingsubstratum of "things,"each characterizedby definite properties. Concepts were detachedfrom each other, relationsand connectionsbeing consideredas non-essential.

Whereas the Hellenic mind saw the world from the perspectiveof the absolute, the moder mind sees it from the perspectiveof therelative. In ancient thought the concreteparticularwas regardedasthe imperfect image of the abstract universal. In moder thoughtindividual phenomena are interpreted by rules correlating their

aspects to different "observers."In our mental backgroundloomsthe metaphysicalassumptionthat the universe s a nexusof relations.

II

THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY

My approach to the epistemology of natural philosophy will bemade in the light of this changein perspective.In particular,I shallbe guided by the effect of this change on the underlyingdiscipline,Geometry.

C. S. Peirce, The Architectureof Theories.2 E. Cassirer, Substance and Function (I923), p. 7.

6

Page 4: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 4/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

In Euclidean geometry each geometrical form was isolated andimmutable.Onthe other hand, in Cartesianand projectivegeometry

attention was directedto the relationsbetween, and the transmuta-tion of, geometrical forms. As a result, the gain in mathematical

power and unity has been enormous. Problems which the ancient

geometersanalysedinto many differentcases can now be solved by a

single construction. Nevertheless, this unification has been accom-

panied by a new alogical "relativistic" multiplicity. In analyticalgeometry the origin of co-ordinates can be chosen at will; in pro-jective geometry any point can be the centre of projection.

This is not the only differencebetween the ancient and modem

conceptions of geometry. Euclidean geometry was regardedas theindisputable science of space and its occupancy by bodies. It was

thought to be real knowledgeof the world, being a rational refine-ment of mensuration. Its proofs were associated with the contem-

plation of matter in the form of diagramsand solid figures.The greatHellenic geometers did not aspire to that degree of abstraction in

geometrywhichLagrangeachievedin mechanics.Their consummateintellectual feat was the invention of the axiomaticmethod, the firstand most remarkableact of

geometricalabstraction. The

significanceof this feat was twofold. Geometrybecamea deductivediscipline, tstruth being guaranteedby the supposedself-evidentcharacterof its

premises;moreover,it becameuniversal,its subject-matterbeing no

longer "this point," "that line," etc., but "any point," "any line,"and so on. However,this astonishing ncrease n the scopeand sweepof the science generated philosophical difficulties, which were re-flected in the perennial disputes concerninguniversals and particu-lars, nominalism and realism. Nevertheless, until the last century

Euclidean geometrywas generallyregardedas the uniquescienceofspace and as the prototype of absoluteknowledge.Thus, to mentionbut two names, Newton, in developinghis Natural Philosophy, and

Spinoza, in constructinghis Ethics, each based his presentationonthe Euclideanpattern.

The first misgivings appear to have been felt in the eighteenthcentury; serious criticism of Euclid's work dates from that age. Thiscriticism has beenconcernednot only with actualflawsin the reason-

ing, flawsmainlyassociatedwith illegitimate"appealsto the figure,"but alsowith the alleged ntuitive anduniquecharacterof the axioms.For example, it has been shown that the axiom of parallelscan be

replaced by other axioms in such a way that the logical consistencyof the resulting systems entirely depends on the self-consistencyofthe originalEuclideansystem. This momentousdiscovery led to thesecond act of abstraction,the developmentof Geometryas a purelyformaldiscipline.This development,in its turn,has generated ts own

philosophical problems. Has Geometry any significance?Are there

7

Page 5: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 5/25

PHILOSOPHY

any objects to which the axioms can be applied so that the axioms

are true? One such set of objects is found in the domain of numbers,

and the consistency and truth of Geometrycan be shown to dependon the consistencyandtruth of Arithmetric.No completelysuccessfulsolution to this further problem has yet been found. Hilbert at-

tempted to develop a philosophyof Arithmeticas purelyformal,but,besides his inability to prove its freedomfrom self-contradiction, t

is difficult to see how Arithmetic, thus regarded, can be usefully

applied to external objects. As F. P. Ramsey' pointed out, ". . . if

I said 'I have two dogs,' that would tell you something; you would

understand the word 'two,' and the whole sentencecould be reduced

to something like 'There are x and y which are my dogs and whichare not identical with one another.' This statement appears to in-

volve the idea of existence and not to be about marks on paper."Without adopting the extreme point of view of the Formalists, it

appears, nevertheless, that our application of Geometry to Nature

is partly conventional,because an element of choice s involved. An

illuminating analogy has been drawn by Nicod.2"As children,"he

says, "we have all seen those picture puzzleswhich representthingsthat

wecannot

distinguishat thefirst

glance;whereit is a matter of

discerninga giraffeor lion in the lines of a landscapedesertedwhenfirst scanned. When we have "discovered" the picture hidden in

them, we have seen nothing new. The contourof this little mountainis now the mane of a lion, and the knot in this tree-trunkis its eye.We had readin this network of lines a certainstructure, he landscape,and now we have just read a second structure, the lion. . . . The

pattern that I have before me is sensible nature. The elementaryrelations that I know how to spell, so to speak, are the originalrela-

tions of my sense-data.Thefigurethat I tried to readis, for example,the geometry G(p, c). What groups, taken as elements, make thisstructure G appearin the relations which flow from their grouping?Would there be several modes of grouping answeringthis require-ment; might one find a lion in the landscape n morethan oneway?"The extreme thesis, that our applicationof Geometryto the descrip-tion of the external world is primarilyconventional,was elaborated

by Poincare. He maintainedthat anyspatialstructurecan be assignedto Nature by appropriatechangesin the statement of physical laws,and used this result as an argumentfor the retention of Euclidean

geometry, mainly because it is simplerthan other geometries,in thesame sense as polynomial of the first degree is simpler than poly-nomialsof higherdegree.The simplicitywhich Poincare hadin mindis purelysyntactic or intrinsic.As Nicod pointed out, it has no refer-ence to the significance or meaning of the fundamental concepts

F. P. Ramsey, The Foundations of Mathematics (I93I), p. 72.2 J. Nicod, Foundations of Geometryand Induction (1930), p. 93.

8

Page 6: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 6/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

considered. Indeed, the comparative epistemological or extrinsic

simplicityof Euclideangeometryis not immediatelyobvious; indeed,

in GeneralRelativity, priority in this respect has been assigned byEinstein, somewhat arbitrarily, to the intrinsically more complexRiemanniangeometry.

It follows that, if the natural philosopher adopts a particulargeometry primarilybecause of its formal simplicity, he cannot besure that he has made a significantchoice, and the laws of nature

may assume an unnecessarily elaborate form. Hence, if possible,deeperconsiderationsshould be taken into account.

The empiricistmaintains that in practicethe question of choosing

a basic geometry of physics does not arise. In direct opposition tothe relativistic point of view, with its explicit recognition of theMindas an active factor in naturalphilosophy,he still subscribes tothe tabula rasa doctrine. This naive conception of scientific methodhas been severely criticizedby Cassirer.I" 'Pure' experience,whichis conceived as separated from any conceptual presupposition, is

appealedto as a criterionof the value or lack of value of a certaintheoretical assumption. The critical analysis of the concept of ex-

perienceshows,on the

contrary,that the

separationhere assumed

involves an inner contradiction. Abstract theory never stands onone side, while on the other side stands the material of observationas it is in itself and without any conceptual interpretation.Ratherthis material, if we are to ascribeto it any definite character at all,must always bear the marks of some sort of conceptual shaping.Wecan neveropposeto the conceptswhich are to be tested, the empiricaldata as naked 'facta'; but ultimately it is always a certain logical

system of connectionof the empiricalwhichis measuredby a similar

system and thus judged."Similarly,Waismannzhas remarked,with particularreferenceto

empiricalgeometric measurements,"The propositions of geometryare a system of rules applied to factual measurementsby which we

determine,e.g.,whethera given line is straight,whethera given bodyis a sphere, etc. . . . These rules are the syntax of the conceptswith which we describe the factual spatial connections ....Idealizationdoes notmeanthat the factual measurementsare refined

in thought without limit. It means, rather, that the observationsare

described by concepts of a previously given syntax (and with a

syntax which is capable of unlimited exactitude). One does not

approximatethe ideal, rather one proceedsfrom it." It follows that

a particular geometry cannot be uniquely imposed on natural

philosophyby an uncriticalappeal to the empirical.The problemof the significanceof geometry was attacked by the

E. Cassirer, op. cit., p. 107.2 J. R. Weinberg, An Examination of Logical Positivism (I936), p. II6.

9

Page 7: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 7/25

PHILOSOPHY

great German physiologist and physicist, Helmholtz, in I868. His

method, subsequently placed on a more rigorousfoundationby the

Norwegianmathematician,Lie, originatedin an examinationof the

problem from the point of view of our general intuition of space;indeed, he first considered the question as arisingout of the physio-logical problem of the localization of objects in the field of vision.He examined the spaces in which the propertiesof rigid bodies are

not affectedby translation and rotation. As a result of his work and

Lie's, it was discoveredthat the only spaces which are continuous,

isotropic and homogeneous are those of constant curvature. Ofthese there are three, spherical, hyperbolic and Euclidean; locally,

i.e. for distances which are small compared with the radius ofcurvature,all three are Euclidean.

From the epistemological point of view, the axiom of parallelsisnot a primitive proposition of Euclidean geometry but a theorem.The significant axioms are those of continuity and uniformity(homogeneityand isotropy). These axioms are not "self evident" or

logically necessary, but, on the other hand, unlike the axiom of

parallels,they do not appearto be arbitrary.They are axioms whichare "natural" to the development of mensuration, at least in its

more primitive and less sophisticatedphases. In generalterms, theyassert that the properties of A's yardstick are independent of itsorientation and are congruent with those of B's yardstick, norestriction being placed on the magnitude of the yardsticks. Theyare axioms of the type which characterizes scientific method in

general, in virtue of their "uniformity" and "communicability."They are epistemologically rimitive.

This argument appears to be the ultimate a priori justification

for basing elementary physics on Euclideangeometry.An analogous situation arises in the practical application of

ordinary arithmetic. In describingparticularsets of natural objects,the degree of usefulness of the laws of arithmetic, e.g., that thenumber of a finite set of objects is independentof the order in which

they are counted, can only be settled empirically. However, pace

J. S. Mill and Harold Jeffreys,it does not follow that these laws are

merely a posterioriinductions from experience. Instead, they con-stitute the syntax of an epistemologicallyprimitive concept of indi-

viduation. Whitehead,has drawnattention to an illuminating egendof the Councilof Nicaea. "When the Bishopstook their placeson thethrones they were 318; when they rose up to be called over, it

appearedthat they were 319; so they could never make the numbercome right, and whenever they approachedthe last of the series hehe immediately turned into the likeness of his next neighbour."Toa set of entities of this type the lawsof ordinaryarithmetic areclearly

I A.N. Whitehead, "Mathematics," Encyclopaedia Britannica, I Ith edition,

10

Page 8: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 8/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

inappropriate.A priori it is not impossiblefor particularobjects of

this type to exist in Nature. The essential point is that, irrespective

of their possible physical existence, such objects would not be ofsufficientepistemologicalsimplicity for the Mind to consider irst, in

evolving afruitful method of scientificenquiry.For guidancein examiningthe foundations of naturalphilosophy,

the following conclusions of our brief survey of geometry are re-

capitulated.The discovery of non-Euclidean geometry showed that the form

of geometry is not unique. It made no assertion concerning the

physical significanceof geometry. Althoughwe can no longerassume

without question that the only physically significant geometry isEuclidean,we cannot automatically eliminate the possibility of dis-

covering a priori reasons for preferringone geometry to another in

building up a system of theoretical physics. In so far as a choice is

opento us, a conventional factor is involved. Similarly,the identifica-

tion of particular objects as approximationsto Euclidean straightlines, for example, necessarily involves an appeal to the empirical.These conventional and empiricalfactors, however, are subordinate

to ourconcept

of scientific method. Thus,therigid

rods of theexperi-mental physicist are not first chosen empiricallyand then found to

be, say, Euclidean. Rather, as Waismannhas indicated, the primi-tive rigidrod is ideal, and approximations o it aresought in Nature.

Our methods of approximationare extremely artificial;witness the

elaborate precautions necessary to define empirical metrical stan-

dards to a high degree of accuracy. However, if our concept of

scientific method implies congruent measurementby a continuum

of hypothetical observers,the initial choice of a particulargeometry

as an ideal background, against which physical phenomena are tobe silhouetted, can be decided by a priori epistemological con-

siderations.

III

THE NATURE OF DYNAMICS

The history of dynamics since the sixteenth century is permeated

by the influence of geometry and by the evolution of relativistic

concepts. These two factors are intimately related, for, in its theoryof congruenceand spatial homogeneity, even Euclidean geometrywas crypto-relativistic. Although the ancient geometers did not

consciouslydifferentiatebetweenthe spaceof geometryand the spaceof physics, the formerwas not subjectto the non-relativisticdoctrine

of "place." On the other hand, the space of physics possessed the

propertythat every naturalobjecthas a naturalplacewhichit seeks.

Ancient natural philosophy was thus more consistent with contem-

II

Page 9: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 9/25

PHILOSOPHY

porary logic and metaphysics and, consequently, more sterile than

geometry. The bankruptcy of ancient physics was due, at least in

part, to its neglect of relations and relativistic concepts. Ancientgeometry, however, has not only survived as a living discipline,butin the scientificrenaissanceprovidedthe missingkey to the mysteriesof motion. The Copernicanrevolution, foreshadowedby the greatmediaeval mathematician,CardinalNicholas of Cusa, was based onthe introduction into kinematics of the relativistic point of view,

implicit in Euclidean geometry, and, as we have already remarked,

explicit in Cartesian.Thus the chasm between ancient and modern

thought was bridgedby mathematics.

We have seen how the initial choice of a particularabstract geo-metry for mapping physical phenomenacan be based on epistemo-logical considerations. By analogy, it is suggested that a similarsituation should arise in dynamics. First, however, I consider afamousobjection of Poincare'si to this possibility.

"The experiments,"he said, "which have led us to adopt as moreconvenientthe fundamentalconventionsof geometrybearon objectswhich have nothing in common with those geometry studies; theybear on the

propertiesof solid

bodies, onthe

rectilinearpropagationof light. They are experimentsof mechanics,experimentsof optics;they are not in any way to be regardedas experimentsof geometry.. . .On the contrary, the fundamental conventions of mechanics

and the experimentswhichprove to us that they are convenientbear

directly on the same objects or analogous objects." However, he wasnot quite at ease with his own argument,for he continued, "Let itnot be said that I trace artificialfrontiers between the sciences; thatif I separateby a barriergeometry,properlyso called,from the study

of solid bodies, I could just as well erect one between experimentalmechanicsand the mechanicsof general principles.In fact, who doesnot see that by separatingthese two sciences I mutilate them both,and that what will remainof conventionalmechanics which shall beisolated will only be a very small thing and can in no way be com-

paredto that superbbody of doctrinecalled geometry?"Such an apology is not convincing, for theoretical mechanics, in-

cluding Lagrange's Mecanique Analytique, the Hamilton-Jacobitheory, the three body theory, the qualitative dynamicsof Poincare

and Birkhoff,GeneralRelativity, etc., can be regardedin the same

way as we regardgeometry and constitutes an equally superb bodyof doctrine.Moreover, he distinction which Poincare draws betweenthe objects of geometry and the objects of mechanicsis artificial.Itis true that in abstract geometry we are concernedwith conceptsand not with concrete objects, but the situation is similar in theo-retical dynamics. A massive particle is just as much an abstract

I H. Poincare, The Foundations of Science (I929), p. 124.

12

Page 10: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 10/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

concept as is a point or a line. The conceptualspaces studied by the

geometerareparalleledby the conceptualdynamical systems studied

by the naturalphilosopher.Furthermore, he applicationofgeometryto particular objects is similar to the application of dynamics.Euclidean geometry is appropriate to the description of certain

phenomena,whereassphericalgeometry,for example,is moreappro-

priate to the description of others (e.g., the night sky); similarly,non-relativistic Newtonian dynamics and relativistic quantum

dynamics, for example, have their appropriate particular appli-cations.

Poincare's objection ultimately depends on an apparent funda-

mental distinction between the character of geometrical anddynamical axioms. As we have seen, the axioms of certain geo-metries can be chosen so as to display not only formal simplicitybut also an epistemologically primitive character. The axioms of

the most elementary systems of dynamics appear to be much more

arbitrary. Thus arises the question which is the kernel of this

essay, viz., can a simple system of dynamics be constructedwhichis epistemologically rimitive, in the sense in which we have seen

that,e.g.,

Euclideangeometry

is? Moreover,just

as Euclidean

geometry can be formally "translated" into spherical and hyper-bolic geometries, do there exist analogous translations of the

simplest type of dynamics?As an essential preliminaryto answeringthese questions, I begin

with a brief survey of the history of dynamics.This sciencewas not bornuntil Copernicusand Galileofreed men's

minds from uncritical subservienceto the authority of Ptolemy andAristotle. The objection to the Ptolemaic-Aristoteliansystem was

not that it failedto account for the observedplanetarymotions, butthat it was eventually found to be unnecessarilycomplicated.Thereasonfor its complexity lay in the assumptionthat all motion mustbe interpreted n terms of circularmotion. The originof this assump-tion was the arbitrary Hellenic postulate that "real" motion is

"perfect"and thus "eternal."Since, in ancientgeometry,all straightlines were conceived as finite in length, with definite end points, itfollowedthat eternal motion could not be rectilinear.This objectiondid not apply to circular motion. Galileo and Newton, no longerobsessed by the logical consequencesof the Hellenicrejectionof theinfinite, regardedthe fundamentaltype of motion as rectilinear,but

they still assumed that it was uniform and eternal. Newton's firstlaw of motionis syntactically superiorto Ptolemy's,but its epistemo-logical character s equally arbitrary.Nevertheless,Newton'sgeneralphilosophyof motion, unlike Ptolemy's, was not purely descriptive.An attempt was made to explain the uniformities in Nature. Eachnew observational discovery necessitated a purely arbitrary addi-

'3

Page 11: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 11/25

PHILOSOPHY

tional complicationto the Ptolemaicsystem. The Newtoniansystem,on the otherhand, was modelledon the patternof geometry,and did

not need to introduce a purely ad hocexplanationfor each new factdiscovered. The only mystery was that the fundamental axiomswere so powerfuland yet so arbitrary.

The keystone of Newtonian mechanicsis the principleof inertia,or Newton's first law of motion. The characterof this law is puzzling.There is a significantsimilarity between the efforts of philosophersand physicists to establish it a priori and the attempts of geometersto "prove"the axiomof parallels n Euclideangeometry.The abstract

conceptualnature of the principleof inertia has made it difficult for

the theoretically minded to regard it merely as an induction fromparticular instances. Not only speculative philosophers but also"sound" physicists, notably Clerk Maxwell,I have endeavoured toestablish this principleby pure deductive reasoning. Indeed, ClerkMaxwell claimed that he had shown "that the denial of Newton'slaw is in contradictionto the only system of consistentdoctrine about

space and time which the human mind has been able to form." His

proof was fallacious, and this was inevitable, for the law, as con-ceived until

recently,was either

meaninglessor else contained an

implicit contradiction.If a "freeparticle"is definedas one which moves in empty space,

Newton's law asserts that "a free particle moves for all time withuniformvelocity in a straightline."If we regardthis law as an axiom,or disguised definition, we observe that a free particle has beendefined in two differentways, which must be either redundant or

incompatible. Consequently, we are led to ask the followingquestions :--

(I) If a particlemoves in empty space, must it do so for all timewith uniformvelocity in a straight line?

(2) If a particle moves for all time with uniform velocity in a

straight line, must it be moving in empty space?The first question raises the problemof definingan inertial frame

in empty space,to which Einsteinand Infeld have recentlyredirectedattention. Given one inertial frame, an infinite number can be de-fined immediately, namely, all those in uniformmotion relative tothe first; the difficultyis to define an initial frame.This was recog-nizedby Neumann,who endeavoured o circumvent t by introducinghis ontological postulate of the immobile body, "alpha," and byMach,whose analysiswas much more acute and laid the foundationfor modern ideas.

Mach cameto the conclusion that in formulatingthe law of inertia

regardmust be paid to the masses of the universe. All bodies, each

contributingits share, are of importance n definingthis law. Motion

Clerk Maxwell, Matter and Motion (I925), p. 29.

I4

Page 12: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 12/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

without referenceto other bodies he regardedas a meaninglesscon-

cept. The argument goes back to Berkeley. In his essay, "De Motu,"

he criticized the ideas of absolute space, time and motion, pointingout that the attributes of absolute space are negative and that itcannot be imagined. He arguedthat, if every place is relative, then

every motion is relative. If everything were annihilatedexcept one

globe, it wouldbe impossibleto imagine any movementof that globe.Consequently,motion in empty space is meaningless,and Newton'sfirst law of motion is devoid of significance, f interpretedin this

context.To overcome this difficulty some physicists have assumed that

reference o other bodies is necessaryto give kinematical ignificanceto the law of inertia; but, in order to retain the law in its originalform, these other bodies are assumed to have no dynamicaleffect onthe "free particle."The reconciliation of these ideas with the law of

gravitation is attempted by postulating that the other bodies are

"very distant." This argument is hopelessly lacking in precision;indeed, the law of inertia thus interpreted, involves an internalcontradiction.

FollowingMach'sargumentto its logical conclusion,we reject thenotion of empty space as a significantframe of reference and con-centrateattention on the secondquestionraisedabove. The Platonic-Newtonian concept of space as "the receptacle"is replacedby theLeibnizian relativistic concept of space as "the order of co-exist-ences." An intermediatestage was dominatedby the ether concept,which in a rudimentaryform was present in the Newtonian philo-sophy of nature. Plausibilitywas lent to this concept by the experi-ments of Newton's rotating bucket and Foucault'spendulum,which

wereexplainedmost easily on the postulate of the absolutecharacterof rotation. Mach pointed out, however, that there is no need tointroducethe ether concept to explain these experiments;it is onlynecessaryto referthe phenomenato the frame of the "fixed stars."He arguedthat, if rotation were absolute and not merelyrelative tothe stellarsystem, then, if the bucket and the earth respectivelywasfixed and the stellar system rotated, the phenomena observed byNewton and by Foucault would not arise. This situation cannot be

realized,as the world is only given to us onceand not twice. Conse-

quently, the crucialexperimentwhich would demonstratethe exist-ence of absolute rotation is impossible, and it is not necessary tointroducethis concept.

Considerationsof this kind have led to the replacementof the ideaof motion as an attribute haracterizinga "thing" by its interpreta-tion as a relationbetween one or more things. The law of inertia thuscomes to be regarded,not as a property of a single body or particle,but as a relation between a certain object or class of objects and a

I5

Page 13: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 13/25

PHILOSOPHY

basic framework of other objects. Thus, it is brought into line withthe concept of gravitation, which is not an inherent property of a

massbut a relation between two

masses.In

this case, however, theaxiomatic character of the law appears even more arbitrary thanbefore. Recalling the similar situation in geometry concerningtheaxiom of parallels, we are led to ask whether, from the epistemo-logical point of view, the law of inertia shouldbe regardedas primi-tive. To answer this question we must return to first principles.

IV

SYSTEMS OF NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

The Natural Philosophy of Newton and the GeneralRelativity ofEinstein are successiveapproximationsto an ideal epistemologicallyprimitivescienceof dynamics;for,whileboth systemscontain certain

arbitrary features, General Relativity contains fewer and at thesame time can account for phenomena,e.g., the motion of the peri-helion of Mercury, inexplicable by the Newtonian method, unlessad hocassumptionsaremade. In both theoriesthereis someobscurity

concerning he method of comparingmeasurementsmadeby differentobservers.In classicaldynamicsthere is practicallyno theory of the

congruenceof clocksand rigidrods, whereasin relativisticdynamics,despite a brilliant investigation of the relations between the clocksand rods used by differentobservers, Einstein gives no analysis ofthe relationsbetween the various clocksand rods whichcan be used,in principle,by the same observer. For Einstein, as for Newton, aclock and a measuringrod are ontological postulates or arbitraryempiricalassumptionssuggestedby the behaviourof certain materials

underrestrictedconditions.However,in the last decade a theory hasbeen developed, primarily by Milne,which is based on explicit rulesfor defining all measurements.This theory, known as "Kinematic

Relativity," is a furtherapproximationto an ideal epistemologicallyprimitivesystem of naturalphilosophy.

Theories of the physical universe fall into three general classes,

accordingas the basic framework of the world is regardedas One,or as a plurality of things, which are either mutually independent,

like the monads of Leibniz, or else "related,"like the "equivalentobservers"of Kinematic Relativity.

(i)

Prototype of unitarysystems is that of Parmenides,who regardedthe world as a continuous sphere always identical to itself. His

cosmology is probably the most logicallyperfect that has ever beendevised. Despite its obvious incompatibilitywith our most elemen-

16

Page 14: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 14/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

tary sense data, it has had a profound nfluenceon the developmentof human thought, for not only has it an easily recognizedprogeny

in idealist philosophy down to Bradley, but it has even left its im-press upon the classical physics of Newton and his successors.Dis-

regardingprimitive mythological systems, with their vague notionsof a controllingFate, the oldest cosmologiesof which we are awareare those of the Ionian philosophers,Thales and his successors,who

sought some invariantprinciple n the apparentlyever-changing luxof phenomena. The system of Parmenides was a sophisticatedexample of this class of theory. Its logical perfection caused thenotion of "invariant" to crystallize in human thought for over two

thousand years as that which is immutableor independentof time.Indirectly, it must have been crucial in determining the basicallygeometricalcharacter of nearly all subsequent natural philosophyand, in particular,in causing Newton to expound his dynamics in

synthetic form, despite the probabilityof his having employedothermethods for inventingit. Indeed,so fundamental s the Parmenidean

concept of "invariant"in the history of science that in recent yearsa distinguishedauthority' has maintained that scientificexplanation"consistsin the identificationofthe antecedent and the

consequent."Thus,2 "science in its effort to become 'rational' tends more andmore to suppress variations in time," so that "the principle of

causality . . . is the elimination of the cause."

Whatever criticism we may bring to bear against this point ofview on philosophicalgrounds,there is no doubt that it is a correct

expression of an historical tendency. Hellenic natural philosophywas almost entirely geometrical and "timeless." Moder natural

philosophy, in the main, has been based on Galileo's concept of

"geometrical," i.e. reversible or "timeless," time. Despite thebrilliant achievementsresulting from the skilful use of this concept,

grave difficultieshave been encountered,e.g., the problemof recon-

cilingthe secular ncreaseof entropywith the reversibilityof the equa-tions of classical dynamics. Indeed, as Meyerson3himself remarked,". .. contrary to what causality postulated, it is not possible to

eliminate time, since this eliminationwould have reversibilityas its

preliminarycondition, and reversibility does not exist in Nature.

The reversiblephenomenonis purely ideal." In particular,it is sig-nificant that, after an exhaustive investigation of the nature ofinertia, this acute thinker can draw only the following lame and

curious conclusions ... "Is the principle of inertia a priori or

a posteriori?It is neither the one nor the other because it is both

at the same time. . . . Perhaps it would be wise to apply to state-

ments of this category, intermediarybetween the a priori and the

E. Meyerson, Identity and Reality (1930), p. 2I9.

2 Ibid., p. 230. 3 Ibid., p. 284. 4 Ibid., p. 148.

I7

Page 15: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 15/25

PHILOSOPHY

a posteriori,a special term. We should propose, for lack of a better

one, the term plausible. Therefore, every proposition stipulating

identity in time, every law of conservation is plausible. . . . Theprincipleof inertia demands that we conceive of velocity as a sub-

stance. . . . How does it happen, then, that our mind accepts this

strange notion? . . . we accept it because it can serve to satisfythe causal tendency...."

(ii)

The theory of Parmenideswas not only the sophisticatedproduct

of a train of thought originallydue to the Ionian materialists, par-ticularly Anaximander. It was devised as a counterblast to an

entirely differenttheory of Nature, of the second of our three main

types. Pythagoras and his school, from whom Parmenidesmay have

broken away, maintained that the ultimate realities in Nature are

numbers.This arithmeticalype of naturalphilosophyshould be dis-

tinguished from the philosophicallycruderatomism of Democritus,in that the pluralityof numbersis not originalbut derived. Indeed,a

large partof

Pythagoreanarithmetic

appearsto have consisted

of a study of the varioussets obtainedby addingone unit to anotherto form geometricalpatterns. The unit itself, however,was regardedas indivisible, so that the Pythagorean model of the world was adiscontinuous ystem of invariantparticles,or small changelessunitsof finite size. Parmenidesrejected this number-atomism because it

seemed to him irrational that "One" could generate "Many." Thedifficultiesconsequent on the discovery of the incommensurabilityof the diagonal of a square also may have influencedhim; but the

coup de grdceto Pythagoreanismwas given by Parmenides'pupiland protagonist, Zeno of Elea, in his famous paradoxes.By appar-ently irrefutable logic he laid bare the Pythagorean confusionbetween the attributes of geometrical point, physical atom andnumerical unit. The influence of Zeno's arguments was decisive;henceforwardGreekthought eschewed"arithmetic,"the infinitepro-cess and monadology; moreover, time was regardedas contrary toreasonand, therefore,unreal.

A highly originaland ingeniousattempt to "save the phenomena"of individuality and to reconcile the "One "and the "Many" wasmade by Leibniz. In order to avoid the "Labyrinth of the Con-

tinuum," Leibniz suggested that the ultimate indivisible units of

reality are spatially unextended elements of consciousness(eitheractual or potential). To be truly individual, these monads must be

mutually independent. To reconcile this conception with the exist-ence of a single, universal world-order,he proposed his celebrated

principleof Pre-establishedHarmony, that each monad reflects the

I8

Page 16: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 16/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

same universe from one particularpoint of view out of an infinite

number,from every one of which some monad mirrorsit.

Leibniz was a Rationalist, believing that laws of nature are lawsof thought, but unlikehis predecessorshe drewa distinction betweentruths of pure reason, which are "necessary,"because they are dueto the principleof contradiction,and truths of fact, which are con-

tingent, as only a "sufficient"reason can be given why they shouldbe so and not otherwise.Propositionsdealingwith physicalexistencewere regardedby him as of this type. Only a sufficientreason canbe assigned to them,because their opposites are not self-contradic-

tory. This causal principlewas used to justify the pre-established

harmony. "Thenature of every simplesubstance,soul or true monadbeing such that its followingstate is a consequenceof the precedingone, here now is the cause of the harmonyfoundout. For God needs

only once to make a simple substance become once and at the

beginninga representationof the universe,according o its own pointof view; since from thence alone it follows that it will do so per-

petually; and that all simplesubstanceswill alwayshave a harmony

among themselves, because they always represent the same uni-

verse." It has beenobjected

that the monadsmight

runthroughtheir perceptionsat differentrates, but as they do not communicate

with each other this objectionis meaningless.

Althoughthe monads wereregardedas mutually independentand

Leibniz'slogic was foundedsolely on the subject-predicateconcept,he invented the relationalconceptsof space and time. He was led to

these conclusionsby applying the principleof sufficientreason. In

his third letter to Clarkehe wrote, "I say then that if space were

an absolutebeing, there wouldhappensomethingfor which it would

be impossible that there should be a sufficient reason. . . . Space issomething absolutely uniform, and, without the things situated in

it, one point of space does not differ in any respect from another

point of space. Now from this it follows that if we suppose space is

somethingin itself, other than the orderof bodies amongthemselves,it is impossiblethat thereshouldbe a reasonwhyGod,preserving he

same positions for bodies among themselves, should have arrangedbodies in space thus and not the other way round (for instance) by

changingeast and west. But if spaceis nothingother than this order

or relation and is nothing whatever without bodies but the possi-

bility of placing them in it, these two conditions, the one as thingsare, the other supposedthe other way round,would not differfrom

one another; their differenceexists only in our chimericalsupposi-tion of the reality of space in itself. . . . The same is true of time.

Suppose someone asks why God did not create everything a yearsooner; and that the same personwants to infer from that that God

B. Russell, A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz (900o), §79.

I9

Page 17: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 17/25

PHILOSOPHY

did somethingfor which He cannot possibly have had a reasonwhyHe did it thus ratherthan otherwise,we should reply that his infer-

ence would be true if time were something apart from temporalthings, for it would be impossiblethat there should be reasonswhythings should have been applied to certain instants rather than toothers, when their succession remained the same. But this itself

proves that instants apart from things are nothing, and that theyonly consist in the successive orderof things; and if this remainsthe

same, the one of the two states (for instance, that in which thecreation was imagined to have occurred a year earlier) would benowisedifferent and couldnot be distinguishedfromthe other which

now exists."From this line of reasoningwe see that, if we adopt the principle

that space is absolute, following Parmenides,then nothing else canexist rationally,and hence, correlatively,time must be not absolutebut non-existent; alternatively, space, and likewise time, must be"relative." The co-existence of absolute space and time with objectsin space and time, as in the Newtonian philosophy, leads to logicaland epistemological ifficulties. Idealist philosophers, e.g., Bradley,have taken their stand with

Parmenides;relations are contrary toreason and the world of Appearanceis an illusion. On the otherhand, the world of Appearance,whether "real" or "illusory,"is of

paramountinterest to the naturalphilosopher.Consequently,he en-deavours,as best he can, to reconcilethe existenceof physical objectswith the laws of thought. In so doing, his point of view has becomealmost inevitably "relativistic." Parodying Archimedes, he can

express his ambition thus: "Allow me 'relations'and I will recon-struct the apparentuniverse."

(iii)

The third of the three main types of cosmologicaltheory is thatin which the basic framework s conceived as a set of mutually de-

pendent entities which are capable, in principle,of communicatingwith each other. Einstein's Special Theory of Relativity is distin-

guished from Newton's Natural Philosophy by this difference, nteralia. There is no intercommunicationbetween the Cartesianframesin Newtonian-Galileansystems. Indeed, it is not accidental that, inorder to bring classical Kinematics into line with relativistic, the

signal velocity, c, must be assumed infinite in the former and socannot be used to measure intervals. In physical interpretation, cis taken to be the velocity of light, and, again,it may be not whollycoincidental that the first difficulties encountered by Newtonianphysics arose in interpreting the properties of light. Nevertheless,irrespective of the explanation of specific phenomena, there is a

20

Page 18: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 18/25

Page 19: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 19/25

PHILOSOPHY

less bydefinition. n particular,the classicallaw of the universal con-

stancy of the velocity of "light" in vacuocan becomea freelychosen

convention in a uniform material system. This is fundamental inKinematic Relativity.

V

KINEMATIC RELATIVITY

Kinematic Relativity is based on the abstractconcept of an ob-server, or mental monad, who experiencesa temporal before-and-after sequenceof events. The essential featuredefining his sequence

is its irreversibility.The co-existence of one other similar observerand of a signalling processof intercommunications sufficientto giveinitial content to the time concept, provided the two observersdonot coincide at all epochs. By definition, the signalling process issuch that the epoch of return of a signal, emitted by one observerand reflected instantaneouslyon arrival by the other, is later thanthe originalepoch of emission, except when the observerscoincide.Conventionaldefinitions can then immediately be assigned to themutual distance,etc., of the two observers.

Although comparison of the signals with light is not essentiala priori, it is physically suggestive and is reminiscentof the first actof Creation,"Let there be light."

The observersare assumedto satisfy the law of self-identity,viz.,A is A at all epochs. It is assumed that the epochs which can be

recorded,in principle,by A can be correlated with numbers,either

continuouslywith the continuum of real numbersor discontinuously.In the first elementary analysis, for ultimate comparisonwith simple

macroscopic physics, we adopt the former. (More sophisticated"quantum" refinementsmay be associated with the former,which

presumablywill give rise to epistemologicallymorereconditesystemsof dynamics.) In accordancewith our concept of scientificmethod,we stipulate that the correlation of epochs with numbersby twoobservers shall be equivalent, so that the observers are on a reci-

procal basis, keeping pace with each other. In this way the unda-mentalclockconceptcan bedefinedoperationally,or it can be provedthat any two observers can calibrate their clocks so that they are

equivalent. There is no need to invoke an arbitrary ontologicalpostulate concerning he measurementof time.

Thus, Kinematic Relativity begins arithmetically. To emphasizethis distinction from General Relativity, which aims at the geo-metrization f physics, we say that Kinematic Relativity aims at itsarithmetization.In this respectthe new method is in line with recent

developmentsin pure mathematics; for it has been shown that ele-

mentarygeometrycan be based on the sequenceof the integers,and,

22

Page 20: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 20/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

accordingto Brouwer,this sequencecan be related to our primitiveintuition of time.) However, it is convenient to introduce at as

early a stage as possible a typically geometricalconcept, correlativeto the purely arithmetical.The essential feature is reversibility. ustas two observersare sufficient o give initial content to the irreversibletime concept,so threearesufficient or the basic reversiblepace con-

cept. We freely choose a triad of observers, such that if a signal isemitted by any one, say A, is passed by another, B, to the third, C,then the time of reception by C must be the same as the time of

reception by A of the signal following the reverse "path," i.e.

travellingvia B and emitted by C at the same epoch by C'sclock as

the first signal was emitted by A, according to A's clock. This iscalled the axiom of reversibilityof "light" paths. It is the analoguein KinematicRelativity of the axiom, basic in all metric geometries,that the "length" of a path is independentof the sense in which it

is measured. This axiom eventually gives rise to conservation

theorems, just as the axiom of time-ordergives rise to theoremsofan irreversiblecharacter.

It can be proved mathematicallythat a quasi-continuoussystemof

observers, satisfyingthese

conditions,is describable at

will, byappropriatechoice of clock-graduation,i.e. epoch-numbercorrela-

tion, either as uniformly expanding from a point singularity at adefiniteepoch (t-time)or as static for all epochs (r-time). An infinityof other modes of description are possible, but these two, besides

being the simplest formally, ultimately appear to be the most

significant.This kinematic system is called an "equivalence."The next step

is to endow it with a definite geometrical form. This procedure

depends on adopting an appropriatetime-scale and a suitable con-vention formeasuring, n terms of clock readings,those "light"pathswhich do not begin or terminate at the observer. The appropriatetime-scaleis that associatedwith the static form of the equivalence.It is not difficultto show, then, how a "public"geometrycan be con-

structed, common to the whole system of observers. Thus, having

adopted appropriateconventions for expressing distances in terms

of the epochsof emissionand receptionof signals,it is not necessaryto invoke the idea of a rigid rod as a primitiveontologicalpostulate,in orderto give content to the useful notion of public space. Hence,the foundationsof KinematicRelativity underpinthose of "physical"

geometry.The existence of public space, subject to a concept of scientific

method which entails congruentmeasurement, mmediately suggeststhat the epistemologicallyappropriategeometriesof a static equiva-lence are homogeneous and isotropic. Consequently,in accordance

with our previousdiscussion,we concludethat the geometryof such

23

Page 21: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 21/25

PHILOSOPHY

an equivalence is either Euclidean, spherical or hyperbolic. When

considering hesystemas whole,there are reasons for assigningprior

consideration to the last, but much of the subsequent theory isapplicable,mutatismutandis, o systems based on either of the othertwo geometries. Locally,of course,all three are Euclidean.

So far an equivalencehas been consideredsimply as an abstractkinematicframework,analogous to the Cartesianframes of classicalkinematics.However, in naturalphilosophy attention is directed tothe problemof how a materialsystem can continue to exist from onestate to another. In Kinematic Relativity this transition from kine-matics to dynamics is made by associating with each observer a

"massiveparticle,"definedby a "causal"law. In a brilliant analysisof the axioms of mechanics, Painleve pointed out that the aim ofnatural philosophy has been to deduce the phenomena of motion

rigorously from a principleof causality. In the past this principlehas usuallybeen taken to assert that, when the same conditions arerealized at two different instants in two parts of space, the same

phenomena reproduce themselves, only transported in space andtime. After some discussion of measurement in classical mechanics,Painleve

concluded:I"Il est

possible d'adopterune fois

pourtoutes

et pourtous les phenomenesune mesure des longueurset une mesuredes temps telle que le principe de causalite soit vrai toujours et

partout.Voila le principe,ou, si on veut, le postulat fondamental,quiest inscrit en tete de la science."

However, in Kinematic Relativity there is no need to invoke anadditionalpostulate of this type, with its arbitraryeliminationof the

possibility of variation in time. Instead, the equivalenceof massive

particles, now called a substratum, needs to be submitted only to

the two principlesof "identity" and "sufficientreason." Together,these constitute an effective "causal"law. The formerimplies thateach massive particle should be anchored to a definite equivalentobserver, while the latter necessitates that the symmetry of the"causes" must persist in the symmetry of the "effects" and viceversa. Consequently,since each equivalent observer is at a centreof kinematic symmetry, it follows that each massive particle asso-ciated with such an observer must be at a centre of dynamic sym-metry. The mass distribution of a substratum must be compatiblewith this law. In general,we deduce that, if a substratum is not

sphericallysymmetrical about each observer, it cannot satisfy the

principleof dynamic permanence,unless certain constraints are in-troducedad hoc.Hence, if a substratumis regardedas an epistemo-logically primitive construct, it must be spherically symmetricalabout each constituent observer. Such a substratumis readily seento be completelydescribable n identicaltermsby each suchobserver.

I P. Painleve, Les Axiomes de la Meconique (I922), p. II.

Page 22: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 22/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

Thus we find that a substratum must satisfy a "harmony"whichneed not be postulatedas pre-established n its entirety.

The next stage in building up our generalabstract natural philo-sophy is to investigate the motion of a free particle. By a lengthytrain of mathematicalreasoning, t canbe shownthat this is uniquelydeterminedby the properties alreadyassignedto the substratum.Noadditional postulate is required. Of course, the description of thismotion depends on the scale of time adopted, but in the r-scale,

according to which the substratum is static, it is rectilinear anduniform. Hence, in this system of natural philosophy, the law

of inertia can be derivedfrom epistemologically rimitive axioms.

Moreover, in agreement with the ideas of Mach, it refers to freemotion against a (continuous) backgroundof "massive" bodies andnot in chimericalempty space.

Furthermore,we can investigate the hierarchyof laws of different

degrees of complexity (vector, second order tensor, etc.) which isdeterminedautomaticallyby the definingcharacteristicsof the sub-

stratum, just as, for example, in Euclideangeometrywe can analysethe hierarchyof curves, etc., of differentorders to which the axioms

giverise. The

comparisonof the

straight lines, circles, parabolas,ellipses, etc., of theoretical geometry with those of mensuration hasits analogue in the comparisonof the laws of the substratum withthe laws of dynamics, electro-dynamics, etc., which appear to be

empiricallysignificant.At presenta limited numberof special postu-lates, e.g., spatial tri-dimensionality,must be invoked to accountfor the laws of gravitation and electromagnetism.However,no addi-tional postulate is requiredto derive the general laws of dynamics,although it is necessary to adopt the t-scale in order to effect the

derivation mathematically. The results can be translated into ther-scale, and the central question of this essay can then be answered.

An elementarysystem of dynamics,similarto Newton's, with certain

relativistic modifications, can be derived from epistemologically

primitiveaxiomsin a manneranalogousto the Helmholtz-Liederiva-

tion of the three elementary geometries of constant curvature.

Moreover,just as these geometries can be formally translated one

into another, so alternative forms of elementary dynamics can be

constructedby appropriatere-graduationsof time-scale.

VI

CONCLUSION

As already remarked, axioms, such as those of geometry, were

regardeduntil recent times as self-evident truths. When they came

to be regardedas conventional, it was natural that reasons should

be sought why one system of axioms should be chosen rather than

25

Page 23: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 23/25

Page 24: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 24/25

NATURAL PHILOSOPHY

famousanalogy with the matching by a geometricalmesh of a whitesurface studded with black spots. The fact that a particularmesh

gives the best fit, e.g., square or triangular of a definite fineness,wouldappearto be arbitrary. ucha conceptionof naturalphilosophymakes its intrinsicsimplicityinexplicable.

Likewise, the failure of the a priori metaphysical theories of

Nature, constructed by the great speculative philosophers of the

past, was mainly due to the adoption of insufficientlyanalysedarbi-

trary assumptions.By reducing he numberof arbitraryassumptions,we increaseour expectation that natural philosophy will provide a

powerful method of interpreting physical phenomena. Thus, New-

ton's mechanics,Einstein's Relativity and Milne'sKinematic Rela-tivity are successive approximationsto an ideal system of natural

philosophy,basedsolelyon the conceptof scientificmethod,regardedas a policy of congruent selection and measurementof phenomenaby an appropriatelydefinedcommunityof hypothetical observers.

The assertion that Kinematic Relativity is a more satisfactorysystem of natural philosophythan previous theories has not passedwithout challenge.For example, Ayer has criticizedMilne'sclaim tohave derived certain laws of nature a

priori.He

writesI". .. the

question whether physics can be made to attain the status of a

geometryhas nothing directlyto do with the characterof the physicalworld,or even with the characterof our knowledgeof it. It is simplya matter of one's being able to organizethe acceptedlaws of physicsinto a self-consistentdeductive system, and then choosing to regardthe premises of this system, not as propositions about matters of

fact, but as implicit definitions. . . . For no one would say that a

propositionexpresseda law of naturemerelybecauseit was assigned

a place in some self-consistent abstract system. . . . Indeed, Milnehimselfhas stated that 'non-verifiablepropositionsabout the worldof nature have no significant content.' But how, then, are we toaccount for his asserting,as he does, that 'it is possible to derivethelaws of dynamicsrationallywithout recourse to experience?'" Theanswer to such criticism is that Kinematic Relativity is not just"some self-consistentabstract system." As we have seen, it can beconstructed as the unique product of a fundamentalconception ofscientific method which is almost completely devoid of arbitraryelements.

Thus, the primitivecongruentforms which we seek to identify, or

approximateto, in Nature can be deduced without initial appeal to

experienceor, more accurately speaking, with a vestigial minimumof such appeal.

In a recent lecture,2Max Born has drawn attention to the fact, A. J. Ayer, The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge (I940), p. 205.2 M. Born, Experiment and Theory in Physics (I943), p. 44.

27

Page 25: Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

8/6/2019 Epistemological Fundation Natural Philosophy (G J Whitrow)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/epistemological-fundation-natural-philosophy-g-j-whitrow 25/25

PHILOSOPHY

that the rival theories of cosmology due to Milne and Eddington,

respectively, both claim to be based on a priori principles, but are

"widely different and contradictory." At first sight this appears tobe a cogent argument for discrediting both. However, Born does not

indicate that, whereas Eddington's theory is entirely concerned with

the actual physical objects which he believes must exist, Milne's

theory falls into two distinct divisions. In that which happened to be

developed first but is logically secondary, the problem considered is

the detailed description of the material universe, suitably "idealised."

The results are indicative rather than necessary. In the other division,Milne has examined the laws which flow automatically from a funda-

mental concept of scientific method applied to the most primitivematerial system, which is itself defined as far as possible by this

concept. (The validity of this "physical" division is entirely inde-

pendent of that of the former "astronomical" division.) There is no

counterpart of this analysis in Eddington's work where, inter alia,the law of inertia is taken as primitive. It is analogous to the attemptof Russell and Whitehead to derive pure mathematics from logic.

I began this essay with a paradox. We now see that some lighthas been thrown on its

possibleresolution. A

prophetic paragraphby WhewellI comes to mind. I suggest that it be modified slightly

by substituting "scientific method" for "cause" and "causation."

. . . "It is a Paradox that experience should lead us to truths con-

fessedly universal and apparently necessary, such as the Laws of

Motion are. The Solution of this paradox is that these laws are inter-

pretations of the axiom of causation. The laws are universally and

necessarily true, but the right interpretation of the terms which theyinvolve is learnt by experience. Our Idea of Cause supplies the Form;

Experience, the Matter of these Laws."I W. Whewell, The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (I840), p. 28.