38
1 Pekka Ihanainen (ihanainenpekka_gmail.com); +358 400 540868) SCHOOL AND INSTRUCTION - ARE THEY REVOLUTIONARILY IMP- ROVABLE Nowadays the discussion about schools and instruction is a major theme in reflecting the applicability of the cognitive approach. Most texts are based on specific empirical studies, and try to describe and understand some particular learning or educational question. Despite many attempts, there has not been very remarkable success: "... no revolutionary improvements in the design of instruction have as yet been derived from such research (Ohlson, 1990, 561)." The Gibsonian ecological psychology has radically criticized cognitive approaches (Gibson,1979, 238-263; Turvey, Shaw, Reed & Mace, 1981), but one might also ask, if it has anything to offer with regard to the practical questions of behavior. However, in this paper, I shall take the Gibsonian approach as a starting point. I shall begin by reflecting on the ecological conception of learning and proceed to questions of social perception and, especially, social affordances. These work as inspirative instruments in an effort to critically surmise today's school and produce fresh ideas for developing the school system and instruction. LEARNING: WHAT IS IT When we try to examine school and instruction, it is natural to start with the question of learning. The task of school and instruction is to help and support students to learn. The

Schoolandinstruction Aretheyrevolutionarilyimprovable 091201141313 Phpapp01

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

1

Pekka Ihanainen(ihanainenpekka_gmail.com);+358 400 540868)

SCHOOL AND INSTRUCTION - ARE THEY REVOLUTIONARILY IMPROVABLE

Nowadays the discussion about schools and instruction is a major theme in

reflecting the applicability of the cognitive approach. Most texts are

based on specific empirical studies, and try to describe and understand

some particular learning or educational question. Despite many attempts,

there has not been very remarkable success: "... no revolutionary imp-

rovements in the design of instruction have as yet been derived from such

research (Ohlson, 1990, 561)."

The Gibsonian ecological psychology has radically criticized cognitive

approaches (Gibson,1979, 238-263; Turvey, Shaw, Reed & Mace, 1981), but

one might also ask, if it has anything to offer with regard to the practical

questions of behavior. However, in this paper, I shall take the Gibsonian

approach as a starting point.

I shall begin by reflecting on the ecological conception of learning and

proceed to questions of social perception and, especially, social

affordances. These work as inspirative instruments in an effort to critically

surmise today's school and produce fresh ideas for developing the school

system and instruction.

LEARNING: WHAT IS IT

When we try to examine school and instruction, it is natural to start with the

question of learning. The task of school and instruction is to help and

support students to learn. The question is: what is learning and what kind of

learning does school and instruction afford?

Within the ecological interpretation, learning, as a quality of the human

being, is an ecosystemic phenomenon (Michaels & Carello, 1981; Turvey &

2

Shaw, 1979). Learning takes place in a human - environment system. It is

not an event, which goes on inside the individual. The human environment is

primarily social. There are, of course, physical and natural surroundings, but

they are normally encountered with other people.

As social event, learning can be compared to evolution (Michaels & Carello,

1981). It is not a long-term event such as evolution, but it lasts throughout

life, in that he/she participates in his/her community and society. As an

evolution-like phenomenon, learning is an adaptive process in(side) the

social environment that the individual takes part in (Johnston & Turvey,

1980).

Learning can be defined as an adaptive and social process in the human-

environment system. As social beings we interact with other people. It is

our normal every-day situation. In the interaction we perceive, first and

foremost, what is most essential to our adaptive activity. For instance,

anger and anxiety are perceived first, because they are most essential to a

person's adaptive behavior (McArthur & Baron, 1983, 219-220). What is

essential to our adaptive behavior, depends on the culture and social setting

we are participating in. In addition, the significance of adaptation is in

maintaining survival to carry out the goal attainment of the individual.

But what do we mean by saying that learning is social and adaptive. To

answer that question one has to examine and focus on the ecological

conception of social perception and social affordances. Thematically it could

be suggested that adaptive learning is learning to perceive and use social

affordances. (People, of course, perceive natural objects and events and

also those made by themselves, but the human situation is that normally

people perceive them in a shared social environment). In the educational

context it could be said that school and instructional instruments, operations

and processes are social affordances which students learn to perceive and

use.

SOCIAL PERCEPTION AND SOCIAL AFFORDANCES

Social perception might be understood in two ways: 1) as perception of

other people (visual aspects, age, gender, movement etc.; the intentions

3

and attentions of others; emotions etc.), 2) as a socially constituted

phenomenon (perceiving takes place in a particular society, in specific

communities, social groups and in interaction with other people) (cf. Va-

lenti & Good, 1991).

Social perception is perceiving of social affordances. In the following I shall

concentrate on the description of social affordances.

A classic example of social affordances is Gibson's (1979) post- box. It is an

affordance which includes the whole postal system from writing a letter to

receiving and reading it. Initially little children do not perceive it as a

postbox, but learn it through enculturation (see Smith & Ginsburg, 1989,

36). Actually all human made products are social affordances like the

postbox, their systemic expanse may vary, but they remain social

affordances.

It is possible to state that all physical cultural objects, places and events are

social affordances, and to perceive them directly, without mental mediation.

Together with physical products one has to think of other people as social

affordances, too.

Ecologically oriented research has perceived that there are individual and

interaction aspects within people, which can be directly perceived (reviewed

for instance in McArthur & Baron, 1983; Baron & Boundreau, 1987; Smith &

Ginsburg, 1989; Valenti & Good, 1991). They are social affordances, which

can be detected via invariants in faces, postures and gestures, behavioral

movements, voices, and in interaction and cooperation structures.

These studies have also revealed that the perceiver can pick up the age,

gender and the style of movement (walking for instance) from the stimulus

information the person offers. It has also been indicated that the perceiver

can detect what a person is going to do (intentions) and on what he/she has

focused his/her attention.

Emotions are also social affordances, i.e., anger affords avoiding and joy

encourages approaching. Also personal abilities or dispositions are

detectable: dominance, shyness, aggressiveness, nurtureness etc. However,

the detection of these dispositions is possible only in dyads or groups, not in

single persons. When a person is perceived as an affordance, it might be

4

possible that the personal type could also be picked up directly from the

stimulus array the person includes in himself (Baron & Boudreau, 1987).

Baron and Boudreau also suggest that it might be better to see attitudes as

affordances, when considering their function in social interaction. It could be

intuitively asked, if values are also directly detectably from the stimulus

array that the person contacted affords.

Linguistic expressions could also be interpereted as affordances (see

Verbrugge, 1985; Chapter III). It could be suggested that they are primarily

social affordances. The understanding and use of language have developed

and develop in social settings, where people have learned and learn to

detect the associations of perceptual-actional objects, places and events,

and the linguistic expressions that indicate them, and then, gradually learn

to use them predicatively (see also Dent, 1990 and Zukow, 1990). Words

and sentences are the same kind of social affordances as for instance

"Gibson's postbox". They are more or less complex social arrangements, and

are perceived directly (if they are!) as the postbox is perceived as a whole

postal system.

In social encounters we interact and cooperate with each other. In these

encounters we perceive the dynamic structure of intentions, attentions,

emotions, personality expressions etc. Through perceiving those social

affordances, their structure and changes, it is possible for us to detect the

interaction and cooperation that the situation requires, and to adapt

ourselves to them. It could be said that interaction and cooperation are also

social affordances that the person in interaction and cooperation is able to

perceive and then to behave in accordance with his or her perception.

Using language - speaking, asking, answering etc. and discussion - is an

essential part of communication. It might be thought that linguistic

communication as a totality is also a social affordance. It affords something

and can be detected from the social setting, where the communication

takes place. What it might afford, is a research question, which has not yet

been - as far as I know - answered.

However, it could be suggested that communication affords that specific

linguistic society or community, wherein the individuals are participating,

and it's manner of perception and behavior. Using "Gibsonian jargon" it

could be said that communication affords the perceptual-actional

5

attunement of the linguistic community. Linguistic communication in some

science society, the way of discussion in some industrial work society, and

the language of instruction and studying in some school affords it's

perceptual-actional attunement.

The description of social affordances can be summarized by the

following figure.

┌─────────────────────────────────────────────────┐ ┤ ┌──────────────────────────────┐ │ │encounters in │ physical objects, places │ │ │social context │ and events in social setting │ │ │(adaptation) <─>└──────┬─────┬─────────────────┘ ││ │ │ │ │ │ ┌──────────────────┴─────┴─────────────────┐ │ │ │ people/companions │ │ │ │ in social setting │ │ │ │ -intentions - interaction and │ │ │ │ -attentions cooperation │ │ │ │ -perceptual structures │ │ │ │ awareness to be - communication │ ││ │ realised in structures │ ││ │ language use │ ││ │ -emotions │ ││ │ -personality │ ││ │ dispositions and │ ││ │ type │ ││ │ -attitudes │ ││ │ -values │ │

6

│ └──────────────────────────────────────────┘ │└─────────────────────────────────────────────────┘

Figure 1: The complex of social affordance.

This summary is to be interpreted as the physical environment and social

reality being perceived directly as they objectively exist, and they are used

to adapt to that social situation, which is formed by those specific physical

and other people's social affordances that the social setting includes.

The nature of social affordances

Affordances are historical and contextual, especially social affordances

(Reed, 1989). This means that when considering the nature of social

affordances, one has to study their involvement with the developing and

actual culture. They are culturally mediated, which does not mean mental

mediation.

On "a macro level" social affordances and their perception is entangled with

the existing culture, for instance, western. A book, for instance is quite a

different social affordance for an American and a Finn than for a member of

some primitive culture. But it might be different for an American and Finn,

too. In American and Finnish culture the book might have a different status

for the average person, and for that reason the perceptual-actional

attunement to the book is dissimilar for Americans and Finns.

On "a middle level" the attunement to social affordances is bound to a real

and actional functional gathering of interacting people. It could be called

the attunement enveloped by the community. Let us take a book as an

example again. In an university community a book is a part of the scientific

system: research, reporting, popularizing. As an instrument of university

work a book is encountered for instance in preparing for exams (readin-

g), in making summaries, as a source of studies etc. They all form the

perception and use of a book in a way that is specific to the scientific

community.

In every-day use, in life or residental communities, a book is a social

arrangement, which includes a writer, printing house, bookshop, library etc.

For the average person a book might be a status object, it is associated with

7

free time, for instance. This kind of aspect might form the perception and

use of the book, which is specific to the inhabiting communities of middle-

class people.

In school communities a book has it's own "habitus". It is part of the whole

school system: an instrument for teaching and learning, a source of tasks, a

substance for exams etc. For a student it is mainly a given object of the

school system, not an object of self interest. It is a tool for studying and

especially for spending time with homework. These characteristics

constitute the perception and use of the book, which is particular to school

communities.

When a social affordance is examined from within some social group, on "a

micro level", its perception receives finer substance for attunement. If we

imagine that there are three subgroups in the classroom - those who

conscientiously participate in formal instruction, those who are interested in

the subject outside the school (e.g. rock-fans) and students, for whom sports

is "a question of life", and think what kind of affordance a book might be

afforded to them, we could get the following "definitions".

The concientiously participating perceive and use a book as an important

working instrument, rock-fans perceive and use it as a belittled tool and

athletes perceive and use it as a selectively interesting instrument. These

are presumed descriptions only, but it is possible to show by them, how the

social affordances are constituted in particular social groups or subgroups.

Personal values, intentions, emotions etc. also "colour" the attunement to

perceive and work with affordances. You might see a book as an object into

which one enters into. It might be an object in which one sinks emotionally

or reads as an outsider. The book could be glanceable, utilizeble etc.

THE ORIGIN OF SOCIAL AFFORDANCES

In the previous chapter I described how social affordances are contextual

and historical. In brief this means that social affordances are born and

develop in historically changing interaction and cooperation situations, in

which people take part.

8

Human interaction and cooperation are behaviors which might be called

intentional. They are not activity in itself, but activity which somehow is

directed to something. The goal of the activity might be unconscious, but it

has some more or less obvious goal. And when the task is to consider the

origin or genesis of social affordances, attention has to focus on the question

of intentions and intentionality.

Intentionality contexts as roots for social affordances

According to Reed (1989), and Turvey and Kugler (1987) intentions can be

crystallized as follows: intentions are realized in the relationships of agent

and his/her task environments, they are the processual ability of the agent,

who is perceiving and performing in some task context. The essential thing

in trying to define intentions is the content of intentions (see Searle, 1983:

"conditions of satisfaction"). As an experienced phenomenon intentions are

some kind energy or force, which individuals have, but that does not tell

much about the substantial quality of intentions. It has to find out, what

really is the content of intentions.

In this paper I will just present a definition of intentions as a given thing (for

a more detail reflection, see chapter IV; about the question of the intention

to use affordances, see Reed, 1989). The content of intentions is the

activity, which individuals alone or as social partners or groups maintain in

the human-environment system.

For instance, when I intend to write about social affordances, the content of

my intention is the process of the activity, which I carry out when I read

texts about social affordances, when I think about them, and when I write

about them. The content of my intention to write about social affordances is

also formed in the discussions and cooperation which I have with my

colleagues, and in the communicative interaction in conference groups or

the like, in which I participate to deepen my conceptions about social

affordances.

These more or less social situations, in which activities happen, are

intentionality contexts, in which social affordances are born and develop.

If we think about ecological social realities in which people participate -

especially family, peer and interest group situations, and school, work and

free time communities - they are those intentionality contexts, mentioned

9

above, and social affordances are firmly established in them.

Cultural and communal environments, and social settings have to be

examined as situations, which "create" both the observeable social

affordances and the attunement of individuals to perceive and use social

affordances. The former are examined earlier in this paper, and I shall now

briefly consider the latter.

The content of the activity (or the actual interaction and cooperation or the

intentionality context), might be the kind that constitutes the perceptual-

actional attunement of aspirement or creating a career and competition.

This kind of attunement contributes to the perception, action, interaction

and cooperation, in which the affordances are encountered. For instance a

colleague might be perceived as an opponent, not as a partner of coopera-

tion.

Intentionality contexts might also constitute the attunement of reclaiming

expectations or established aims, the attunement of finding and developing

oneself, the attunement of indifference or insignificance etc., and these

attunements are the basis for encountering other people for example as

authorities, companions or "non-persons" etc. Of course it is possible to see

a different kind of attunement than the previously mentioned. They are my

personal examples of attunement that intentionality contexts might

"produce".

After this general discussion about intentionality contexts as the origins of

social affordances, I will proceed to the contemplation of schools as

intentionality contexts, which constitute social affordances of the school

today.

THE SCHOOL AS AN INTENTIONALITY CONTEXT: THE QUALITY OF

SCHOOL AFFORDANCES

It might already sound tautological to say that school - as every other social

institute - basically grows from the interaction and cooperation people

implement, and it might be claimed that the interaction and cooperation

people upheld in school has to made explicit. This is worth doing, but in this

10

presentation I will not concentrate on it and just take for granted that

interaction and cooperation are the basis of intentionality and social

affordances.

The school is a culture institute, and has especially developed in the

industrial world. It is an essential part of industrial (division of labour)

societies. One of the important features of industrial societies is that all

segments of life are institutionally distributed: the school is a place for

education and training, work places are a habitat for survival and produc-

tion, free time events are also diverged as many kinds of institutional

spheres which try to uphold a meaningful life that has a tendency to

disappear in the scattering process of the industrial (modern) life style.

As a fragment of industrial life, school retains the splintering of society.

School has the interaction and cooperation forms, which are specific to the

schools of the industrial world, and that is why the school can or has to be

apart from the other spheres of society. That means that, interpreted as

intentionality context, the content of interaction and cooperation, which

goes on in the schools, creates and develop social affordances, which af ford

differentiateness. The perception and use of these affordances educates

attunement, which has the quality of spliting and shattering oneself.

Interpreted as a culture institute the school is part of the whole industrial

world. The school can also be interpreted as a social institute, which means

that the interaction and cooperation that takes place in the school maintain

the economic and ideological purposes the society has. In western societies

these goals are the reproducing of the labour force, the retaining of the

existing power and submission relationships, and the isolation of teachers

and students from the external society and their preservation into an

"introvert" school.

The interaction and cooperation forms that function as means of economic

and ideological purposes of western societies, generate and elaborate the

intentionality contexts of the school in the western industrial world.

The reproduction of the labour force and the interaction and cooperation

forms included in it create and develop an intentionality context that can

be described as a maintenance of the do minating society and the

relationships in it. This kind of intentionality context is the basis on which

11

social affordances arise, and where one perceives and works with them.

There are, of course, many social affordances in this kind social context, but

their quality could be defined as following the social beha vior of previous

generations: school as a social institute af fords the repeating of the existing

social arrangements.

The retaining of the existing power and submission relationships produces

and keeps up social layers, and preserves authority structures that are

included in society. As an intentionality context the interaction and

coordination activities, which these power and submission relationships

constitute, can be depicted as the supporting of inequality and the

demanding of obedience. The social affordances, which rise from this kind of

activity, have the character of subserviency. It is also the sound of the at-

tunement or resonation, which this kind of intentionality context generates.

The isolation and preservation means that the interaction and cooperation is

directed at the internal processes and problems of the school. The

orientation to the external questions of the society is only a curiosity.

Students, for instance, might have a task to analyse and describe the

content of a newspaper.

The activities in the situation of isolation and preservation maintain artificial

group coherence, because "the work, which is done at school", has no

relevance to real activities in society - school work is almost always some

kind game of outsiders. Artificial coherence is actually real anguishing lo-

neliness, and there are also many students and teachers, who are in fact

alone in the schools today.

It could be noted that schools, which have a stutus of isolation and

preservation, are the intentionality context of a solitary and individual

(private) interaction and cooperation. In fact, it means that the activity,

which occurs in an atmosphere of isolation and preservation affords no

interaction and cooperation, but privateness. It is also the "colour" of

attunement, which this kind of intentionality context "procreates".

After describing the school as an intentionality context of the existing

culture and society, I will proceed to the study of the teaching and learning

situations of the school.

12

The school includes two main interaction and cooperation processes: the

mediation of a subject matter (knowledge) and social participation (see for

a more detailed examination chapter II). I suggest that they are fullfilled as

unconnected processes. It can be observed for instance by examining how

they go on in the structures of the work at schools. The mediating of subject

matter happens in accordance with the structure of the curriculum: periods

of teaching of some subject. The social participation in school life takes

place in accordance with a timetable structure: lesson, break, lesson etc.,

school day, school week etc. This means that mediating the subject matter

and participating in school life do not run into each other; they proceed in

different cycles.

These two interaction and cooperation processes of schools are the basis for

my interpretation of the intentionality contexts which the teaching and

learning situations of the school might generate (see Chapter IV for the more

detailed treatment of the topic).

It might be felt that the primary activity of school is mainly focused on

mediating subject matters or social participation. The first mentioned is a

situation, where the teacher transmits the teaching substance (knowledge)

to the students, who are the objects of transmitting. The teacher is the

distributor of knowledge, and his/her task is to carry out the cognitive

instruction. The teaching is teacher-centered. I call this kind of interaction

an event of distribution of know le dge.

The student's activity might be more durable than that which takes place

during instruction, which barely transmits knowledge. The students can ac-

quire the required knowledge by themselves. The teacher's duty is to put

forth materials for acquiring knowledge and to guide students. The teaching

is student-centered. This kind of interaction I call an event of acquiring

knowledge.

The interaction might also have a content, by which there is an attempt to

mediate the cognitive substance through social interplay. In a way a teacher

is the leader of a social group, and the task of the students is to handle the

cognitive matter in social events. This kind of interaction I call an event of

so cial inte racti on, which is cognitively oriented .

If the focus of interaction is on social cooperation and interplay, it means

13

that the teaching situation is understood as one event in a shared social life

among teachers and students. The cognitive aims and activity do not have a

specific purpose; they become the content of interaction, if the situation

allows it. The teacher is an equal adult member of the group, and the pri-

mary task of the group is the developing of social relations and group

forming. This kind of interaction might be called an event of social

interaction, which does not have a specific cog nitive function .

The described types of teaching and learning interaction (of course they are

mixed many ways in real settings) are the field for intentionality contexts

that the school settings include.

The instruction, which transmits knowledge can be characterised as

repeating and imitating. The students are mainly passive. The participation

is external: a teacher repeats the given substance and students are

subjectless objects. Sociability is not permitted into a teaching situation.

Both the teacher and students have to mask it in their behavior which

means the denying or nullifying of oneself as a social being. The interaction

is mainly the encountering of the things to teach and learn, not human

intercourse.

This kind of relationship between agents and their interaction environment

creates an intentionality context, which is possible to define as extinguished

reactivity to "ready offered" teaching substance. Teaching is a reacting

activity to fulfil the transmitting of the required knowledge. Studying is a

reacting answering and the like to the reactions of a teacher. The reactions

of teachers and students are extinguished, because they do not have in-

ternal motivation to interact.

The extinguished reactivity is the basis for social affordances of school

events, which only transmits knowledge. It also gives the quality for the

attunement of individuals and the social setting they establish.

In instruction, in which knowledge is acquired, the activity of teachers

and students is not independent, but controlled. A teacher's activity is

directed by cognitive aims, and the actions of students by operations of

the teacher. The social events are used to implement instructional aims.

This kind of interaction and cooperation creates an intentionality

14

context, which I define as directed activity, which is concentrated on tasks. It

is the basis for social affordances and attunement to them.

In instruction, which can be characterized as social interaction

and cognitively oriented, social participation is the basis of the

instruction. The instruction does not have an "open" character, but there is

an attempt to utilize it in practicing cognitive instruction. Social participation

is manipulative and supervised.

This conflict between real and instrumental participation creates an

intentionality context, which might be defined as social cooperation, which

takes place in the tension between real and instrumental participation or in

other words conditional coope ration . This is the field where social

affordances develop, and they are perceived and used. It is also a context

wherein attention can be educated and attuned to encounter social affor-

dances.

In instruction, which takes place as social interaction, but has no

special cognitive function, social events are to be participated in as they

are happening. There is no attempt to utilize them. The participation is

personal, and cognitive tasks and problems are born in this real

participation.

This kind of interaction and cooperation generate an intentionality

context, which could be defined as social cooperati on which is maintained

by personal interaction or in short as authentic cooperation. It is the basis

for social affordances and the perceiving and using of them.

The social settings in teaching and learning activities are nowadays- I would

suggest - mainly the ones of either transmitting or acquiring of knowledge.

This means that the intentionality contexts which take place in the school

settings are mostly ones which can be characterized as extinguished

reactivity to "ready offered" teaching substance and directed activity which

is concentrated on given tasks. They give the quality for social affordances

in these settings: the afforded interaction and cooperation is external,

passive, repeating and controlled. If the interaction proceeds in trying to

establish real social participation, there is a tendency for it to be realized as

an instrumental activity and utilized for cognitive purposes.

15

It is now possible to draw a picture of social affordances within the schools

of today. As a culture and society institute, the school affords

differentiateness and attunement for splitting and shattering oneself, the

repeating of the existing social arrangements, and the subserviency and

privateness (not interaction and cooperation). And the singular social

settings of schools afford only external, passive, repeating, controlled and

inst rumental activity.

When considering the social affordances of the school developed over the

previous pages, it is essential to notice that they are nes ted . What a single

setting affords is nested in the affordances the school has as a cultural and

social institute. All these social affordances are directly perceivable. They

might be only perceptual awareness, not conscious experience, but they are

- in any case - the world, which the teachers and students encounter in their

everyday life at school. They are the social reality which educate the

attention and attunement of people who participate in today's schools.

Social affordances of the school and the hidden curriculum

The situation of the school described above from the perspective of social

affordances is examined especially by educational sociologists (see Giroux,

A., Penna, A., 1979; Apple, M., King, N., 1977; Jackson, P., 1968). They

point out that existing social and economic institutions are maintained by

the curriculum system, classroom teaching and evaluation of today's school

(hidden curriculum).

The normative and dispositional social and economic meanings

(affordances) in the hidden curriculum are communicated to students by

the forms of interactions of school life. Students internalize (become attuned

16

to) the values of respecting authority, punctuality, cleanliness, docility and

conformity. They learn to be members of crowds, potential receivers of

praise or reproof, and pawns of institutional authorities.

This all happens in the life of today's school, which affords waiting to use

resources, posponing or giving up desires, being quiet, being isolated in a

crowd, being patient with respect to authority, suffering in silence, and

bearing the continued delay, denial and interruption of personal wishes and

desires.

Is it possible to see an alternative? Educational sociologists (see e.g.

Aronowitz, S., Giroux, H., 1991) have tried to approach the solution of

school problems by developing a new image of the teacher. S/he is

especially a public intellectual, who tries to be a critical member of the

whole society, not only a participant in a school institute. This work is to be

done by using border pedagogy, which educates critical and independent

citizens. But what would be the alternative, and having it's roots in the

ecological conception of learning and sociability? I will next proceed to

examine that question.

LEARNING AND INSTRUCTION RESTATED

The ecological conception about learning rests on sociability. Learning is a

social phenomenon, which happens in all those interaction and cooperation

situations where people are and work together. The social situation

determines what kind of learning could take place. In the previous pages I

have provided a brief outline of learning situations which are common in the

western school system of today.

The interpretation of school affordances has been critical. Is it possible to

see some other alternative? Could the ecological point of view offer new

social situations and contexts, where pedagogy inspired by the Gibsonian

approach could take place.

The modification of the Zone of Proximal Development

My starting point in this work is the idea of the Zone of Pro ximal

17

Development. It's origin is in the Vygotskian tradition (Vygotski, 1978;

Wertsch, 1984; Valsiner, 1984). Reed (1989) has given new substance to it

from an ecological perspective. I will now proceed first to briefly describe

the Vygotskian conception of the Zone of Proximal Development (ZPD) and

then present the modulation of it made by Reed, and finally my own inter-

pretation.

Vygotsky (1978,86) defines ZPD as "the distance between the actual

developmental level as determined by individual problem solving and the

level of potential development as determined through problem solving under

adult guidance or in collaboration with more capable peers. The Zone of

Proximal Development defines those functions that have not yet matured

but are in the process of maturation, functions that will mature tomorrow but

are currently in an embryonic state. These functions could be termed the

"buds" or "flowers" of development rather than the "fruits" of development."

In the neo-vygotskian movement Wertsch (1984) for instance has focused

on the problem of guidance carried out by adults and cooperation with

more capable peers. He proposes that to understand the mechanism of

guidance and cooperation, it has to comprehend the situation definition,

intersubjectivity and semiotic mediation, which takes place in learning and

instruction processes inside the ZPD. The development through the ZPD can

be explained as redefinition of the situation. It happens through intersub-

jectivity of learners and adult and peers. The intersubjectivity, in which the

redefinition occurs, is carried out through semiotic mediation.

Tharp and Gallimore (1988, 33-39) examine ZPD in the school context. They

describe four stages of ZPD, through which assisting performance develops.

In the first stage, performance is assisted by more capable others, and the

task of that stage is the transferring from the regulation of others to

self-regulation in assisting. During the second stage, the performance is as-

sisted by oneself (speaking aloud for instance). However, this does not mean

that performance is fully developed or automatized. In the third stage, the

performance is developing and automatized. It is not dependent on others or

self-assistance. Inside the fourth stage, the performance might de-

automatize, which leads to falling to previous stages. Tharp and Gallimore

note "that de-automatization and recursion occur so regularly that they

constitute the fourth stage in the normal development process".

18

Valsiner's (1984, 66-67) model of ZPD has connections to the Gibsonian

approach. He writes that the idea that "the structure of child's environment

defines the set of possible actions that are available to the child at the given

state of environment ... is closely related to the concept of affordance in

contemporary ecological psychology." According to Valsiner "the major

function of adult-child interaction from the perspective of child development

lies in the regulation of child-environment relationships."

Valsiner develops Vygotskian ZPD as following: it consists of the Zone of

Free Movement (ZFM) and the Zones of Promoted Actions (ZPA). The ZFM

structures the child's access to different areas in the environment, and it is

a changing and socially constructed structure of the child-environment

relationship. Inside the ZFM it is possible to specify subzones that organize

the child-environment relationship further. These are the ZPA, where

assistants attempt to promote certain actions with particular objects and

events.

Reed (1989, 36) takes the previously mentioned concepts of Valsiner as

starting points, when he develops the ecological modification of the Zone of

Proximal Development. He enlarges them to systemic human-environment

fields, inside which development goes on. He calls them Field of

Promoted Action (FPA) and Field of Free Action (FFA).

The FPA encompasses the affordances to which a child`s (or adult`s)

attention and activities are directed by others. The orientation is done

through encouragement and indication that ones fellow men carry out in

social interaction. The FFA encompasses affordances and activities, which

the individual is capable of working on by himself/herself, and which one is

permitted to do by social circumstances.

The FPA and FFA comprise the Zone of Proximal Development. Learning and

development happen inside that zone, when the FPA attains more

refinement and sophistication and, at the same time, there is an overall

increase in the FFA. It is essential to notice that FPA and FFA are

indistinguishable. They are fields, which are interlocked in the social

intercourse of - conscious or unconscious - assisting performance.

Although Reed has been positively influenced by the Vygotskian concept of

the Zone of Proximal Development (ZPD), he also criticizes it. He notes

19

(1989, 37) that from an ecological point of view, the notion of ZPD as a

general range, reflecting the general difference between a child`s individual

cognitive function and that same child`s ability to function with instructi-

on, is not viable. He thinks that ZPD emerges only in highly channelled and

specialized environments. The emergence of ZPD is dependent on different

skills, and it is strongly affected by ecological, cultural and individual factors.

For these reasons he argues that "there is no general ZPD, only specific

ZDPs for different skills, reflecting particular relationships that emerge

between FPAs and FFAs".

Could the ZPD be connected in natural situations of intercourse?

When learning is understood primarily as adaptation to life and activity

surroundings, the idea of ZPD has to be considered in customary social

environments: family, groups of interest and free time, work communities.

Could they be environments, which are both highly channelled and

specialized?

A family as a social environment is not a specialized learning environment.

However, from the point of view of the growth and development of a child,

s/he is continuously - consciously or unconsciously - guided to learn new

values, norms and habits of behavior. The fields of free and promoted

actions are not always conscious, but in any case, they are the reality of

every-day activity, according to which the quality of interaction (free and to

be promoted or promoted) is constituted.

Interest and free time groups, and communities are also environments for

new learning. Purposeful instruction and learning situations might be part of

interest groups, and also within the environs of free-time social intercourse

learning might be the existing reality. In other words, also the interest and

free- time surroundings can comprise unique ZPD, in which free and

promoted actions are interlocked as a developmental continuity.

In work communities the assisting of new and inexperienced comrades in

performing assignments is a natural phenomenon. Also in them the "to be

able to" and "to be learned" comprise a zone, where interaction of

employees is realized. The work activities might of course be boring routines

which will mean that the willingness to promote and to receive support

20

will weaken, and then the existing intercourse could be depicted as "a field

of being prevented"

Through these discussions I have tried to show that the dependence of the

ZPD on highly channelled and specialized environments does not mean only

specific instruction and learning situations. The ZPD can be realized in

natural interaction environments, or it might even be suggested that

authentic learning in social environments really happens in the ZPDs,

regardless of being labelled ZPDs. But how can Reed's modification be

connected to school learning?

I feel that Reed`s conception about the uniqueness of ZPD is very essential,

when considering pedagogical and instructional consequences. Before

considering this I would like to comment briefly on the developmental

substance included in the ZPD.

The substance of the Zone of Proximal Development

Vygotskian tradition has employed the ZPD primarily from the perspective of

cognitive or intellectual development. In Reed`s modification the substance

of development is the perception and use of affordances, the education of

attention to affordances and the activities that the affordances of the

situation could afford.

In the ecological view the affordances and the use of them already consist

of emotions and different kind of social activities and phenomena. Despite

this, I think, one has to emphasize that the development through ZPD is not

only the development of cognitive problem solving and the like, but it is the

developing of the entire person, wherein intellectual or "cognitive" and emo-

tional, actional and social factors belong as a comprehensive unity.

From the perspective of thinking, feeling and doing, the unity of a person (a

student and a teacher, for instance) can be seen as abilities of analysing,

joining in and performing. Analysing is a developing ability of perceiving

and using "cognitive-like" affordances. Joining in is a developing ability to be

acquainted with the emotional affordance structure of people and a

situation. Performing is a developing ability to work with natural, human-

made and social affordances.

21

Inside the field of free action, we encounter, or it is possible to encounter,

the abilities of the individuals, and the group they constitute, to analyze, join

in and perform. This FFA is the basis for perceiving the potentionalities of

people in the situation to analyze etc., and to try to create the field of pro-

moted action for the development of the personal unity of the abilities of

analyzing, joining in and performing. The realization of FPA takes place

through assisting procedures performed by the participants and the

assistants in the situation.

The Zone of Proximal Development as a teaching and learning

situation

The Zone of Proximal Development is always unique. It always has to

discover and recreate. It has to find out what is the field of free action in the

situation; what is the free individual and joint attunement or state of

intentionality, and the ability to perceive and use affordances. Through this

it is possible to try to enter into and observe the potential attunements and

abilities, and then to realize and establish the field of promoted action. Let

us take an example.

There is a group of students, who have to study the philosophy of education.

The realization of the FFA can take place as follows. The teaching and

studying begins with discussions about personal experiences and views on

the topics or themes which have influenced students to form their

conceptions about man, reality, education, encountering other people etc.

The students tell about their feelings and impressions when reading

scientific literature and belles-lettres, enjoining and consuming art and

music presentations, familiarizing themselves with educational thinkers,

philosophers etc.

This kind of discussion reveals the field of free action, when the purpose is

to study the philosophy of education, for instance. It also tells something

about the possibilities to proceed in trying to refine and sophisticate the

conceptions of the questions of the philosophy of education: the vista for

the field of promoted action. Together they are the unique zone of the

proximal development in the mentioned situation, and the task of

pedagogical efforts is to obtain it as conscious and flexible as possible.

The example shows, I suppose, that the pedagogical or instructional ZPD

22

has to be created in a unique and authentic social setting. In the school it is

especially the task of teachers. I shall try to reflect on that process briefly.

The first thing is to encourage the students (people) to "open" or explicate

their individual FFAs, and through that process to focus on the FFA of the

group in question. This cannot happen by beginning to teach directly, but by

encouraging the individuals to express their acute and developmental states

which they brought to the studying situation. This might take place through

discussions, free performances and exercises, in an atmosphere of open,

unprejudiced and reliable interaction.

By this process of free expression, the FFA becomes public and shared,

which means that the attunement of the group and it`s members, and

shared social affordances are explicitly known. The established FFA is the

basis for a growing FPA. The expressions of one member or a teacher might

attune in another person something, which for him/her means a promoted

perception and action. Through development - fast or slow - the grown FPA

changes into FFA, which is the ground for the growth of a "new" FPA.

Together they form the instructional ZPD.

The first phase in the creation and realization of instructional ZPD is the

explication of the FFA of the social setting in question. The second phase is

the recognition of the FPA situation which happens through the definition of

task of the existing social setting.

For instance in the social setting of studying the philosophy of education this

transition, i.e. the task definition, might take place as follows. On the basis

of the discussed conceptions of man, reality, education etc. the teacher can

indicate how they are individual views of the same questions that the

philosophy of education handles. S/he fixes the individual views to general

problems and concepts in the philosophy of education, and in that way

shows the study procedure. The content of the FFA is already implicitly part

of the common discussion of the philosophy of education, which will be the

substance of the study course. The teacher makes public the FPA of the

situation.

It has to be noticed here that the "creation" of FPA happens all the time on

the basis of students' authentic conceptions and opinions (FFA), not

23

programmatically on the basis of the teacher's repertoire of questions

about the philosophy of education.

The third phase is individual and shared working with tasks discussed

during the phase of task definition. It can take place by individual and

shared reading, and making references, presenting papers and discussing

relevant questions, debating about them etc. During this working phase FPA

might change into a FFA (and that is the aim of the studying), which is the

basis for further FPAs.

During and after the working phase the evaluation of the studying and

learning processes takes place. It is not evaluation from outside, e.g by

exams or the like, but discussion about the acute social biography of the

participants and the unique study group. The content of that discussion

grows from personal and shared views, how opinions and conceptions

explicated in the first phase have been refined and become more

sophisticated during the task definition and working phases. This evaluation

processually defines and redefines the actual FFA and the growing FPA.

However, every teaching and learning situation is always unique. For

instance, the studying of the philosophy of education is one entity. The

course consists of separate settings, all are unique, which means that the

ZPD has to be created or realized again every time the study group is

together. If that is not done, it means that the social setting cannot be a real

setting of studying educational philosophy (or some other subject), but

something else, which has (unconscious) aims and an intentionality of it's

own.

The realization of ZPDs is rooted in the intentionality context that the quality

of interaction and cooperation maintain. I have discussed earlier about the

intentionality contexts that are common in the schools of today. I now

claim that the ZPDs, described above, can not be established in the inten-

tionality contexts of extinguished reactivity to "ready offered" teaching

substance and directed activity, which is concentrated on given tasks. It is

impossible, because there is no room for broadcasting/announcing the

individual and shared FFAs in them.

The social cooperation, which takes place in the tension between real and

instrumental participation, does allow the formation of ZPDs, because of the

24

free sociability of the starting point. However, there is a risk that FFAs and

FPAs are forced to be established by the advice of a teacher. This is also a

problem in the previously mentioned example of the study group of the phi-

losophy of education.

If the teacher "compels" the students to direct their social participation to

some intellectual aims, it would mean that the authentic ZPD, including

emotional and social factors, cannot emerge. An intentionality context of

social cooperation, which is maintained by personal interaction does not

have that risk. It might, however, cause an ZPD, inside which it is impossible

to handle the problems of the philosophy of education, for instance.

Nevertheless, it means that the established ZPD can exist; it gives room for

the "real" FFA, and the instruction (e.g. social interaction and cooperation)

has to proceed according to it.

THE ZONE OF PROXIMAL DEVELOPMENT AND THE SCHOOL

From an ecological point of view the school situations are contexts where

teachers and students encounter and work affordances which are not only

explicite knowledge, but a variety of all kinds of social phenomena. This

means that there is a conflict between creating an instructional ZPD and

ZPD, which is constituted by the authenticity of the situation. Is this conflict

possible to solve?

It is tempting to cry out a solution that pedagogically meaningful ZPDs are

out of question in the schools today. The school is too formally defined

(forms and contents of instruction, the progress of instruction) that a

successful ZPD could take place and grow as a purposeful instructional ZPD.

This extreme outcry would mean that the whole school system must be

modified. I think that this kind of conclusion is justified. The school of today

has to be put under scrutiny.

However, I do not want to blunt myself by such an enormous task. I should

like proceed with small steps and to think that it is possible to be directed

towards the solution of the conflict between authentic and instructional ZPD.

It might simply be that one can learn to perceive authentic ZPDs and then

promote them into instructional ZDPs inside the existing school system. This

will, however, require that the relationship between teacher and students is

25

seen in a new way.

Teacher-student relationship

The traditionally understood teacher-student relationship is based on a

situation, where a teacher has the knowledge and skill of the subject or

activity to be taught. By different kinds of teaching methods s/he tries to

teach them to students, who do not have the knowledge and skills in

question. This arrangement includes a double dualism: 1) a teacher

possesses knowledge and skills separated from the environments where the

knowledge and skills do exist, 2) that possessed by a teacher can be

transferred to be possessed by students. This kind of conception is criticized

by a Gibsonian ecological view.

The application of the Gibsonian subject-environment reciprocity or oneness

to teacher-student relationships means that they can be understood only as

a unity, which is born and maintained by the interaction and cooperation

between teacher and students.

The teacher-student relationships are based on shared affordances in the

social settings in question. A teacher does not distribute or mediate

something which s/he has, but in teacher-student relationships the shared

perception and use of (social) affordances of the situation is realized.

The shared encountering situation of affordances is based on the practice of

interaction and cooperation, which comes true in a setting (see intentionality

contexts above). The ability of a teacher and students to analyze, join in

and act receive their expression in this interaction and cooperation

practice. However, they are not private properties of subjects, but unique

shared abilities constituted by the authenticity of the situation. In this

shared encountering of affordances the solitary Zone of Proximal

Development is born.

From the ecological perspective the basis of the encountering of a teacher

and students is not a teaching and learning relationship, but the shared

performance of a task, which takes place in the situation. There is tension

between the more experienced (a teacher) and less experienced (a

student). Inside this tension a common activity is materialized as a coopera-

tion of individuals with different experiential abilities, not as a distributing

26

and receiving of possessed knowledge and skill.

If we think of a class teacher activity in a classroom situation, the shared

task is primarily the participation in social interaction. A teacher is more

experienced in carrying out the sociability, and in the living of the social life

of the class, the teacher`s behavior gets the students to perceive new social

affordances and to perform according to them.

The shared social activity develops individual and group attunement of all

participants to meet and act with more sophisticated and multiplying

affordances relevant to the situation. In a situation of this kind, the teacher

does not teach, but the less experienced (students) and also the more

experienced (a teacher) learn in a shared activity.

The situation described reveals that learning takes place in an authentic

cooperation of more and less experienced participants. Defined as a

teacher-student relationship it is a question of a master-apprentice

relationship during apprenticeship, in which the learning of students does

not happen specifically by teaching, but by cooperating with a more

experienced adult or peers (see Reed, 1991).

I have so far spoken only of the social intercourse as school work and

shared tasks. Is it not true that certain specific learning tasks are proper

school work, which take place in social contexts? I think that this question

in particular includes the core of problems of traditional teaching and lear-

ning conception.

The primary tasks of school work are not the specific learning tasks, but the

learning of sociability during cooperation. The specific learning tasks are

included in it, but they have to be seen as subordinate to social cooperation.

When beginning school and during the class teacher system, a teacher is

primarily a master or expert in carrying out the sociability (or s/he should

be). Secondly s/he is an expert in a subject matter of the school. How then

does the "teaching" of a subject matter take place?

When the basic task of a class teacher is putting social expertise into

practice, s/he becomes orientated to the subject matter only through it. The

mutual cooperation of a teacher and students defines how the expertise and

27

experience of a teacher, with regard to reading, writing, counting, biology,

geography, history and natural sciences, becomes the content of the social

interaction and cooperation. For example, the teaching of reading cannot be

formed by specific learning tasks, but the social intercourse arouses the

cooperation, in which a teacher's ability to read and to indicate affordances,

which includes reading, is the "substance" for learning. Students can learn

reading in cooperation, which has somehow focused on reading, but which

is not specifically teaching.

Nowadays it is a common phenomenon that many children learn to read in

natural interaction settings of homes and other environments without

specific teaching. In principal school work should be the same kind of

natural cooperation without the specific purpose to teach the subject matter

by certain teaching methods.

What would this mean for the learning of contents of different traditional

school subjects is of course a difficult question dealing with the developing

of school practice. But it is a question worth looking into, and there are

some references in the literature, in which learning and cognition taking

place in natural interaction settings are studied (see Lave, 1989).

The previously mentioned examination of the teacher-student relationship

as an expert-apprentice cooperation taking place primarily as social

participation, belongs mainly to the intercourse inside a class teacher

system. When subject teachers are the more experienced experts in the

mutual cooperation of teacher and students, the implementation of a

sociability is not a teacher's basic task any more (although it is always very

essential). A subject teacher is an experienced performer of the work tasks

of his or her own knowledge and skill disciplines. What does this mean in

school practice?

Traditionally subject teachers teach their subject matters to students in

specific teaching situations. They are artificial, although. For instance a

biologist cannot be a biologist in a teaching class, but only in performing the

tasks of a biologist. This means that subject teaching (e.g. biology) should

be developed in a direction that could occur in natural task environments

and situations.

The primary task of subject teachers should be the performing of work tasks

28

of his or her own discipline, and students would participate in it as less

experienced work comrades. This would mean that learning would not

happen by teaching, but by cooperation, in which a teacher is an expert of

her or his work field, and where students would learn from the more

experienced when they perform shared tasks. This kind of arrangement

could also connect the school and the rest of society closer to each other,

because the shared tasks might somehow be associated to needs and

problems of the near-community and the whole society.

The teacher-student relationship has been defined as a master or an expert-

apprentice relationship, which takes place during apprenticeship (e.g. school

time). In addition it is based on cooperation, and not on the separateness of

a teacher and students. The developmental continuity is essential to it. It

does not commit itself only to separate teaching situations.

To summarize, the expert-apprentice relationships of the school might by

their content be of two kinds: they root themselves 1) to a social

intercourse, in which a teacher is mainly a socially more mature and

competent adult (a class teacher), 2) to professional expertise, in which a

teacher is mainly an experienced professional of his or her knowledge and

skill discipline (a subject teacher).

The transformation of a teacher-student relationship from social

intercourse to cooperation based on expertise of some discipline cannot

happen radically. It can take place since students have a need to proceed

from school work, based on social intercourse, to cooperation, based on

professional competence. This means that tight age and class levels, and

group forming has to be more flexible.

BACK TO BASICS

This examination has proceeded from studying social affordances to a

critique of the western school system, and beyond to the searching for an

alternative, inspired by Gibsonians, for the arrangements of school and

instruction. The Zone of Proximal Development, modified from the neo-

vygotkian conception, and the regestalting of the teacher-student

relationship, have been established for the foundation of the instruction,

which has its roots in real socialility. Before ending this paper, I would like to

comment on the Gibsonian psychological basis of interaction and coopera-

29

tion, which takes place inside the Zone of Proximal Development.

According to the cognitive conception the mental construction made by

agents is the basic event in teaching and learning (cf. Aebly, 1991). The

Gibsonian basic event is resonation or attunement. The question of

attunement is not examined explicitly inside the ecological movement, but

implicitly it is always present, when the ecological way of thinking is

contrasted with the cognitive one. What does attunement mean?

It means the state of an organism in an organism-environment system. If we

think of a student in the learning situation, the attunement means his/her

actual state in the encountering of the affordances relevant to him/her in

the social setting, and in the working and cooperating with them. I think

that the attunement is the same as the intentionality (see the systemic

definition of the intentionality chapter IV) in every acute and longstanding

social event, in which an individual participates.

The attunement or intentionality is not a phenomenon outside

social settings but becomes realized only in them. It is not the processing

and constructing taking place inside the individual, but the ability to

perceive, know, feel and act, which is realized and changed in the social field

of individuals.

The systemics of an attunement is fulfilled as a oneness of affordances,

which have a structure and function (meaning), and a person, who is picking

them up and putting them to use. Picking up and using is a changing and

developing energetic and living state, which, however, cannot exist without

affordances. Or, it might be said that the attunement is a part of affordan-

ces or vice-a-versa. In a way the attunement is an unstructured state,

because it is changing and developing all the time according to affordances

(structures, meanings) that the subject is encountering and learns to

encounter. But because it is impossible to examine the attunement apart

from affordances, it also includes the structurality. As an experience the

affordances are structural energetic formations, while the attunement is, as

an experience, an energetic and unstructured structurality of affordances.

The phylo- and ontogenetic history of man is the developing of attunement,

and when teaching and learning is examined attunement is studied. How

can pedagogy and instruction support the development of attunement?

30

Previously it has developed the idea of the Zone of Proximal Development

for the pedagogical context for the attunement taking place in the

immediate social environments, and the teacher-student relationship

gestalted as an activity oneness between the more and less experienced, in

which the attunement can change and proceed.

If teaching is examined from the perspective of attunement, its task is to

support the attunement towards more sophisticated affordances of objects,

places, events, humans, interaction and cooperation. The previously

mentioned aspect can be non-linguistic. The task of instruction is also to

support the attunement to linguistic affordances. What would the support be

as a pedagogical practice?

I have earlier noted that school work has to give up the traditional

instruction and proceed towards natural cooperation, in which it is learned

without particular teaching. And I think that it could be assumed that

natural cooperation is also the basis for supporting attunement.

The starting point of a teacher's activity to support the attunement of

students to different affordances cannot be the implementing of the plan of

instruction or something else. This is impossible, because the activity that

takes place according to a scheme does not make room for the publishing

and sharing of the authentic individual and social attunement.

The basis of the activity of a teacher has to be his/her social expertise to

work in the jungle of immediate social affordances, and his/her ability to

allow the attunement to social affordances to grow as an attunement to

affordances of contents of subject matter.

This is also the basis for developing of linguistic attunement, because the

authentic sociability is the "cache" for shared linguistic affordances. The

verbal sociability produces and refines the attunement to words and

linguistic events, which are shared and explicit instruments of communica-

tion included in social interaction and cooperation. I have dealt with use of

language based on the theory of affordances in detail in the text "The

perceptual language and instruction" (Chapter III).

Despite the fact that attunement is examined as a phenomenon in the

organism-environment system, it, however, clearly refers to an individual.

31

As a psychic basic event it is still "the background" of a comprehensive

basic process, which, according to the Gibsonian view, is the continuum of

perception and action (including cognition) which takes place in the social

context. The essential thing of the perception-action unity is the unin-

terruptedness: there is no different perceptions and actions (cognitions).

The continuity of cognition (perception and action) means that individuals

and groups of people in certain social environments are more or less actively

in contact with their own history of close and long-term experience or

attunement, and also with their future experiences.

With respect to pedagogy and instruction this means that, to be successful,

they cannot withdraw from the uninterrupting process of experiencing,

which in certain social settings happens to be realized at that moment. This

processuality is the basis of the idea of a unique Zone of Proximal Develop-

ment elaborated. So that the pedagogy and instruction could lean on the

processuality of perception and action, and to support it, it has to "grow"

from the authenticity of the existing social settings.

References:

Aebly, H. 1991. Opetuksen perusmuodot, Helsinki:WSOY

(originally Grundlagen des Lehrens, Klett-Gotta:

Stuttgart, 1987).

Apple, M., King, N. 1977. What Do Schools Teach? Curruculum

Inquiry, vol. 6, no. 4, 341-358.

Aronowitz, S., Giroux, H. 1991. Postmodern Education.

Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Baron, R., Boundreau, L. 1987. An Ecological Perspective on

Integrating Personality and Psychology. Journal of

Personality and Social Psychology, vol. 55, no. 6,

1222-1228.

Dent, C. 1990, An Ecological Approach to Language Development:

An Alternative Functionalism. Developmental

Psychobiology, vol. 23, no. 7, 679-703.

Gibson, J. 1979. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.

Boston:Hougton Mifflin Company.

Giroux, H., Penna, A. Social Education in The Classroom: The

32

Dynamics of The Hidden Curriculum. Theory and Research

in Social Education, vo. VII, no. 1, 21-42.

Jackson, P. 1968. Life in Classrooms. New York: Holt, Rinehart and

Winston, Inc.: New York.

Jonhston, D., Turvey, M. 1980. A Sketch of An Ecological

Metatheory for Theories of Learning. In Gordon &

Bower (eds.), The Psychology of Learning and

Motivation. New York: Academic Press.

Lave, J. 1988, Cognition in Practice. New York: Combridge

University Press.

McArthur, L., Baron, R. 1983. Toward an Ecological

Theory of Social Perception. Psychological

Review, vol. 90, no. 3, 215-238.

Michaels, C., Carello, C. 1981. Direct Perception.

New Jersey: Prentice Hall, Inc.

Ohlson, S. 1990. Cognitive Science and Instruction:

Why The Revolution Is Not Here (Yet). In

Mandl,H., De Corte, E., Bennett, S. &

Friedrich, H. (eds.), Learning and Instruction.

European Research in an International Context,

vol. 2:1. Social and Cognitive Aspects of

Learning and Instruction. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

Reed, E. 1989. The Intention to Use a Specific Affordance:

A Conceptual Framework for Psychology. Invited Lecture:

Piaget Society Meeteing, June, 1989.

Reed, E. 1991. Cognition as the Cooperative Appropriation

of Affordances. Ecological Psychology vol. 3, no. 2,

135-158.

Searle, J. 1983, Intentionality. An Essay in the Philosophy

of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Smith, D., Ginsburg, G. 1989. The Social Perception Process:

Reconsidering the Role of Social Stimulation. Journal

for the Theory of Social Behavior, vol. 19, no. 1,

31-45.

Tharp, R., Gallimore, R. 1988. Rousing Minds to Life. Teaching

Learning and Schooling in Social Context. New York:

Cambridge University Press.

Turvey, M., Shaw, R. 1979. The Primacy of Perceiving: An

Ecological Reformulation of Perception for Under-

33

standing Memory. In Nilson, L.-G. (ed.), Perspectives

on Memory Research. Essays in Honour of Uppsala

University's 500 th Anniversary, Hillsdale, N.J.:

LEA.

Turvey, M., Shaw, R., Reed, E. & Mace, W. 1981. Ecological

Laws of Perceiving and Action: In Reply to Fodor

and Pylyshyn, Cognition 9, 237-304.

Turvey, M., Kugler, P. 1987. Information, Natural Law and

the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement. Hillsdale, N.J.:

LEA.

Valenti, S., Good, J. 1991. Social Affordances and Inter-

action I: Introduction. Ecological Psychology, vol. 3,

no. 2, 77-98.

Valsiner, J. 1984. Construction of the Zone of Proximal

Development in Adult-Child Joint Action: The

Socialization of Meals. In Rogoff, B., Wertsch J. (eds.)

Children's Learning in the Zone of Proximal Development.

New Directions for Child Development, no 23. San

Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

Verbrugge, R. 1985. Language and Event Perception: Steps

toward a Synthesis. In Warren, W., Shaw, R. (eds.),

Percistance and Change. Proceedings of the First

International Conference on Event Perception.

Hillsdale, N.J.: LEA.

Vygotsky, L. 1978. Mind in Society: The Development of

Higher Psychological Processes. Cambridge Mass.:

Harvard University Press.

Wertsch, J. 1984. The Zone of Proximal Development: Some

Conceptual Issues. In Rogoff, B., Wertsch, J. (eds.),

Children's Learning in the Zone of Proximal Development,

New Directions for Child Development, no. 23, San

Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

Zukow, P. 1990. Socio-Perceptual bases for the Emergence of

Language: An Alternative to Innatist Approaches. In

Dent, C., Zukow, P. (eds.), The Idea of Innateness:

Effects on Language and Communikation Research (Special

Issue), Developmental Psychobiology vol.23, no. 7,

705-726.