19
Gregorianum 86, 4 (2005) 723-741 Το test or preserve? The prohibition of Gen 2.16-17 in the thought of two second-century exegetes. «Why forbid the tree?» Of ali the questione that arise from a reading of the Genesis protology, that over why God prevented Adam and Ève from partaking of the tree of knowledge is of perennial curiosity. Of ali the trees in Paradise humanity is given to eat, except that which it seems most logi cai, and indeed desirable, for a loving God to provide to his beloved crea tion. That which is denied is knowledge, not of evil only but also of good, and in the most absolute manner. «On the day that you partake of it, on that very day you shall surely die» (Gen 2:17). The tree of knowledge, whose subject is so deeply at the heart of the human image of God that many rea ders equate it, partially or fully, with the divine imago, is the only element of existence which God forbids his newly-fashioned creature. Why should God do such a thing? Reflections on this question go back to the earliest days of Christian theological consideration, predating even the advent of what most would cali «theology» proper (usually attributed to Irenaeus), figuring prominently in the work of the apologists. Yet the abi ding fascination, and in many cases discomfort, with the dilemma reveals its continuing centrality and importance to Christian visions of the nature of God in his relationship to humankind. In our own day it holds the same power to challenge the Christian mind as it did in the first and second cen turies ad, and thus is eminently deserving of our continued consideration. In what follows, I shall aim to explore the contrasting answers to the que stion posed by two second-century sources: the apologist Theophilus in Antioch (fi. c. 180)1 and the heresiologist and «proto-theologian» Irenaeus 1 The dates for Theophilus are difficult. Eusebius' Chronicon sets the start of his episcopacy at ad 169, concurrent with the papacy of Soter. His successor, Maximus, served concurrently with Eleutherus of Rome (177-193), to whom Irenaeus was commended by the Church in Lyons. Theophilus lived at least past 180, since he mentions the death of M. Aurelius at Ad Autolycum (hereafter AdAutol.) 3.28, which took place on 17 March of that year. On the dating of Theophilus, cf. R.M. Grant, Theophilus of Antioch - Text and Translation, Oxford, 1970, ix-x; F.W. Norris, «Theophilus of Antioch» in E. Ferguson, Enciclopédia ofEarly Christianity, London, 1998,1122.

To test or preserve - The prohibition of Gen 2,16-17 in the thought of two second-century exegetes_Censurado.pdf

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • Gregorianum 86, 4 (2005) 723-741

    test or preserve? The prohibition of Gen 2.16-17

    in the thought of two second-century exegetes.

    Why forbid the tree? Of ali the questione that arise from a reading of the Genesis protology, that over why God prevented Adam and ve from

    partaking of the tree of knowledge is of perennial curiosity. Of ali the trees in Paradise humanity is given to eat, except that which it seems most logi cai, and indeed desirable, for a loving God to provide to his beloved crea tion. That which is denied is knowledge, not of evil only but also of good, and in the most absolute manner. On the day that you partake of it, on that

    very day you shall surely die (Gen 2:17). The tree of knowledge, whose

    subject is so deeply at the heart of the human image of God that many rea ders equate it, partially or fully, with the divine imago, is the only element of existence which God forbids his newly-fashioned creature.

    Why should God do such a thing? Reflections on this question go back

    to the earliest days of Christian theological consideration, predating even the advent of what most would cali theology proper (usually attributed to Irenaeus), figuring prominently in the work of the apologists. Yet the abi

    ding fascination, and in many cases discomfort, with the dilemma reveals its continuing centrality and importance to Christian visions of the nature of God in his relationship to humankind. In our own day it holds the same

    power to challenge the Christian mind as it did in the first and second cen turies ad, and thus is eminently deserving of our continued consideration. In what follows, I shall aim to explore the contrasting answers to the que stion posed by two second-century sources: the apologist Theophilus in Antioch (fi. c. 180)1 and the heresiologist and proto-theologian Irenaeus

    1 The dates for Theophilus are difficult. Eusebius' Chronicon sets the start of his episcopacy at ad 169, concurrent with the papacy of Soter. His successor, Maximus, served concurrently with Eleutherus of Rome (177-193), to whom Irenaeus was commended by the Church in Lyons. Theophilus lived at least past 180, since he mentions the death of M. Aurelius at Ad Autolycum (hereafter AdAutol.) 3.28, which took place on 17 March of that year. On the dating of Theophilus, cf. R.M. Grant, Theophilus of Antioch - Text and Translation, Oxford, 1970, ix-x; F.W. Norris,

    Theophilus of Antioch in E. Ferguson, Enciclopdia ofEarly Christianity, London, 1998,1122.

  • 724 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    in Lyons (c. ad 140-202/3).2 Though Theophilus' contribution to our study will be the shorter of the two (for his treatment of the text is less extensive than that of Irenaeus), we shall see that it is of no less importance. In the end, the views of these authors will be brought together in what we might consider a composite response to the matter at hand.

    The stage is set

    While it may now be commonplace in Pentateuchal scholarship to

    identify multiple authors and source accounts in the Genesis protology, and

    specifcally two creation narratives in chapters 1-3 of that text, we must note from the outset that Christian commentators and expositors of the second century did not share this source-critical methodology or its con clusione. For the two sources presently under consideration, namely Theophilus and Irenaeus, the account of creation in Genesis is single and unifed, with modem scholarship's second account (i.e. Gen 2:4-25) understood by both authors as a clarification and expansion of the broader details of what modem scholarship calls the first (Gen 1:1-2:3). The pro gression of the creation narrative from Gen 1 to Gen 2 is seen as the unfol

    ding revelation of a single whole, which may be divided thematically more

    appropriately than by source influence. Gen 1:1-25 speaks of the creation of the cosmos and the physical world with its non-human inhabitants; 1:26-27 recounts the creation of the human person, then situated by 1:28-2:3 into the cosmos previously fashioned; Gen 2:4-24 goes on to focus more closely upon this human formation in its particular elements (constitution of the

    person, relationship to the earth, relationship to God). For both Theophilus and Irenaeus, the details of Gen 2 expand on those of 1:26-27, with the nar rative's second chapter containing what we might cali anthropology proper, whereas Gen 1 had contained, insofar as it touched upon man, only the basic anthropogony (though with the text's most potent declaration of the fundamental anthropological reality of the imago Dei). In Gen 2, the cha racter of human nature is set out in its being called forth into existence and

    placed into the context of the cosmos prepared for the sake of its develop

    2 Early suggestions of ad 98 (Dodwell) or 120 (Lightfoot) for Irenaeus' birth have largely

    given way to the between 130 and 140 of Osborn (E. Osborn, Irenaeus ofLyons, Cambridge, 2001, 2) based on Irenaeus' recollections of Polycarp (d. 155/156) whom he saw as a young man. For Grant, this suggests a rather firm date of about ad 140 (ibid.), though for Osborn this makes Irenaeus too young to take up the episcopacy c. 177/178. On the date of Irenaeus' death, the usually-ascribed date is sometime at the dose of the second or beginning of the third

    century, in agreement with the record in Jerome's Commentary on Isaias 64, which reports Irenaeus' martyrdom in 202/203 (often discounted as a later interpolation); cf. R.M. Grant, Irenaeus of Lyons, London, 1997, 2; J. van der Straeten, Saint-Irne fut-il martyr? in Les

    martyrs de Lyon, Paris, 1978,145-52.

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 725

    ment and growth. Gen 3, then, expands on 2:16-17 (the prohibition against the tree of knowledge), recounting the events which led to the disruption of the intended course of that development.

    In this reading the prohibition of 2:16-17 stands at the pinnacle of the

    anthropological narrative of Genesis. The earth has been fashioned, filled and handed to humanity, and as God presents this new life and order to the first humans, his final words in the creative monologue are those forbidding access to the tree of knowledge.

    And the Lord God commanded the man, saying, Of every tree of the garden

    you may freely eat; but of the tree of the knowledge of good and evil you shall

    not eat, for in the day that you eat of it you shall surely die.

    Ali that has gone before has led up to the placement of man in Paradise and his being gifted by God with stewardship of the place. As the anthropo gony thus concludes and the story of the human economy proper begins, it is this - a prohibition - that serves as its initiation.

    To test and inspire: Theophilus ofAntioch

    For Theophilus, how we understand this prohibition sets the tenor of our whole conception of God's relationship to man, and indeed our vision of the cosmos and humanity's place within it. He addresses his exposition to three particular questions prone to arise from a reading of the text: Was the tree evil? Is knowledge evil? Does (and if so, why does) God hold back his

    blessings from man? The first two questions are interrelated, and the most obvious to arise

    from a basic reading of the prohibition. Assuming that God is benevolent and loving in his interactions with the human formation, one may conse

    quently assume that he would only prevent from the latter's access that which is harmful or damaging. As such, are we to understand that there is in the tree of knowledge something which, though we may not necessarily wish to cali it evil, nonetheless is in some sense negative? This seems a feasible reading, but Theophilus comes down staunchly in the negative:

    The tree of knowledge was itself good, and its fruit was good. For the tree did

    not contain death, as some suppose; death was the result of disobedience. For

    there was nothing in the fruit but knowledge, and knowledge is good when one

    uses it properly.3

    3 Ad.Au.tol. 2.25. Cf. the Apocalypse ofjohn in NagHammadi Corpus (II,1) 21.21-36, for an

    example of one Gnostic tradition (ofValentinian descent) that flts the caricature of Theophilus'

    anonymous some. A similar sentiment is expressed in the Gospel ofTruth in NagHammadi

    Corpus (1,3) 17.18-20. Grant puts forward Apelles, of Marcionite background, as the some to

    which Theophilus may have been referring (cf. R. M. Grant, Theophilus ofAntioch, 67 . 1).

  • 726 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    To attribute evil or fault to the tree or the knowledge it contains is, by Theophilus' reading, fundamentally to misunderstand the text. There can be no evil in the tree, for the tree contains but knowledge, which of itself is

    good when one uses it properly. Indeed, how could it be else - for we must not forget that the tree was created and planted by God (cf. Gen 2:9), for

    ming part of the creation which God beheld and saw that it was good, yet very good. Whatever evil may come from the partaking of the fruit must not, therefore, be attributed to the fruit or its contents. Rather, Theophilus identifes the source of the evil - of the death promised in Gen 2:17 - with the act of disobedience by which Adam and ve partook of the fruit forbid den them by God. It is in this, in the sin of transgression, that the tree brings death, itself only the passive agent and focal object of the act. The conse

    quence of sin, namely death, springs up from the will of man, not the fruit of the tree.

    This reading, however, only begs more urgently the great puzzle of the narrative: why did God prohibit the eating of this particular tree in the first

    place? Given Theophilus' statement that there was nothing in the fruit but

    knowledge, and knowledge is good when one uses it properly, God's pre vention of man's approach to this fruit seems even more inexplicable than it might, were we to consider that there was something genuinely negative in the tree from which God was protecting man. But the tree is good, its

    contents are good, and from these God holds man back. In explication of this seeming paradox, Theophilus puts forward a reading of Gen 2:16-17 which would, by and large, become the standard among future expositors. He writes later in the same passage:

    God wanted to test [Adam], to see whether he would be obedient to his com mand. At the same time, he also wanted the man to remain simple and since re for a longer time, remaining in infancy. For this is a holy duty not only befo re God but before men, to obey one's parente in simplicity and without malice.

    And if children must obey their parents, how much more must they obey the God and Father of the universe!

    The prohibition is a test. It is not a malignant test, wrought at God's hands as a domineering gesture of power, but a test designed to foster

    humanity's obedience to its maker. God wishes to see whether Adam will be obedient (here a strong similarity to the Akedah, cf. Gen 22:1,12, where God is similarly said to have wanted to see whether Abraham would be obe dient), yet he wishes also to encourage and engender obedience. Theophilus' implication is that one cannot be obedient without a law or command to which obedience might be given, and thus God provides the prohibition in order that man might learn to obey the God and Father of the universe.

    In his reading of the prohibition, Theophilus' point of emphasis may be

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 727

    identified as the propriety of humanity's relationship to God. The creator establishes the divine command in order that proper humility and obe dience might be engendered in the human formation. The evil (including death) which comes from the transgression is the result of those virtues

    being distorted and abused. God sees, and ultimately man also sees, that

    propriety, obedience, is not evident in humanity, and from this revelation the economy of salvation can be set properly in perspective.

    We might also note that Theophilus hints at, but does not greatly deve

    lop, the reality of the tree of knowledge as indicative of a dynamic relation

    ship between God and man. To say that knowledge is good when one uses it properly suggests that there may at some point be a time when the discretion to do so shall lie within man's power. Theophilus calls to mind a child who must drink milk before progressing to solid foods, and even says outright that as one grows in age and in an orderly fashion, so one grows in

    ability to think.4 The impropriety of partaking of the tree of knowledge is

    temporary, temporal. Theophilus does not further expand this notion within the context of the prohibition against the tree, though he does so in other contexts in the Ad Autolycum. We find, however, that it lies right at the heart of the reading of the prohibition put forth by Irenaeus of Lyons.

    To protect and preserve: Irenaeus of Lyons

    It seems to be of importance for Irenaeus that Gen 2:16-17, which pre sente the prohibition in question, is offset from the full account of the tran

    sgression (Gen 3), appearing earlier in the text as part of the creation narra

    tive of Gen 1-2 and indeed bisecting that narrative. The verses which prece de it describe the contente of the Garden (including the tree of life and the tree of knowledge in 2:9), and those to follow address Adam's activities in his new home, while the contents of 2:16-17 represent the first words, the first commands, given by God since his pronouncement of a blessing upon the

    completed six days' work (Gen 2:3). Irenaeus extrapolates, from the inser tion of this prohibition into the very heart of the creation saga in its anthro

    pogonic element, that the commandment itself forms part of the formative work of the creator for his creation. The prohibition is an active manoeuvre of God in fashioning his human formation, even as were the drawing up from the dust and the breathing of the divine breath. It is not merely a nega

    4 Ad.Autol. 2.25. The allegory of the newborn child unable to eat solid food and thus nou

    rished by its mother's milk, but which, with increasing age, comes to solid food, is employed also by Irenaeus, drawing from this text in Theophilus, at Adversus haereses (hereafter AH) 4.38-39. See also Ad.Autol. 2.26. In 2.24, Theophilus specifcally indicates that God intends

    Adam to grow into perfection and ascend to heaven, having been declared a God. Cf. A.J.

    Droge, Homer or Moses? Early Christian Interpretations of the History of Culture, TUbingen, 1989, 104.

  • 728 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    tive proscription, but a positive affirmation of the proper limits of human

    knowing in its present stage of development. It is in this sense that Irenaeus utilises the text of the prohibition at Epideixis (hereafter Epid.) 15, where it is placed at the end of his long treatment of the creation saga, in some sense completing ali that has gone before:

    But, in order that the man should not entertain thoughts of grandeur nor he exal

    ted, as if he had no Lord, and, because of the authority given to the man and the

    boldness towards God his creator, sin, passing beyond his own measure, and adopt an atttude of self-conceited arrogance against God, a law was given to him from

    God, that he might know that he had as lord the Lord of ali. And he placed certain

    limits upon him, so that, if he should keep the commandment of God, he would

    remain always as he was, that is, immortai; if, however, he should not keep it, he

    would become mortai, dissolving into the earth whence his frame was taken. And

    the commandment was this: You may eat ffeely from every tree of Paradise, but of

    that tree alone, whence is the knowledge of good and evil, you shall not eat; for on

    the day that you eat of it, you shall surely die (Gen 2:16-17).

    Such words clearly demonstrate Irenaeus' understanding of the prohibi tion against the tree of knowledge as an active work in forming the character of man. Even as the physical limitations of the flesh provide the boundaries within which humanity's carnai nature is meant to be expressed, so does the

    divinely imposed limitation of the Edenic law provide the boundary within which its intellect and free will shall properly function. The prohibition again st eating from the tree of knowledge is, for Irenaeus, God's establishment of the proper realm within which the human creature's intellect and reason may be employed in the course of its growth. This is a unique observation on Irenaeus' part, and one whose implications have not figured prominendy enough in modem scholarship. Through it, Irenaeus puts forth the idea that

    knowledge itself, as an element within the composite being of humankind, must have reign only within the proper scope of its capabilities and prepa redness at any given point in its development. Knowledge must not exalt man to a state of self-professed grandeur that exceeds his own measure. To do so is to use improperly the authority, the rational faculty given to man by God, for a purpose beyond that for which it is intended. The prohibition of 2:16-17 is a safety provided to guard against a potential danger inherent in man's possession of a free and self-determining will.5

    It is only possible to understand fully the manner of Irenaeus' analysis if one reads Epid. 15 in the light of A/75.20.2, where he employs Gen 2:16 in an ad hominem manner against the heretics;

    5 See S. Korolyov, Heavenly Life on Earth in Journal of the Moscow Pairiarchate 3 (1983) 74 for a modem writer's assertion of the same point: The commandment not to eat of the fruit of the Tree of Knowledge of Good and Evil was given in order to train man's will through obedience to Goodness.

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 729

    Itbehovesus [...] toavoidtheir doctrines, and to take careful heed lest we suffer

    any injury from them; but to flee to the Church and be brought up (educari) in

    her bosom, and be nourished with the Lord's scriptures. For the Church has been

    planted as a garden (paradisus) in this world; therefore the Spirit of God says, You may freely eat from every tree of the garden, that is, you may eat from every

    scriptum of the Lord, but you shall not eat with an uplifted mind, nor touch any heretical discord. For these men profess that they themselves have the knowled

    ge of good and evil, and they set their own impious minds above God who made

    them. On this account they form opinions on what is beyond the limits of under

    standing. Wherefore also the Apostle says, Do not be wise beyond what it is fit

    ting to be wise, but be wise prudently (cf. Rom 12:3), that we not be cast forth

    from the paradise of life by eating of the knowledge of these men - that know

    ledge which knows more than it should.6

    If we accept the common dating of Irenaeus' two works and place the

    composition of the Epideixis after the completion of the Adversus haereses (and there is no convincing reason to challenge this7), it seems hard not to conclude that Epid. 15 is a refined and generalised summation of what Irenaeus had written within a narrower context at AH 5.20.2. Both passages take as their grounding Gen 2.16-17 {Epid. 15 directly quotes both verses; AH 5.20.2 quotes only 2:16 but makes obvious allusion to 17), and both treat the prohibition as dealing with the fitting and proper limitations to be pla ced on man's use of his intellect and reason. The heretics profess a full

    knowledge of good and evil, and set their own impious minds above the God who made them - precisely the state of affairs against which, Irenaeus

    argues at Epid. 15, God had originally invoked the prohibition as a guard. Irenaeus' use of Paul, via Rom 12:3, in his argument in the Adversus haere ses clarifies that he does not regard the wisdom of the tree itself as proble matic, or even the genuine subject of God's prohibition; rather, the com mandment guards against the misuse of such knowledge as the tree repre sents and grants, against the act of being wise beyond what is fitting.8

    6 Sources Chrtiennes 153, 258-61. This is the only instance in the corpus where Irenaeus relates the garden of Paradise to the Church.

    7 The intriguing sentiments of J. Behr (see J. Behr, The Formation of Christian Theology, voi. 1: The Way to Nicaea, New York, 2001, 30 . 34; Id., Ori the Apostolic Preaching, New York, 1997,118 n. 229) and others notwithstanding, I am unconvinced of the validity of those argu ments in favour of inverting the traditional chronology of these texts, based in part upon what seem to be refnements in argumentative structure front the ad hominem motif of the Adversus haereses to the more general, and more coherent, systematisation of the Epideixis - as for exam

    ple is evidenced in the two passages presenty under review. For a more developed considera

    tion of this question, see my eariier comments in M.C. Steenberg, Cosmic Anthropology: Genesis 1-11 in Irenaeus ofLyons, with special reference to Justin, Theophilus and select Gnostic contem

    poraries, D. Phil thesis, University of Oxford, 2003, 24-5. 8 This in distinction, for example, to the Gnostic Apocryphon ofjohn, where in 21.21-36

    the tree is described as godlessness, whose fruit is deadly poison and its promise death: Nag

  • 730 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    Should human knowledge be kept within appropriate bounds (not passing beyond its own measure), then it is a knowledge that eats freely from

    every tree of the Garden and nourishes man in his growth.9 The notion that specific proscriptions of the Law are meant to prevent

    the overreaching of nature or of the bounds imposed on one's relationship to the cosmos through his or her own nature, is found well antecedent to Irenaeus. Philo had interpreted many of the regulations of the Old Testament in such a manner: proscriptions against covetousness mitigate more deeply against uncontrolled desire, which leads to such antisocial activities as plunderings, robberies, false accusations, adulteries, even murders;10 the Decalogue's commandment against covetousness and desire strives to prevent injustice and warfare;11 and the proscription of murder is handed down for the benefit of public utility ( ).12

    In a similar vein, H. Maier has composed a study on the ancient rea

    ding of legai traditions through such an interpretive methodology, which in Philo he rightly attributes to Stoic influences.13 By his analysis both of Philo and of similar interpretations of metaphysical proscriptions from within the philosophical tradition,14 Maier conceives primarily of social motiva tions for such readings. His brief survey of Sirach, for example, concludes with the declaration that regulations on wealth and riches are meant ulti

    mately to protect the social structure of the Israelite community. Maier

    notes, For this writer [i.e. the author of Sirach], then, the proper use of

    Hammadi Corpus (II, 1) 21.21-36. Yet cf. the anonymous Origin ofthe World in Nag Hammadi

    Corpus (11,5) 110.8-111.1 on the tree of gnosis which shall open the mind of man. For one of the few scholarly reflections on the prohibition as protection, see D. Ramos-Lissn, Le rle de la femme dans la thologie de saint Irne in Studia Patristica 21 (1989) 167-8.

    9 William Wordsworth put forward a similar concep, showing its popularity - if not predo minance - throughout history. The poet discemed in life the need for a limitation on knowledge and freedom, as an aid required to prevent men front becoming those who have felt the weight of too much liberty (Wordsworth, The Sonnet, i). His Ode to Duty spells out a view of divine law

    quite similar to that Irenaeus takes front Genesis: Stern Lawgiver! yet thou dost wear / The Godhead's most benignant grace; / Now know we anything so fair / As is the smile upon thy face: / Flowers laugh before thee on their beds, / And fragrance in thy footing treads; / Thou dost pre serve the stars front wrong; / And the most ancient heavens, through Thee, are fresh and strong (Ode to Duty, stanza 7). It is precisely this sense of preserving front wrong that Irenaeus detects in the prohibition against partaking of the tree of knowledge before the appointed time.

    19 See Spec.Leg. 4.80-94. 11 See De.Dec. 152-53. 12 De.Dec. 170. Cf. similar readings in Dee. 142; De agric. 43; Spec.Leg. 1.173-74, 2.190; De

    praem. et poen. 15; Quod omn. prob. 20, 79; De Joseph 29 ff. These and others mentioned with discussion in H.O. Maier, Purity and danger in Polycarp's Epistle to the Philippians: The sin of Valens in social perspective in Journal ofEarly Christian Studies 1 (1993) 240 n. 40, ofwhich we shall say more below.

    13 See ibid. 240. 11 Ibid. 239-41.

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 731

    riches indicates an allegiance to the ideals of the community of Israel.15 This pattern is traced through apocalyptic Judaism, where the abusers of wealth [...] certainly bring social ills, but more importantly they symbolize an unredeemed realm of sin awaiting destruction,16 indicating primarily that they are excluded from the true community of Israel. Ali this is the preamble to the centrepiece of Maier's argument, namely that the brief refe rence to the sin ofValens in the epistle of Polycarp [Poi. 11) reveals a similar social context through which Polycarp understood the proscriptions of the law. Maier's thesis here is straightforward:

    In the case of Polycarp, to connect avarice with defllement is to establish a group

    boundary and to relegate greed to the space outside the community; the primary

    danger of avarice is that it leads one away to a dangerous state of idolatry.17

    Maier may be reading a bit much into what is, after ali, an extremely brief and almost passing reference to Valens in the Polycarpian epistle, but his analysis of the tradition of legai interpretation through the philosophi cal schools, into Judaism through Philo and the apocalyptic era, right into the Apostolic age is of interest. Throughout, he discovers an awareness on the part of the ancient authors that the divine commandments are to some

    degree protective. They do not simply establish boundaries based upon God's authority and regal intent for his people, but based also on what is best for that people in light of the naturai limitations or weaknesses of its character.18

    To this end, Maier's conclusions have hearing upon our present look at Irenaeus' reading of the prohibition on the tree of knowledge. Just as Philo could say that prohibitions against greed of money were meant to prevent warfare and general immorality, and as Polycarp could imply that avari ciousness leads to the destruction of communal or societal order, so can Irenaeus come to regard the prohibition of Gen 2:16-17 as God's control

    against a weakness in humanity's immature character. And even as wealth

    may be good when used wisely, so, too, can the knowledge of the tree one

    day come to be of good to humankind.

    The relationship of knowledge and obedience

    Ali this is in stark contrast to the Gnostic view on knowledge, which Irenaeus has been attacking throughout the AH and to which our above

    15 Ibid. 240-1. 16 Ibid. 242. 17 Ibid. 243. 18

    Precisely the end toward which Barnabas' interpretation of the Mosaic dietary regula tions is aimed (cf. Barn. 10).

  • 732 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    text, AH 5.20.2, refers in summation. For these, a knowledge that knows more than it should is, provided that the knowledge in question is true and

    genuine, hardly a possibility. It is only false knowledge - deception or igno rant belief - that is harmful; the restoration of true knowledge and true

    knowing is indeed the primary aim of Gnostic praxis.19 Irenaeus, however, insists that at humanity's creation even true and genuine knowledge, be it in too full a measure for the limited status of the newly-formed creature, can be harmful to man. Here he follows Theophilus precisely, from this latter's comments in the AdAutol. that we have already discussed. There is nothing iniquitous in the knowledge the tree contains, which will be passed along to the human creature who partakes of its fruit. Yet in eating of this fruit, evil does come to the partaker, though the source of this evil lies in the disobe dience of the one who has eaten in contradiction to God's commandment not so to do.

    Irenaeus does not disagree with Theophilus here. There are passages throughout both his works that explicidy identify the sin of the tree with disobedience to God's command, and more generally link together sin and disobedience as theological synonyms. Indeed, disobedience may rightly be called the chief sin in Irenaean thought. Epid. 2 opens with a brief definition of sin as not keeping the commandments of God; AH4.41.3 rela tes the effects of disobedience to the disinheritance one would receive from

    parents at a similar act. As disobedience to family brings, eventually, disinheritance from family, so does disobedience to God bring a divine disinheritance. At 3.18.6, Irenaeus spells out that such disobedience - which he specifically equates to sin - renders man weak, open to the devil's captivating powers. Irenaeus is nowhere clearer in his identification of diso bedience and sin than in his discussions on the parallelism between

    Eve/Mary and Adam/Christ. He shows that Christ comes to dissolve the old disobedience of Adam,20 and Mary the knot of ve,21 with specific attention drawn to the fact that the transgression which occurred through the tree was undone by the obedience of the tree and virginal disobedience recti fied by virginal obedience.22 Christ's obedience in the Passion and Mary's obedience to the word of the angel are both corrections of the sin in Paradise, which is thus explicitly a sin of disobedience.

    This is also spelled out clearly and emphatically in an important text from the opening section of the Epid.:

    19 Cf. H.B. Timothy, The Early Christian Apologists and Greek Philosophy - exemplified by Irenaeus, Tertullian and Clement of Alexandria, Assen, 1973, 24-5 on Irenaeus' conception of

    knowledge and these Gnostic views. 20 Cf. AH 3.18.6, Epid. 37. 21 Ci. AH 3.22.4. 22

    Epid. 33.

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 733

    Sinners are those who have the knowledge of God, but do not keep his com

    mandments - that is, the disdainful.23

    This passage must be qualified in the present context, lest the identifi cation of sinners with those who have the knowledge of God be taken in some sense to disqualify Adam and ve from such a title, given the fact that the tree of knowledge was precisely that of which they were forbidden to eat. Does this fact free them from the qualifcation required by Epid. 2 for sinners? In the most basic sense, Irenaeus' answer is certainly no. Disobedience comes in defance of such knowledge as man has of God, and

    though Adam and ve had not partaken of the knowledge of good and evil, they nonetheless had a direct knowledge of the God who walked with them in the Garden and himself spoke in their hearing the law of life.24 Irenaeus can say elsewhere that the disobedient do not consent to his doc trine25 - and there was but one doctrine, one teaching, to which the first humans had been bound - reminding his readers that the law is the com mandment of God.26 This latter comment is offered in reference to the devil's activities in the Garden, summarised by Irenaeus:

    In the beginning he enticed man to transgress his maker's law, and thereby got him into his power; yet his power consiste in transgression and apostasy, and

    with these he bound man to himself.27

    Despite their limited knowledge, Adam and ve yet possessed a know

    ledge of their maker's law, that is, God's commandment, sufficient unto either obedience or disobedience. Their exercise of the latter was therefore an act of those who have the knowledge of God, but do not keep his com mandments - an act of disobedience, and thus of sin.

    The dynamic ofmaturing knowledge and responsibility

    At the same time, the knowledge of God possessed by Adam and ve was weak and basic. It was sufficient for the generation in humanity of the

    ability to heed or to depart from the will of God, but minimal enough to make understandable (if not excusable) Adam and Eve's susceptibility to a

    provoked disobedience. Disobedience, suggests Irenaeus, may be exercised at any level of knowledge. While the Israelites after Moses may have had laws by the hundreds bound up in the covenant by which they were direc ted to live, Adam and ve had only one; yet even this was sufficient for the

    23 Epid. 2; cf. Ps 1.1.

    24 J. Behr's sectional title for Epid. 15 (see J. Behr, Apostolic Preaching, 49); cf. Epid. 6. 25 AH 5.27.1. 26 AH 5.21.3. 27 Ibid. (Sources Chrtiennes 153; 274-5).

  • 734 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    act of obedience. Nonetheless, Israel's detailed Law was based on a deeper and more substantially revealed knowledge of God, was in some sense a

    portion of the knowledge of good and evil greater than that to which Adam and ve had been privy in Paradise.28 To be disobedient in such a state

    is, for Irenaeus, less understandable than was the disobedience in Eden, for

    humanity as a whole had been given to mature in its knowledge of God since the era of Paradise. To be disobedient when in communion with the Church and the new covenant of Christ is less understandable stili, for the rein has man's knowledge of God been brought to yet a higher level. This

    knowledge makes one stronger in his or her discernment of the right and the wrong, of good and of evil, and thus makes ever less pardonable any disobedience from the right. Just as a child, when maturing through her

    years, grows more accountable for her actions and less able to attribute her falls to the influence of others, so Irenaeus sees humanity as coming to know better than to sin as the economy unfolds. Adam and ve, however, were young, inexperienced, immature. They knew enough to be obedient when tempted otherwise, but not enough fully to comprehend the nature of such temptation, of deceit, of wickedness. Thus will Gen 3 present the story, not of Adam and ve spontaneously or for reasons of self-generated desire

    transgressing God's commandment, but so sinning at the provocation of a deceiver. On this account, Irenaeus speaks of the first humans predomi

    nantly as being involved in the transgression prompted by the devil. They maintain personal responsibility throughout for the fact that the decision to

    disobey is ultimately one made by Adam and ve as freely acting, self-deter

    mining individuale, but their decision is motivated by the actions of a decei ver they were little prepared to combat.29 Irenaeus here makes use of Jesus' parable of the sower to prove his point:

    The Lord, indeed, sowed good seed in his own field. Thus he says, The field is the world (Mt 13:38). But while man slept, the enemy carne and sowed tares in the midst of the wheat, and went on his way (Mt 13:25). Hence we learn that

    this was the apostate angel and enemy, because he was envious of God's work

    manship (p/asma), and took up the task of rendering this workmanship an

    enmity with God. For this cause God has banished from his presence him who did of his own accord stealthily sow the tares, that is, him who brought about the transgression: but he took compassion upon man, who, through want of care (neglegenter) no doubt, but stili wickedly, on the part of another became involved in the disobedience.30

    This passage is dense and speaks predominantly of the devil who is

    28 Cf. AH 2.11.1,2.30.9, 3.10.2. 29 Cf. T.G. Weinandy, St. Irenaeus and the Imago Dei: The Importance of Being Human in

    Logos 6A (2003) 24-6. 30 AH4.40.3 (Sources Chrtiennes 100: 978-81).

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 735

    pre-eminently at fault in the sin, for it is he who actively, in a deliberate and deceitful way acts against God and man (as later in the same passage: the devil had designed to make man the enemy of God). Man's deception by such a force is understandable, and God himself takes compassion upon his deceived creature. Irenaeus' notion of knowledge in degree of maturity bears directly upon his conviction of guilt and responsibility.31 Nonetheless, there remains a definite culpability in Adam and ve following their actions. These may have sinned at the provocation of a great foe, and through want of care (Irenaeus here implies a certain neglect (neglegenter) in Adam and ve, promoted by the lack of need and anxiety in the Garden), but stili

    wickedly. One may condemn the devil for his role in the transgression, but

    responsibility for the act of disobedience itself must rest with the man and woman who themselves contravened the divine command.32

    A prohibition but not a test

    In ali this, Irenaeus follows Theophilus in his reading of the same Genesis text, though he has greatly expanded upon the Antiochene's discus sion. God sets forth the prohibition, and the departure from obedience to this commandment brings consequences not through the tree itself or the

    knowledge it presente, but from the disobedience of the eater. Yet Irenaeus

    goes notably further than Theophilus, and while he does place pronounced emphasis upon Adam and Eve's disobedience as at fault in the transgression of God's prohibition against the tree, he refrains from any implication that a test of obedience was the primary reason for that prohibition. Rather, the commandment is an important and integrai element in the economy of man's maturation, preventing him from laying hold of that which he is una ble to bear, preserving the fullness of knowledge for a time - and there will be a time - when humanity shall be ready and able to partake of the full

    knowledge God offers.33 He will be like God just as the serpent had pre dicted, however flawed may have been the latter's intentions and under

    standings. Moreover, Irenaeus does not follow the Antiochene with respect

    31 Cf. V.K. Downing, The Doctrine of Regeneration in the Second Century in Evangelical Review ofTheology 14.2 (1990) 110, where Adam's sin, according to Irenaeus, is not a radicai infrac don of the Law but a moral mistake attributable to the spiritual and intellectual immaturity of

    Adam and ve. In this light, it is hard to accept Klebba's terminology of die Katastrophe vis--vis

    the transgression; cf. E. Klebba, Die Anthropologie des hi. Irenaeus, Munster, 1894,45. 32 On Irenaeus' belief that responsibility/guilt for disobedience cannot be imputed to

    another, seeAH4.27.2-3, 4.33.2, 5.15.2. 33 See AH 4.39.1, where Irenaeus suggests that the knowledge of good and evil will, at a

    later stage in man's development, become the foundation by which he shall be able to chose the

    one over the other. At 4.38.4, a knowledge of good and evil is considered part-and-parcel of the

    image and likeness.

  • 736 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    to the two reasons the latter had put forth in AdAutol. 2.25 for the prohibi tion, namely, as a test and a preserver of childlike innocence. There is no

    question in Irenaeus' treatment of God wishing to test Adam and ve. Their disobedience becomes apparent in the transgression, but God is not pre sented as having provoked the incident as an investigation of their respon se. Similarly, Irenaeus does not take up Theophilus' comment on God

    wishing for Adam and ve to remain in infancy for a longer period, but

    suggests simply that their infancy required such a time of expectant growth. Irenaeus extols the beauty and virtue of a simple and loving faith, but never

    suggests that this faith and its connected obedience are constrained to

    infancy and not to maturity.34 To the contrary, he makes a point of showing that such faith and obedience are perfected with the maturation of humankind, made stronger and more binding in the perfect man than

    they were in the infant Adam and ve.35 Faith becomes friendship only in

    maturity. Where Theophilus had intimated this idea in describing knowledge as

    good when one uses it properly, as we saw above, Irenaeus is explicit in his assertion that humanity one day will partake of the full measure of true

    knowledge. This is the subject of his celebrated discussion at AH 4.38-39, where he speaks most clearly of the growth and development of the human creature into perfection. Man shall, indeed, make progress day by day and ascend toward the perfect; that is, be approximated to the Uncreated One,36 but this only after he has become accustomed to eat and drink the Word of God through this arrangement [...] and these harmonies, and a sequence of this nature - i.e., the divine economy of salvation.37 This growth into the receptivity of ever increasing knowledge is an essential part of Irenaeus' larger belief in the growth of the whole person and of human nature itself, over the course of the economy, into that which one day shall behold in divine vision its creator and partake of the life of God.38 Man beco mes physically able to bear such life through the accustomisation of the Spirit made possible by the Incarnation of the Son; and even as the body grows in its receptive capabilities, so too does the intellect. Ali such growth, however, must be maintained within its due measure;39 and with respect to the intellectual aspect in particular, God thus prohibits the free eating of the tree of knowledge in Paradise.

    34 See AH 2.26.1: It is better [...] that one should have no knowledge whatever [...] but should believe in God and continue in his love; 4.12.2.

    35 See AH 4.38.4. 36 AH 4.38.3. 37 AH 4.38.1. 38 See AH4.38.4,4.39.1. 38 Cf. again Epid. 15.

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 737

    The fall ofknowledge and knowing

    Irenaeus thus employs the prohibition of Gen 2:16-17 at Epid. 15 and AH 5.20.2 to considerable effect, and its importance may be encapsulated in the observance that the divine commandment of those verses, the sole

    prohibition of Eden, is interpreted anthropocentrically by Irenaeus as per taining to the life and growth of man, and not primarily to the sovereignty or otherwise independent will of God who therein tests his new creation. It is not the exertion of God's authority, but evidence of his dedication to the

    perfection of the human handiwork. The third passage in which Irenaeus makes use of Gen 2:16-17 (and where he in fact makes far more extensive and contextualised use of these verses than he does in the passages addres sed above) demonstrates this same characteristic of interpretation, though it does so by addressing the prohibition front a different perspective: the devil's deception of Adam and ve with regard to the command. Irenaeus' intention at AH 5.23 is primarily to demonstrate the character of the devil as deceiver, and in this regard the primary example of such deception is found in his manoeuvre regarding the fruit of the tree of knowledge. Irenaeus sets

    up the situation with a complete quotation of the present verses, then pro ceeds to explicate the devil's actions, along with Eve's responses, through quotations of Gen 3:1-5 interspersed with his own commentary. In this dia

    logue, pride of place is given to Gen 3:4-5, the devil's response to Eve's reas sertion of the divine prohibition, and the promised consequence that on the day one eats of the fruit, on that day he will surely die:

    Then the serpent said to the woman, You will not surely die. For God knows

    that in the day you eat of it your eyes will be opened, and you will be like God,

    knowing good and evil.40

    Irenaeus goes on to explain the content of the deception wrapped up in the devil's words. First, he speaks of God as absent, as if the creator were not present in the garden with him and ve; and then he lies, since the pro mise of death was indeed true.41 Irenaeus is again careful to explain that this death was not caused by the fruit but by man's disobedience, for disobe dience to God entails death.42

    Irenaeus' wording at the dose of AH 5.23.1 is especially interesting:

    For along with the fruit they did also fall under the power of death, because

    they did eat in disobedience.43

    40 Quoted at AH5.23.1 (Sources Chrtiennes 153, 288-9).

    41 Cf. AH 5.23.1. The subsequent section constitutes Irenaeus' principal defence of the notion that the on the same day you eat of it of Gen 2.17 was not proved false by the long life of Adam and ve.

    42 Afi 5.23.1. 43 Sources Chrtiennes 153, 290-1, emphasis mine.

  • 738 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    The fruit itself, the potential for genuine knowledge of good and evil, the capability for godly knowledge in humanity, is, together with that

    humanity, become forfeit to death in the eating. Man's disobedience to the divine prohibition not only entails the death of his personal being, the immediate and direct consequence of his defance of God's economy; it entails also the disruption of the very nature of his potential within the eco

    nomy designed and wrought for his sake. Adam and Eve's eating in disobe dience does not disturb solely the eaters, but the very fruit of which they are partaking. This represents a substantial Irenaean insight. The forfeiture of life is both personal and historical: Adam and ve will die on that same

    day, but so also will ali human generations from that time forward perish and the fruit of the tree of knowledge will become more elusive stili.

    Irenaeus does not expand further upon his comment on the fruit fal

    ling together with man under the forfeiture to death, but his consideration of the expulsion from the Garden proffers the same essential point. Adam and ve are expelled from Paradise upon their transgression; God put the man far from his face.44 To behold God, to attain to the divine vision, is for Irenaeus the very definition of full and true knowledge.45 The casting of

    humanity out of the Garden, away from God's face and thus from pure vision, represents the same anthropological teaching as the falling of the fruit of the tree into the sway of death. The perfection of true knowledge, so much the goal of the rational human being that God planted this tree at the

    very centre of Paradise, moves outside the grasp of humankind upon its

    transgression. Adam's potential for growth in the course of the economy has been altered. This loss shall require restoration. Thus Irenaeus, like

    Theophilus, ultimately uses the prohibition and transgression as means for

    establishing the framework of salvation.

    Synthesis

    Through the eyes of Theophilus and Irenaeus we thus perceive two dif

    fering pictures of the prohibition and its purpose. Each ascertains a lack of

    negative value or evil character to the knowledge of the tree itself, but the reason for the prohibition against it differs between them. For Theophilus, God forbids the fruit primarily as a test. For Irenaeus, he does so primarily to safeguard the proper limitation of knowledge in an immature humanity. How, then, might these two views converge in a broader theological fra mework?

    As has already been mentioned, Theophilus' understanding of the

    prohibition is that which has predominated throughout history. Yet of itself,

    1 Epid. 16.

    5 See AH4.20.5, cf. E. Osborn, Irenaeus, 204-5.

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 739

    such a test-based vision poses the same ethical problems for readers today that it did in the second century, when the so-called Gnostics were keen to point out the cruelty of such an action, attributing it to a renegade demiurge rather than the benevolence of the true divinity. Marcion's solu tion was more radicai stili. The parallel in Theophilus' language vis--vis the event, to the language in the story of Abraham's near-sacrifice of Isaac, inadvertently points to the unease with which many readers encounter both texts: why be it in the nature of a good God to test in such a manner that which he has created? Either the test is a joke, given that God knew the true fabric and merit of what he had made, and in any case as omniscient would already know the outcome of any such test; or God is not in control of his creation, unable to know internally the ilk and intention of his own creatures. Neither is a supposition plausible to most Christian readers. What then to make of the test?

    Irenaeus' response is to go to the other extreme: there was in fact no test at ali. God was not challenging but defending his creation. In the face of

    knowledge which, when apprehended improperly can so easily become

    knowledge falsely so-called (its moniker in the full title of the Adversus hae reses), God lays down a commandment designed to hold back the full breadth of that knowledge until such time as newly-created man has grown into a ful ler measure of cognitive capability. It is only of love and in a spirit of paternal shepherding that God forbids the fruit of this tree, and precisely because it is that which might seem so appealing to humanity in its immaturity.

    Yet there is an inherent problem in Irenaeus' reading if taken in extrac -

    tion. If there is no element of a test in the prohibition, if there is solely pre ventative limitation in its intention, then its weight as commandment is in some sense diminished. Such a reading makes the prohibition a part of the naturai law - knowledge is limited as an aspect of humanity's rational fini tude; its fullness is proscripted not arbitrarily, but necessarily. Man ought not eat of the fruit of the tree because he cannot receive what it contains. The prohibition becomes, to some degree, part of the naturai order of laws and fundamentals in the cosmos and loses its particularity as a command, which is the source of its role as harbinger of obedience. Irenaeus will not, of course, allow this - his reading of the transgression is always sourced from the disobedience of Adam and ve to the divine law; but he is able to do this only because he believes that these in some sense failed a test never

    explicitly given as such. God did not actively test his creation in proscribing the fruit of this tree, but in fading to heed the divine guidance which forba de it, Adam and ve failed the universal test of human communion with God: obedience to the divine will.

    In the end, then, Theophilus and Irenaeus are not so far apart. The lat ter may disagree with the former on the nature of the prohibition qua prohi bition as itself a test, but this is only as regards the specific intention of the

  • 740 MATTHEW C. STEENBERG

    divine proclamation. In effect, if not in cause, humanity's obedience was tested by the primal law. And Theophilus, in turn, is not wholly without the notion of prohibition as preventative limitation which dominates the rea

    ding of Irenaeus. Knowledge is good when one uses it properly - there is a proper use, but one not available at this stage in humanity's existence. God guards against knowledge improperly attained and employed by pre venting access to the tree that represents its fullness.

    Modern-day theological readings of the Genesis protology, and speci fically anthropology, must likewise balance the two views emphasised in these second-century authors. Each dismisses outright the notion (ali too common in modem perceptions) that there is something negative in true, full and genuine knowledge, or that God for whatever reason simply did not want humanity to possess it. Then, in the mix, they offer a balance on inter

    preting the nature of the prohibition. If we read Gen 2:16-17 as only God's authoritative demand and test, we lose sense of God's sovereignty over the

    economy and existence as one who acts always for the benefit and growth of his creation. Thus Irenaeus teaches us to see economie purpose in the

    prohibition: not ali things are beneficiai at ali times, and God's law works to

    protect his creation from exceeding the bounds of that which it is able pro perly to access and contain. Yet there is always something of a test in obe dience, always a challenge to humanity's freely determining and acting will. To be obedient is to obey, and to obey is a choice, a determination. And if children must obey their parents, how much more must they obey the God and Father of the universe!46 Theophilus thus balances Irenaeus with the reminder that God's law, however economie and salvific its purpose, is

    always a challenge set against human freedom. That ali things are possible, but not ali things beneficiai (cf. 1 Cor 6:12; 10:23) is the basic presupposi tion of both our authors. Possibility is set into the context of beneficiality -

    God holds back what is ultimately good until we are ready to receive it, la Irenaeus. Yet, as in the thought of Theophilus, we must heed God's refrain, should we ever attain to that goodness.

    University of Oxford Fellow in Patristic Theology and Early Church History Greyfriars Hall

    Iffley Road Oxford 0X4 1SB

    Matthew C. Steenberg

    'Ad.Autol. 2.25.

  • TEST OR PRESERVE? 741

    SUMMARY

    Why forbid the tree? Of ali the questions that arise from a reading of the

    Genesis protology, that over why God forbade Adam and ve the fruit of the tree of

    knowledge is of perennial curiosity. The present article examines the exegesis of two

    second-century sources, Theophilus of Antioch and Irenaeus of Lyons, each of

    whom considered the question of profound importance in anthropological and

    soteriological reflections. An emphasis on the prohibition as a test in Theophilus meets the alternate interpretation of the prohibition as a formative construct in

    defining the limits of human intellectual capability according to Irenaeus. These are

    explored in detail, and at the article's end are synthesised in a reading of the Genesis

    prohibition that makes use of both points of emphasis.

    Perch vietare l'albero?. Di tutte le questioni che sorgono dalla lettura della

    protologia della Genesi quella riguardante il perch Dio vieti ad Adamo ed Eva il frutto dell'albero della conoscenza suscita da sempre curiosit. Il presente articolo

    esamina due fonti del II secolo, Teoflo d'Antiochia e Ireneo di Lione, ciascuno dei

    quali consider la questione d'estrema importanza riflettendovi dal punto di vista

    antropologico e soteriologico. Un'enfasi sulla proibizione come prova in Teofilo

    incontra l'interpretazione alternativa della proibizione come concetto formativo nel

    definire i limiti della capacit intellettiva umana secondo Ireneo. Queste posizioni sono esaminate dettagliatamente e sintetizzate, infine, in una lettura della proibi zione della Genesi che tenga conto dell'enfasi di entrambi i punti di vista.

    Article Contentsp. [723]p. 724p. 725p. 726p. 727p. 728p. 729p. 730p. 731p. 732p. 733p. 734p. 735p. 736p. 737p. 738p. 739p. 740p. 741

    Issue Table of ContentsGregorianum, Vol. 86, No. 4 (2005) pp. 723-952To test or preserve? The prohibition of Gen 2.16-17 in the thought of two second-century exegetes [pp. 723-741]The Inevitability of Allegory [pp. 742-753]Grazia e Ordine nel dialogo anglicano-romano cattolico [pp. 754-775]Das Naturgesetz als dialogische Emergenz des Ethischen: Zum Verhltnis zwischen lex aeterna, lex naturalis und motus rationalis creaturae im De-lege-Traktat der Summa Theologiae Thomas von Aquins [pp. 776-805]Jews and Judaism in Asian Theology. Historical and Theological Perspectives [pp. 806-836]Von der Schwierigkeit eines evidentiellen Arguments gegen die Existenz Gottes [pp. 837-856]Filosofia da Aritmtica em Kant [pp. 857-874]Intensitt oder die Phnomenalisierung durch reine Erprobung [pp. 875-897]RECENSIONESTHEOLOGIAReview: untitled [pp. 898-899]Review: untitled [pp. 899-901]Review: untitled [pp. 902-903]Review: untitled [pp. 903-904]Review: untitled [pp. 904-905]Review: untitled [pp. 905-907]Review: untitled [pp. 907-908]

    PHILOSOPHIAReview: untitled [pp. 909-910]Review: untitled [pp. 910-911]Review: untitled [pp. 912-912]

    SPIRITUALITASReview: untitled [pp. 913-914]Review: untitled [pp. 914-915]Review: untitled [pp. 915-917]Review: untitled [pp. 917-919]Review: untitled [pp. 919-919]

    HISTORIAReview: untitled [pp. 920-921]Review: untitled [pp. 921-923]Review: untitled [pp. 923-924]Review: untitled [pp. 924-925]Review: untitled [pp. 926-926]

    CONCILIAReview: untitled [pp. 927-928]Review: untitled [pp. 928-929]Review: untitled [pp. 929-931]Review: untitled [pp. 931-932]Review: untitled [pp. 932-933]

    INDICATIONESReview: untitled [pp. 934-935]Review: untitled [pp. 935-935]

    LIBRI NOSTRIReview: untitled [pp. 936-936]Review: untitled [pp. 937-937]Review: untitled [pp. 937-938]Review: untitled [pp. 938-938]Review: untitled [pp. 939-939]Review: untitled [pp. 939-939]

    Opera accepta: 16.V.2005 1.IX.2005 [pp. 940-947]Back Matter