The battle between rationality and subjectivity in scientific theory choice

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/14/2019 The battle between rationality and subjectivity in scientific theory choice

    1/5

    The battle between rationality and subjectivity in scientifictheory choice

    IntroductionIt is by far accepted in science the existence oftheories, despite the differences in the interpretation

    of the word's meaning, although most commonly referred to as the set of beliefs regarding our

    reality (e.g. the New Oxford American Dictionary defines a theory as a supposition or system of

    ideas intended to explain something). This paper will take for granted the existence of something,

    even not quite specified, called theory and move on to examine instead what happens whenscientists are confronted with choosing among different theories, for the purpose of determining

    where the truth lies in science.

    Choosing a theory or another has great implications on the current conception of the world by the

    scientist, as well as on the future possible developments of a certain scientific field. Therefore,

    carefully selecting the first step of a determined scientific direction is a very heartfelt topic, both inscience and in philosophy of science.

    Theory choice involves a decision on which, among different theories, can be considered more

    true than another. Being a decision, it can be characterized as either rational/objective, or

    subjective, or a mix of the two. Philosophers have for long time debated the character of this

    decision, in order to determine its validity and its consequences. Additionally, philosophers have

    been exploring theory choice both as a normative issue (i.e. confronted with two theories, which

    oneshouldwe pick?) and as a historical issue (i.e. how have been theories chosen in the history ofscience?).

    This paper will outline the history of such debates in light of both battlefields (rational vs.

    subjective and history of science vs. philosophy of science). Then, an authors own intepretation

    will be advanced. In the end, the open issues still to be resolved will be presented.

    Rationality 101: Bacon

    In the dawn of scientific method, Francis Bacon was a keen supporter of observationism. To him,

    Nature would disclose its secrets and its truth only to the people who observed with no prejudice in

    mind, with no particular bias to hamper their observations. Prejudice, manifesting itself in

    traditions, culture and habits, produced expectations of our observations; those expectations

    distorted the results of our observations, by interpreting them against our preconceived theories.

    In this methodology, science was an objective discipline: with the proper mindset one could reveal

    the truth of Nature and therefore, of life; Nature was there for all of those with a pure mind who

    would have access to it and the truth was one and available for everybody with the right tools.

    To Bacon, Aristotle's geocentric theory was the truth, since he was able to open his eyes and see that

    the sun is revolving around the earth and not the other way round. Theory choice for Bacon was

    more a matter of revelation, than choice.

    A little bit of subjectivity in the picture: Popper

    Karl Popper opposed Bacon's methodology: to him, a pure mind is an empty mind and no

    observation could be done without preconceived notions. The very fact of observing something

    would prove that we're explicitly choosing an observation object and we have expectations about it.

    In Popper, we can see the first differentiation of two important areas: the context of discovery and

    the context of justification. In the first one, the scientist would come up with a theory; in the second

    one, the scientist would prove it right/wrong. According to Popper, the context of discovery was notso much important as the one of justification: a famous example given by the philosopher is the

    discovery of the structure of a benzene molecule in a dream of some scientist. The context of

  • 8/14/2019 The battle between rationality and subjectivity in scientific theory choice

    2/5

    justification is where Popper's main idea comes into play: theories should be falsifiable; an instance

    or an observation that proves the theory wrong should be possible. For example, one could derive

    the theory that all swans are white by observing some white swans in a lake: in that case, finding

    anywhere else a black swan in the world would prove the theory wrong; the very idea of having an

    observation that could prove the theory wrong makes the theory falsifiable.

    In Popper's philosophy, theory choice works by gradual substitution of theories with better ones and

    with the growth of knowledge: as soon a theory is falsified, it is substituted by another one whohasn't been yet falsified. In case of more not yet falsified theories, the one that accounts for the

    biggest number of observations should be considered the best one.

    Subjectivity big time: Kuhn

    Kuhn shifts the attention from the normative field, where Popper has been mostly focusing on, to

    the historical development of science. In his The structure of scientific revolutions, he shows to thereader that theory choices (or better, in his terms, paradigm shifts) occur as a leap of faith by

    scientists, with no real objective criteria underneath them.

    However, as a response to his critics, he explains more in detail the fact that he does indeed see

    rational/objective criteria for theory choice, but their interpretation is highly subjective.

    Rationality hits back: Lakatos

    Kuhn's works turned the issue of theory choice, in the words of his own critics, to a matter of mob

    psychology. Imre Lakatos, reflecting on Popper's and Kuhn's writings, produced an elaborate

    methodology which tried to encompass both views and gain back the elements of rationality that

    were missing in Kuhn. His methodology of scientific research programmes outlines a network oftheories, some more fundamental than others, that constitutes a scientific programme. Each

    programme can grow, by acquiring new detailed theories that confirm the observations, or shrink,

    according to falsifying observations. At one point in history, one programme overcomes the other,

    because of its bigger capacity in explaining existing observations; there's no guarantee however that

    the defeated programme won't come back to prove itself right.In this context, choosing between scientific programmes is a rational endeavour, since it involves

    observing whether a programme is growing (progressing) or not (degenerating).

    History of science confirms this view and shows also how one can never be sure of which

    programme will eventually succeed.

    Subjectivity all the way: Feyerabend

    The latest writings on the topic at hand are by Paul Feyerabend. His view on the normative aspect

    of theory choice is totally demeaning: no real progress can be made with a methodology that limits

    the scientist's activities when approaching and working with reality and that deprives scientists from

    their human component.To Feyerabend, anarchism rules and history of science confirms it.

    A look at the issues

    Throughout this long historical debate, philosophers have put forward arguments related a number

    of elements related with theory choice. In order to discuss about the current topic, an overview of

    these elements is necessary, to identify connections and influences among them, as well as their

    current status of development throughout the various philosophical positions.

    Theory-ladeness of observation

    One of the main arguments against rationality in theory choice is that observations are influencedby our own prior theories and beliefs. Differently from Bacons prejudice, these beliefs and theories

    cant be ultimately separated, isolated and eliminated from our mental processes, since theyre

    either born naturally with us or theyre product of our own personal history and development. In

  • 8/14/2019 The battle between rationality and subjectivity in scientific theory choice

    3/5

    other words, we might not know it, be were naturally biased. The extent of the bias is and has been

    debated as one of the central issues in theory choice.

    Algorithms of choice

    Once theories are put forward, the other step of the process is actually choosing them, or more

    specifically executing a certain algorithm of choice. For Popper, the algorithm was accepting the

    theory with the bigger number of observations explained. For others, the algorithm involvedcomparison and ranking theories according to a certain set of criteria.

    Criteria of choice

    The criteria according to which theories are evaluated and subsequently chosen one over the other is

    another central issue. Kuhn, for example, admits that such criteria might exist, but their

    interpretation is subjective so they dont play in favour of the rational interpretation of theory

    choice.

    Progress

    And finally, when a pattern comes out of all the theory choices made over the years, a fundamental

    question is: what does this pattern look like? Is there progress? What is progress?

    Discussion

    Rational = agreed upon?

    One of the first elements that strike my attention in the whole debate is the use of the word

    rational. It is my belief that the meaning of the word rational in the discussion on theory choice

    is most often assumed to be agreed upon by a significant number of fellow scientists/researchers.

    In fact, there is no definite proof of the existence of an abstract rational truth, but rather a truth

    that many people practicing the same profession hold to be true. A person not belonging to that

    same group might perceive and assign a different meaning to that word, and consequently

    characterize a certain process or behavior or choice as rational or not rational in different casesas a member of the scientific community.

    I attribute this linguistic misunderstanding to the accumulated knowledge of past history of science.

    Current scientists are both voluntarily and involuntarily accepting the influence of rational

    concepts related to their discipline (e.g. the scientific method, the use of experiments as validating

    proof, etc.). In the same way that recent cognitive science is uncovering the rationality of processes

    and behaviors that have seemed for a long time irrational, I claim that behaviors and processes

    considered at many times as rational are a result of that labeling only through the collective

    agreement of a significant amount of scientists and related members of the scientific community.

    Another proof of that is the interpretationpost hoc of past history of science: many of the theories

    advanced and supported in the past centuries might appear highly irrational to the modern scientist,

    but they were for sure considered rational at the time of their discovery or creation.

    This turns the whole debate on whether theory choice is in a scale between rationality and

    subjectivity into a debate on whether theory choice is in a scale between common agreement and

    agreement with just one person. Lakatos methodology is a good example of that debate: to him,

    however, the perspective is on two sets of theories (research programmes) that contend each other,

    until one prevails (even if temporarily) on the other. But what is this victory if not the significant

    outnumbering by supporters of the first research programme over the supporters of the other one?

    Or, in other words, doesnt the shift in choice happen when most scientists agree on one of the

    options?

    The process of theory choice in history of science

  • 8/14/2019 The battle between rationality and subjectivity in scientific theory choice

    4/5

    If seen under this assumption, history of science becomes a series of shifts in the opinions of

    scientists communities, to support one theory or the other, according to the extent to which that

    theory fits with their views.

    Imagine a theory that is put forward, regardless of the way its born. There will be an initial

    individual of group of scientists supporting it, according to the way the theory fits them: either

    through subjective appeal, or through more rational methods (e.g. experiments, etc.). What this

    initial differentiation determines is simply what will be the initial degree of support to that theory. Ifthe theory fits their creators for its rational characteristics, then a wider community of scientists

    will most probably accept it, since rational characteristics are very commonly agreed upon in the

    scientific community. On the contrary, if it will have more subjective (i.e. uncommon)

    characteristics, then it will probably appeal to a smaller group.

    Neither of the two sets of characteristics however can predict if that theory will survive or not in the

    progress of science. History of science shows us that theories with both sets of characteristics have

    advanced in the centuries, lived on the scientists scrutiny or been rejected shortly after creation. No

    conclusive evidence can show a connection between the type of theory choice (rational or

    subjective or better, agreed upon or not commonly agreed upon) and its current status as valid

    explanation of reality.

    Normative theory choice

    What all this doesnt tell us is: if theory choice is a matter of mob psychology, how are scientists

    supposed to make decisions that distinguish between a valid theory that is an explanation for reality

    and another one that isnt?

    I believe there are two issues at stake: individuality and free will.

    Individuality is simply the fact that two individuals are different in their perception of reality. As

    such, it is impossible to formulate a theory choice algorithm that will yield the same results for any

    two individuals within or out of the scientific community. Or, in other words, There is no neutral

    algorithm for theory-choice, no systematic decision procedure which, properly applied, must leadeach individual in the group to the same decision. (Kuhn, 1970, p. 200).

    Secondly, even if there were such algorithms, the underlying assumption would be that each one of

    us would be willing and able to use them properly and by them achieving the right choice.

    However, I believe that that choice is conditioned by the existence of free will, which is something

    yet to be proven conclusively. Genetic dispositions, as well as environmental factors contribute to

    the mix of elements that enter the decision of a person for on theory or another. Recent discoveries

    in the human genome proof how certain behaviors and processes are hard-wired in our DNA and

    not a result of our own self-generated brain activity. Also, the context of our personal development

    has a strong influence on who we are and therefore what decisions we make. A highly educated

    Western scholar in philosophy of science might have different interpretations and therefore makedifferent choices using the same algorithms and/or criteria, than somebody brought up, for example,

    as a Tibetan monk.

    What this all amounts to is the impossibility of determining a norm for theory choice, but rather

    determining its boundaries and exposing its root causes. We know more about what were likely to

    choose rather than what we should choose. We know more about why we make those choices,

    rather than having a significant degree of control over them.

    As Feyerabend wrote, anything goes (1975, p. 28): theres no method or criteria or algorithm that

    can be successfully applied to choose between a theory and another one. I would modify it into

    anything goes, within the constraints set on us and on the world at large by nature itself: we can

    choose anything, but we know that the choice is influenced by the constraints within us and outsideof us.

    Truth and progress

  • 8/14/2019 The battle between rationality and subjectivity in scientific theory choice

    5/5

    One last issue is the one of truth and progress of science. If all I wrote above is true, where does

    truth lie in science? Are our conditioned choices bringing us to the truth? Is there real progress in

    the patterns of theories and scientific paradigms in history? Are we getting closer to the truth and to

    a valid explanation of reality as it is?

    I believe that patterns in theory choice reflect a pattern of evolution. The way theory choice impacts

    our lives reflects the degree to which we make use of those theories: when we choose for theories

    that can validly depict reality, not only we try to explain reality but we also try to predict it; whenour predictions turn true and we benefit from their success, then the theory is described as accurate

    and we mark it as proven. Whenever instead we realize that a theory is delivering wrong predictions

    and therefore negative consequences occur, we discard it and label it as wrong.

    Usefulness and survival of theories reflects survival and development of our species: if were

    choosing accurate theories, we develop on them accordingly. Theories about aerodynamics allow us

    to benefit from airplanes, theories about human biology allow us to live longer and healthier lives;

    and so forth. Progress in science proceeds together with progress of our human species. More than

    that, the development of mankind is the proof that those theories are workable explanations of

    reality and the fact were using them to our benefit is a proof that they fit the reality thats out there

    and that we try to understand.

    Conclusions

    In the previous chapters, I have tried to outline the developments on the issue of theory choice in

    science. From Bacon to Feyerabend, philosophers have been giving different explanations of how

    theories are chosen and how should they be chosen. Nowadays, the rational positions of Bacon are

    overcome by a large part of scholars, whereas the rational elements in Popper and Lakatos still hold

    true in many cases. On the other hand, subjective elements are hardly proved wrong and the battle

    looks more favourable for them at this point of time.

    Then, I introduced some issues that I think lay before the debate between rationality and

    subjectivity. First of all, the interpretation of the terms in the discussion (rational = agreed upon?),then the elements of individuality and free will in normative theory choice.

    Within this framework of explanation of theory choice, there are still some open issues to be

    answered: how does linguistics affect philosophy of science and its terminology? What is the

    impact of modern genetic research into the workings of our brain processes and how does that

    impact theory choice? The debate on these questions is still open and, perhaps, even more important

    than the central question of this paper.

    References

    Popper, Science: problems, aims, responsibilities, 1963

    Kuhn, Objectivity, value judgement and theory choice, 1973

    Kuhn, The structure of scientific revolutions, 1970

    Lakatos, The methodology of scientific research programmes, 1977

    Feyerabend,Against method, 1975