Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    1/274

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    2/274

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    3/274

    Naturalism and Realism in Kant ’s Ethics

    In this comprehensive assessment of Kant ’s metaethics, Frederick Rauscher 

    shows that Kant is a moral idealist rather than a moral realist and argues that 

    Kant ’s ethics does not require metaphysical commitments that go beyond

    nature. Rauscher frames the argument in the context of Kant ’s nonnaturalistic

    philosophical method and the character of practical reason as action-oriented.

    Reason operates entirely within nature, and apparently nonnatural claims   –

    God, free choice, and value  – are shown to be heuristic and to reect reason’s

    ordering of nature. The book shows how Kant hesitates between a transcen-

    dental moral idealism with an empirical moral realism and a complete moral

    idealism. Examining every aspect of Kant ’s ethics, from the categorical impe-

    rative to freedom and value, this volume argues that Kant ’s focus on human

    moral agency explains morality as a part of nature. It will appeal to academic

    researchers and advanced students of Kant, German idealism, and intellectual

    history.

    f r e d e ri c k r a u s c he r   is Professor of Philosophy at Michigan State

    University. He is the editor and co-translator of   Kant: Lectures and Drafts

    on Political Philosophy   (with Kenneth R. Westphal, Cambridge, 2015),

    co-translator of  Notes and Fragments (with Paul Guyer and Curtis Bowman,

    Cambridge, 2005), and editor of  Kant in Brazil  (2012).

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    4/274

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    5/274

    Naturalism and Realism in

    Kant ’s Ethics

    Frederick Rauscher 

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    6/274

    University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom 

    Cambridge University Press is part of the University of Cambridge.

    It furthers the University’s mission by disseminating knowledge in the pursuit of education, learning and research at the highest international levels of excellence.

    www.cambridge.orgInformation on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107088801

    © Frederick Rauscher 2015

    This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exceptionand to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,no reproduction of any part may take place without the writtenpermission of Cambridge University Press.

    First published 2015 A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library

     Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication dataRauscher, Frederick, 1961–Naturalism and realism in Kant ’s ethics / Frederick Rauscher.   –  1 [edition].

    pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index.ISBN 978-1-107-08880-1 (Hardback : alk. paper)1. Kant, Immanuel, 1724–1804. 2. Ethics. 3. Naturalism. 4. Realism. I. Title.B2799.E8R38 2015170.92–dc23 2015020982

    ISBN 978-1-107-08880-1 Hardback 

    Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracyof URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication,and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,accurate or appropriate.

    http://www.cambridge.org/http://www.cambridge.org/9781107088801http://www.cambridge.org/http://www.cambridge.org/9781107088801

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    7/274

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    8/274

    Acknowledgments

    I thank   rst and more than anyone else my spouse Delores and my children

    Konrad, Bennett, and Audrey for their love and support as I spent long days

    working on this book over too many years. Without their patience this book 

    would never have been  nished. This book is for them.Numerous colleagues and students have helped me to shape my ideas and

    I here want to particularly thank several people who most generously com-

    mented on this book as it was being drafted. Darlei Dall’Agnol pushed and

    prodded me into better explaining and defending my views both in conversa-

    tions and through his published criticisms. I greatly beneted from conversa-

    tions and exchanges with Oliver Sensen and Patrick Kain. All three of them,

    along with Paul Guyer, also kindly read parts of the  nal manuscript. Robert 

    Louden and an anonymous reviewer for Cambridge University Press provided

    extensive comments that helped me to improve my presentation and argu-ments. I am deeply grateful to them all, as well as to those who helped me in

    earlier years when some of this material was published in independent papers.

    I am also indebted to Cambridge University Press editors Hilary Gaskin and

    Rosemary Crawley for their guidance in this project.

    I am grateful to Michigan State University for a research leave and Inter-

    mural Research Grant that allowed initial work on the book, and a sabbatical

    that allowed me to complete it. In between, I was grateful to have many oppor-

    tunities to present my work, resulting in quite a different book than originally

    conceived. The Federal University of Santa Catarina, the Federal University of Rio Grande do Norte, the Federal University of Pelotas, the Federal University

    of Pernambuco, the Pontical Catholic University in Rio de Janeiro, the Ponti-

    cal Catholic University of Parana, the State University of Campinas, and

    the University of São Paulo in Brazil, Pisa University in Italy, the Philipps

    University in Marburg and the University of Siegen in Germany, the Uni-

    versity of Illinois, University of Pennsylvania, Brown University, Western

    Michigan University, and Michigan State University in the United States all

    provided opportunities either directly or by hosting conferences for me to

    present this work in various stages of development. I am indebted to the many

    vi

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    9/274

    contributors to discussions at these events who have stimulated my thought 

    and caused me to deepen my interpretation.

    I wish also to thank the original publishers of material reproduced here.

    With the exception of   “‘God’   Without God”, which forms the content of 

    Chapter 5   with little alteration, these papers have been excerpted and/or modied. In most cases, only parts of the paper are included in the book, even

    scattered over several chapters.

    Part of   Chapter 4:   “Freedom and Reason in Groundwork III”   in

    Kant ’ s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical 

    Guide, edited by Jens Timmermann (Cambridge University Press,

    2009), pp. 203–23.

    Part of   Chapter 2:   “Why Kant ’s Ethics is A Priori   –   and Why It 

    Matters”, in   Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants: Akten

    des X Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, Band 3, hrsg. Valerio

    Rohden, Ricardo Terra, Guido de Almeida, and Margit Ruf ng

    (Berlin: Walter deGruyter, 2008), pp. 347–57.

    Chapter 5:   “‘God’   Without God: Kant ’s Postulate”   Kant e-Prints

    Série 2, v. 2, n. 1, jan.– jun., (2007), pp. 27–62 [www.cle.unicamp.

    br/kant-e-prints/ ]

    Part of  Chapter 4:   “Reason as a Natural Cause”, in Moralische Moti-

    vation. Kant und die Alternativen,   edited by Heiner F. Klemme,

    Manfred Kühn, and Dieter Schönecker. Reihe  Kant Forschungen

    Band 16. (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2006), pp.97–110.

    Parts of  Chapters 1 and 3:   “Kant ’s Moral Anti-Realism ”,  Journal of 

    the History of Philosophy  40 (2002): 477–99.

    Parts of   Chapters 2   and   3:   “Kant ’s Two Priorities of Practical

    Reason”,   British Journal for the History of Philosophy   6 (3)

    (1998): 397–419.

    Parts of  Chapters 2 and 4 were originally published in Portuguese as

    “Razão prática pura como uma faculdade natural” [“Pure Practical

    Reason as a Natural Faculty”], translated by Milene Consenso

    Tonetto,   Ethic@   5 (2006), pp. 173–192 [https://periodicos.ufsc.

    br/index.php/ethic/issue/view/1453]

    Part of   Chapter 7   was originally published in Portuguese as   “Os

    limites externos da  losoa prática e as limitações da Dedução na 

    Fundamentação  III”, translated by Kariel Giarolo,  Studia Kantiana

    14 (2013): 127–41 and in German as   “Die äußerste Grenze aller 

    praktischen Philosophie und die Einschränkungen der Deduktion in

    Grundlegung  III”, in Kants Begründung von Freiheit und Moral in

    Grundlegung III: Neue Interpretationen edited by Dieter Schönecker,

    (Münster: Mentis Verlag, 2015), pp. 217–31.

    Acknowledgments vii

    http://www.cle.unicamp.br/kant-e-prints/http://www.cle.unicamp.br/kant-e-prints/https://periodicos.ufsc.br/index.php/ethic/issue/view/1453https://periodicos.ufsc.br/index.php/ethic/issue/view/1453http://www.cle.unicamp.br/kant-e-prints/http://www.cle.unicamp.br/kant-e-prints/https://periodicos.ufsc.br/index.php/ethic/issue/view/1453https://periodicos.ufsc.br/index.php/ethic/issue/view/1453

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    10/274

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    11/274

    Introduction

    Among the  rst conceptions I had of Kant ’s philosophy, provided second- or 

    third-hand when I was in college before I had studied him enough to be able to

     judge it, was the tale that Kant had divided the world into two separate realms,

    that of appearances in space and time, constituting nature, and that of things inthemselves eerily existing not in space and time, constituting morality. This

    neat division seemed like a tidy way of dealing with the potential conict 

    between our moral lives and the scientic world view. As I learned more about 

    Kant, it became clear that the ontological division was not that simple and that 

    whatever it was, it did not map onto the nature/morality division. The proper 

    understanding of these issues became a lasting puzzle.

    This book is an attempt to solve that puzzle by showing what morality is and

     just how nature and morality relate to one another in Kant. I have two main

    goals. The   rst is to show that Kant ’s ethics is fully compatible with a 

    metaphysical naturalism, meaning that no property or entity outside of empir-

    ically real nature in space and time is needed. The second is to determine the

    extent to which Kant is a moral realist, which can be decided only through a 

    detailed look at the nature of Kant ’s ethics and its specic elements. I will

    conclude that the most plausible interpretation is that Kant is a moral idealist 

    (the term I prefer to   “anti-realist ”   or    “constructivist ”) rather than a realist,

    although given the resources in his philosophy, he could have been a realist in

    a limited sense.

    Part One,   “Laying the Ground,”

     sets the stage for the detailed assessment byproviding denitions of metaphysical naturalism and moral realism and by

    showing how ethics  ts into Kant ’s philosophical project as a whole. This part 

    is crucial for the overall project because it assesses the inadequacy of some

    ways of approaching realism and naturalism, and provides an explanation for 

    the particular approach I take. The review of Kant ’s philosophical project 

    importantly shows the way in which transcendental philosophy allows for a 

    metaphysical naturalism and the way in which the claims of practical reason

    are prima facie not ontological. While some readers are familiar with these

    basic positions, the details and conclusions I draw here bear specically on theparticular topics in later chapters and form the foundation of their arguments.

    1

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    12/274

    Chapter 1 provides a denition of realism in terms of the independence of some

    moral principles, properties, or objects from the moral agent. I argue that this is a 

    better denition for use in assessing Kant than one focused on the truth of moral

    claims because the real issue between realists and idealists is not whether Kant ’s

    morality claims objective validity but how to understand Kant ’s a priori moral

    law, the nature of practical reason, and autonomy in relation to moral agency.

    I treat moral agency in two ways: as actual agents in nature (empirical) and as the

    necessary conditions for the possibility of any moral agent at all (that I label

    “transcendental”   in reference to the transcendental method of justication).

    This distinction allows for Kant to be both an idealist and a realist at different 

    levels, and provides the complexity necessary to resolve the multi-faceted issue.

    I then turn to naturalism, which is divided into methodological and metaphysical

    naturalism. The former would claim that the only proper methodologies for 

    nding knowledge are those of the natural sciences; Kant rejects this in light of his use of a priori concepts and his transcendental method. I explain metaphysical

    naturalism, which claims that the only entities that exist are those determined by

    the natural sciences, in relation to Kant ’s own conception of nature as consisting

    of matter studied by physics (and less strictly also by chemistry and biology) and

    thinking nature studied by empirical psychology (and related disciplines).

    A metaphysically naturalistic Kantian ethics would hold that nothing beyond

    the entities in space and time, physical and mental, is needed for morality. The

    chapter concludes with a list of the eight elements of Kant ’s ethics that need to be

    assessed as realist or idealist: particular ends, particular duties, absolute value, thehighest good and the postulates, moral obligation, the moral law itself, pure

    practical reason, and free choice. Thus, the task of the remainder of the book is

    to assess these elements in terms of the transcendental and empirical levels of 

    realism and the possible limitation to nature in space and time.

    Chapter 2 examines the nature of Kant ’s philosophy overall in order to place

    morality in its proper context and show how that framework affects realism 

    and naturalism. I note that Kant insists that philosophy aims at systematically

    organized cognitions, with the overall aim at the essential ends of human

    reason. Each part requires a domain and further subdivision into parts inaccordance with a system. I look at several broad divisions of philosophy in

    Kant  – critique/system, pure/empirical cognition, and theoretical/practical, and

    note how they interrelate. I show how the method of transcendental argument 

    provides Kant with a general way to defend ethical claims without resorting to

    a non-natural metaphysics. Transcendental argument justies the use of a 

    priori cognitions by cognizers in nature as part of their empirical cognitive

    systems. In looking at various ways to construe the theoretical/practical dis-

    tinction, I show that the domain for practical philosophy is free acts understood

    from the perspective of agents engaged in deliberation. With these founda-tional issues settled, the detailed work can begin.

    2 Introduction

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    13/274

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    14/274

    when he denies that the moral law can be subject to a transcendental deduction

    and when he limits his claim to the practical point of view. Kant would then be

    an empirical moral idealist about reason and the status of the moral law.

    The  nal part of the book,   “Morality Beyond Nature?,”  looks at God, free

    choice, and absolute value. These elements of Kant ’s ethics represent apparently

    non-natural entities or properties and cannot be understood in the same meta-

    physically naturalistic way that reason itself can, that is, they cannot be an actual

    part of nature operating as the empirically real manifestation of the transcen-

    dental conditions of moral agency. Instead, I show that God and free choice have

    a role through the postulates that comprehends them as concepts created by

    reason without reference to the purported non-natural object or property but 

    only with an immanent reference as aids to moral action. I argue that value for 

    Kant cannot be an independent property of objects either within or outside

    nature, but is merely a part of the order imposed on nature by practical reason.I then link that order back to the status of practical reason itself.

    Chapter 5  argues that Kant ’s conception of a postulate has much more in

    common with the general nature of ideas of reason than it does with any claim 

    to existence. I trace Kant ’s development of the notion of a postulate along with

    the similar notions of transcendental hypothesis, idea of reason, and belief.

    I show that the idea of the highest good has no ontological implications of its

    own and focus on the postulate of God, since the same solution will also hold

    of the postulate of immortality. The postulate of God, I show, is supposed to

    have immanent reference, that is, to empirical agents’

     moral lives, rather thantranscendent reference, that is, to a being in itself. In the practical point of 

    view, empirical moral agents operate with the concept of God for certain

    purposes but relate it only to the ought, not to the is.

    Chapter 6 assesses the most dif cult problem for a naturalist interpretation

    of Kant ethics: freedom of the will as the freedom of the power of choice in

    making a decision uncaused by anything in nature. I have two strategies in this

    chapter. I  rst show that Kant insists that free choice is needed for two reasons

    related to ought-implies-can and moral responsibility. Both reasons require

    only one non-natural choice, not a multitude as some commentators prefer.This single timeless choice of the entirety of one’s phenomenal character is the

    best interpretation of his claims about freedom, timelessness, distinct causality,

    and the intelligible character in relation to free choice. While still unnatural, it 

    is at least the minimal non-natural interpretation. Second, I argue that stressing

    the status of freedom as a postulate, which Kant himself does not, allows for a 

    naturalistic interpretation of this choice as a concept merely playing a heuristic

    role in moral life.

    The  nal chapter  moves from value in particular to the status of the practical

    point of view, or moral experience more broadly, in general. I reject thepossibility of any non-natural, intrinsic value property and instead show that 

    4 Introduction

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    15/274

    the value of humanity as an end in itself is nothing more than the highest rank 

    in the order of ends that reason imposes on nature through the categorical

    imperative. The intelligible order of things is not an order of intelligible things

    but a rational ordering of natural things. I draw together Kant ’s various

    discussions of this direct application of the moral law to experience as a moralworld. This is the way that practical reason applies to nature within the

    practical point of view. Culminating this chapter is a look at the limits to

    practical reason that Kant reveals in   Groundwork   III, where he admits that 

    reason’s own structure that requires both systematic connection and uncondi-

    tional explanation is responsible for the claim that there is a necessary moral

    law, and holds, in language similar to that of the Third Antinomy, that reason,

    the source of morality, is itself ultimately incomprehensible.

    In a postscript, I review the particular assessments I made regarding the

    eight elements of Kant ’s moral theory laid out in Chapter 1. I pull together the

    features of my interpretation of Kant as a metaphysical naturalist. The various

    claims about transcendental and empirical realism and idealism are arranged

    into their basic sets and the core interpretive points that ground the main

    disagreement set out. I have identied a Kantian transcendental moral idealism 

    that is also an empirical realism, thus dissolving some of the realist/construct-

    ivist disagreement. I show, however, that Kant is himself hesitant to endorse

    this transcendental validity for morality and, particularly in light of the priority

    of the practical point of view as an agent-perspective rational ordering of 

    nature with no ontological claims of its own, that the more appropriateconclusion is that Kant was an empirical moral idealist.

    A brief word about my methodological approach. I am not providing a 

    strictly exegetical work. There are passages in Kant ’s writings that are incon-

    sistent with elements of my interpretation, but I would argue that the same is

    true of all interpretations of Kant given his own inconsistent use of termin-

    ology and the diverse contexts in which he applies the same terms. The

    purpose of this book is not merely historical but is aimed at assessing Kant ’s

    ethics in light of twenty-rst century concerns about naturalism and realism.

    My work is reconstructive in that I pursue the philosophical implications of Kant ’s positions to sometimes make connections that Kant himself does not 

    explicitly make. I believe that all of my claims are consistent with Kant ’s

    general philosophical aims, methods, arguments, and conclusions, and nearly

    always with his particular stated positions. Given the novelty of Kant ’s

    philosophy, the complexity of the issues he raises, the vast range of his project,

    the transformations of some of his positions over time, and above all, the

    requirement of the interpreter to go beyond merely quoting texts in order to

    explain a great philosopher ’s work in ways relevant to the present, no compre-

    hensive interpretation can offer more than that.

    Introduction 5

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    16/274

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    17/274

    Part I 

    Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    18/274

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    19/274

    1 Moral realism and naturalism 

    My study aims at providing an interpretation of Kant ’s ethics that cuts across

    the issues of realism and naturalism. I see these two issues as closely con-

    nected. One cannot resolve the question of whether and to what extent Kant 

    was a moral realist without resolving questions about the metaphysical statusof the elements of Kant ’s ethics. These elements, such as the status of reason

    itself, the nature of value, and freedom of the will, relate to the conception

    Kant has of the limits of human experience and legitimate claims that go

    beyond experience. This concern in turn raises the issue of nature as a limit for 

    experience. Whether ethics goes beyond nature is in this way tied to the issue

    of realism. The reverse is also true: When asking about whether Kant ’s ethics

    is compatible with naturalism, one has to start with a conception of nature in

    Kant and then turn to the particular elements. One would expect that anything

    in nature would count as real for Kant, and on the empirical level, that is true of objects and of mental states and faculties. Questions arise, however, about how

    to place in nature the distinctive perspective of the practical and its distinctive

    role in determining what ought to be rather than what is. And since Kant also

    invokes a transcendental level of analysis, some elements of the experience

    moral beings have in nature might be ideal in the same sense that space and

    time and the categories are ideal. A detailed understanding of what might be

    real and what ideal, and in what senses, will help to resolve the issue about 

    whether morality requires more than is available in nature.

    Both the term   “naturalism ”

      and the term   “moral realism ”

      need to bespecied and adapted to the peculiarities of Kant ’s philosophy. Contemporary

    philosophical work on these issues does not always approach these issues in a 

    way amenable to Kant ’s critical philosophy. Kant ’s different conceptions of 

    the sciences and his transcendental idealism inform his understanding of 

    nature. His use of the terms   “realism ”   and   “idealism ”   in both empirical and

    transcendental senses, and the very nature of his critical philosophy as largely

    subject-centered, do not easily map onto discussions of realism in terms of 

    objective facts or empirical properties of human nature.

    My aim in this chapter is twofold. First, I will provide an analysis of denitions of moral realism and nonrealism with a focus on how well they

    9

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    20/274

    can account for the peculiarities of Kant ’s general philosophical approach.

    I use the term   “nonrealism ”   to capture  all  alternatives to moral realism until

    their particular characteristics are dened in this chapter. The analysis of 

    realism I adopt stresses the independence of elements of morality from moral

    agency as such; I contrast realism with idealism. I examine the transcendentaland empirical levels of realism and idealism in Kant and show where my

    approach differs from the typical emphases in constructivism.

    Second, I will examine the meaning of   “naturalism ”. I stress that my aim is

    limited to showing that Kant ’s ethics is compatible with a metaphysical

    naturalism, understood in Kant ’s own terms as including both the physical

    and the mental. He rejects methodological naturalism. In fact, his methodo-

    logical antinaturalism will play an important role in my interpretation.

    Third, I will identify the particular elements of Kant ’s moral theory that can

    be interpreted as real or ideal, natural or nonnatural. This taxonomy willilluminate the point that inquiring whether Kant is a moral realist or naturalist 

    is not a simple yes-or-no question. On different levels and about different 

    elements, Kant holds realist as well as idealist views. Further, by highlighting

    particular issues, this taxonomy will push the debate beyond mere terminology

    to the concrete differences among Kant interpreters.

    Dening moral realism and moral idealism

    Philosophy over the past three decades has included extensive discussion of the nature of moral realism and its alternatives.1 The issue entered the Kantian

    literature with John Rawls’   John Dewey Lectures in April 1980,   “Kantian

    Constructivism in Moral Theory”,2 which also introduced the term   “construct-

    ivism ” into the literature on Kant ’s practical philosophy.3 Rawls’ intention was

    not simply to provide an interpretation of Kant ’s ethics along constructivist 

    lines but mainly to present Kantian constructivism as a  general moral theory

    alongside utilitarianism, intuitionism, and perfectionism.4 Kant commentators

    1 Some of the earliest contributions to the debate are collected in (Sayre-McCord   1988a ). My

    discussion will invoke contributions to the debate about moral realism in general only whendoing so is useful for understanding the particular debate within Kant circles.

    2 The Dewey Lectures were published in (Rawls   1980) and reprinted in (Rawls   1999b,pp. 303–58).

    3 Larry Krasnoff traces the   rst use of the term   “constructive”   in moral theory to a review byRonald Dworkin in 1973 (reprinted in [Dworkin   1978, pp. 150–83]) of John Rawls’   book 

     A Theory of Justice. Rawls did not use the term   “constructivism ”   in   A Theory of Justice   but soon adopted it to describe his own theory. See (Krasnoff  1999).

    4 Since constructivism was introduced by Rawls, one might think that it can be applied in politicalphilosophy in addition to moral theory. In this book, I exclude directly political principles in

    favor of moral ones, broadly speaking. For work on the political use of constructivism, whichdraws more directly on Rawls’ own work in A Theory of Justice  and  Political Liberalism  rather 

    10 Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    21/274

    soon took up this suggestion with greater or lesser attention to historical claims

    about Kant ’s own theory.5 Since that time, Kant commentators have almost 

    exclusively characterized the discussion of the question of moral realism as a 

    choice between the alternatives of moral realism and moral constructivism,

    effectively lumping together all possible nonrealist interpretations of Kant asconstructivist. While doing so, these same commentators have generally

    bemoaned the lack of specicity of the term   “constructionism ”   and have

    attempted to dene or rene it using various taxonomies they present. Rarely

    do these taxonomies match precisely; still more rarely do they cross-reference

    or incorporate one another. The result is that much philosophically interesting

    work on the issue of moral realism in Kant is scattered in individual articles in

    isolation from one another.

    Moral realism is one of those issues about which philosophers spend much

    of their time simply dening the terms of the debate. There is no clear consensus on what   “realism ” actually means, and many acknowledge that tha t 

    the meaning of   “realism ”   has shifted along with the philosophical tide.6

    According to this last view, some theories which would have counted as

    antirealist  fty or hundred years ago would count as realist today. Even this

    admission seems too optimistic since it assumes that there is a general consen-

    sus at any given time.

     A popular de nition

    Two problems beset the task of dening moral realism. One is that various

    metaethical theories differ in their interpretation of key terms such as   “truth”

    and   “validity”,   “objective”  and   “subjective”,   “obligatory”  and   “permissible”.

    Disagreement about these key terms allows various different theories to claim 

    to present moral realist positions although they vary widely with one another.

    The debate over moral realism also suffers from the connotation of one of the

    central terms of the debate:   “antirealism ”. As an   “anti”, the latter connotes that 

    one is opposed to some positive claim rather than that one is giving a positive

    claim of one’s own. In ethics, this tendency is exaggerated by the moral import 

    of the terms involved. To deny moral realism seems to imply a lessening of the

    claims or values of morality itself. For this reason, I and others prefer the more

    than his particular interpretation of Kant, see (O’Neill 2002), (O’Neill 2003), (Bagnoli 2014),and (Kaufman 2012).

    5Two of the earliest Kant commentators to employ the language and method of constructivism areThomas Hill (Hill  1989) and Onora O’Neill (O’Neill 1989). They were soon followed by themost inuential constructivist after Rawls, Christine Korsgaard (Korsgaard 1996b). The intense

    debate about moral realism in Kant began in the wake of Korsgaard’s book.6 See, for example, (Railton 1996).

    Moral realism and naturalism 11

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    22/274

    positive-sounding term   “idealism ”  and still other theorists,   “constructivism ”

    over   “antirealism ”.

    These two problems are highlighted by a famous illustration of this bias

    toward supporting moral realism. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord suggests that one

    might want to be able to say that   “the Nazis were  really  bad”

    , but might feeluna ble to make such a strong claim without a theory of moral realism behind

    one.7 Moral idealism is then saddled with the burden of being implicitly

    equated with a rejection of any kind of validity to moral claims. An analogous

    claim regarding objects would illustrate the fallacy in this attitude:

    A traditional early modern realist about objects might be one who holds to

    the existence of objects independent of human perception of them; a traditional

    idealist about objects might hold that objects are nothing more than collections

    of sense data. Someone who rejected idealism about objects on the grounds

    that it  really  cannot be about objects would simply be begging the questionabout the denition of   “object ”, as if the idealist were denying the existence of 

    objects entirely rather than identifying them as collections of sense data. In the

    same way, someone who thinks that saying that the Nazis were really bad

    requires moral realism is begging the question about the denition of   “bad”.

    A moral idealist can easily make essentially the same claim as   “the Nazis were

    really bad” when the claim is stated in some non-question begging sense such

    as   “bad without qualication”.

    Sayre-McCord himself offers a denition of moral realism that has gained

    traction. He claims that   “realism involves embracing just two theses: (1) theclaims in question, when literally construed, are literally true or false (cogni-

    tivism), and (2) some are literally true”.8 Many recent Kant commentators

    writing on the issue of moral rea lism either use his denition or assess one

    much like it, generally critically.9 According to his denition, a theory is not 

    realist if it either (a) denies cognitivism, in which case it is some kind of non-

    cognitivist theory, or (b) denies that there are any moral truths, in which case it 

    is some kind of error theory.

    As these commentators note, Sayre-McCord’s denition does not adequately

    capture the crux of the debate regarding Kant ’s metaethics. Prima facie, Kant is

    neither a noncognitivist nor an error theorist. Constructivists and other non-

    realists allow that in Kant there are moral claims that bear truth or falsity.

    Under this denition, they would count as realist theories. Sayre-McCord’s

    7 (Sayre-McCord 1988b, p.1) credits the illustration to Philip Gasper. Sayre-McCord does not takethe illustration to be more than a caricature and subsequently discusses ways that nonrealism can

    capture moral condemnation. It is still useful as a caricature.8 (Sayre-McCord 1988b, p. 5).9 Paul Formosa (Formosa  2013) and I (Rauscher  2002) cite Sayre-McCord’s denition directly.

    Others who also note that this sort of denition does not really settle the issue of realism andidealism include Jochen Bojanowski (Bojanowski  2012), and Sharon Street (Street  2010).

    12 Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    23/274

    denition casts too wide a net. It makes every single possible moral theory

    that allows for moral truth into a realist theory. It co-opts the use of truth claims

    in a moral theory so that any kind of nonrealist theory is seen to deny validity

    to morality. Using the analogy with realist and idealist denitions of objects

    again, both the traditional realist and idealist hold that there are truths about objects, yet they have quite different conceptions of what those objects are.

    Similarly, a moral realist and a moral nonrealist can hold that there are moral

    truths, yet they can have quite different conceptions of what constitutes the

    bearer of those truths.

    Roughly speaking, the kind of denition Sayre-McCord provides equates

    “real”  with   “true”   and places the fault line between moral realism and moral

    idealism precisely atop the fault line between acceptance and denial of moral

    truth. Kantians should be skeptical that this perfect correspondence does

     justice to Kant ’s theory, which, incorporates transcendental idealism yet 

    af rms moral truth.

    Sharon Street phrases this point with regard to constructivism in general:

    “if we understand realism this way, then metaethical constructivism counts as

    a brand of realism  – as indeed do an extremely wide range of views, including

    even a simple subjectivism according   to which what ’s good for a person is

    whatever that person thinks is good”.10 She is right to stress the overextension

    of the term   “realism ” to any moral theory that offers some criterion for truth. In

    particular, if Kant has a theory of moral truth that can be understood as

    subject-dependent, perhaps even only dependent upon a certain kind of activityof subjects, then it would be peculiar to count his theory as realist although it 

    would contain a criterion for judging certain moral claims as true or false. The

    basis of the truth or falsity would seem to make a great deal of difference in our 

    view of whether a theory should count as real.

    This kind of denition of realism centered on truth claims is more suited to

    consequentialist than Kantian moral theories. Because consequentialists hold

    to the priority of the good over the right, they tend to take moral facts primarily

    as facts about some good to be attained rather than some formal laws of right;

    for a consequentialist, the content of laws that express right is derived from theconception of the good to be attained. One can picture how accepting the truth

    value of claims about the good can make one a realist in a more metaphysical

    sense by noting that goods are taken to be independent of the belief that they

    are good; those who deny this independence are expressivists and those who

    deny that there are any goods are error theorists. Right, on the other hand, has a 

    more ambiguous connection to belief. It is possible to conceive of moral agents

    who are so constituted that, in a roughly Kantian way, their practical cognitive

    10 (Street  2010, p. 370).

    Moral realism and naturalism 13

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    24/274

    faculty both produces the moral law as rational and produces belief in it. The

    truth value of the moral facts, here the criterion for right, would not be

    independent of rational belief in moral agents. This kind of Kantian view

    would open up space between the denial of the truth of some moral facts

    (expressivism and error theory) and the af rmation of moral facts on someindependent basis. Thus, consequentialists might be more inclined to be

    satised with the kind of denition that Sayre-McCord offered while Kantians

    ought to be skeptical of its value.

     A better de nition

    In order to move beyond this problem, a conception of the proper division

    between realism and nonrealism more appropriate for Kantians should include

    a metaphysical dimension, as some Kant interpreters recognize.11

    I offer thefollowing denitions that are more appropriate for Kantian ethics:

    Moral realism: The moral principles, properties, or objects of the world

    are independent of the transcendental or empirical moral agent.

    Moral nonrealism: The moral principles, properties, or objects of the

    world   a re dependent upon the transcendental or empirical moral

    agent.12

    11 Paul Formosa labels realism that excludes only noncognitivists and error theorists a   “weak senseof moral realism ”  that   “amounts to nothing more than a claim about the truth of some moral judgments” in contrast to a  “strong realism ” that holds that what makes the moral judgments trueor false is   “an independent moral order ”   (Formosa   2013, p. 172). The weak sense of moralrealism accords with the kind I have just criticized. Formosa is correct in noting the need for a stronger, more meaningful sense of moral realism. This   “strong sense”   requires ontologicalindependence. Richard Boyd offers a denition that identies a requirement for independencefrom   “our moral opinions, theories, etc”. and also claims that ordinary moral reasoning is a reliable method for obtaining moral knowledge (Boyd 1988, p. 182). The dif culty with Boyd’sdenition is the vagueness included in his   “etc.”. Allen Wood alludes to Boyd’s denition in hisrst book on Kant ’s ethics as   “the most agreed-upon sense” of the term   “moral realism ” (Wood1999, pp. 157, 374, n. 4) but claims (quite emphatically) in his second book on Kant ’s ethics that 

    he does not endorse Boyd’s own type of   “Cornell Realism ”   as the proper way to construerealism in conformity with that denition (Wood 2008, p. 295, n. 8).

    12I offered a similar set of denitions in (Rauscher  2002, p. 482). There I used the term   “moralidealism ” while here I use   “moral nonrealism ”; the latter term broadens the denition’s scope toinclude anyone who rejects moral truth such as error theorists and expressivists. I will focus myargument on idealism as I proceed. I also used the term    “moral characteristic” while here I am clearer in using   “moral principle, property, or object ”, the original intent of the former term;there is no change in meaning accompanying this clarication in terminology. Finally,I formerly used the term   “human mind”  while here I say   “transcendental or empirical moralagent ”; this change is intended to allow for the different levels of realism or nonrealism at theempirical and transcendental levels and reects a shift in my analysis over the past decade. I am very grateful to Darlei Dall’Agnol for his criticisms of my earlier approach and for many

    discussions in which we have attempted to   nd the best Kantian position on moral realism.Some of his concerns are in (Dall’Agnol 2012b) and are discussed in my reply (Rauscher  2012).

    14 Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    25/274

    These denitions dene the difference as metaphysical since both the term 

    “moral principle, property, or object ”  and the relation of   “independence”  are

    metaphysical. Very roughly, they are intended to put the onus on the moral

    nonrealist to prove that there are no essentially moral principles, properties, or 

    objects, or if one wants to phrase it differently, no moral truth that wouldcorrespond to any principle, property, or object, such that the principle,

    property, or object would be a part of the cosmos were moral agents qua 

    moral subjects not to exist. By   “nonrealism ” I mean all possible alternatives to

    moral realism, including expressivism, error theory, the constructivist views

    that are not realist, and idealism, to be explained later in this chapter.

    A moral principle, property, or object is not the same as a principle,

    property, or object required for morality. The difference between a moral

    principle, property, or object and a principle, property, or object required for 

    morality is that the latter consists of principles, properties, or objects which arenot solely moral, the former of principles, properties, or objects which are

    solely moral. Moral principles, properties, or objects are to be understood as

    exclusively involving moral normativity or value. For example, the human

    mind may be an object required for morality, but because it can play a role in

    other areas not pertaining to moral normativity or value, such as theories of 

    qualia, it is not a moral object. An individual’s being good, however, is a moral

    property, since this characterization can play no role except in situations

    involving moral normativity or value or those derivative upon it such as

    descriptions of morally good persons. For denitional purposes, moral proper-ties and objects are not limited to a particular metaphysics. As examples of 

    moral principles, properties, or objects, consider the following: Good, evil,

    bad, rightness, wrongness, justice, value, moral law. As examples of prin-

    ciples, properties, or objects required for morality, consider the following: The

    existence of minds, pragmatic or technical means–ends principles, and so on.

    Of course, particular moral theories might differ regarding which specic

    principles, properties, or objects are solely moral rather than more general

    principles, properties, or objects, and whether the solely moral principles,

    properties, or objects are separable from the more general principles, proper-ties, or objects. In Kant, we might legitimately question whether freedom of 

    the will, agent causality, or the existence of God count as moral properties or 

    objects or as simply properties or objects required for morality. I will treat 

    them as moral properties or objects and include them in my arguments in this

    book.

    The term   “independent ”   invokes a metaphysical separation between the

    moral agent  qua agent   and whatever moral principles, properties, or objects

    are at issue. I do not intend to hold that the moral principles, properties, or 

    objects are to be independent of all moral agents in existence but rather independent of the individual moral agent or particular type of moral agent 

    Moral realism and naturalism 15

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    26/274

    (to be specied) as a moral subject . There is no quick route to idealism through

    a claim that morality depends upon the existence of any moral beings at all.

    Thus, if moral agents themselves were to have independent intrinsic value as

    objects  of consideration for a moral agent who is the  subject   facing a moral

    decision, that value would be real because it would be independent of themoral agent  qua subject . Similarly, if moral value were to reside in satisfaction

    of desires for moral agents in general and that moral value had a justication

    beyond simply moral agents considering satisfaction of their own desires to be

    good, the value of desire satisfaction would be real. Beca use moral agents are

    not passive, dependence on mental activity is included.13 This emphasis on

    moral agents  qua subjects rather than objects   is extremely important for a 

    Kantian theory that places much weight on the practical point of view or the

    structure of moral agency.

    A divine command theory or any theory that grounded moral laws onsomething independent of moral agents would be realist on this account, as

    would any theory that held that there are values independent of moral agents’

    acts of valuation or capacity of valuation. A moral theory that depended solely

    on contingent facts about particular persons, such as a theory referenced in the

    quote from Street earlier that the good for a person is merely whatever that 

    person happens to think is good for her, would not count as realist. An error 

    theory would be nonrealist because it denies that there are any moral prin-

    ciples, properties, or objects.

    I use the phrase   “transcendental or empirical moral agent ”

     in order to invoketwo possible levels of assessment of moral agency. The transcendental moral

    agent would be the subject of an assessment of the conditions for moral agency

    as such. In Kant, such an assessment would be transcendental, in other kinds of 

    theories conceptual. The description of the transcendental moral agent would

    be valid for all possible moral agents. The empirical moral agent would be

    the subject of an assessment of the particular mental structure of human

    and similar beings as moral agents. This approach, which looks not at a 

    13 Jochen Bojanowski cites my earlier denition but claims that his   “moral idealism ”, which he

    takes to be a third alternative between moral realism and moral antirealism in Kant, does not utilize the sense of dependence he sees in my denition”. The idealism I want to ascribe to Kant holds not that the good depends on the human mind, but that its  existence  depends on self-affection in human cognizers”   (Bojanowski   2012, p. 4). I hope that my clarication hereadequately shows that, as I had always intended and as is clear from the position I detail inmy earlier paper, the kind of dependence on the human mind can include mental activity such asdecision-making, reection, and self-affection. Bojanowski hints in the claim quoted here that 

    he might mean that the  meaning  of the term   ‘good’  is dependent upon something besides thehuman mind while the  existence   of good depends upon self-affection; because he does not utilize semantic terminology, this attribution is speculative. Later in his article, he holds that 

    practical cognition precedes normative facts, which implies that the meaning of the term   “good”is also the result of practical activity (Bojanowski  2012, p. 13).

    16 Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    27/274

    transcendental moral agent but at a humanlike agent in particular, is empiric-

    ally informed, including facts about the existence or types of desires, the actual

    capabilities of the agent such as a capacity for free choice amid various

    possible determinants of action, the access the mind has to any moral facts,

    and so on. This approach is both empirical and conceptual in Kant in theapplication of practical principles and ideas that are not derived empirically. It 

    is not the equivalent of anthropology. The description of the empirical moral

    agent in Kant would be valid only for moral agents sharing the particular moral

    characterization at issue. Of course, at the empirical level, moral agents may

    instantiate the transcendental moral agent, but whether they do, what the latter 

    consists of, and precisely what the relationship between them is depends upon

    the nature of Kant ’s transcendental/empirical distinction (to be discussed later 

    on) and the success of particular philosophical arguments.

    The scope of the   “empirical”

     agent in my argument is essentially restrictedto   “humanlike” and should be taken to refer to the relevant characterization of 

    the moral nature of human beings, not to similarity to human beings in morally

    irrelevant ways. In Kant, a humanlike moral agent could be dened roughly as

    a   nitely rational being capable of a pursuit of happiness, conscious of the

    categorical imperative, and capable of choosing between following that 

    imperative or not. From now on, I will use the terms   “human moral agent ”

    and   “empirical moral agent ”   to refer to all humanlike beings. I stress the

    human moral agent in order to emphasize that dependence upon some particu-

    lar type of existing moral agent is at issue. A comparison wit h more generalmental features is useful. Some features of the human mind14 such as the

    ability to sense only a particular portion of the electromagnetic spectrum are

    certainly contingent and not a necessary feature of universal sensibility; other 

    organisms can see ultraviolet light or respond to magnetic  elds. Kant holds

    that space and time must be considered dependent in some way on the human

    mind and are not conditions for experience for all possible minds. Arguably, a 

    similar variation is possible in theory with regard to mental processes more

    closely related to morality. Supposing that various other types of mental

    organization were differently instantiated in different species   –  and here onemust imagine something like a mind without memories or one determined

    immediately by emotion   – the particular parts of that mental organization that 

    were unique to one species might, on some theories, ground moral truth for 

    14Human moral agents would have human minds. When I use the term   “mind”, I do not intend toinvoke any Cartesian substance; rather, I intend to be agnostic about the true nature of minds. At the same time, I limit this to the human mind as we generally experience it and conceive of it. If 

    it were to turn out that the true nature of human minds were that they are parts of God ’s mind, a resulting morality could be realist. I take this possibility as incompatible with Kant ’s theory.

    Moral realism and naturalism 17

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    28/274

    them.15 Were there some general theory that showed that only one type of 

    mental organization could possibly exist, or that morality could be grounded

    only in some particular core of mental functions that all possible moral agents

    must exhibit, then those moral principles, properties, or objects would be

    characteristic of both the empirical human and the transcendental moral agent.To prove this identity is Kant ’s goal.

    The aforementioned discussion makes clear an error in equating realism with

    objectivity. Objectivity can coincide with nonrealism provided that the minds in

    question are all structured in such a way that they necessarily produce the same

    ideas. An analogy can be made with the question of color perception. Simply

    because our color qualia may be ideal and phenomenal colors may not inhere in

    objects independent of the human mind, does not mean that the color qualia we

    perceive are not objective. There might be some necessary causal connection

    between our physical sensations and our mental perceptions. We might have a particular mental faculty which provides for the objectivity. This objectivity is

    nonetheless not universal for all possible sensible beings but restricted to beings

    with the particular kind of physical and mental constitution we have. This

    objectivity lacks a transcendental foundation. For morality, objectivity can be

    preserved even when nonrealism is accepted, provided that the theory explains

    how the structure of the human moral agent dictates that all humans share the

    same moral properties and objects at the empirical level or how the structure of 

    15 As an example of this kind of variation, consider Sharon Street ’s ants (Street  2012, pp. 53–54).She supposes for the sake of argument that a species of intelligent, conscious ants could exist.Because of the complex genetic relationships among ants, all female ants share seventy-vepercent of their genetic code with one another while only one, the queen, is able to reproduce.There are relatively few male ants. Survival of the colony relies on individual ants sacricingthemselves to protect the queen to ensure the existence of future generations. Street imaginesthat a female worker ant would exhibit a value system to reect these facts, valuing the survivalof the queen above her own survival and not seeing herself as intrinsically valuable. Street offers this as a counterexample to the Korsgaardian/Kantian claim that all reective beings whoare capable of valuing anything must value themselves as ends in themselves. I take thisexample to illustrate my point that some kind of organism with a suf ciently different kindof nature could have a different kind of moral system. I would like to make two observations

    about this thought-experiment. First, it is extremely unlikely that such intelligent ants, or similarly genetically related social beings with the same behavioral patterns, would evolve.Such complex intelligence in animals requires a great deal of investment in the rearing of offspring and a great deal of relative mass devoted to the brain. Given the costs of producingand maintaining a functioning intelligent adult, it would be nearly impossible for a species tomass-produce them to such an extent that they could be easily expendable in such menial waysas providing a live bridge for others of her kind. Still, as Street notes, the point is not theplausibility of such a species actually evolving but the fact that the conceivability of the speciesprovides a counterexample to Korsgaard’s argument that all creatures capable of valuing must value themselves the most. Second, it is interesting to note that human beings sometimes think the same way that Street ’s ants do. Soldiers or others who willingly sacrice themselves for their nation are a case in point. This puzzling kind of altruism, which cannot be explained either 

    as inclusive  tness (near genetic relations such as offspring or cousins) or as reciprocal altruism appears to have no genetic basis. For an attempt to explain such behavior, see (Kitcher  1993).

    18 Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    29/274

    the transcendental moral agent dictates that all possible moral agents share the

    same moral properties and objects at the transcendental level.

    Transcendental and empirical realism

    The term   “realism ” in Kant has a vital twofold signicance largely overlooked

    in the realism debate: Kant ’s distinction between, on the one hand, transcen-

    dental idealism or realism and on the other hand, empirical idealism or realism.

    This distinction does not appear in the contemporary general debate about 

    realism in moral theory because it applies to Kantian but not consequentialist 

    theories. Most of contemporary Kantian ethics does not even employ Kant ’s

    transcendental/empirical distinction, presumably taking it to be an ontological

    claim about the real versus apparent nature of objects that is not relevant to

    ethics beyond a discredited theory of free will. These Kantian moral theoristsappropriate Kant ’s discussion of a practical point of view without linking it to

    transcendental idealism. Interpreters of Kant ’s own moral theory who operate

    without   the distinction have incomplete models of Kant ’s moral realism or 

    idealism.16

    In the   Critique of Pure Reason,   Kant differentiates between the transcen-

    dental and empirical senses of realism and idealism. The four resulting possi-

    bilities   –  transcendental idealism, transcendental realism, empirical idealism,

    and empirical realism   –  work roughly as follows in relation to space: Tran-

    scendental idealism is the claim that all objects in space are mere appearancesand not things as they are in themselves because the space in which they exist 

    is only a form of our intuition. Transcendental idealism allows objects to be

    empirically real, that is, directly knowable by the empirical subject in an

    objective order in space. Transcendental realism holds that space is something

    given in itself independent of human intuition and hence, that things as they

    are in themselves are spatial. But this transcendental realism leads to empirical

    idealism, that is, that empirical objects in space are not directly accessible to

    the empirical mind because space exists independently of human intuition

    (B69–

    71, A369–

    70). Kant, of course, is a transcendental idealist with regardto time as well as space. The transcendental ideality of space and time means

    that objects as they are in themselves are not spatiotemporal and cannot be

    experienced by human beings, who are limited to experiences provided in

    intuition. Human beings are able to know only appearances, that is, empirically

    real objects. But the possibility that other objects exist that are not spatiotem-

    poral remains.

    16 This criticism holds for my earlier work as well (Rauscher   2002), but I do approach the

    transcendental/empirical distinction without a comprehensive treatment in (Rauscher   2006b)and with a better but still incomplete treatment in (Rauscher  2006a ).

    Moral realism and naturalism 19

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    30/274

    Kant ’s argument for the transcendental ideality of space is given through a 

    transcendental exposition of the concept of space as a basis for the a priori

    truths of geometry (B40–41). To be able to function as the basis for a priori

    truth in geometry, space as an outer intuition   “has its seat merely in the

    subject ”

    . Similar reasoning holds for the transcendental deduction of the pureconcepts of the understanding: They are held to have their transcendental

    ground as necessary conditions for the synthetic unity of apperception

    (B159–60). Transcendental idealism thus takes these crucial formal features

    of experience to depend upon the subject in a transcendental but not empirical

    sense.

    The transcendental/empirical distinction is relevant for morality because we

    can take certain aspects of experience like objects in space to be dependent 

    upon the transcendental subject although they are in some sense independent 

    of the empirical subject. There is use for this distinction in practical philoso-phy. Just as objects in space are really independent of the subject in an

    empirical sense but dependent on the subject in a transcendental sense, there

    might be moral principles, properties, or objects that are really independent of 

    the moral agent in an empirical sense but dependent on the moral agent in a 

    transcendental sense, making Kant an empirical moral realist but a transcen-

    dental moral idealist. Or some moral principles, properties, or objects might be

    transcendentally real, that is, entirely independent of the transcendent al moral

    agent, in which case, Kant would be a transcendental moral realist.17

    For this overall transcendental/empirical distinction to work in practicalphilosophy, the concept of empirical experience, or the everyday experience

    of human beings, must be understood to have a practical dimension in addition

    to the theoretical dimension provided in the analytic of the  rst  Critique. Given

    Kant ’s interest in anthropology as a natural level at which we can understand

    human beings as moral beings, a practical dimension of experience in Kant is

    at hand. Kant discusses our consciousness of ourselves as moral in relation to

    our moral predisposition in the   Anthropology  (7:324). Even in the less obvi-

    ously empirical works, Kant discusses everyday moral experience. He begins

    the Groundwork  by invoking common moral cognition or beliefs actually held

    17One might be further tempted to conclude that a transcendental moral realist would have to bean empirical moral idealist, in which case, some moral principles, properties, or objects wouldbe not directly known in experience. As with Kant ’s claim that with regard to objects in space, a transcendental realist ends up as an empirical   “skeptical”   idealist, this translates into anempirical moral skepticism. Suppose that the moral value of a rational agency were understoodto be transcendentally real, that is, independent of the transcendental moral agent qua agent. Theempirical moral agent might have no transcendental justication for a recognition of this moralvalue, since it is independent of that moral agent considered transcendentally. Hence, on theempirical level, an empirical moral agent might need another argument that would show the

    actuality of those moral values. For an argument along these lines, see (Sensen   2011,pp. 18–20).

    20 Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    31/274

    by people (4:393); in the second   Critique,   he takes his project not be a 

    replacement of an old principle of morality with a new one but a philosophical

     justication of it through a new formulation (5:8, ftn.). In other words, he is not 

    denying that the principle of morality is part of the actual experience of human

    beings. Moral duties and values are experienced by human beings in nature,that is, human beings as appearances. Given the possibility of empirical moral

    experience, the controversial interpretive issue relevant to current purposes is

    whether morality would be empirically real or empirically ideal, that is,

    independent of or dependent on the empirical moral agent.

    In order for this empirical/transcendental distinction to apply to ethics, we

    have to be able to identify transcendental arguments for the necessary condi-

    tions for a moral agent. Kant attempts to provide a deduction of the moral law

    in Groundwork  III and later discusses a deduction in the  Critique of Practical 

     Reason. Although Kant does not identify them as  such, these deductions havebeen treated by commentators as transcendental.18 If it is proper to consider 

    them as transcendental deductions, then they might be understood as the basis

    for claims that the moral properties and objects are dependent on the transcen-

    dental moral agent. Further, one might be tempted to treat Kant ’s derivation of 

    the value of humanity as a k ind of transcendental deduction (as Korsgaard does

    without using that term 19), even though Kant never calls it a deduction.

    Understanding these issues requires a look at the nature of Kant ’s philosophy

    in general and practical philosophy in particular. Chapter 2 will examine these

    issues in detail.The importance of this discussion of the empirical/transcendental distinction

    is that there can be two levels of possible moral realism or idealism. At the

    transcendental level, one might ask whether moral principles, properties, or 

    objects are dependent or independent of some possible transcendentally iden-

    tied moral agent, that is, an idealist might argue that autonomy of the will as

    pure practical reason might be a transcendentally ideal ground for the categor-

    ical imperative, or a realist might argue that humanity as an end in itself should

    be understood as a transcendentally real value independent of the transcenden-

    tal moral agent. There is a third option besides moral transcendental realism and idealism: There might be no transcendental justication for morality at all.

    If human moral experience is dependent upon some contingent features of the

    human moral agent and cannot   nd any transcendental basis, Kant ’s ethics

    would be empirically ideal but would have no transcendental status, in the

    18 See, for example, the articles by John Rawls, Henry Allison, and Barbara Herman in (Förster 1989).

    19 See (Korsgaard 1996a , p. 123). Recently, Robert Stern has endorsed a version of her transcen-dental argument (Stern 2011a ).

    Moral realism and naturalism 21

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    32/274

    same way that color sensations are empirically ideal and have no transcenden-

    tal status (B44–45).

    At the empirical level, an empirical realist might argue that the transcenden-

    tally ideal ground for the law might be compatible with the empirical reality of 

    duties such that those duties are not dependent upon the empirical moral agent but only the transcendental moral agent. This distinction might prove useful in

    dissolving some strong disagreements about whether the categorical impera-

    tive is independent of rational moral agents. The effect of the transcendental/ 

    empirical distinction on the realism/nonrealism debate can come only after a 

    look at the nature of philosophy in Kant in Chapter 2.

    Allow me to briey note the importance of the distinctions made so far.

    A standard denition of moral realism has been shown to be inadequate in

    capturing the elements peculiar to Kantian ethics. A denition that stresses

    the role of the metaphysical independence of moral principles, properties, or objects from either the transcendental or empirical moral agent serves better.

    Kant ’s moral theory   –   the target of discussion in this book   –   will be

    subjected to a more appropriate denition that illuminates the genuine fault 

    line between Kantian realism and Kantian nonrealism in terms of independ-

    ence or dependence on the moral agent. The independence or dependence

    appears at two possible levels when Kant ’s transcendental/empirical distinc-

    tion is applied. If there is a transcendental dependence of all moral prin-

    ciples, properties, and objects upon the transcendental moral agent, Kant 

    would be a transcendental moral idealist; if the transcendental justication of morality requires that some moral principles, properties, or objects be inde-

    pendent of the transcendental moral agent, then Kant would be a transcen-

    dental moral realist. A similar distinction would operate at the empirical level

    of everyday moral experience with reference to the empirical moral agent.

    The conception of the human moral agent and the status of Kant ’s justica-

    tory arguments for morality will have to be determined in detail in order to

    resolve this dispute.

    This fourfold division crossing empirical/transcendental and real/ideal is

    still too stark a choice for interpreting Kant. There can be interpretations that hold Kant to be a transcendental realist regarding some moral principles,

    properties, or objects and a transcendental idealist regarding others. No one

    takes Kant to be a realist about every moral principle, property, or object and

    few take him to be a complete idealist. Philosophically, it is more fruitful to

    avoid slapping a blanket identication on Kant as one or the other and instead

    to assess all aspects of Kant ’s moral theory in light of the issue. I will devote a 

    later section of this chapter to listing the various kinds of moral principles,

    properties, or objects that are raised in the literature. Before that, however,

    I will evaluate various conceptions of constructivism to show how they  t intothe realism/nonrealism debate I have just characterized.

    22 Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    33/274

    Comparison with constructivism

    No single denition of   “constructivism ”   garners universal or even wide

    acceptance. Kantian moral realists tend to tr eat all opponents as constructivists,

    but some identify themselves otherwise.20

    The positions are further compli-cated because some constructivists label themselves moral realists while others

    seem to reject realism.21 And   “constructivism ” itself is an unfortunate term to

    use when discussing Kant ’s philosophy because he had a particular meaning

    for the term in his theoretical philosophy that conicts with its use by contem-

    porary Kantians in ethical theory.22 In this section, I will   rst review two

    possible general types of construction, showing which ought to be taken as

    20 Robert Stern labels the debate about Kant ’s moral realism   “the constructivist/realist contro-

    versy” (Stern 2012, p. 119). Paul Formosa ’s very title makes the assumption:   “Is Kant a MoralConstructivist or Moral Realist?”  (Formosa  2013). Although I have described my position asidealist and never as constructivist, I have been lumped with others as a constructivist severaltimes (Kain   2006, Stern   2011b), (but see Dall’Agnol   2012b   for a notable exception). KarlAmeriks, in contrast, is to be praised for his argument against two   “nonrealist ” interpretations of Kant, those of J.B. Schneewind and Charles Larmore, in which he does not see them primarilyas constructivist (Ameriks 2003).

    21 In part, this is due to their differing conceptions of moral realism. The most famous of the self-proclaimed constructivist realists is Christine Korsgaard, who distinguishes Kant ’s   “proceduralmoral realism ”   from metaphysical realism, which she calls   “substantive moral realism ”(Korsgaard 1996b, p.35) or   “objective realism ”  (Korsgaard 1996a , pp. 278–282). She claimsthat   “procedural moral realism is the view that there are answers to moral questions; that is, that 

    there are right and wrong ways to answer them ”. Substantive (or objective) moral realism further holds that there are moral facts or truths which account for the right answer to thosequestions. This claim implies that any method of answering a question about right and wrongcounts as a procedure. She seems to conrm this a few pages later when she claims that substantive realism, which holds that moral facts are true in virtue of something independent of the moral agent, is a version of procedural realism. This understanding of procedure would beitself too broad. The universality of the term   “procedure” when taken to include any method of answering questions makes it useless when trying to   nd something distinctive about proce-duralism. Her description would encompass a procedure of logical deduction from a set of statements, which is of course one way to try to   nd right or wrong answers. She later characterizes constructivism as a form of problem solving, making it appear that all attemptsto   nd answers to practical problems are constructivist, although without invoking the term 

    “procedure” (Korsgaard 2003). In these statements, Korsgaard effectively erases any meaning-ful distinction between  nding an answer and creating an answer. Any attempt to answer moralquestions by reference to independently existing moral facts would still count as constructivist.Hence, Korsgaard is not a good source for an account of the distinctiveness of a procedure for construction.

    22 In the Critique of Pure Reason,  he distinguishes philosophy from mathematics when noting that concepts are constructed in mathematics but not constructed in philosophy (A713–16/ B741–44). To construct a concept is to   “exhibit a priori the intuition corresponding to it ”. Onlymathematics can construct concepts because philosophical concepts cannot be represented in

    intuition. A mathematically constructed concept is a specication of the universal, for example,the properties of triangles in general, in a particular, say, a specic triangle drawn on paper or inthe imagination, because the concept already contains a pure intuition that needs to be exhibited.

    Philosophical concepts, in contrast, are not constructed because they do not contain any pureintuition but only   “nothing but the synthesis of possible intuitions which are not given a priori”

    Moral realism and naturalism 23

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    34/274

    paradigm, before showing how my approach is situated in relation to con-

    structivist theories.

    At its most general level, a constructivist theory claims that some particular 

    moral principles, properties, or objects such as norms, values, or moral facts,

    are derived from some other particular principles, properties, or objects,whether purely moral, for example, a highest value, or not, say, rationality

    itself, through a procedure of some sort.23 Rawls initially used the term 

    “procedure”   in   A Theory of Justice   as a way to understand the process by

    which individuals   would determine principles of justice by means of the

    original position.24 Constructivists who had studied with Rawls adopted the

    term, and even Onora O’Neill, who sharply differentiates her constructivism 

    from Rawls’, sometimes characterizes her position this way.25 Yet the specic

    procedures they invoke are not of the same type. I see two general types of 

    constructivism in the literature. I will suggest that the one that is closest to theapproach I have to moral idealism ought not to be considered to construct 

    anything.

    Thomas Hill offers a Rawlsian understanding of the nature of a procedure in

    what he calls a   “procedure of construction”. In this type, moral principles (for 

    Hill, the target of construction) are valid   “ just in case and because they would

    be endorsed by all members of an appropriately dened initial choice

    and hence can relate to objects in intuition only synthetically and discursively (A719–20/ 

    B747–48). In the   Critique of Practical Reason,  Kant makes an analogous claim with regardto the practical in a discussion of how to separate the doctrine of happiness from the doctrine of morals. He suggests that making this distinction requires the care and precision of a geometer.

    “A philosopher, however, has greater dif culties to contend with here (as always in rationalcognition through mere concepts without construction of them) because he cannot put anyintuition (a pure noumenon) as its basis”   (5:92). Presumably, Kant is making an analogybetween the pure intuition used in geometry with any pure conceptual space (noumena) that would be used in practical philosophy. Practical philosophy cannot construct its concepts in a 

    pure conceptual space but must show how they affect actual human beings in their actualdecisions. To resolve this, Kant suggests that practical philosophy can use a method similar to a chemist who adds alkali to a certain solution in order to separate the acid from the remainder of the solution. The experiment that Kant suggests is that in a particular person awareness of the

    moral law will similarly separate considerations of advantage from rational considerations in theperson’s mind, allowing for a focus on moral motivation. For a thorough examination of thisparticular analogy, see (Rohden 2012). Like other claims stemming from reason, for example,the concept of a soul, the moral law is not constructed in Kant ’s sense of the term.

    23 Sharon Street believes that inclusion of a procedure is not a necessary element of constructivist views (Street  2010, p. 366). Constructivism is better characterized as a metaethical theory that stresses the practical point of view. Ultimately, I agree that theories that stress the practical point of view are superior theories, but I hesitate to label them as   “constructivist ” and instead use theterm   “idealist ”. Street denes a constructivist position in terms of the justication of some moral judgments by reference to another set of moral judgments (Street  2008, p. 208).

    24 (Rawls 1999a , p. 17).25 O’Neill does not generally describe her position as proceduralist but has used the term (O’Neill

    1989, p. 216, n. 10). Korsgaard uses the term quite prominently when she characterizes her position as   “procedural realism ” (Korsgaard 1996b, p. 35).

    24 Laying the ground

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    35/274

    situation”.26 I will call this the   “decision procedure”   type of constructivism.

    The crucial element of this denition is the requirement that a decision in an

    initial situation, one that provides some material the agents may use while

    deciding, is used to determine the result. This kind of procedure could produce

    various kinds of moral principles, properties, or objects, not merely principles,from some other set of moral or nonmoral principles, properties, or objects.

    O’Neill’s discussion of the construction of principles by agents seeking agree-

    ment is another example.27 An exemplary mainstream denition that stresses

    the role of choice stemming from an idealized process of deliberation is given

    by Carla Bagnoli.

    As a   “metaethical account ”  – an account of whether there are any normative truths and,

    if so, what they are like   –  constructivism holds that there are normative truths. These

    truths are not   xed by facts that are independent of the practical standpoint, however 

    characterized; rather, they are constituted by what agents would agree to under somespecied conditions of choice.

    28

    The crucial characteristic of the decision procedure is that it entails some

    ability to m ak e a decision, whether real or hypothetical, on the part of the

    participants.29 A procedure of this kind differs from a procedure in which the

    creation of the moral principles (or norms or values)   conceptually precedes

    any capability for agents to make decisions. In other words, this type of model

    of a construction procedure requires that the agents in the hypothetical or real

    situation can be conceived as capable of making a decision to endorse or reject 

    the outcomes of the procedure. Neither agency itself nor any prerequisites for 

    agency can be constructed through a decision procedure because one needs

    agents in order to make decisions in the  rst place.

    26 (Hill 2012, p. 78).   27 (O’Neill 1989) and (O’Neill 2002).  28 (Bagnoli 2011).

    29 Paul Formosa calls actual constructivism   “all the way down” because it involves actual willing

    by individuals either collectively as a culture or individually. Hypothetical constructivism is

    “not all the way down” because both the content and the authority of the procedure itself are

    “laid out ” rather than the subject of some actual choice (Formosa  2013, pp. 173–74). Formosa does not provide any example of an   “all the way down” constructivist but suggests that a model

    would be someone who takes moral norms to be embodied in cultural practices but nonethelesssubject to the   “individual or collective” act of will. This characterization is problematic because

    if the norms are embodied in the cultural practices, they are not the result of any direct acts of will at all. If he means that the acts of will are those of an agent independently endorsing thecultural norms, then his characterization would not capture the spirit of constructivism inparticular but would be applicable to any acts of an agent who faces the question of whether to subject himself or herself to moral norms. Formosa does not discuss actual procedures in theremainder of his article but defends a   “not all the way down” reading of Kant.An example of an   “all the way down” constructivism might be what Andrews Reath calls the

    “Principle of Individual Sovereignty”   in which each particular will is subject only to laws it actually legislates for itself. Reath and Patrick Kain cite problems with this view on its owngrounds and as an interpretation of Kant and the two philosophers to whom they attribute this

    view, Robert Paul Wolff and Rüdiger Bittner, do not themselves take it to be Kant ’s view. See(Reath 2006, pp. 97–98), (Kain 2004, pp. 262–65), (Wolff  1974), and (Bittner  1989).

    Moral realism and naturalism 25

  • 8/19/2019 Naturalism and Realism in Kants Ethics

    36/274

    A kind of constructivism that alleges to construct moral principles, proper-

    ties, or objects on the basis of agency itself is thus the second kind of 

    constructivism in the literature. What I will call the   “nature of agency proced-

    ure”   allows for the generation of norms, laws, or values by means of the

    expression of the nature of moral agents conceptually prior to their ability tochoose anything. This procedure does not involve conscious endorsement,

    whether real or hypothetical, by agents but is simply the product or character-

    istics of a particular kind of active being. Korsgaard’s attempt to ground the

    categorical imperative on rational beings’   very ability to make reective

    decisions is one example of this kind of procedure. Although she has claimed

    to construct agency itself, the actual procedure she offers is one in which she

    takes rational agency as the starting point  from which she then draws out the

    categorical imperative and moral value.30 The main question asked is about 

    which moral norms are intrinsically tied to the nature of free agency itself.Certainly, the agents might later reect on their situation and endorse the

    results of the activity, but this reective endorsement is not the source of the

    construction.

    30 Korsgaard’s position is more ambiguous than stated here. She sometimes describes her positionas one of a constitution of agency, but when giving details, she shifts to a constitution of  agents

    as particular individuals who use their ability as agents to make choices that dene who they are(Korsgaard 2008, p. 109). It seems clear that she does not construct agency as such but usesagency to construct other elements of her moral theory.

    She also sometimes argues that the categorical imperative is a result of a decision by an agent tobe a certain kind of person, for example, one committed to the kingdom of ends or to egoism (Korsgaard   1996b, p. 101). At other times, she insists that acceptance of the categoricalimperative is a  requirement  stemming from the   “reective structure of human consciousness”and thus not a result of a decision by such an agent (Korsgaard  1996b, pp. 103–04). The former approach is what I call   “decision procedure” and the latter   “nature of agency procedure”.Some opponents of constructivism claim that Korsgaard’s constructivism is not only not a genuine alternative to moral realism, it is also not even a metaethical claim. Nadeem J.Z.Hussain and Nishi Shah argue that Korsgaard’s constructivism makes no metaethical claims but is better described as making claims in normative ethics or moral psychology (Hussain andShah   2006). Allen Wood hints that   “no distinctive metaethics or metaphysics of value”   isimplied by the procedural account of practical reason but does not offer details (Wood  2008,

    pp. 282–83, n.3). I   nd these charges dif cult to accept. Korsgaard and other constructivistsmight not have offered a clear and internally consistent metaethics, but they have made somemetaethical claims. The constr