In Defence of Thrasymachus

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    1/12

    North American Philosophical Publications and University of Illinois Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,preserve and extend access to American Philosophical Quarterly.

    http://www.jstor.org

    North merican Philosophical Publications

    In Defense of ThrasymachusAuthor(s): T. Y. HendersonSource: American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 7, No. 3 (Jul., 1970), pp. 218-228

    Published by: on behalf of theUniversity of Illinois Press North American PhilosophicalPublicationsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20009351Accessed: 16-01-2016 14:31 UTC

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/publisher/illinoishttp://www.jstor.org/publisher/napphttp://www.jstor.org/publisher/napphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20009351http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20009351http://www.jstor.org/publisher/napphttp://www.jstor.org/publisher/napphttp://www.jstor.org/publisher/illinoishttp://www.jstor.org/
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    2/12

    American Philosophical

    Quarterly

    Volume

    7,

    Number

    3,

    July

    1970

    IV.

    IN

    DEFENSE OF

    THRASYMACHUS

    T.

    Y.

    HENDERSON

    CRITICS

    and

    commentators

    on

    the

    dispute

    between Socrates

    and

    Thrasymachus

    which

    occurs

    in

    Book

    I

    of

    the

    Republic

    come

    closest

    to

    unanimity

    on

    two

    points

    :

    that

    Thrasymachus'

    view

    is

    not

    consistent

    throughout

    the

    dispute

    and

    that

    Socrates'

    arguments

    are

    fatal

    to

    Thrasymachus'

    position.

    Not

    all

    commentators

    by

    any

    means,

    however,

    are

    in

    agreement

    as

    to

    just

    what

    position

    Thrasymachus

    is

    defending,

    or

    on

    what

    points,

    precisely,

    he

    is inconsistent. Nor

    is

    there

    general

    agreement

    as

    to

    how

    Socrates'

    arguments

    refute his

    position.

    The

    dispute

    between

    Socrates

    and

    Thrasymachus

    centers around

    two

    major points

    of

    disagreement

    :

    (

    i

    )

    what

    the

    nature

    or

    essential

    quality

    of

    justice

    is,

    and

    (2)

    whether

    the

    just

    or

    the

    unjust

    life

    is the

    best

    (in

    the

    sense

    of

    most

    profitable)

    life

    for

    men

    to

    live.

    It is

    not

    clear

    that

    every

    commentator

    agrees

    that

    Plato

    was

    even

    aware

    of the different

    nature

    of

    these

    two

    questions,

    but

    in

    the

    text

    he has Socrates

    postpone

    attention

    to

    (2)

    until

    he has

    silenced

    Thrasymachus

    on

    question

    (1).

    An

    examination

    of

    the

    arguments

    involved

    in

    both

    of

    these

    questions

    would

    render

    this

    discussion

    much

    too

    lengthy,

    so

    I

    shall

    concentrate

    my

    attention almost

    entirely

    upon

    question

    (

    1

    ).

    I

    propose

    to

    offer

    an

    interpretation

    of

    Thrasymachus'

    view

    of

    the

    nature

    of

    justice

    and

    the

    just

    life

    which,

    in

    its essential

    points,

    is

    consistent

    throughout

    Book

    I.

    It

    is

    true

    that

    Socrates

    forces

    him

    to

    reformulate

    his

    position

    in

    a

    couple

    of

    instances,

    but

    in

    so

    doing,

    I

    shall

    argue,

    Thrasyma?

    chus

    does

    not

    change

    his

    basic,

    or

    original,

    position.

    Not

    only

    do

    I

    believe

    that

    Thrasymachus

    is

    consistent

    in

    essentials

    throughout

    the

    dispute

    with

    Socrates

    over

    the

    nature

    of

    justice,

    I

    shall

    also

    argue

    that

    Socrates'

    most

    vigorous

    attacks

    fail

    completely

    to refute, or even seriously to damage, Thrasyma?

    chus'

    position.

    Yet

    I

    want

    to

    be

    very

    clear

    that

    my

    interpretation

    of

    Thrasymachus

    is

    not

    meant

    to

    be

    a

    "contemporary

    reformulation,"

    in the

    sense

    of

    claiming

    that this

    is

    the

    way

    Thrasymachus

    should

    have

    argued;

    nor

    am

    I

    claiming

    either

    that Plato

    deliberately

    had Socrates

    misunderstand

    Thrasy?

    machus'

    position,

    or

    that

    Plato

    himself

    really

    didn't

    understand

    what

    Thrasymachus

    was

    saying.

    My

    claim is

    stronger:

    I

    believe that the

    interpretation

    I

    shall

    give

    is

    the

    position Thrasymachus

    held,

    that

    Plato

    understood

    it

    in this

    way,

    and

    that

    in

    the

    dialogue

    Socrates addresses

    himself

    to

    it

    directly.

    If his

    arguments

    fail to

    refute

    Thrasymachus,

    as

    I

    think

    they

    do,

    it

    is

    not

    because

    the

    disputants

    are

    arguing

    at

    cross-purposes,

    but rather

    because

    Socrates'

    arguments

    are

    defective.

    In

    regard

    to

    the

    question

    of the essential

    nature

    of

    justice,

    Thrasymachus

    is

    most

    often accused

    of

    inconsistency

    on

    the

    following points

    :

    (

    i

    )

    He

    offers

    two

    formulations

    of

    his

    definition

    of

    justice,

    which

    I

    shall

    refer

    to

    hereafter

    as

    Ja

    and

    Jb

    :

    Ja:

    "I

    declare

    that

    justice

    is

    nothing

    else

    than

    that

    which

    is

    advantageous

    to the

    stronger."1

    Jb:

    ".

    .

    .justice

    and the

    just

    is

    really

    the

    good

    of

    another,

    the

    advantage

    of

    the

    stronger

    who

    rules,

    but

    the

    self-inflicted

    injury

    of

    the

    subject

    who

    obeys;

    that

    injustice

    is the

    opposite,

    and

    rules

    those

    very

    simple

    just

    souls; that the

    governed

    serve the advantage of the

    stronger

    man,

    and

    by

    their

    obedience

    contribute

    to

    his

    happiness,

    but

    in

    no

    way

    to

    their

    own

    (343C2-7)."

    The

    alleged

    inconsistency

    here

    is that Ja

    can

    be

    interpreted

    as

    implying

    that

    whenever

    a

    strong

    man

    acts

    justly

    this will

    result

    in

    benefit

    or

    profit

    to

    himself;

    whereas

    Jb

    can

    be viewed

    as

    implying

    that

    whoever

    acts

    justly,

    the

    strong

    or

    the

    weak,

    such

    action

    never

    results

    in

    profit

    to

    the

    agent,

    but

    rather

    to

    someone

    else.

    (2)

    Thrasymachus

    maintains

    that

    it is

    most

    often

    the

    case

    that

    the

    strongest

    man

    in

    the

    state

    is the

    ruler, and that the rulers in every type

    of

    state

    make

    laws

    which

    are to

    their

    own

    advantage

    (338

    e

    1-5).

    Thus

    according

    to

    Ja,

    if

    the

    subjects

    obey

    the law

    they

    should

    be

    acting justly.

    But

    Socrates

    points

    out

    that

    rulers

    are

    capable

    of

    making

    mistakes

    in

    their

    legislation

    and

    thus

    might

    mistakenly

    enact

    a

    law

    which

    was

    not

    to

    their

    own

    advantage

    (339

    c

    1-38).

    In

    such

    case

    the

    subjects

    would

    be

    acting justly

    if

    2l8

    1

    Republic,

    338CI-2,

    tr.

    A.

    D.

    Lindsay

    (London,

    1935).

    All

    quotations

    herein

    are

    taken

    from

    this translation.

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    3/12

    IN

    DEFENSE OF THRASYMACHUS

    219

    they

    obeyed

    the

    law,

    but their

    actions would

    not

    result

    in

    benefit

    to

    the

    stronger,

    thus

    contradicting

    Ja.

    (3)

    Following

    Socrates'

    appeal

    to

    the

    analogy

    of

    other

    arts

    to

    the

    "art of

    ruling," Thrasymachus

    refuses to draw the conclusion which Socrates

    believes the

    argument

    entails,

    but instead

    appeals

    to

    another kind

    of

    "art,"

    that of

    shepherding.

    Socrates himself

    then

    accuses

    Thrasymachus

    of

    inconsistency,

    in

    that in

    speaking

    as

    he

    does

    of

    shepherds,

    he

    fails

    to

    follow

    his

    own

    recommenda?

    tion

    to

    discuss

    only

    the

    practitioner,

    qua

    practi?

    tioner,

    of

    an

    art

    exclusively.

    Socrates

    claims

    that

    instead of

    discussing

    the

    shepherd

    "in

    the strict

    sense,"

    Thrasymachus

    is

    speaking

    of the

    shepherd

    as

    an

    earner

    of

    wages

    or

    fees

    (345b5~346d7).

    Other

    alleged

    inconsistencies

    have

    to

    do with

    the

    second

    major

    point

    of

    disagreement

    between

    Socrates and

    Thrasymachus

    (whether

    the

    just

    or

    the

    unjust

    life is

    more

    profitable)

    and

    will,

    there?

    fore,

    not

    be

    discussed

    in detail.

    * *

    *

    In

    defending Thrasymachus

    against

    the

    above

    charges

    I

    require

    a

    bit of

    stage-setting:

    (1)

    I

    shall

    assume

    that

    Thrasymachus

    and

    Socrates

    are

    in

    implicit

    agreement

    that

    just

    action

    requires

    for

    its

    occurrence

    some

    form of human

    society. Justice

    is

    treated

    throughout

    the

    dispute

    as

    a

    social

    phenomenon,

    demanding

    for

    its

    instantia?

    tion

    a

    context

    in

    which

    people

    act

    upon,

    interact

    with,

    and in

    various

    ways

    deal

    mutually

    with each

    other,

    and the

    same

    goes

    for

    injustice,

    of

    course.

    The

    examples

    of

    just

    actions

    appealed

    to

    in

    the

    text are

    all

    such

    as

    to

    involve

    normally

    some

    form

    of

    reciprocal

    action

    by

    those

    toward whom

    just

    action is

    directed

    :

    the

    mutual

    keeping

    of

    contracts

    and

    bargains,

    business

    deals,

    etc.

    (e.g., 343d

    i-e5).

    (2)

    It is

    a

    truism

    to

    observe

    that

    genuine

    dis?

    agreements

    can occur

    only

    within

    a

    context

    of

    shared

    views. It

    is

    conceivable

    that

    Socrates

    and

    Thrasymachus

    share

    so

    few

    points

    of

    agreement

    that

    their whole

    dispute

    is

    a

    series of

    arguments

    at

    cross-purposes.

    Some

    commentators

    implicitly

    or

    explicitly

    presume

    that this

    is

    just

    what

    happens.

    I

    submit that

    there

    is

    no

    direct

    textual evidence

    for

    this

    conclusion.

    If it

    were

    true,

    it

    would

    constitute

    a

    serious

    indictment

    of

    Plato,

    since

    he

    nowhere has

    Socrates

    or

    any

    other character

    point

    this

    out.

    What

    I

    propose

    to

    do

    is

    to

    assume

    the widest

    possible

    range

    of shared views between

    the

    two

    antagonists

    which

    is consonant

    with

    the

    text;

    that

    is,

    on

    each

    point

    relevant

    to

    the

    argument,

    if

    there

    is

    not

    some

    textual

    reference

    precluding

    it,

    I

    shall

    assume

    that

    Socrates

    and

    Thrasymachus

    are

    in

    general

    agreement.

    For

    example,

    since

    it

    is

    nowhere denied, I shall assume that on the whole

    they

    agree

    as

    to

    the

    general

    types

    of

    actions

    normally

    designated

    "just"

    and

    "unjust." Honoring

    contracts,

    paying

    debts,

    paying

    taxes,

    keeping

    bargains

    and

    so

    on

    would

    be

    some

    examples

    of

    actions

    which

    they

    could,

    and

    apparently

    do,

    agree

    are

    just

    actions

    and

    their

    opposites

    unjust.

    Their

    disagreement

    is

    not,

    or

    need

    not

    be,

    as

    to

    which

    types

    of

    acts

    are

    just,

    but rather

    as

    to

    the

    essential

    property

    which

    all

    just

    acts

    share.

    (3)

    I shall

    also

    assume

    that Socrates

    and

    Thrasymachus

    both

    understand

    what is

    meant

    by

    an

    essential

    property,

    and that

    they

    are

    not

    arguing

    at

    cross-purposes

    in

    their

    attempt

    to

    arrive

    at

    the

    essential

    property

    shared

    by

    all

    just

    action,

    and

    only

    by

    just

    actions,

    which

    is

    designated

    by

    the

    universal

    term

    "justice."

    It

    might

    be

    objected

    that

    Thrasymachus

    is

    not

    seeking

    a

    definition of

    justice,

    but rather

    presents

    his conclusion

    baldly

    at

    the

    beginning.

    Nevertheless,

    he is

    willing

    to

    argue

    for

    the

    truth of

    his

    contention and

    to

    abide

    by

    the

    outcome

    of

    the

    argument.

    It is

    no

    logical

    error

    to

    state

    one's conclusion first and

    then

    present

    one's

    arguments.

    * * *

    Does

    Thrasymachus'

    formulation of his

    definition

    of

    justice

    in Jb

    contradict

    Ja?

    Perhaps,

    but

    not

    necessarily,

    and

    it

    is

    surely

    not

    poor

    scholarship

    to

    give

    Thrasymachus

    the

    benefit of

    the

    doubt.

    Cross

    and

    Woozley

    interpret

    Ja

    to

    mean

    that

    every

    time

    anyone

    acts

    justly

    the

    consequences

    of such

    acts

    will

    be

    in

    the

    form of

    some

    benefit

    or

    profit

    to

    the

    strong

    man.2 But

    in

    Ja

    Thrasymachus

    does

    not

    refer

    to

    the

    consequences

    of

    just

    actions;

    he

    says

    that

    justice

    is

    nothing

    else

    than

    .

    .

    .

    etc.

    Why

    not

    take him

    at

    his

    word and

    assume

    that he

    is

    desig?

    nating

    what

    he

    believes

    to

    be

    the essential feature

    of

    just

    action

    itself,

    rather

    than

    the

    consequences

    which

    accrue

    from

    performance

    of

    just

    action?

    If

    Cross and

    Woozley's

    interpretation

    is

    accepted,

    then

    Thrasymachus'

    account

    of

    justice

    can

    be

    a

    definition

    only

    if

    one

    interprets

    him

    as a

    subjectivist

    who is

    claiming

    that

    any

    action

    which results in

    benefit

    or

    profit

    to

    the

    stronger

    is,

    for

    that

    reason,

    just.

    The

    only

    reasonable

    alternative

    would

    be

    that

    2

    R.

    C. Cross

    and A.

    D.

    Woozley,

    Plato's

    Republic:

    A

    Philosophical

    Commentary (London,

    1964),

    cf.

    pp.

    27,

    37,

    38

    ff.

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    4/12

  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    5/12

    IN

    DEFENSE

    OF

    THRASYMACHUS

    221

    grand

    scale

    and

    get

    away

    with

    it.

    Finally,

    one

    needs

    the

    courage

    to

    engage

    in

    and

    pursue

    such

    a

    program.

    Thrasymachus points

    to

    examples

    of

    unjust

    men

    who

    lack

    either

    the

    wit

    or

    the

    courage

    or

    both

    to

    practice

    injustice

    on a

    grand

    scale

    (pickpockets,

    cutpurses,

    temple-breakers, etc.),

    and

    although

    he thinks of these

    as

    stronger

    than

    their

    counterparts

    of

    similar

    station

    among

    just

    men,

    they

    fall

    short

    of

    the

    ideal

    strong

    man

    (348d5~9).

    The

    just

    man,

    on

    the other

    hand,

    could

    never

    be

    a

    strong

    man,

    for he

    lacks

    at

    least

    one

    necessary

    quality

    :

    the

    understanding

    that

    justice

    is

    advanta?

    geous

    to

    the

    stronger.

    The

    ruler

    "in the strict

    sense" is

    defined

    by

    Thrasymachus

    as one

    who

    always

    makes laws

    which

    are

    to

    the ruler's

    advantage

    (34069-34

    ia2).

    He is

    defined,

    be

    it

    noted,

    neither

    as

    an

    unjust,

    nor

    as

    a

    strong

    man.

    Finally,

    the

    unjust

    man,

    on

    Thrasymachus'

    view,

    is

    simply

    a man

    who

    performs

    unjust

    actions,

    and

    as

    I

    pointed

    out

    above,

    since there

    seems

    to

    be

    no

    textual

    considerations

    precluding

    it,

    I

    am

    assuming

    that

    Thrasymachus

    and

    Socrates

    are

    in

    general

    agreement

    as to

    which

    actions

    unjust

    actions would

    be.

    It

    is

    true

    that

    Thrasymachus

    argues

    that rulers

    of

    countries,

    whatever the

    form of

    government

    might

    be,

    are

    the real

    strong

    men.

    Yet,

    there

    is

    no

    textual

    reason

    to

    believe

    that for

    Thrasymachus

    the

    ruler

    is

    the

    strongest

    man

    because

    he

    is

    the ruler

    of a state. Rather, the strongest man in the state is

    most

    likely

    to

    be,

    or

    to

    become

    the

    ruler.

    He

    rises

    to

    the

    top

    naturally

    because

    he

    takes

    advantage

    of

    every

    opportunity

    to

    make

    an

    unjust profit

    and

    to

    further his

    own

    cause

    at

    the

    expense

    of

    others.

    Everyone

    and

    every group

    who

    deal

    with

    him

    justly

    are

    exploited

    by

    him for his

    own

    profit.

    It

    could

    hardly

    be

    the

    case,

    as

    some

    commentators

    have

    suggested,

    that

    the

    ruler

    is

    by

    definition

    the

    stronger,

    because

    Thrasymachus

    admits

    the

    possibility

    of

    there

    being

    a

    just

    ruler

    (343a).

    A

    just

    ruler

    would

    not

    be

    the

    strongest

    man

    in

    the

    state

    in

    Thrasy?

    machus'

    sense

    of

    "strong":

    indeed

    he

    would

    not,

    in this sense, be

    strong

    at all. For

    Thrasymachus

    says

    that the

    just

    ruler loses

    on

    all

    counts:

    his

    business suffers

    through

    neglect,

    and

    he loses the

    respect

    of his

    friends

    and

    relatives

    because he will

    not

    grant

    them

    special privileges

    during

    his

    tenure

    of office.

    It

    should be

    obvious

    by

    this

    time

    that

    if

    the above

    interpretation

    of

    Thrasymachus'

    position

    is

    ac?

    cepted,

    there is

    no

    inconsistency

    between

    Ja

    and

    Jb.

    Just

    action,

    by

    its

    very

    nature,

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger,

    for

    the

    stronger

    by

    definition

    is

    one

    who takes

    advantage

    of

    all

    opportunities

    to

    benefit

    himself.

    Justice

    is

    the

    good

    of

    another,

    in

    that

    acts

    of

    justice

    afford

    others the

    opportunity

    to

    cheat

    and

    defraud

    the

    just

    agent.

    Injustice

    is

    advantageous

    to

    oneself, in that acts of injustice are those in which

    one

    takes unfair

    advantage

    of

    others. Ja

    does

    not

    imply,

    on

    my

    interpretation,

    that if

    the

    strong

    man

    acts

    justly

    it

    is

    to

    his

    own

    advantage.

    Rather,

    Ja

    entails that

    just

    action

    always

    creates

    opportunities

    for the

    unjust

    exploitation

    of

    just

    agents,

    which

    is

    repeated

    in

    slightly

    different

    words in

    Jb.

    Let

    us

    consider

    in

    more

    detail what

    the life

    and

    character of the

    completely

    unjust

    ruler

    might

    be

    like,

    given

    Thrasymachus'

    view

    of

    the

    nature

    of

    justice

    and

    injustice.

    Some

    commentators

    seem

    to

    think

    that the

    only

    sort

    of

    man

    who

    could fulfill

    Thrasymachus' conception

    of

    such

    a

    ruler

    would be

    an

    absolute dictator

    who rules his

    country

    with

    an

    iron

    fist,

    stealing,

    killing,

    and

    imprisoning

    whenever

    his

    slightest

    whim is

    opposed.

    It is

    possible

    that

    Thrasymachus

    would

    agree

    that

    such

    a

    ruler

    would,

    or

    could,

    be

    a

    strong

    man

    in

    his

    sense

    of

    the

    term.

    But it

    should

    not

    be

    forgotten

    that

    he

    claims

    that

    the

    rulers

    in

    every

    state,

    no

    matter

    what

    the form

    of

    government,

    usually

    fit his

    conception

    of

    the

    strong

    man :

    Well, every

    government

    lays

    down

    laws for

    its

    own

    advantage?a

    democracy

    democratic,

    a

    tyranny

    tyrannical

    laws,

    and

    so

    on.

    In

    laying

    down these

    laws

    they

    have made it

    plain

    that what is to their

    advantage

    is

    just.

    They

    punish

    him who

    departs

    from

    this

    as

    a

    law-breaker and

    an

    unjust

    man.

    And

    this,

    my

    good

    sir,

    is

    what

    I

    mean.

    In

    every

    city

    justice

    is

    the

    same.

    It is

    what

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    established

    govern?

    ment.

    But the

    established

    government

    is master

    and

    so

    sound

    reasoning

    gives

    the

    conclusion

    that the

    same

    thing

    is

    always

    just?namely,

    what

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger

    (338e).

    It

    follows

    that

    even

    in

    a

    country

    where

    the

    ruler

    is

    elected

    by

    majority

    vote,

    and

    where

    to

    retain

    his

    position

    as

    ruler,

    he

    must

    retain

    the

    esteem

    of

    the

    electorate,

    the

    ruler

    may

    still

    be,

    and

    usually

    is,

    the strongest man in the state. This means that such

    a

    ruler

    could

    be

    a

    complete

    villain,

    a

    man

    who

    believes

    that

    the

    unjust

    life is

    the best

    life for

    man,

    and that

    justice

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger.

    Bearing

    this in

    mind,

    let

    us

    consider

    a

    possible

    alternative

    to

    the

    view that

    Thrasymachus'

    ruler

    type

    would

    have

    to

    be

    an

    iron-fisted

    dictator.

    Imagine

    the

    following

    rather

    extended

    hypothetical

    case:

    Early

    in

    life

    a

    politically

    ambitious

    man

    named

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    6/12

    222

    AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL

    QUARTERLY

    Setarcos

    comes

    to

    believe

    that

    Thrasymachus'

    position

    is

    entirely

    correct.

    Suppose

    that

    Setarcos is

    both

    intelligent

    and

    courageous.

    While

    taking

    advantage

    of

    every

    opportunity

    to

    profit

    unfairly

    and

    to

    advance

    his

    own

    fortunes

    at

    the

    expense

    of

    others, Setarcos is clever enough to maintain a

    public

    facade

    of

    honesty

    and

    integrity.

    He

    publicly

    proclaims

    his absolute

    faith in

    the view

    that

    the

    just

    life

    is

    the

    best and

    most

    profitable

    life

    for

    man.

    "Mutual

    trust

    is the

    cornerstone

    of

    society,"

    he

    tells

    everyone,

    "and mutual

    trust

    is

    possible only

    when

    the citizens

    of

    a

    state

    deal

    justly

    with

    one

    another."

    His

    voice is

    loudest

    in

    condemnation

    of

    every

    unjust

    and

    dishonest

    act

    by

    an

    official

    in

    power.

    He ferrets

    out

    or,

    if

    need

    be,

    manufactures

    evidence

    of

    im?

    morality

    and

    corruption against

    all

    those who

    oppose

    him

    or

    stand

    in

    the

    way

    of his

    rise

    to

    power.

    Eventually

    he

    campaigns

    for

    the

    highest

    office

    in

    the

    land

    on

    a

    reform

    ticket,

    pleading

    for

    a

    return

    to

    honesty,

    justice,

    and

    fair

    dealing

    in

    government.

    He

    pledges

    himself

    to

    the elimination

    of

    graft

    and

    corruption

    in

    high places.

    When he achieves

    power,

    he

    is

    too

    clever

    to

    perform

    an

    about-face

    and

    become

    a

    tyrant,

    perpetuating

    his

    rule

    by

    force.

    Rather,

    he decries

    the

    fraud,

    waste,

    ineptitude,

    and

    corruption

    which he

    claims

    is his

    legacy

    from

    the

    previous

    administration,

    and reiterates

    his

    belief

    that

    justice

    is the

    best

    policy.

    After

    all,

    he

    is

    a

    just

    man,

    and hasn't

    he

    become

    ruler of the land?

    Once

    he

    becomes

    the

    ruler,

    Setarcos

    may

    be

    able,

    if he is clever enough and bold enough, tomaintain

    his

    public

    facade

    of

    justice

    and

    honesty

    for

    a

    long

    time

    or

    even

    indefinitely,

    while

    remaining

    a

    thoroughly

    unjust

    man.

    But is

    this

    at

    all

    a

    plausible

    account

    ?

    If

    Thrasy?

    machus

    is

    correct,

    such

    a

    ruler,

    to

    the best of his

    ability,

    would

    always

    enact

    only

    those laws which

    are

    advantageous

    to

    himself.

    Do

    we

    have

    to

    imagine

    an

    entire

    citizenry

    so

    incredibly

    naive and

    innocent

    as

    to

    overlook

    this fact

    indefinitely

    ?

    For

    if

    people

    were

    to

    notice

    that

    the laws of

    the land

    are

    of

    this

    nature,

    would

    this

    not

    immediately

    reveal Setarcos

    as

    a

    completely

    unjust

    man

    ?

    The answer to both

    questions

    is :Not at all. One

    of

    the

    strongest

    reasons

    for

    acceptance

    of

    my

    interpretation

    of

    Thrasymachus'

    view

    is

    that

    it

    would

    entail the

    possibility

    that

    a

    completely just

    and

    a

    completely

    unjust

    ruler

    might

    enact

    exactly

    similar

    sets

    of laws

    Thrasymachus

    says

    that

    justice,

    not

    injustice,

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger,

    so

    that

    an

    unjust

    ruler would be foolish

    to

    enact,

    e.g.,

    repressive

    or

    discriminatory

    laws.

    He

    would

    want

    the

    citizens

    to

    act

    toward each

    other and toward

    him

    as

    a

    ruler

    in

    ways

    which both

    Thrasymachus

    and

    Socrates would

    agree

    are

    just.

    For

    Setarcos

    holds,

    with

    Thrasymachus,

    that if the

    subjects

    believe that the

    just

    life is the

    most

    profitable,

    and

    thus

    are

    just

    and

    law-abiding

    in

    their

    dealings

    with

    one another and with their government, they will

    be

    most

    vulnerable

    to

    exploitation

    by

    the ruler.

    All

    states must

    collect

    taxes to

    finance

    legitimate

    governmental

    functions,

    for

    example.

    If the

    citizens

    realize this fact

    and

    willingly obey

    the

    tax

    laws

    of

    the

    state,

    they

    place

    themselves

    in

    a

    perfect position

    to

    be

    unjustly

    exploited by

    the ruler. It

    is

    often

    very

    hard for the

    subjects

    in

    a

    country

    to

    determine

    whether

    all

    of their

    tax

    money

    is

    being

    spent

    wisely

    and

    justly

    for the

    purposes

    for

    which

    it

    is

    collected.

    Furthermore,

    by

    convincing

    the

    people

    that

    they

    are

    serving

    their

    own

    interests

    by

    living

    completely

    just

    lives,

    Setarcos eliminates

    a

    major

    source

    of

    expense

    and

    anxiety

    which often

    plagues

    tyrants:

    he does

    not

    have

    to

    employ nearly

    as

    large

    an

    internal

    security

    force

    to

    preserve

    order,

    enforce his

    laws,

    and

    suppress

    possible

    rebellions.

    It is

    interesting

    to

    note

    in

    passing

    that

    Thrasy?

    machus

    might

    well have

    argued

    that

    Socrates,

    who

    is known for his

    attempts

    to

    defend

    the

    just

    life

    as

    the

    best

    and

    most

    profitable

    life

    for

    man,

    is

    actually

    playing

    into

    the hands

    of the

    unjust

    ruler. Setarcos

    would

    want

    everyone

    in

    the

    state

    (except

    himself

    who

    knows

    better)

    to act

    justly,

    to

    live

    just

    lives,

    and

    to

    believe

    sincerely

    that in

    so

    doing

    they

    were

    serving their own best interests.

    It is

    not

    merely

    because

    one

    sees

    clearly

    that

    acting justly

    renders

    the

    just

    agent

    vulnerable

    to

    exploitation

    that

    one

    can

    become

    a

    strong

    ruler

    of

    a

    state.

    He

    might

    lack

    the

    intelligence

    to

    effect

    a

    master

    plan

    of

    injustice

    and

    power-seeking,

    or

    else

    he

    might

    lack the

    courage

    for

    such

    a

    large-scale

    operation.

    In the

    context

    of

    the

    present

    hypothetical

    case,

    our

    unjust

    ruler, Setarcos,

    might

    be ranked

    as

    to

    his

    degree

    of

    "strength,"

    in

    Thrasymachus'

    sense,

    on

    the basis of

    how well

    he

    was

    able

    to

    convince

    the

    populace

    of the

    folly

    of

    living

    un?

    justly,

    especially

    in

    their

    dealings

    with the

    govern?

    ment of their state. If Setarcos were able to

    convince

    everyone

    in

    the

    state

    that

    he

    is

    a com?

    pletely

    just

    man,

    that because

    he is

    just

    he is

    happy,

    that

    justice

    in

    general

    is

    most

    profitable

    to

    man

    as

    a

    way

    of

    life,

    while

    at

    the

    same

    time

    being

    able,

    covertly,

    to

    cheat

    and steal

    from

    the

    people

    systematically,

    then

    he would

    conform

    perfectly

    to

    Thrasymachus'

    conception

    of

    the

    strong

    man.

    If

    Thrasymachus

    were

    to

    prove

    his

    case

    that the

    unjust

    life

    is the

    good

    life for

    man,

    would

    this entail

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    7/12

    IN

    DEFENSE OF

    THRASYMACHUS

    223

    that

    Socrates,

    or

    you,

    or

    I,

    or

    anyone

    who under?

    stands what he is

    talking

    about

    ought

    to

    begin

    living

    the

    unjust

    life ? This

    conclusion would

    at

    least

    not

    follow from

    such

    a

    proof.

    I

    find

    no

    textual evidence

    that

    Thrasymachus

    was

    advocating

    universal

    injustice

    as a

    way

    of life

    for

    everyone.

    In

    fact,

    the

    greater

    the ratio of

    just

    to

    unjust people

    in

    a

    state,

    the

    better life

    can

    be for

    the

    unjust

    few.

    Even

    if

    everyone

    were

    to

    begin

    to

    live

    completely

    unjust

    lives,

    however,

    this

    would

    not

    negate

    Thrasy?

    machus'

    claim

    that

    justice

    is

    the

    advantage

    of the

    stronger,

    only

    no one

    would

    then be

    acting

    justly.

    At

    any

    rate,

    to

    describe

    a

    certain

    way

    of life

    as

    the

    best life

    for

    man

    is

    not

    equivalent

    to,

    nor

    does

    it

    entail that

    everyone

    should,

    or even

    can,

    live

    such

    a

    life.

    Thrasymachus

    could

    be

    implying

    no

    more

    than

    that

    Socrates and the

    others

    ought

    to

    wake

    up

    and

    realize

    that

    they

    are

    like

    sheep

    being

    kept

    for

    the

    profit of the unjust man, and that sheep-like, they

    assume

    naively

    that

    to

    be

    fleeced

    and

    slaughtered

    for

    mutton

    is

    better than

    wearing

    warm

    clothes

    and

    being

    well-fed.

    It

    is

    important

    to

    understand

    that

    Thrasymachus

    does

    not

    argue

    that

    the

    ruler of

    a

    country ought

    to

    live

    an

    unjust

    life for

    the

    following

    reason:

    when

    Thrasymachus

    defines the

    "ruler

    in the

    strict

    sense"

    as

    the

    one

    who

    infallibly

    enacts

    laws which

    are

    advantageous

    to

    the

    ruler,

    he

    might

    be

    interpreted

    as

    meaning

    that it

    is

    logically

    impossible

    for

    a

    just

    man

    to

    be

    a

    ruler in

    the

    strict

    sense.

    If

    so,

    then

    of

    course

    he

    would be

    inconsistent,

    for

    he

    has

    ad?

    mitted

    that

    a

    just

    man

    could

    be

    a

    ruler.

    But

    it

    would

    be

    a

    mistake

    to

    interpret Thrasymachus

    as

    claiming

    that

    when

    a

    ruler

    makes laws which

    give

    him

    the

    opportunity

    to

    exploit

    the

    people

    for

    his

    own

    profit,

    that

    he

    ought

    to

    exploit

    them,

    and

    that

    if

    he

    does

    not,

    he is not

    a

    ruler

    in

    the strict

    sense

    at

    all.

    On

    the

    contrary,

    the

    just

    man

    certainly

    could

    be

    a

    ruler

    in

    the

    strict

    sense,

    if

    we

    do

    not

    read into

    Thrasymachus'

    definition

    something

    which isn't

    there

    in the

    text.

    The

    laws

    which

    the

    just

    ruler

    makes,

    as

    pointed

    out

    above,

    might

    be

    exactly

    similar

    to

    the

    set

    of

    laws

    which

    an

    unjust

    ruler

    would

    make

    (even

    if

    neither

    made

    any legislative

    mistakes).

    Thus the

    just

    ruler's

    laws,

    like those of

    the

    unjust

    ruler,

    would

    afford

    him the

    opportunity

    of

    taking

    unfair

    advantage

    of the citizens

    when

    they

    act

    justly. Being

    just,

    however,

    he

    would

    not

    do

    so.

    But

    in

    failing

    to

    cheat

    the

    populace

    he is

    not

    failing

    to

    do

    something

    which

    he

    ought

    to

    do,

    if

    he

    is

    to

    be

    a

    ruler

    in

    the

    strict

    sense.

    On

    Thrasy?

    machus'

    view,

    he

    is

    merely

    being

    stupid.

    To

    sum

    up

    briefly,

    I

    interpret

    the

    dispute

    between

    Socrates

    and

    Thrasymachus

    as

    a

    genuine

    disagree?

    ment

    on

    issues

    which

    are

    quite

    important,

    his?

    torically,

    for moral

    philosophy.

    It is

    a

    genuine

    disagreement,

    in

    the

    sense

    that it

    arises within

    a

    context

    of

    shared

    opinion,

    and

    on

    no

    major point

    are

    they arguing

    at

    cross-purposes.

    I

    view

    Socrates

    and

    Thrasymachus

    as

    being

    in

    broadly

    general

    agreement

    as to

    the

    practical

    content

    of the

    just

    and the

    unjust

    lives?that

    is,

    as

    to

    the

    types

    or

    kinds

    of

    actions

    which

    are

    correctly

    called

    "just"

    and

    "unjust."

    The

    dispute

    between them is

    not

    a

    simple

    semantic

    one

    regarding

    the

    correct

    moral

    designa?

    tion of

    various

    types

    of actions. There

    is

    nothing

    in

    the

    text

    to

    suggest

    that

    they

    would

    not

    both

    con?

    sider

    just

    such

    actions

    as

    honoring

    contracts,

    paying

    taxes,

    obeying

    the

    law,

    giving

    honest

    measure,

    and

    so

    on.

    I

    interpret

    Thrasymachus

    as

    claiming

    that

    just

    action is intrinsically disadvantageous to the

    performer

    because

    by

    its

    very

    nature

    it

    places

    the

    just

    agent

    in

    a

    vulnerable

    position

    with

    respect

    to

    those

    with

    whom he deals

    in

    practical

    life.

    By

    acting

    justly

    toward

    one's fellow

    man,

    ipso

    acto,

    one

    places

    oneself in

    a

    position

    to

    be

    unjustly

    taken

    advantage

    of.

    When

    Thrasymachus

    says

    that

    "justice

    is

    nothing

    else

    than

    that

    which is

    advanta?

    geous

    to

    the

    stronger"

    he is

    referring

    to

    this

    characteristic

    of

    justice,

    which

    he

    believes

    to

    be its

    essential

    property.

    By

    the

    "stronger,"

    he

    means

    the

    person

    who

    sees

    justice

    and

    the

    just

    life for what

    he,

    Thrasymachus,

    believes

    it

    to

    be,

    and who

    has

    the

    intelligence

    and

    the

    courage

    to

    practice injustice

    on

    a

    grand

    scale. One who

    is

    truly

    a

    strong

    man

    in

    his

    sense

    would

    thus

    never

    voluntarily

    live

    a

    just

    life.

    * * *

    Let

    us

    now

    consider the

    major

    criticisms

    which

    Socrates

    offers

    to

    Thrasymachus'

    view:

    If

    an

    unjust

    ruler

    makes

    a

    law which

    he mis?

    takenly

    believes

    to

    be

    advantageous

    to

    himself,

    aren't

    the

    subjects

    acting justly

    when

    they

    obey

    this

    law ?

    If

    so,

    then

    justice,

    in

    this

    case,

    would

    not

    be

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger. Cleitophon

    and

    Polemarchus

    immediately

    conclude

    that this

    criticism is

    devastating

    to

    Thrasymachus'

    stated

    position

    (339e9~340C4).

    If the

    essential

    quality

    of

    justice

    is

    that it

    is

    always

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger,

    then

    there

    could

    not

    be

    a case

    of

    justice

    which

    was

    not

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger.

    Socrates'

    criticism

    seems

    to

    them

    to

    offer

    a

    perfect

    counter-example

    to

    Thrasymachus'

    account of

    the

    nature

    of

    justice.

    ?

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    8/12

    224

    AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL

    QUARTERLY

    Gleitophon,

    however,

    believes

    that

    Thrasy?

    machus

    has

    merely

    misstated

    his

    view,

    and

    suggests

    that

    "...

    by

    what

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger

    he

    meant

    fiwhat

    the

    stronger

    thinks

    is

    to

    his

    advantage.'

    This

    is what

    the weaker

    must

    do,

    and

    this is his definition of justice (34ob5~7)."

    Cross

    and

    Woozley

    argue

    that

    Thrasymachus

    would

    have done well

    to

    accept

    Cleitophon's

    reformulation

    in

    order

    to

    escape

    inconsistency,

    "for

    while

    a

    ruler

    may

    make

    a

    mistake

    as

    to

    what

    actually

    is

    his

    interest he

    will

    hardly

    make

    a

    mistake

    as

    to

    what he

    believes

    to

    be

    his

    interest;

    and if

    it

    is

    right

    for

    subjects

    to

    do what

    the ruler

    believes

    to

    be

    in

    his

    interest,

    it

    will

    not matter

    that

    the ruler is

    mistaken in

    believing

    so."4

    Sparshott5 disagrees

    with

    this

    suggestion,

    and

    I

    believe

    rightly

    so.

    If

    Thrasymachus

    had

    agreed

    with

    Cleitophon

    he

    would

    have been inconsistent. For

    he has claimed that

    justice

    is

    advantageous

    to the

    stronger,

    and

    Cleitophon's suggestion

    entails

    that

    justice

    is

    obedience

    to

    the law. If

    justice

    is

    nothing

    more

    nor

    less than

    obedience

    to

    the

    law, however,

    then

    the

    grounds

    or

    reasons

    for

    enacting

    the

    laws

    (the

    advantage

    of

    the

    stronger)

    drop

    out as

    irrelevant.

    Thrasymachus,

    however,

    emphatically rejects

    Cleitophon's

    suggestion

    on

    the

    grounds

    that

    in

    the

    strict

    sense

    of

    ruler,

    a

    ruler

    never

    makes mistakes

    (34odi~34ia2). Thrasymachus,

    of

    course,

    is

    not

    here

    claiming

    either

    that

    some

    rulers

    are,

    have

    been,

    or

    might

    be

    infallible,

    or

    that

    any

    ruler

    who

    is

    unjust

    will

    be infallible.

    His

    case

    does

    not

    depend

    upon

    the

    actual

    existence

    of

    an

    infallible ruler.

    He

    never

    says, e.g.,

    that

    a

    doctor

    who

    prescribes

    the

    wrong

    medicine

    on a

    particular

    occasion is

    not

    really

    a

    doctor,

    nor

    that

    an

    accountant

    is

    not

    really

    an

    accountant

    if he

    sometimes

    makes

    mistakes

    in

    calculation.

    He

    simply

    says,

    in

    effect,

    that

    our

    grounds

    for

    calling

    a man a

    doctor

    or

    an

    accountant

    are

    not

    that

    he

    makes,

    or

    is

    capable

    of

    making,

    mistakes

    in the

    practice

    of

    his

    profession,

    and

    the

    same

    holds

    true

    for rulers.

    Thrasymachus

    is,

    I

    suggest, doing

    something

    here

    which is quite common in contemporary moral

    philosophy:

    he

    is

    distinguishing

    a

    role

    or

    office

    from

    the

    man

    who holds

    the office

    or

    plays

    the role. If

    someone

    were

    to

    ask

    what

    a

    doctor

    is,

    and

    if

    we

    know

    of

    a

    particular

    doctor

    who has

    made

    a

    mistake

    in

    the

    diagnosis

    of

    a

    certain

    patient's

    illness,

    we

    would

    be

    responding

    in

    a

    misleading

    and

    inappropriate

    way

    if

    we were

    to answer

    by

    saying

    that

    a

    doctor

    is

    one

    whose

    job

    it

    is

    to

    make

    mistaken

    diagnoses

    of

    people's

    illnesses.

    There

    is

    still

    an

    important

    question

    at

    stake

    here,

    however

    :

    If

    a

    doctor

    prescribed

    a

    certain medicine

    on the basis of a mistaken diagnosis of a patient's

    illness,

    would

    the

    patient

    be

    acting

    as

    a

    patient

    should

    if

    he

    obeyed

    his

    doctor?

    By

    analogy,

    we

    might

    ask

    Thrasymachus:

    If the

    unjust

    ruler

    makes

    a

    law which

    he

    mistakenly

    believes

    to

    be advanta?

    geous

    to

    himself,

    would the

    subjects

    be

    acting

    justly

    if

    they obeyed

    this law

    ?

    We

    know,

    of

    course,

    that

    normally

    what

    the

    doctor

    prescribes

    is

    what

    a

    patient

    ought

    to

    do

    to

    treat

    his

    particular

    illness

    or

    affliction.

    It is

    the

    proper

    job

    of the doctor

    to

    prescribe

    the

    types

    of

    treatment

    which

    are

    appropriate

    to

    the

    particular

    ills

    and afflictions of

    his

    patients.

    Thus

    "doing

    what

    the doctor orders" is

    commonly

    accepted

    as

    roughly

    synonymous

    with

    "applying

    the

    appropriate

    treat?

    ment to

    the

    proper

    illness

    or

    affliction." But

    this

    does

    not

    mean

    that

    appropriate

    treatment

    for

    any

    given

    disease

    or

    affliction

    is

    correctly

    defined

    as

    "whatever the

    doctor

    prescribes."

    If

    I

    smashed

    my

    toe

    with

    a

    hammer

    and

    immediately

    consulted

    a

    doctor,

    his

    advice

    to

    have

    my

    leg

    cut

    off

    at

    the

    hip

    would

    not

    be

    acceptable

    (at

    least not

    if

    the smashed

    toe

    were

    all

    that

    was

    wrong

    with

    me).

    Hence,

    in the

    case

    of

    Thrasymachus,

    we

    could

    say

    that in

    one

    sense,

    a

    vulgar

    or

    loose

    sense,

    a

    man

    would be

    acting justly

    if

    he

    obeys

    a

    law

    which

    a

    ruler

    mistakenly

    thinks

    to

    be

    to

    his

    own

    advantage,

    but

    in

    another

    more

    strict

    or

    absolute

    sense,

    he

    would

    not.

    One

    might today

    want

    to

    contest

    the

    legitimacy

    of such

    a

    distinction,

    but

    obviously

    Plato

    would

    not,

    since this is

    a

    characteristically

    Platonic

    way

    of

    arguing.

    At

    any

    rate,

    Socrates

    accepts

    Thrasymachus'

    answer

    as

    satisfactory.

    Subsequently,

    he

    speaks

    only

    of

    the

    ruler

    in

    the

    strict

    sense,

    and

    indeed,

    as

    Nettleship6 points

    out,

    he

    thereafter identifies

    the

    practitioner,

    qua

    practitioner,

    of

    an

    art

    or

    profession

    with

    the

    art

    or

    profession.

    Socrates next asks Thrasymachus whether the

    physician,

    qua

    physician,

    is

    a

    "money

    maker,

    an

    earner

    of

    fees,

    or

    a

    healer

    of

    the

    sick,"

    and

    Thrasy?

    machus,

    of

    course,

    says

    the

    last

    (341C2 ff.).

    And if

    a

    man

    is

    sick,

    it

    is

    obviously

    to

    his

    benefit

    to

    have

    the

    services of

    a

    healer

    available.

    Socrates then

    refers

    to

    other

    examples,

    each

    of

    which

    is

    designed

    4

    Gross

    and

    Woozley, op.

    cit., p.

    46.

    5

    F.

    E.

    Sparshott,

    "Socrates

    and

    Thrasymachus,"

    The

    Monist,

    Vol.

    50

    (1966),

    pp.

    424

    ff.

    6

    Richard L.

    Nettleship,

    Lectures

    on

    the

    Republic of

    Plato,

    2nd

    ed.

    (London, 1964),

    p.

    30.

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    9/12

    IN DEFENSE OF THRASYMACHUS

    225

    to

    show

    that it is

    the

    subject

    matter

    of

    an

    art,

    which

    is benefited

    by

    the

    perfect practicing

    of the

    art.

    Thrasymachus

    grudgingly

    agrees

    in

    each

    case.

    Thus in

    regard

    to

    the

    ruling

    of

    a

    state,

    which

    Thrasymachus

    has

    agreed

    is

    an

    art,

    it

    would

    seem

    by analogy that it is the subjects as "subject matter"

    of

    the

    art

    of

    ruling,

    who benefit

    from the

    perfect

    practice

    of

    this

    art,

    rather than

    the ruler

    who

    practices

    it.

    It

    seems

    obvious

    in the

    text

    that Socrates believes

    that his

    argument

    from

    analogy

    of the other

    arts

    to

    the

    art

    of

    ruling

    has

    dealt

    Thrasymachus'

    account

    a

    death

    blow.

    It

    is

    at

    first difficult

    to

    see

    why

    he

    should

    think

    so.

    The

    principle

    question

    at

    issue has

    to

    do with

    the

    nature

    of

    justice.

    Even

    if it is

    true

    that

    the

    perfect practice

    of the

    art

    of

    ruling

    is

    beneficial7

    to

    the

    subjects, why

    should

    this

    force

    Thrasymachus

    to

    give

    up

    his

    claim

    that

    justice

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger?

    After

    all,

    he has

    not

    claimed

    that

    the ruler

    is

    a

    strong

    man,

    by

    definition,

    nor

    has

    he

    argued

    that in

    order

    to

    be

    a

    ruler, qua

    ruler,

    one

    must

    be

    unjust.

    Admittedly

    he would

    have

    to

    give

    ground

    on

    some

    points,

    but

    even

    so,

    why

    could

    he

    not

    rebut

    Socrates'

    argument

    success?

    fully

    by saying,

    "All

    right,

    if

    a

    strong

    man

    becomes

    ruler,

    he

    won't

    act

    as

    a

    ruler

    should,

    strictly

    speaking,

    but he could

    still be

    a

    great

    strategist

    and

    an

    unparalleled grafter"?

    I

    believe

    that

    the

    reason

    why Thrasymachus

    does

    not

    take this line

    is

    that

    Socrates

    (or

    perhaps

    Plato)

    has accepted a suppressed premiss which Thrasy?

    machus fails

    to

    question

    :

    it

    is

    that

    the

    only

    reason

    why

    a

    practitioner

    of

    an

    art

    would

    fail

    to

    manifest

    perfectly

    the definition of that

    art

    in

    his

    practice

    is

    that he is

    ignorant.

    Either he

    does

    not

    know

    the

    definition,

    or

    else he doesn't

    know

    in

    every

    case

    which action instantiates the

    definition

    (although

    in

    the

    actual

    dispute,

    the latter

    kind of

    ignorance

    is

    seldom touched

    upon).

    When

    Thrasymachus

    first

    makes

    the

    vulgar-sense

    vs.

    strict-sense

    distinction,

    the

    examples

    he

    uses are

    those

    of

    a

    doctor who mis

    diagnoses

    a

    patient's

    illness and

    an

    accountant

    who

    makes

    a

    mistake in calculation.

    It is

    implicitly

    assumed that the

    examples

    referred to are

    examples

    of

    unintentional

    errors,

    and

    this kind of

    example

    is

    extended

    across

    the

    board

    to

    all

    the

    arts,

    including

    the

    art

    of

    ruling.

    Thus

    in

    the

    analogy

    of the

    arts,

    Socrates

    assumes

    without

    argument

    that the

    only

    deviations

    from

    perfection

    in

    ruling

    must

    be

    in

    the

    form of unintentional

    errors,

    due

    to

    ignorance

    of

    the

    true nature

    of

    ruling.

    Because

    Thrasymachus

    accepts

    this

    suppressed

    premiss,

    he

    believes

    himself

    to

    be

    in

    the

    following

    dilemma

    :

    Insofar

    as

    a

    man

    is

    unjust,

    he

    is

    concerned

    only

    with

    self-aggrandizement;

    anyone

    who

    prac?

    tices

    an

    art

    less than

    perfectly

    does

    so

    out

    of

    ignorance of the nature of perfect practice of that

    art;

    the

    perfect

    practice

    of

    the

    art

    of

    ruling

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    subjects,

    and

    not

    to

    the ruler.

    Therefore,

    an

    unjust

    ruler,

    to

    the

    extent

    that he is

    unjust,

    and

    in

    virtue of

    the

    fact that he is

    unjust,

    is

    ignorant

    of the

    nature

    of

    ruling.

    Hence

    a

    com?

    pletely unjust

    ruler would

    be

    completely

    ignorant

    of

    the

    art

    of

    ruling.

    He would

    be

    directly analogous

    to

    the

    man

    who

    knows

    absolutely nothing

    about

    music

    or

    musical

    instruments,

    yet

    who

    attempts

    to

    attune

    a

    stringed

    instrument

    properly

    (cf.

    349e).

    Although

    Thrasymachus

    can

    see

    no

    way

    out

    of

    this

    dilemma,

    Socrates'

    conclusion

    seems

    to

    fly

    in

    the face of obvious facts.

    Thrasymachus

    believes

    that the

    vast

    majority

    of

    actual

    rulers

    are

    grossly

    unjust

    men,

    and,

    far

    from

    being ignorant

    of

    the

    nature

    of

    ruling, they

    seem

    to

    him

    much

    more

    knowledgeable

    than

    the ruler

    who

    has

    the

    oppor?

    tunity

    to

    defraud

    his

    subjects

    on

    a

    grand

    scale,

    but

    deliberately

    refrains from

    doing

    so.

    Socrates' view

    seems

    to

    him

    incredibly

    naive. An

    analogy

    Thrasymachus

    might

    have used would be that of

    a

    gambling

    game

    between

    an

    honest

    man

    and

    a

    cheat,

    in

    which

    the

    cheat wins

    (by cheating)

    the

    money, lands,

    possessions,

    servants,

    slaves,

    titles,

    even the clothes on the back of the honest man. By

    analogy,

    Socrates'

    position

    would

    seem

    to

    imply

    that

    the

    honest

    man

    actually

    comes

    out

    ahead,

    because

    he

    plays

    the

    game

    as

    it

    should

    be

    played,

    and

    that

    every

    time

    the

    cheater

    cheats,

    he

    thereby

    merely

    reveals his

    ignorance

    of the

    game.

    Surely

    Thrasymachus

    should

    have

    rejected

    Socrates'

    suppressed premiss. Nothing

    in

    Thrasy?

    machus'

    account

    requires

    it.

    To

    accept

    this

    premiss

    would be

    to

    place

    in the

    same

    category

    of

    ignorance

    a

    young,

    inexperienced

    physician

    who mis

    diagnoses

    an

    illness,

    and/or

    mis-prescribes

    treat?

    ment,

    on

    one

    hand,

    and

    an

    experienced physician

    who prescribes removal of organs and tissue which

    he knows

    to

    be

    healthy

    (tonsils, appendices,

    etc.),

    to

    gain

    an

    undeserved

    fee,

    on

    the

    other hand.

    Nevertheless,

    in

    the

    text

    Thrasymachus

    does

    not

    reject

    Socrates'

    suppressed premiss,

    but

    rather,

    in

    frustration,

    turns

    the

    full

    force

    of his

    scorn

    and

    derision

    upon

    him

    (343a ,

    ff.)

    :

    Socrates

    needs

    a

    nurse

    to

    wipe

    his

    nose.

    He

    is

    such

    a

    child

    in

    7

    The

    term

    translated

    "advantageous"

    in

    Ja

    is

    the

    same

    as

    that

    translated

    "beneficial"

    in

    Socrates'

    analogy

    of the

    arts

    (To

    Xump?ron).

    Thus

    his

    claim could

    have

    been

    worded,

    "the

    perfect

    practice

    of

    an

    art

    is

    advantageous

    to

    its

    subject

    matter."

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    10/12

    226

    AMERICAN

    PHILOSOPHICAL

    QUARTERLY

    practical

    matters

    that he

    cannot

    see

    that

    shepherds

    and

    cattle

    herdsmen tend

    sheep

    and

    cattle for their

    own or

    their masters'

    profit,

    rather than for the

    benefit of

    the

    sheep

    and

    cattle,

    and that the

    rulers

    of

    states

    treat

    their

    subjects

    like

    sheep, caring

    for

    them only to gain greater profit from them.

    Socrates'

    answer

    to

    this

    attack

    (345b4, ff.)

    is

    to

    chide

    Thrasymachus

    for

    failing

    to

    draw the

    conclusion which follows from the

    former

    argument

    (i.e.,

    that

    the

    art

    of

    ruling

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    subjects

    and

    not

    to

    the

    ruler),

    and

    to

    maintain

    that

    the

    same

    kind of

    argument

    applies

    to

    the

    "art"

    of

    shepherding

    :a

    shepherd

    is

    correctly

    defined,

    not

    as

    an

    earner

    of

    wages

    or

    fees,

    but

    as one

    who

    cares

    for

    sheep.

    Thus

    again

    it

    is the

    subject

    matter

    of this

    art

    (the sheep)

    which

    benefits from excellent

    practice,

    rather

    than

    the

    practitioner.

    It is

    interesting

    to note

    that

    Thrasymachus

    never

    actually

    admits

    that

    Socrates

    has

    refuted

    his claim

    that

    justice

    is

    advantageous

    to

    the

    stronger.

    Thus

    we

    are

    left

    to

    decide for ourselves

    whether

    he

    really

    believed his view

    to

    be

    defeated,

    or,

    alternatively,

    whether

    he still

    believed

    his

    original position

    to

    be

    perfectly

    correct,

    even

    though

    he

    was

    unable

    at

    the

    time

    to

    see

    a

    mistake in

    Socrates'

    reasoning.

    Does

    Socrates

    make

    such

    a

    mistake? Even

    if,

    purely

    for the sake of

    argument,

    we

    were

    to

    grant

    him

    his

    suppressed

    premiss

    (i.e.,

    that

    any

    deviation

    from

    perfection

    in

    the

    practice

    of

    an

    art

    is

    uninten?

    tional and due

    entirely

    to

    ignorance

    of the

    true

    nature of the art), has he indeed shown that, in the

    appropriate

    sense,

    the

    art

    of

    ruling, strictly

    speaking,

    is

    beneficial

    (advantageous)

    to

    the

    subjects

    ?

    It

    is

    not

    unimportant

    that,

    in

    the

    dispute

    with

    Thrasymachus,

    Socrates

    does

    not

    spell

    out

    the

    ways

    in

    which

    the

    perfect practice

    of the

    art

    of

    ruling

    would be

    advantageous

    to

    the

    subjects:

    he

    merely

    concludes

    that

    it

    must

    be

    so,

    because

    in the

    case

    of

    the other

    arts

    examined,

    the

    subject

    matter

    of

    the

    arts,

    rather

    than the

    artists,

    were

    the beneficiaries

    of

    excellent

    practice.

    Note

    also

    that

    it

    is

    absolutely

    vital

    to

    Socrates'

    case

    that

    the

    benefits derivable

    from the perfect practice of an art be seen as such

    by

    the

    subject

    matter,

    in

    the

    sense

    that the

    practice

    of

    the

    art must

    provide

    something

    needful,

    worth?

    while,

    or

    desirable

    from

    the

    viewpoint

    of

    the

    subject

    matter.

    Granted

    this

    presents

    a

    real

    difficulty

    in

    those

    cases

    in

    which the

    subject

    matter

    is

    inanimate,

    as

    for

    example,

    in

    the manufacture

    of musical

    instruments,

    even

    here,

    by

    extension,

    one

    might

    think of the

    objective

    worth

    of, e.g.,

    a

    violin

    being

    enhanced

    by

    the

    skill of

    a

    master

    craftsman,

    whereas

    a

    hack

    might

    have

    used the

    same

    materials

    and

    made

    an

    inferior

    instrument.

    In

    fact,

    Socrates does

    not

    focus

    attention

    on

    those

    arts

    whose

    subject

    matter

    is inanimate when

    he is trying to prove his point about the art of

    ruling.

    His

    primary example

    is that

    of the

    physician.

    A

    physician

    is

    defined

    as

    a

    healer

    of

    the sick.

    Healing

    the sick

    is

    an

    activity

    which

    is

    beneficial

    to

    the

    patients,

    in

    the

    sense

    of

    providing

    a

    service

    which

    is

    needful

    and desirable

    from the

    patients'

    point

    of

    view.

    It

    is

    this feature which

    Socrates

    believes

    has

    its

    analogue

    in

    all

    the

    other

    arts,

    including

    the

    art

    of

    ruling.

    But

    even

    though

    this

    may

    be

    true

    of

    medicine,

    it

    is

    a

    mistake

    to

    conclude

    that

    all

    arts,

    if

    practiced

    excellently,

    are

    desirable

    or

    needful

    from

    the

    point

    of

    view

    of the

    subject

    matter.

    This

    can

    easily

    be shown

    by

    appeal

    to

    other sorts of

    practices

    which would

    surely

    fit into

    Socrates'

    broadly

    general

    concept

    of

    an

    art.

    The

    art

    of

    torture,8

    for

    example,

    would

    surely

    fit

    Socrates'

    model. As

    an

    art,

    it

    can

    be

    practiced

    well

    or

    badly.

    The

    proficient

    torturer

    is

    the

    one

    who

    can

    keep

    his victims

    alive

    and in

    constantly increasing

    agony

    for

    the

    longest

    period

    of

    time.

    He is

    the

    one

    who

    never

    fails

    to extract

    the

    confession,

    or

    the

    recantation,

    or

    the oath

    of

    allegiance,

    or

    the

    suppressed

    information

    from

    unwilling

    victims.

    It

    follows

    that,

    just

    as

    in

    the

    case

    of

    the

    physician,

    one

    cannot

    correctly

    define

    a

    torturer,

    qua

    torturer,

    as

    an

    earner

    of

    wages

    or

    fees.

    Thrasymachus

    himself

    provides

    another

    example

    which,

    with

    a

    few

    hypothetical amplifications,

    could

    also

    serve

    to

    illustrate

    Socrates'

    mistake:

    Suppose

    it

    were

    the

    case

    that

    extremely

    fat

    sheep

    bring

    the

    best

    price

    on

    the

    market.

    Suppose,

    however,

    that

    very

    fat

    sheep

    suffer from shortness

    of

    breath,

    constant

    pain

    in the

    lungs,

    aching

    ankles,

    and

    continual

    nausea.

    As

    Socrates

    says,

    the

    shepherd,

    qua

    shepherd,

    is

    defined

    as

    one

    who

    cares

    for

    sheep,

    not

    as an earner

    of

    wages

    or

    fees.

    Yet in

    this

    case,

    no

    one

    could

    deny

    that the best

    shepherd

    would

    be the

    one

    who

    was

    able

    to

    bring

    the

    fattest

    sheep to market (i.e., this is what "caring for the

    sheep"

    would

    consist

    of,

    at

    least

    in

    part).

    The

    above

    are

    only

    two

    of

    many

    possible

    examples

    which

    could

    be

    given

    to

    illustrate

    the

    point

    that the

    perfect

    practicing

    of

    an

    art

    may

    not

    be such

    as

    to

    fulfill

    the

    needs

    of,

    improve,

    or

    in

    other

    ways

    be desirable

    from

    the

    point

    of

    view

    of

    the

    subject

    matter.

    Socrates

    speaks

    of

    the

    function

    of

    an

    art

    as,

    in

    8

    This

    example

    was

    first

    suggested

    to

    me

    by

    T. G.

    Smith.

    This content downloaded from 192.76.8.25 on Sat, 16 Jan 2016 14:31:45 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 In Defence of Thrasymachus

    11/12

    IN

    DEFENSE

    OF THRASYMACHUS

    227

    one

    way

    or

    another,

    alleviating

    the

    "defects"

    of

    its

    subject

    matter

    (342a2,

    ff.).

    The

    art

    of

    medicine has

    come

    into

    being

    because

    the

    human

    body

    is

    defective. But

    this

    sort

    of

    language

    unjustifiably

    prejudices

    the

    case.

    In what

    sense

    is

    the

    subject

    matter of the art of torture "defective" ?Only in

    the

    sense

    that

    various

    forms of

    external stimuli

    are

    capable

    of

    causing

    people pain.

    The

    art

    of

    torture,

    then,

    would

    never

    have

    come

    into

    being

    if

    people

    were

    unable

    to

    feel

    pain

    and

    anguish.

    If

    Socrates'

    discussion

    of

    the function

    and

    origins

    of

    the

    various

    arts

    are

    purged

    of such

    question

    begging

    language,

    what remains

    ?What

    conclusion

    can one

    draw

    from his

    analogy

    of the arts?

    I

    suggest,

    merely

    the value-neutral

    point

    that

    for

    any

    art

    or

    artist

    to

    exist,

    there

    must

    be

    an

    appropriate

    subject

    matter

    on

    which the

    art

    can

    be

    practiced.

    For

    there

    to

    be

    physicians

    and

    an

    art

    of

    medicine,

    there

    must

    exist

    patients

    on

    whom

    it can

    be

    practiced;

    i.e.,

    people

    with bodies

    that

    are

    not

    invulnerable

    to

    disease, accident,

    or

    infirmity.

    For

    the

    art

    of

    shepherding

    to

    exist,

    there

    must

    be

    sheep

    to

    care

    for. And

    for there

    to

    be

    rulers,

    there

    must

    be

    subjects

    to

    rule. Whether the

    subject

    matter

    "benefits"

    from

    the

    proficient

    practicing

    of

    an

    art,

    in the

    sense

    of

    having

    something

    needful

    or

    desir?

    able

    provided

    for

    it

    or

    done

    to it

    (from

    the stand?

    point

    of

    the

    subject

    matter

    itself,

    that

    is),

    is

    contingent

    upon

    the

    type

    of

    art

    involved.

    It

    is

    certainly

    not true

    of all

    the

    arts.

    Socrates' argument that the perfect practice of

    the

    art

    of

    ruling

    is

    necessarily advantageous

    to

    the

    subjects

    thus fails

    completely

    to

    refute

    Thrasyma?

    chus.

    All that

    one

    is

    justified

    in

    concluding

    from

    his

    argument

    is

    that there

    must

    be

    subjects

    on

    which

    to

    practice

    this

    art,

    or

    else

    neither

    art

    nor

    artist could

    exist.

    One

    can now

    also

    draw

    the conclusion

    that

    even

    if

    Socrates

    is

    granted

    his

    highly questionable

    premiss

    that

    failure

    to

    conform

    perfectly

    to

    the

    definition

    of

    an

    art

    entails

    ignorance

    on

    the

    part

    of

    the

    artist,

    it

    remains

    possible

    that

    a

    ruler

    might

    be

    unjust

    and

    still be

    a

    ruler

    in

    the strict

    sense.

    If the textual Thrasymachus had seen the error

    in

    Socrates'

    analogy

    of the

    arts,

    he

    could

    have

    turned

    the tables

    on

    him

    by

    pointing

    out

    that

    Socrates

    is not

    dealing

    with

    the

    ruler,

    qua ruler,

    but

    rather

    with

    the

    ruler,

    qua

    just

    man,

    which,

    of

    course,

    is

    precisely

    what Socrates

    is

    doing.

    On

    Thrasymachus'

    view,

    one

    is

    a

    ruler

    in

    the

    strict

    sense

    of this

    term

    if

    he

    always

    makes

    laws

    which

    are

    advantageous

    to

    himself. As

    we

    have

    seen,

    it

    would be

    a

    mark of

    ineptitude

    on

    the

    part

    of

    the

    ruler if these laws

    were

    other than what

    both

    Socrates and

    Thrasymachus

    would

    agree

    were

    just

    laws. If

    a

    ruler

    were

    in this

    sense

    infallible,

    he

    would

    be

    a

    just

    ruler in the

    strict

    sense

    of ruler

    if

    he

    did

    not

    take unfair

    advantage

    of

    the

    opportunities

    for

    exploitation which are afforded him by the law

    abiding

    acts

    of

    his

    subjects;

    he

    would be

    an

    unjust

    ruler

    in

    the strict

    sense

    of ruler if

    he did cheat and

    defraud

    his

    subjects

    in

    their

    just

    dealings

    with

    him.

    *

    *

    *

    A transition

    in

    Socrates'

    line of

    argument

    be?

    comes

    evident

    at

    this

    point.

    Socrates

    obviously

    believes

    that the

    appeal

    to

    the

    analogy

    of

    the

    arts

    has refuted

    Thrasymachus'

    claim that

    justice

    is

    the

    advantage

    of the

    stronger,

    and he

    then

    turns

    to

    the

    question

    whether the

    just

    life

    or

    the

    unjust

    life is

    more

    profitable,

    a

    very

    complex

    problem,

    but

    separate

    and distinct from

    the

    question

    of the

    essential

    nature

    of

    justice,

    and thus

    beyond

    the

    scope

    of the

    present

    inquiry.

    I believe that Plato views

    Thrasymachus'

    account

    of the

    nature

    of

    justice

    as

    plausible

    and

    persuasive,

    and

    as

    one

    which,

    as

    far

    as

    it

    goes,

    is

    accurate.

    Justice

    as

    a

    way

    of

    life is

    a

    social

    pheno?

    menon,

    as

    Socrates and

    Thrasymachus

    implicitly

    agree.

    It

    requires

    the mutual

    interaction

    of

    the

    members

    of

    a

    society

    or a

    social

    group

    for its

    occurrence.

    And

    it

    is

    surely

    true

    that

    just

    action,

    in the absence of any legal guarantees or collateral

    held,

    does

    place

    the

    just

    agent

    in

    a

    position

    to

    be

    unfairly

    exploited.

    And

    it

    further

    strengthens

    Thrasymachus'

    case

    to

    point

    out

    that in

    most

    organized

    societies there

    are

    such

    guarantees.

    For

    this

    is

    an

    admission

    that

    the

    vulnerability

    involved

    in

    acting justly

    has

    to

    be

    compensated

    for

    by

    the

    imposition

    on

    society

    of

    a

    system

    of

    laws,

    police,

    courts,

    and

    prisons

    to

    protect

    the

    just

    from the

    unjust.

    To

    counter

    Thrasymachus'

    insight,

    Socrates

    could

    have

    attempted

    to

    show

    that

    a

    just

    man

    need

    not

    be

    so

    naive

    as

    to

    believe

    that

    all

    the

    people

    with whom he deals will be just. He could have

    examined the

    many

    ways,

    both

    legal

    and

    social,

    by

    which

    in