European Journal 2007 1

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    1/28

    Are innovative, participatory and deliberative procedures in policy

    making democratic and effective?

    YANNIS PAPADOPOULOS1 & PHILIPPE WARIN2

    1University of Lausanne, Switzerland; 2CNRS/CERAT-PACTE, Grenoble, France

    Abstract. The overall project aims to establish a dialogue between normative democratic

    theory and research on policy formulation and implementation.This introductory article first

    notes the growth of various participatory and deliberative procedures in policy making,

    portrays the context of this growth and justifies the cases selected. It then presents the

    conceptual framework used for the study of these procedures, which mainly draws on

    participatory and deliberative democratic theory and the literature on the shift from

    government to governance. Based on this conceptual framework, the article focuses on

    four research questions the authors consider particularly important for the assessment of the

    contribution of the devices under scrutiny to democratic and effective decision making:

    questions of openness and access (input-legitimacy); questions regarding the quality of

    deliberation (throughput); questions of efficiency and effectiveness (output-legitimacy);

    and the issue of their insertion into the public space (questions of transparency and

    accountability).

    The context of the growth of participatory and deliberative procedures

    in policy making

    New participatory tools for policy making have been proliferating recently so

    that today so-called communal activity (Verba et al. 1978) supplements tradi-

    tional modes of democratic participation in several countries.1 Such innovations

    include public inquiries, right-to-know legislation, citizen juries, policy dia-logues, impact assessment with public comment, regulatory negotiation, media-

    tion and other kinds of third-party-facilitated conflict resolution (Dryzek 2000:

    164). Weale (2001: 416417) distinguishes between deliberative opinion polls

    where the participants form a representative sample, and devices involving

    smaller groups like focus groups, consensus conferences or citizens juries.2

    Labels vary in fact: consensus conferences are similar in their design to citizens

    juries (and the same applies to German Planungszellen); policy dialogues in

    Germany are frequently called Risikodialogen because they mainly deal with

    the assessment and treatment of collective risks; mediation procedures are

    called alternative dispute resolution or public conflict resolution, and so on.3

    Most of these innovations can be subsumed under the label of democratic

    experimentalism (Dorf & Sabel 1998) that is a complement to traditional

    European Journal of Political Research 46: 445472, 2007 445

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

    Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden,

    MA 02148, USA

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    2/28

    parliamentary and administrative policy making.4 They can be considered part

    of what has been portrayed as a broader shift fromgovernment togovernance

    that is, from vertical and hierarchical to more horizontal and cooperative

    forms of steering. However, such a shift towards more stakeholder involve-

    ment5 is primarily explained in functional terms by the imperatives of govern-

    ability (output-side of legitimacy according to Scharpf (1970: 2128)), whereas

    the mechanisms under scrutiny here may also aim in some cases at least to

    remedy the deficiencies of representative democracy in terms of input-

    legitimacy (as shown particularly in the article on Spanish citizens juries).

    These innovations are increasingly introduced at different levels of

    government, mainly to cope with political conflicts surrounding development

    projects, siting-decisions, new technology, risk, environmental impacts, and the

    distribution of the associated burdens and benefits (Holzinger 2001: 71). Inscientific and technological policies, for instance, participatory mechanisms are

    considered suitable for different facets of risk-management: risk detection, risk

    control, but also risk dramatisation (Joss & Durant 1995; Joss 1999; Rehmann-

    Sutter et al. 1998; Vig & Paschen 2000). They are part of the public discussion

    of science that is expected to make expertise more responsive to the public

    and the public more enlightened through its participation both contributing

    to the acceptance of policy choices (Weale 2001; Callon et al. 2001). In policies

    entailing geographically concentrated costs, participatory governance schemesare set in the implementation phase (Renn et al. 1995; Papadopoulos 1998:

    276ff; Kuebler 1999; Hunold 2000) to overcome local protest and the nimby

    syndrome (Mazmanian & Morell 1994) against public bads (risk can be one

    of their properties, but so can their cost, their ugliness, their social conse-

    quences, etc.), and to insulate policy choices from irresponsible (e.g., narrowly

    partisan) manipulation.6

    The scope of these innovations has now extended to several policy areas,7

    some of which are covered in this special issue. Although it would not bepossible to claim that the innovations studied here thoroughly mirror the

    immense variety of experiences, we think that they are representative of the

    most significant trends in contemporary advanced democracies. In fact, space

    constraints prevented us from providing a wider sample of available proce-

    dures, but we have selected from among the most widespread. Each article

    refers to a different form of experiment located in a different European

    country (all having consolidated democratic regimes). The chapters of this

    special issue deal with:

    Decisional arrangements implying network forms of collaborative

    governance in various policy fields in Swiss agglomerations (D. Kbler &

    B. Schwab).

    446 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    3/28

    Local participatory devices involving associations and neighbourhood

    councils in the nationally decided French politique de la ville

    (Y. Sintomer & J. de Maillard).

    Individual participatory experiments such as the nationwide deliberative

    opinion poll on the Euro in Denmark (V. N. Andersen & K. Hansen) and

    local citizens juries in Spain (J. Font & I. Blanco).8

    The topicality of these issues should not cause us to forget that debate on

    the role of citizens or social groups in the production of public decisions is

    much older. For instance, claims about participatory urban regeneration, which

    are central today in the debate on transformations of local democracy (Fung

    2004; Booth & Jouve 2005), were central to social movements as early as in the

    1960s (Bacqu et al. 2005). Or to take the example of the environment, ques-tioning of narrow economic thinking has been a constant feature of all Western

    countries from the early 1960s as well. For decades, the crisis of confidence in

    professional knowledge as well as the wish to solve environmental conflicts

    without court action has spawned a number of rather top-down inspired

    methods aimed at involving a wide diversity of actors in policy making from

    the earliest possible stage on the basis of a win-win rationale. Examples in this

    respect include working groups run by political parties in Sweden; public

    hearings, citizen assessment committees or impact statement procedures in theUnited States; boards of inquiry in Canada; and referenda and scientific debate

    on television in Austria. These methods have been far more attentive to

    problem-setting than to puzzle-solving (Shon 1983), and some topical ques-

    tions today have been on the environmental agenda for a long time the

    environment being an area where the definition of priorities and the anticipa-

    tion of future developments have always predominated. It is, moreover, inter-

    esting that these approaches were often developed in contexts that were

    hardly conducive to ideas of cooperation, solidarity or mutual aid.9

    Theirsuccess derives primarily from the fact that the search for optimisation of

    investments progressively led to a search for policy-making tools that contri-

    bute to consensus and hence to the reduction of the conflict potential of

    projects. Note in this respect that in the current debate on deliberative democ-

    racy, key questions are: What is optimal deliberation?, and consequently:

    What sorts of deliberation are best? as regards the possibility of reducing

    conflict (Shapiro 2002).

    These procedures are also related to a more general context in which

    we witness concern to involve consumers or clients more fully in the

    implementation or even definition of public services (Gilliat et al. 2000). The

    development of new public management is often called upon to explain

    the generalisation of these mechanisms to all Organisation for Economic

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 447

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    4/28

    Cooperation and Development (OECD) countries. The co-production of

    public policies attests to the quest for more effective political choices through

    the establishment of participatory mechanisms. This theme, born in the United

    States in the late 1970s in various approaches relative to the upsurge of the

    service economy and service society (Fuchs 1968; Gartner & Riessman 1974),

    was taken up and developed in the theory of public choices (Whitaker 1980).

    It is currently present in debate on administrative reorganisation and the

    measurement of public performance, with a focus on the key question of

    transformation of the role of the state (in very different research perspectives,

    e.g., Kooiman 1996; Gaster & Rutqvist 2000). In Europe, and particularly

    Germany, the co-production model has enjoyed success both in theory and

    practice because debate on social policies and public services has drawn atten-

    tion to citizens role in the production of the public welfare (Wirth 1986). Thetheme of co-production of public policies has been addressed extensively by

    administrative officials not only to find ways of improving the quality of

    services, but also to implement budgetary restrictions. Other applications of

    this model have concerned the restructuring of urban services, especially in the

    United States and the United Kingdom (Savas 2002). National contexts also

    have to be taken into account, and the new mechanisms created seem to be

    strongly influenced by the pre-existing institutional contexts and political tra-

    ditions.10 Precisely the polysemy of the notion of participation allows a con-vergence between quite different challenges to the bureaucratic state, such as

    the neo-liberal and the new-left critique (Ansell & Gingrich 2003; Bacqu

    et al. 2005).

    Participatory devices are not only innovative to various degrees and embed-

    ded in different contexts, they are also characterised by dissimilarities. Their

    decisions when any are taken can be binding or merely consultative, and they

    can emerge at different territorial levels or different stages of the policy cycle.

    Their emergence is, however, dictated to a large extent by a common rationale.As argued by McLaverty (1999: 23), the promoters aims for such initiatives are

    more instrumental than expressive in that they mainly wish to maximise com-

    munity support for policies and improve the quality of decisions. And as the

    editors of a volume on participatory policy making maintain:

    [P]articipatory governance is definitely less a matter of democracy in the

    sense of institutionalizing a set of procedures for electing those in charge

    of the policy-making, than it is a kind of second best solution for

    approaching the question of effective participation of the persons likely

    to be affected by the policies designed. . . . [P]articipation can be effective

    in the realisation of policy objectives because it can help to overcome

    problems of implementation by considering motives and by fostering the

    448 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    5/28

    willingness of policy addressees to comply as well as through the mobili-

    sation of the knowledge of those affected. (Gbikpi & Grote 2002: 23)

    The main assumption is that norms are legitimate only if they are based on

    public reason-giving resulting from a process of inclusive and equitable delib-

    eration, in which citizens can participate and in which they are prompted to

    cooperate freely (Bohman 1996). This assumption is present in the practical

    approaches developed in the United States and Europe to manage (or antici-

    pate and avoid) environmental conflicts. It has been recycled in the procedures

    implemented today in other areas, as shown by studies on public participation

    based on the analysis of actor networks.11

    In F. Scharpfs terms, participatory procedures are supposed to enhance

    the output legitimacy of policy making by achieving decisions that are moreefficient, owing to the involvement of actors with much local or sectoral

    knowledge.12 At the same time, their decisions are more likely to be effective,

    owing to the involvement of strongly concerned stakeholders. Duran (1999),

    for instance, notes that the more general shift that took place in France

    during the last two decades of the twentieth century from a tutelary state to

    partnership relations derived mostly from the obligation to obtain consent

    for policies from the relevant target groups. Likewise, in the European

    Union (EU), fostering participatory democracy was interpreted as a sign ofthe instrumental value attributed to nongovernmental organisations (NGOs)

    by the Commission: [T]hey are held in high esteem because it is assumed

    that they contribute to the formation of European public opinion, they

    provide feedback so the Commission can adjust its policy, they contribute to

    managing, monitoring and evaluating EU projects, and their involvement

    helps to win acceptance (Kohler-Koch 2000: 525). Majones argument on the

    reasons for the proliferation in Europe after the United States of non-

    majoritarian institutions such as independent administrative agencies andregulatory bodies also applies to participatory procedures: In a world where

    national borders are increasingly porous, the possibility of achieving policy

    objectives by coercive means is severely limited; credibility, rather than the

    legitimate use of coercion is now the most valuable resource of policy

    makers (Majone 2000: 561). Regarding their functions, these mechanisms

    are also expected to contribute to de-fundamentalising the positions of con-

    flicting parties (Holzinger 2001: 72). To sum up, the procedures under scru-

    tiny can be considered as being targeted to counteract (although not

    necessarily in a similar way) some of the pressures that reduce the ability to

    practise political steering effectively.

    As we shall see below, whether or not participatory procedures do indeed

    fulfil these functions, and are not, for instance, viewed by policy makers

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 449

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    6/28

    primarily as public relations exercises designed to legitimise decisions actu-

    ally taken in other arenas, needs to be checked. However, because of their

    participatory orientation, such innovations are also considered by political

    theorists as democratic (Bohman & Rehg 1999; Dryzek 2000: 164), or as

    forms of empowered deliberative democracy (Fung & Wright 2001).13

    Hence, it is also expected that the direct involvement of people (or their

    representatives) that are usually only policy takers will strengthen the input

    legitimacy of democratic policy making, and at the same time inject more

    throughput legitimacy by generating widespread beliefs about procedural

    fairness. For that reason, each contribution in this special issue devotes par-

    ticular attention to an assessment of the democratic content of the partici-

    patory instruments.

    The conceptual framework

    The literature often tends to be somewhat idealistic as regards deliberation,

    public consultation and democracy. It has only been in the past ten years, for

    example, that normative theories of justice and positive theories of democracy

    have started to move closer together (Saward 2003).14 Two normative schools of

    thought have influenced the positive assessment of participatory mechanisms,probably motivated by a concern to identify experiments that would embody

    their prescriptions: theories of participatory and of deliberative democracy.

    Any normative theory of democracy privileges some specific conditions for

    policy-making processes to be judged democratically legitimate. Participatory

    and deliberative theories share a common target of improving legitimacy by

    improving the quality of public life albeit by slightly different means.15

    Participationists16 primarily believe not only that participation is highly valued

    by the public, but also that public virtue is likely to arise from citizens sustainedand direct involvement in public affairs (irrespective of its forms, conventional

    or not, etc.).Deliberationists17 focus more on the virtues of discussion leading

    to choices that thus become more quiet, reflective, open to a wide range of

    evidence, respectful of different views (Walzer 1999: 58). Other-regardingness,

    associated with reflection, is considered a necessary ingredient of decision

    making in plural societies.18 With few exceptions (see below) advocates of

    deliberative democracy pay less attention to practical obstacles to inclusion,

    problems of representation, and so on, in spite of their own undeniably strong

    normative commitment to equality.They are more attentive to thethroughput

    dimension of policy making, while participationists favour questions of open

    access and care less about the refinement of preferences likely to occur among

    participants through the deliberation process.

    450 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    7/28

    It is therefore possible that these theories have competing objectives.

    There is, for instance, a trade-off between democracy and deliberation

    since the latter would only be possible in small circles (Fishkin 1991).19

    As a result, participation and deliberation are not necessarily co-terminous:

    deliberation might be inescapably elitist, while strong democracy at the mass

    level would hardly be favourable to sustained deliberation.20 Fishkin, for

    example, is a deliberationist who strongly disagrees with the increasingly

    populist-majoritarian design of American political institutions. Like him

    and unlike most participationists who do not break with an aggregative

    though enlarged conception of democracy,21 few deliberationists would,

    for instance, consider with much sympathy a mere extension of direct

    democracy provisions without any safeguards to ensure the quality of

    opinion formation, avoid the risk of majority tyranny, and so on.22 In areappraisal of their theory, for instance, two major deliberative theorists

    (Gutmann & Thompson 2004: 7, 3031, 60) stress the need for public justi-

    fication and reason-giving in decision making, and think at the same time

    that the quality of deliberation may be better in representative, rather than

    direct, democracy.

    Nevertheless, participationist and deliberationist theories should not be

    seen as strongly opposed: there are no controversies between advocates of

    participatory and deliberative democracy similar to the theoretical clashesbetween participationists and elitists, or between deliberationists and advo-

    cates of aggregative versions of democratic theory, with the former stressing

    the need for reason-giving in decision making as opposed to sheer reliance

    on voting procedures that are considered in the aggregative model as a suf-

    ficient basis for decisional legitimacy. The participatory and the deliberative

    school converge on the belief that existing democratic institutions should be

    improved and supplemented by novel institutions (which should not merely

    replace the existing ones: see Fishkin (1996); Smith (2000: 30); Saward(2003a)). However, participationists criticise principal-agent problems in

    representative democracy, while deliberationists criticise the limited place of

    public discussion in voting mechanisms. Deliberative theory claims to be a

    more just and indeed democratic way of dealing with pluralism than aggre-

    gative or realist models of democracy. . . . Talk-centred democratic theory

    replaces voting-centric democratic theory. Voting-centric views see democ-

    racy as the arena in which fixed preferences and interests compete via fair

    mechanisms of aggregation. In contrast, deliberative democracy focuses on

    the communicative processes of opinion and will-formation that precede

    voting (Chambers 2003: 308), or a deliberative approach focuses on quali-

    tative aspects of the conversation that precedes decisions rather than on a

    mathematical decision rule (Chambers 2003: 316).23

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 451

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    8/28

    Virtually no participationist thinker would dispute that associating more

    ordinary people with political deliberations is necessary for their empower-

    ment and for the governability of the political system.24 However, not all new

    tools for policy making rely on the inclusion of lay people; depending on the

    mechanism, even grassroots movements or local residents can be represented

    by delegates.This can cause principal-agent problems between spokespersons

    and their constituencies, with negative effects on both the input and the

    output legitimacy of policy choices. Are the latter determined from below

    (input)? If not, are they at least responsive to the wishes of the constituencies

    (output)?

    This is a problem increasingly addressed by another body of literature:

    works on network governance. As noted above, these works emphasise the

    proliferation of numerous cooperative schemes involving civil society actorsin policy making at local, national and now EU, transnational or multi

    (i.e., involving actors of different territorial units) levels as opposed to classic

    top-down steering by a government endowed with uncontested central author-

    ity. Governance schemes take the form of partnerships, contracts, roundtables,

    intergovernmental conferences, committees of various sorts and the like. Pref-

    erence for this form of contextual steering (Kontextsteuerung; see Willke

    1992) primarily results from the necessity to counteract the centrifugal dynam-

    ics of interest fragmentation, along with recognition of the fact that the statelacks the necessary resources to carry out this task on its own. Like other

    participatory devices, governance networks aim to enhance state resources in

    terms of knowledge (learning about complex and uncertain causal relations),

    organisation (ensuring adequate expertise and capacity to implement policy

    choices) and authority (avoiding blackmailing by veto groups and inducing

    compliance by policy takers) in policy making. It is expected that well-

    designed and well-organised participation of stakeholders in the policy process

    will favour a win-win logic because policies will be increasingly perceived asthe outcome of a co-production including their addressees. As a result, gov-

    ernance networks not only include public actors (government officials and

    state administrators) who can represent different territorial levels, but also

    experts and representatives of interest groups (business groups, life-

    style communities, etc., depending on the policy area). Finally, governance by

    networks presupposes an accommodative orientation among participants, who

    are expected to demonstrate an inclination for compromise-seeking instead of

    engaging in conflictual relations, and possibly a shared willingness to learn

    from one another that may induce participants to behave in a deliberative

    manner.

    The literature on governance arrangements has gradually shifted from a

    focus primarily on managerial considerations (are these arrangements func-

    452 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    9/28

    tional for steering?) to a deeper concern with issues of democracy, partici-

    pation and representation and to more scepticism as to the actual

    achievement of these goals.25 Horizontality in fact means cooperation

    between actors that count, or to add yet another step in terms of selec-

    tivity cooperation between the leaderships of collective organised actors.

    As such, it is not tantamount to the inclusion of ordinary citizens and there-

    fore not necessarily conducive to genuine democratisation. As Andersen and

    Burns (1996: 229) argue with regard to what they call post-parliamentary

    governance:

    In these specialised policy settings, the democracy of individual citizens

    tends to be replaced by a de facto democracy of organised interests,

    lobbies and representatives of organisations (and movements) thatengage themselves in policy areas and issues that are of particular

    concern. In other words, the system of post-parliamentary governance

    tends increasingly to be one of organisations, by organisations and for

    organisations. Expert sovereignty tends to prevail over popular sovereignty

    or parliamentary sovereignty. (emphasis in original)26

    To sum up, we pursue two major goals in this special issue. First, we wish to

    contribute towards establishing dialogue between the more normative litera-ture on participation, deliberation, new forms of democracy, and so on, and the

    analytical literature on policy formulation and implementation (steering,

    governance, networks, partnerships, etc.). And second, we test the conclu-

    sions of these bodies of theory on concrete experiments, and particularly

    regarding their contribution to democratic and effective decision making, as

    highlighted by their openness and access (input-legitimacy), the quality of

    their deliberative activity (throughput), their impact (output) and ulti-

    mately their insertion in the public space (issues of transparency and account-ability).We thus hope, through case studies nourished by theoretical reflection,

    to contribute to cumulative knowledge by providing additional tests not only

    of theories of deliberative and participatory democracy, but also of theories of

    the policy process that emphasise the virtues of concerted policy making for

    governability.

    The case studies of participatory mechanisms presented here examine

    the extent to which such procedures keep their promises with respect to

    the above-mentioned forms of legitimacy, and whether they face some

    limitations. In particular, we asked the authors dealing with individual

    experiments to address a common set of questions on the basis of criteria

    drawn mainly from the literature on participatory policy making and policy

    deliberation. These case studies provide several interesting responses to

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 453

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    10/28

    these questions, even though, due to limitations in the available em-

    pirical evidence, not all questions are always extensively covered in all

    articles.

    Referring in her account of deliberative democratic theory to Gutmann

    and Thompsons work, Chambers (2003: 316) writes:

    In designing and proposing deliberative forums, scholars generally have

    four goals in mind: to augment legitimacy through accountability and

    participation; to encourage a public-spirited perspective on policy issues

    through cooperation; to promote mutual respect between parties through

    inclusion and civility; and to enhance the quality of decisions (and opin-

    ions) through informed and substantive debate.27

    Clearly, these goals can be formulated in a different ordering or can even

    conflict with each other: if legitimacy cannot be acquired through participa-

    tion, then accountability of delegated authorities can be a substitute; mutual

    respect, public-spiritness and cooperation seem to be interrelated (even

    though cooperation can also be achieved by egoistic actors for strategic

    reasons); inclusion does not necessarily lead to civility; good quality debate

    has no necessary impact on decisions, and so on. To assess more specifically

    citizens juries, Smith and Wales (2000) use the criteria of inclusiveness, thequality of deliberation and empowered citizenship. While the first criterion

    refers to inputs and the second to throughput (procedures and substance of

    deliberation), it is hard to operationalise the third (a kind of long-term

    outcome?). Hunold (2000) also uses inclusiveness, and adds equality and

    publicity. We propose to include considerations of the impact of participatory

    procedures on decision making (output) as well, as this is important for the

    assessment of their political relevance.28 Normative political theory claims

    that deliberative forms of stakeholder participation in policy making aremore adequate in dealing with these four basic aspects than pure aggregative

    models of decision that tend to underplay normative and practical problems

    resulting from power inequalities (the fictitious character of the one man,

    one vote adage), elite autonomy, a narrowly utilitarian view of actors pref-

    erences considered to be given and fixed, and so on. Participatory theories

    emphasise inclusiveness as a condition for policy effectiveness and legiti-

    macy, deliberative theories stress the importance of public discussion for the

    same purpose, and both theories are sensitive to issues of transparency and

    accountability. Therefore four types of questions are central to this thematic

    issue: questions of openness and access; questions of the quality of delibera-

    tion; questions of efficiency and effectiveness; and questions of publicity,

    transparency and accountability.

    454 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    11/28

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    12/28

    who have to concert with each other and at the same time consider the

    preferences of their constituencies.

    Quality of deliberation

    Classic theory of representation (Burke, Madison) viewed deliberation as a

    necessary step in the formation of individuals preferences. Contemporary

    political theory also attaches a number of improvements to the deliberative

    process. Deliberation is expected to contribute to competent policy making

    through reflection and, as far as possible, to consensual decisions. It should

    help to improve understanding of problems and of alternative solutions, and

    thus to reduce bounded rationality. It should also help people to become aware

    of possible contradictions between the objectives they would like to achieve,and thus to clarify the reasons for their preferences and to rank them better

    (Fearon 1998: 4952; Manin 1985: 8284).

    The belief that actors have learning capacities and, moreover, are willing to

    engage in learning processes is central for proponents of deliberative deci-

    sional formulas that are considered to play an educative role. Hence, not only

    is deliberation expected to clarify peoples preferences; it is also expected to

    help them to acquire information on others preferences and to take account

    of others needs and interests (Benhabib 1996: 7172; Cohen & Rogers 1995:256; Hunold & Young 1998: 87).34 Deliberation should also enhance mutual

    respect and recognition because participants are forced to think of what

    would count as a good reason for all others involved in, or affected by, the

    decisions under discussion (Cooke 2000: 950). Exchange of arguments and

    discussion on them thus aim at producing shared collective meaning;35 they are

    conducive to mutual understanding, if not to full consensus (Warren 2002:

    184185).36 Deliberation is also deemed favourable to the acquisition of a

    stronger sense of community, which is all the more important considering thatmodern fragmented societies experience centrifugal forces likely to under-

    mine solidarity and cohesion. Deliberation and participation are therefore

    believed to spawn virtuous citizens an idea on which all theses in favour of

    these mechanisms are based, and that international institutions seeking good

    governance tools honour (EU, IMF, WB, OECD, etc.). In this way, citizens

    participating in deliberative procedures can be asked to do what voters can

    supposedly no longer be expected to do that is, be encouraged to learn

    enough to be able to vote for their interests intelligently (Hardin 2002: 212).

    Of course it is not at all sure that the deliberative ideal will prevail. Moreover,

    even though strategically minded actors can also learn through deliberation to

    behave more argumentatively, after having deliberated at length without

    reaching a consensus, actors might prefer for reasons of time and energy saving

    456 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    13/28

    (reduction of transaction costs) to agree on mutual compromises (Benz 1994:

    112168).Although such compromises should not be viewed as less noble than

    consensus achieved through deliberation (Mansbridge 2003), they clearly

    reflect the balance of forces, not the weight of arguments (Walzer 1999: 62).

    Strategic bargaining as opposed to persuasion or to argumentative problem

    solving (Scharpf 1991) is therefore also of relevance here.37 Oebergs (2002)

    work on Swedish administrative corporatism lends some support to the thesis

    that governance networks operate along deliberative rather than bargaining

    principles, while Holzinger (2001a), using discourse analysis techniques, tests

    whether mediation procedures operate along deliberative lines or whether

    bargaining prevails. Benz (1994) invites us to consider the sequence of the

    policy process as an explanatory variable. Elgstroem and Joensson (2000: 701)

    were able to test some other hypotheses on the conditions favouring delibera-tive problem solving within the comitology procedures in the EU.They express

    reservations on the alleged role of deliberation: the level of politicisation of

    decisions has to be low, deliberation mostly takes place at the preparatory and

    implementation (as opposed to the decisional) phases of the policy cycle, and

    redistributive or constituent issues are not suitable for it.38 Whether actors in

    participatory mechanisms behave according to deliberative principles is thus

    an empirical question.

    Efficiency and effectiveness

    One of the alleged properties of the procedures under scrutiny is that they will

    improve the quality of outputs in several respects, although not to the same

    extent. Governance networks, for instance, often make de facto binding deci-

    sions, which is not true for deliberative polls mainly because, unlike elected

    representatives accountable to their constituencies, their participants lack

    authorisation (Parkinson 2003: 192193).In conditions of uncertainty and complexity, stakeholders involvement

    increases the chances of policy acceptance. Furthermore, stakeholders contrib-

    ute their local or sectoral knowledge, which can be of help in preventing causal

    errors in policy choices that, in turn, are likely to impede goal achievement,

    generate perverse effects and so on. This is an important component of the

    contribution of participatory tools to policy efficiency, but not the only one. In

    fragmented societies, ordinary majoritarian procedures can result in choices

    made by ill-informed majorities, causing prejudice to minorities whose intense

    preferences are thus violated (Guggenberger 1984;Scharpf 1999) for instance,

    socially stigmatised groups (Waelti et al. 2004). Moreover, as suggested by

    the literature on neo-corporatism considered as a governability device, elec-

    toral competition can engender over-promising and short-term calculations

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 457

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    14/28

    (Lehmbruch 1977). By contrast, consultation between the relevant interests

    (Kontextsteuerung) is expected to lead to more responsible and sustainable

    (i.e., more fact-, other-, and future-regarding (Offe & Preuss 1991)) decisions

    or proposals for decisions.39 This assumption should, however, also be scruti-

    nised.The literature on distributive coalitions and rent-seeking (Olson 1982)

    mostly driven by a Madisonian view of the role of organised interests

    (suspicious of factionalism) rather than by a Tocquevillian view that would

    instead emphasise the positive role of the intermediate system for citizens

    empowerment and control over the government40 teaches us that rational

    participants in decisional circles will be tempted by their particularistic capture

    that is, they will seek to maximise benefits of policy choices and externalise

    costs to actors excluded from them (Benz 1998: 206; Pierre & Peters 2000: 20).

    It is therefore necessary to clarify whether the bodies under considerationreally enhance the overall support for policy outputs by the population, or

    whether acceptance is limited to participants. This again raises the problem of

    the consequences (this time on the output side) of limited participation. Do the

    specific forms of participation under scrutiny actually contribute to broader

    policy acceptance and, as a result, to more effective policy making (as argued

    in general by works on implementation and on responsive evaluation)? As

    noted above, another property of these tools is their alleged contribution to

    conflict resolution, be it through deliberation (conducive to consensus) orthrough bargaining (conducive to compromises). This is debatable too: among

    the major theorists of deliberative democracy, Gutmann and Thompson (1996)

    think that (consensual) discursive agreement is hard to reach on moral issues.

    In fact, if discussion can effectively reveal private information about peoples

    preferences on policy outcomes, then there is no reason why in particular cases

    it might not reveal that the extent of conflict is greater than previously

    believed (Fearon 1998: 57; see also Ferejohn 2000: 85).

    Empirical evidence on these issues can hardly be considered conclusive.The alternative dispute resolution literature, for example, concentrates for

    the most part on what happens inside participatory procedures, while external

    factors likely to influence consensus or conflict (such as alternatives available

    to participants, restrictions on solutions set by their constituencies, political

    directives, etc.) are not given systematic attention. Holzinger (2001: 93),

    however, maintains that no negotiation or discursive procedure, regardless of

    how well it otherwise progresses, can overcome exogenous restrictions and

    better outside options. Such restrictions not only have an impact upon access

    to, and influence within, participatory forums, they also condition the actors

    behaviour in them and, consequently, their collective outputs and the extent of

    the overall support for those outputs. Even if internal cohesion in these forums

    is achieved, its effects will have to be qualified if some relevant, albeit more

    458 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    15/28

    weakly organised interests, are excluded. We should consider in that respect

    that consensus is not valued among all deliberationists because it can be

    criticised as the outcome of strategic action and symbolic manipulation (Smith

    & Wales 2000: 63 n.; Young 2000: 4344). It can be perceived as an impediment

    to critical dialogue by powerful interests that dominate the agenda and wish to

    veil the interests of the weaker (Sanders 1997; Mansbridge 2003: 183).

    The actual impact of these procedures on policy choices must also be

    assessed because they can result from motivations typical of symbolic politics

    leading to participatory window-dressing (Fung & Wright 2003a: 265).

    Blondiaux (2005: 126), for instance, criticises the fetichism of rhetorics of

    proximity in official political discourses. Participatory and deliberative pro-

    cedures are useful tools for public relations exercises, where good gover-

    nance and deliberative democracy become catchwords manipulated bypolitical elites (Blondiaux & Sintomer 2002). Their implementation allows

    rulers to show that they are willing not only to deal with crucial issues, but also

    to associate the profane in decision making. As argued recently by Bernard

    Manin (2002: 41), whose pioneering article on normative political theory

    (Manin 1985, 1987) became one of the major points of reference for the

    deliberationist school: It seems that deliberative democracy became an ide-

    ology whose presence is noticed as a social phenomenon in several sectors, and

    in particular in the implementation of public policies (our translation fromFrench).41 Whether practice corresponds to discourse depends on the more or

    less reflexive devices used for conflict management, and must again be

    empirically established. According to a path dependence hypothesis, involve-

    ment of non-public actors in polities with a strong state is very likely to be

    mere window-dressing instrumentalised by politicians (for an example from

    French local economic development policies, see Taiclet 2006). In such cases,

    one can hardly consider these procedures as effective in terms of actual policy

    implementation. Similarly, path dependence theory also suggests that policychoices that are objects of deliberation in participatory forums are locked in

    chains of past choices and therefore not easily reversible (Barthe 2002).

    Finally, one could argue that after all it does not make much sense to assess

    the impact on the decisional system of procedures that were not designed for

    that purpose, such as most citizens juries and above all deliberative polls

    although Saward (2003a) makes some interesting proposals for integrating

    them into specific phases of decision making. Rather, their effectiveness could

    be assessed by checking the extent to which they achieve their own proclaimed

    aims, such as the improvement of the political skills of their participants or

    even of the citizenry at large. As suggested by participatory theory, participa-

    tion in such mechanisms is expected to create a virtuous feedback in the future,

    and is therefore deemed to produce its effects in the long run.

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 459

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    16/28

    Publicity and accountability

    Institutionalisation of participatory procedures is another dimension to be

    considered, and one that may be independent from their effectiveness: proce-

    dures can be institutionalised, but merely play a symbolic role; and they can be

    effective, but weakly institutionalised. Are procedures formalised or ad hoc?

    This is an important question that is often overlooked by the relevant litera-

    ture (e.g., works on governance by networks focus more on the latters rela-

    tional properties than on the processes of their institutionalisation in codified

    procedures: committees, etc.). In fact, procedural visibility which is strongly

    correlated with institutionalisation is a key condition for accountability.42 The

    extent to which accountability channels are associated with these procedures

    must also be discussed especially if these mechanisms have an influence onlegally binding decisions. It cannot be asserted as a principle that, because the

    procedures under scrutiny are participatory or imply consultation of wider

    interests, they satisfy criteria of accountability as well. Governance arrange-

    ments, for instance, are oriented towards cooperative decision making; yet at

    the same time effective cooperation can more easily take place in oligarchic,

    non-transparent and selective political structures (Benz 1998: 212).

    The issue of the (more or less loose or tight) coupling of new policy-making

    tools with the well-institutionalised processes of representative democracy(perhaps also in a country like Switzerland with direct democracy) also has to

    be examined (Van Eeten 2001: 424). These procedures may, for example,

    contribute to governability (policy implementation, conflict resolution, etc.),

    although that could be problematic if they become substitutes for legitimate

    democratic procedures (and problematic not only in normative terms, because

    the procedures will in all likelihood be challenged by those dissatisfied with

    their outcomes). This is not so much the case for deliberative opinion polls or

    citizens juries that are usually limited to a consultative role, but can be true fornetwork forms of governance. Although actors in these networks are not

    authorised as a rule to make firm decisions, they can acquire such a crucial

    influence on policy choices that formally authorised bodies like parliaments

    will not really be able to challenge their options.Thus if these procedures tend

    to replace in practice the influence of the demos exerted through its elected

    representatives by group influence tied to sectoral or local expertise, this is

    likely to engender legitimacy problems.A crucial problem is that of the uneasy

    coupling of decisional arenas that operate under different principles of legiti-

    mation:43 deliberation and negotiation between (sometimes collective) stake-

    holders in participatory procedures versus competition for authorisation in the

    representative circuit. These neglected problems have received more interest

    recently in the literature on network governance (Benz 1998, 2000; Pierre

    460 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    17/28

    2000; Pierre & Peters 2000; Rhodes 1997), although without much empirical

    research so far.They are of particular relevance if we do not take it for granted

    (see above) that deliberation and negotiation between stakeholders neces-

    sarily yield outputs that are beneficial to the public interest. If this is uncertain,

    then participatory procedures must be all the more subject to ex ante autho-

    risation and act under the shadow of ex post control.

    Acknowledgements

    The title of this special issue alludes to Fritz W. Scharpfs (1999) book on

    European governance with democracy preceding effectiveness, however.

    For his or her insightful critical comments and very useful suggestions forimprovement, we are indebted to an anonymous reviewer of EJPR.

    Notes

    1. Communal activity combines two types of activity: individual contacts by citizens with

    government officials where the subject of that contact is some general social issue, and

    cooperative, non-partisan activities involving group or organizational attempts to deal

    with some social issue. Such activity is outside of the regular electoral process. It conveysa great deal of information to leaders. The amount of pressure depends on the influence

    of the participating individual or group (Verba et al. 1978: 54).

    2. For a synthesis of the consequences of minipublics (participatory devices implicating

    rather a small number of individuals) on participation, information, civic education,

    efficiency and justice in policy, consequences that depend on the forms of their design,

    see Fung (2003).

    3. Participatory governance networks at the local level are added here (see below), as

    could experiments made possible by the Net, such as electronic voting that raises specific

    problems (e.g., the digital divide: Norris (2000), or privatisation of the vote: Barber

    (1995)) but that alone would require a special issue.4. For Dorf and Sabel (1998), democratic experimentalism implies a sophisticated frame-

    work where local deliberative units transfer their experiences to a governance council

    in charge of coordination a property that is often missing in the local experiences. Its

    major task is to enhance learning across deliberative units through formulation of best

    practice standards. Parliaments are expected to facilitate experimentalism through del-

    egation and bureaucracies can act as further learning instances.

    5. In so-called multilevel governance, along with governmental and administrative units

    of different territorial levels, all sorts of NGOs, groups and even private firms are

    associated to the formulation or the implementation of collectively binding decisions.

    The literature on governance has rapidly grown: among the major recent books, seeKjaer (2004), Kooiman (2003), Pierre (2000), Pierre & Peters (2000).

    6. Kuebler (1999) convincingly holds that discursive devices were established in the imple-

    mentation of Swiss drug policy to curb the risk of the nimby syndrome being exploited

    by anti-establishment parties who found fertile soil for their claims in local opposition.

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 461

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    18/28

    7. See Goss (1999), Lowndes et al. (2001), OECD (2001) and Smith (2005), where a variety

    of experiments in different countries are presented.

    8. The articles on Switzerland, Denmark and Spain are thoroughly revised versions of

    papers presented by their authors to an ECPR workshop directed by the special issue

    editors on Governance and Democratic Legitimacy (Grenoble joint sessions, 611April 2001). The co-authored article on France was commissioned by the editors to two

    French specialists who presented distinct papers at the ECPR workshop.

    9. E.g., it was during the Reagan period that the collaborative approach was developed in

    the United States, inspired by ideas of Kropotkine, the early twentieth-century anarchist

    geographer. With this approach, an alternative to court action (increasingly frequent,

    costly and slow) is presented for environmental conflicts. Above all, this approach allows

    consensus on the way of addressing environmental problems on which the federal

    government has no specific policy, while public opinion is more and more mobilised on

    these issues. For examples of collaborative dialogues in policy making in California, see

    Innes & Booher (2003).10. Concerning, e.g., the influence of direct democracy and of traditions of power-sharing in

    Switzerland, see Linder (1994: 8596).

    11. For the French case, which is an element of a more global approach, see Warin & La

    Branche (2005).

    12. Fischer (2000) is an example of work that emphasises the positive contribution of lay

    knowledge to policy making.

    13. Referring to five reforms that they present, Fung and Wright (2001: 7) argue: Although

    these five reforms differ dramatically in the details of their design, issue areas and scope,

    they all aspire to deepen the ways in which ordinary people can effectively participate in

    and influence policies that directly affect their lives. Apart from this special issue of

    Politics & Society (29(1), March 2001) edited by A. Fung and E.O. Wright (and subse-

    quently expanded into a book with additional commentaries: Fung & Wright 2003) with

    the normative aim to establish Real Utopias (such concerns are not central to our

    undertaking and we are instead more concerned with possible problems and limits of

    innovative experiments), case study monographs on procedures similar to those studied

    in this issue are still scant. Some can be found in Khan (1999); McLaverty (2002); Bacqu

    et al. (2005); Gastil & Levine (2005). For a more critical approach, see the special issue

    ofPolitix on Limpratif dlibratif (Blondiaux & Sintomer 2002). The discussion has

    now spread over to the transnational level as attested by the special issue of Governance(January 2003) edited by M. Verweis and T.E. Josling and entitled Deliberately Democ-

    ratizing Multilateral Organization.

    14. See, e.g., the special issue of the Journal of Political Philosophy, 10(2), June 2002, which

    launched the series Philosophy, Politics and Society.

    15. Clearly these are not the only schools of thought in political science preoccupied with

    the impact of participation on the quality of democracy. One simply needs to think of the

    prescriptions drawn (including by governance bodies like the World Bank) from

    research on social capital (Putnam 1993, 2000), or the normative concerns of commu-

    nitarian political thinkers (Etzioni 1993, 1995).

    16. Classic works of contemporary theory are Pateman (1970) and Barber (1984), butseveral others point in the same direction, including Bachrach & Botwinick (1992) and

    Berry (1989). Budge (1996) is a participatory approach of direct democracy, and De

    Leon (1997) of policy making. Some variants emphasise the role of organised societal

    actors like theories of associative democracy (Hirst 1994; Cohen & Rogers 1995), and

    462 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    19/28

    others the diffusion of democratic institutions and practices in new fields (economy,

    education, etc.): see Gould (1988); Graham (1986).

    17. It is again impossible to quote the abundant literature, which is frequently inspired by

    Jrgen Habermass (1984, 1993) arguments on communicative action, and whose con-

    clusions and prescriptions are not always concordant. To mention but a few: Chambers(1996); Dryzek (2000); Gutmann & Thompson (1996, 2004), and numerous contributions

    in edited volumes: Benhabib (1996); Bohman & Rehg (1999); Elster (1998); Macedo

    (1999).

    18. This is the reciprocity condition of deliberation as stated by Gutmann and Thompson

    (1996) that requires reasonableness from actors (Young 2000). In the flourishing lit-

    erature on deliberation, not all authors agree on its properties, and in practice there

    might be incompatibilities between some of its ideal dimensions (e.g., publicity that is

    advocated by authors concerned with transparency can generate demagogy and thus be

    inimical to argumentative rationality).

    19. Unfortunately, examples do not abound in the literature on deliberative democracy andthe few empirical pieces are often so strongly driven by normative concerns that one

    should be sceptical about their optimistic conclusions. On the lack of concretisation of

    theories of deliberative democracy, see Abromeit (2002). For a few exceptions, see Eder

    et al. (1997); Elgstroem & Joensson (2000); Fischer (2000); Holzinger (2001a); Hunold &

    Young (1998); Joerges & Neyer (1997); Oeberg (2002).

    20. Ackerman and Fishkins (2002) proposal for a deliberation day that would reconcile

    deliberation with mass participation is considered by the authors themselves as utopian.

    21. Participationists usually favour more voting procedures, either by introducing referenda

    on political issues or by introducing elections of representatives in traditionally non-

    political spheres (in private companies, the education system, etc.).

    22. See, e.g., Marx Ferree et al. (2002) for a comparison of conceptions of the public space

    in theories of participatory and deliberative democracy.

    23. It has however been asserted that the incompatibility between the aggregative and the

    deliberative approach to democracy has been exaggerated (see Saward 2003a: Note 10).

    E.g., although Chambers (2003: 308) also argues that through the central role conferred

    to justification in deliberative theory, accountability replaces consent as the conceptual

    core of legitimacy; accountability is crucial for aggregative theories, too, through the

    central role conferred to the anticipation by decision makers of the retrospective vote of

    their constituencies, that forces them to behave in a responsive way. And consent isexpected to occur in deliberative theories, too, as the result of mutual learning and

    persuasion. The co-existence of accountability and consent as sources of legitimacy

    appears in consent being expressed in electoral support (input-legitimacy) and in

    support being in turn generated by convincing public justifications of incumbents about

    their action (output-legitimacy).

    24. These can be viewed, respectively, as bottom-up and top-down perspectives on par-

    ticipation (Papadopoulos 1995).

    25. Interestingly, R. Mayntz, together with F. Scharpf one of the leading figures of the school

    of Akteur-zentrierter Institutionalismus, which is authoritative in Germany in the field

    of research on Steuerung, provided a short intellectual history of studies of governance(Mayntz 1997) where she showed that they were strongly practice-oriented initially and

    aimed above all at preventing policy failures in top-down planning processes. One of the

    editors of this special issue addressed elsewhere the democratic question raised by

    cooperative forms of policy making (Papadopoulos 2003; Benz & Papadopoulos 2006).

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 463

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    20/28

    26. Furthermore, it should be noted (although this is not the object of this special issue) that

    similar concerns regarding the democratic quality of policy-making procedures are

    raised about expert regulatory bodies that are becoming increasingly important in

    Europe, too (Majone 1996), such as central banks, administrative agencies, commissions

    and boards operating outside the oversight of democratically elected governments.In that case, the question is Who regulates the regulators? (Rhodes 2000: 359). One

    should not overestimate, however, the cohesiveness of expert advice (Dumoulin et al.

    2005).

    27. See also the section Why is Deliberative Democracy Better than Aggregative Democ-

    racy?by Gutmann and Thompson (2004: 1321) where they expose in more detail these

    four points (and also emphasise the advantages of deliberation in terms of learning).

    28. The decisional impact of participatory procedures is seldom a subject of discussion in the

    literature. E.g., Saward (2000), which is a theoretically well-informed volume on related

    subjects, favours issues of participation and deliberation over the output dimension.

    29. See the literature on mass behaviour about political stratification. Usually critiques onparticipatory devices have an elitist flavour; see, however, the ground-breaking study of

    town meetings by Mansbridge (1983), the issue of class power in Latin American

    countries raised by Huber et al. (1997), and the discussion in Papadopoulos (2001a).

    Empirical evidence does not always confirm the thesis of the selectivity of participation

    in such bodies: see the contributions in Politics & Society (29(1), March 2001), and in

    Jouve & Gagnon (2005). Institutional design can explicitly aim to safeguard represen-

    tativity as in deliberative opinion polls (Fishkin 1996); see also some interesting

    attempts to produce representative samples in citizens juries in France (Boy et al. 2000:

    783, 803) and in Germany (Sintomer 2005).

    30. See Olsons (1965) famous paradox of collective action: broad interests are more diffi-cult to organise than narrow interests.

    31. Holzinger (2001a) lists a number of reasons that can make some actors opt for less

    deliberative alternatives instead of joining mediation procedures.

    32. Cohen and Rogers (2003: 248249) write:[A]ctors with sufficient power to advance their

    aims without deliberating will not bother to deliberate. . . . Equally, if parties are not

    somehow constrained to accept the consequences of deliberation, if exit options are

    not foreclosed, it will be implausible that they will accept the discipline of joint reason-

    ing (see also Ferejohn 2000: 80, 84).

    33. For a synthesis, see Bendor et al. 2001.34. Through the process of public discussion with a plurality of differently opinioned and

    situated others, people often gain new information, learn of different experiences of

    their collective problems, or find that their own initial opinions are founded on prejudice

    or ignorance, or that they have misunderstood the relation of their own interests to

    others (Young 2000: 26, 115120).

    35. Specialists of the role of ideas in policy making such as Jobert and Muller (1987) call

    this a rfrentiel global that would make the synthesis between various rfrentiels

    sectoriels.

    36. See also Gutmann and Thompson (2004: 2629), who distinguish between consensual

    and pluralist conceptions of deliberation.37. Persuasion . . . involves changing peoples choices of alternatives independently of their

    calculations about the strategies of other players. People who are persuaded . . . change

    their minds for reasons other than a recalculation of advantageous choices in light of

    new information about others behaviour. . . . Unlike bargaining on the basis of specific

    464 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    21/28

    reciprocity, persuasion must appeal to norms, principles and values that are shared by

    participants in a conversation (Keohane 2002: 341; emphasis added).

    38. Pollack (2003: 138) also finds that deliberation is much more likely to occur within

    comitology committees on issues where there is uncertainty about policy effects (e.g.,

    risk management) than when national delegates have clear preferences, as is the rule forredistributive policies (e.g., in the EU structural funds).

    39. For a similar categorisation of individual preferences (more considered, empathetic and

    far-reaching), see Goodin (2003: 7).

    40. See the discussion on the role of associations by Fung (2003a).

    41. There is indeed a parallel to be drawn between the success of participatory and delib-

    erative conceptions of democracy in political theory and the diffusion of participatory

    recipes with much ambiguity and variation as to their content in policy-making

    practice (their deliberative component is less strongly emphasised in practical dis-

    courses). However, no empirical studies are available to our knowledge that would

    substantiate causal mechanisms between evolutions in the scientific and in the political-administrative system (e.g., the influence on policy practice of experts familiar with

    developments in current democratic theory), especially as there are but few actors

    participating in both systems (Bacqu et al. 2005a: 42). The article by Yves Sintomer and

    Jacques de Maillard in this special issue briefly addresses this point with respect to the

    French politique de la ville (role of policy evaluations, etc.). The growth of participatory

    procedures is particularly striking in local development projects within less developed

    countries, where it is part of broader managerial attempts for good governance (as

    opposed to partisan and bureaucratic inefficiency and corruption), in all likelihood

    favoured by the weakness of traditional democratic institutions (Bacqu et al. 2005b:

    304) (see, e.g., the IDS (Institute of Development Studies) Bulletin, 35(2), April 2004,entitled New Democratic Spaces?). Yet initiatives more strongly oriented towards

    empowerment exist too, such as the widely publicised participatory budget in Porto

    Alegre (Brazil).

    42. Accountability of course also requires in a deliberative perspective that decision

    makers be constrained to give reasons for their choices to target groups and to the

    citizenry at large. This means that the policy takers have adequate resources to credibly

    threaten decision makers with sanctions if they do not behave in a responsive manner.

    43. For a very sensitive assessment of problems related to incongruence between different

    logics of action coupled together in policy-making processes, see Lehmbruch (1999: 403).

    For an illustration of problems of coupling between direct and representative democracy

    in Switzerland, see Papadopoulos (2001).

    References

    Abromeit, H. (2002). Wozu braucht man Demokratie? Die postnationale Herausforderung

    der Demokratietheorie. Opladen: Leske + Budrich.

    Ackerman, B. & Fishkin, J.S. (2002). Deliberation day.Journal of Political Philosophy 10(2):

    129152.

    Andersen, S.S. & Burns, T.R. (1996). The European Union and the erosion of parliamentary

    democracy: A study of post-parliamentary governance. In S.S. Andersen & K.J. Eliassen

    (eds), The European Union: How democratic is it? London: Sage.

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 465

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    22/28

    Ansell, C. & Gingrich, J. (2003). Reforming the administrative state. In B.E. Cain, R.J.

    Dalton & S.E. Scarrow (eds), Democracy transformed? Expanding political opportunities

    in advanced industrial democracies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Bachrach, P. & Botwinick, A. (1992). Power and empowerment. Philadelphia, PA: Temple

    University Press.Bacqu, M.-H., Rey, H. & Sintomer, Y. (eds) (2005). Gestion de proximit et dmocratie

    participative. Paris: La dcouverte.

    Bacqu, M.-H., Rey, H. & Sintomer, Y. (2005a). La dmocratie participative, un nouveau

    paradigme de laction publique? In M.-H. Bacqu et al. (eds), Gestion de proximit et

    dmocratie participative. Paris: La dcouverte.

    Bacqu, M.-H., Rey, H. & Sintomer, Y. (2005b). La dmocratie participative, modles et

    enjeux. In M.-H. Bacqu et al. (eds), Gestion de proximit et dmocratie participative.

    Paris: La dcouverte.

    Barber, B. (1984). Strong democracy: Participatory politics for a new age. Berkeley, CA:

    University of California Press.Barber, B. (1995). Participatory democracy. In S.M. Lipset (ed.), The encyclopedia of democ-

    racy. London: Routledge.

    Barthe, Y. (2002). Rendre discutable. Le traitement politique dun hritage technologique.

    Politix 15(57): 5778.

    Bendor, J., Glazer, T. & Hammond, T. (2001). Theories of delegation. Annual Review of

    Political Science 4: 235269.

    Benhabib, S. (1996). Toward a deliberative model of democratic legitimacy. In Democracy

    and difference: Contesting the boundaries of the political. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Uni-

    versity Press.

    Benz, A. (1994). Kooperative Verwaltung. Funktionen, Voraussetzungen, Folgen. Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlag.

    Benz, A. (1998). Postparlamentarische Demokratie? Demokratische Legitimation im

    kooperativen Staat. In M.T. Greven (ed.), Demokratie eine Kultur des Westens?

    Opladen: Leske + Budrich.

    Benz, A. (2000). Politische Steuerung in lose gekoppelten Mehrebenensystemen. In

    R. Werle & U. Schimank (eds), Gesellschaftliche Komplexitt und kollektive Handlungs-

    fhigkeit. Frankfurt-am-Main: Campus.

    Benz, A. & Papadopoulos, Y. (eds) (2006). Governance and democracy: Comparing national,

    European and international experiences. London: Routledge.

    Berry, C.J. (1989). The idea of a democratic community. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Blondiaux, L. (2005). Lide de dmocratie participative: enjeux, impenss et questions

    rcurrentes. In M.-H. Bacqu et al. (eds), Gestion de proximit et dmocratie participa-

    tive. Paris: La dcouverte.

    Blondiaux, L. & Sintomer, Y. (2002). Limpratif dlibratif. Politix 15(57): 1735.

    Bohman, J. (1996). Public deliberation: Plurality, complexity and democracy. Cambridge,

    MA: MIT Press.

    Bohman, J. & Rehg, W. (eds) (1999). Deliberative democracy: Essays on reason and politics.

    Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Booth, P. & Jouve, B. (eds) (2005). Metropolitan democracies: Transformation of the state andurban policy in Canada, France and Great Britain. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Boy, D. et al. (2000). Un exemple de dmocratie participative: La confrence de citoyens

    sur les organismes gntiquement modifis. Revue franaise de science politique 50(45):

    779809.

    466 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    23/28

    Budge, I. (1996). The new challenge of direct democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Callon, M., Lascoumes, P. & Barthe, Y. (2001). Agir dans un mode incertain. Essai sur la

    dmocratie technique. Paris: Le Seuil.

    Chambers, S. (1996). Reasonable democracy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Chambers, S. (2003). Deliberative democratic theory. Annual Review of Political Science 6:307326.

    Cohen, J. & Rogers, J. (1995). Solidarity, democracy, association. In E.O. Wright (ed.),

    Associations and democracy. London/New York: Verso.

    Cohen, J. & Rogers, J. (2003). Power and reason. In A. Fung & E.O. Wright, Deepening

    democracy. London/New York: Verso.

    Cooke, M. (2000). Five arguments for deliberative democracy. Political Studies 48: 947

    969.

    De Leon, P. (1997). Democracy and the policy sciences. Albany, NY: State University of New

    York.

    Dorf, M.C. & Sabel, C.F. (1998). A constitution of democratic experimentalism. ColumbiaLaw Review 98(2): 267473.

    Dryzek, J.S. (2000). Deliberative democracy and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Dumoulin, L. et al. (2005). Le recours aux experts. Raisons et usages politiques. Grenoble:

    Presses Universitaires de Grenoble.

    Duran, P. (1999). Penser laction publique. Paris: Librairie gnrale de droit et de

    jurisprudence.

    Eder, K. et al. (1997). Reflexive Institutionen? Eine Untersuchung zur Herausbildung eines

    neuen Typus institutionneller Regelungen im Umweltbereich. Final report to the

    Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft, Munich.

    Elgstroem, O. & Joensson, C. (2000). Negotiation in the European Union: Bargaining orproblem-solving? Journal of European Public Policy 7(5): 684704.

    Elster, J. (ed.) (1998). Deliberative democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Etzioni, A. (1993). The spirit of community: Rights, responsibilities and the communitarian

    agenda. New York: Crown.

    Etzioni, A. (1995). Rights and the common good: The communitarian perspective. New York:

    St Martins Press.

    Fearon, J.D. (1998). Deliberation as discussion. In J. Elster (ed.), Deliberative democracy.

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Ferejohn, J. (2000). Instituting deliberative democracy. In I. Shapiro & S. Macedo (eds),

    Designing democratic institutions. New York: New York University Press.

    Fischer, F. (2000). Citizens, experts and the environment: The politics of local knowledge.

    Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Fishkin, J.S. (1991). Democracy and deliberation: New directions for democratic reform.New

    Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Fishkin, J.S. (1996). The voice of the people: Public opinion and democracy. New Haven, CT:

    Yale University Press.

    Fuchs, V.R. (1968). The service economy. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Fung, A. (2003). Recipes for public spheres: Eight institutional design choices and their

    consequences. Journal of Political Philosophy 11(3): 338367.Fung, A. (2003a). Associations and democracy: Between theories, hopes and realities.

    Annual Review of Sociology 29: 515539.

    Fung, A. (2004). Empowered participation: Reinventing urban democracy. Princeton, NJ:

    Princeton University Press.

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 467

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    24/28

    Fung, A. & Wright, E.O. (2001). Deepening democracy: Innovations in empowered partici-

    patory governance. Politics & Society 29(1): 541.

    Fung, A. & Wright, E.O. (eds) (2003). Deepening democracy. London/New York: Verso.

    Fung, A. & Wright, E.O. (2003a). Countervailing power in empowered participatory

    governance. In Deepening democracy. London/New York: Verso.Gartner, A. & Riessman, F. (1974). The service society and the consumer vanguard. New

    York: Harper & Row.

    Gastil, J. & Levine, P. (eds) (2005). The deliberative democracy handbook. San Francisco, CA:

    Jossey-Bass.

    Gaster, L. & Rutqvist, H. (2000). Changing the front line to meet citizen needs. Local

    Government Studies 26(2): 5370.

    Gbikpi, B. & Grote, J.R. (2002). From democratic government to participatory governance.

    In Participatory governance:Political and societal implications.Opladen:Leske+Budrich.

    Gilliat, S., Fenwick, J. & Alford, D. (2000). Public services and the consumer: Empowerment

    or control. Social Policy and Administration 34(3): 333349.Goodin, R.E. (2003). Reflective democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Goss, S. (1999). Managing working with the public. London: Kogan Page.

    Gould, C.C. (1988). Rethinking democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Graham, K. (1986). The battle of democracy. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Guggenberger, B. (1984). An den Grenzen der Mehrheitsdemokratie. In B. Guggenberger &

    C. Offe (eds), An den Grenzen der Mehrheitsdemokratie. Opladen: Westdeutscher

    Verlag.

    Gutmann, A. & Thompson, D. (1996). Democracy and disagreement. Cambridge, MA:

    Harvard University Press.

    Gutmann, A. & Thompson, D. (2004). Why deliberative democracy? Princeton, NJ: PrincetonUniversity Press.

    Habermas, J. (1984). Theory of communicative action. London: Heinemann.

    Habermas, J. (1993). Justification and application: Remarks on discourse ethics. Cambridge:

    Polity Press.

    Hardin, R. (2002). Street-level epistemology and democratic participation.Journal of Politi-

    cal Philosophy 10(2): 212229.

    Hirst, P. (1994). Associative democracy: New forms of economic and social governance.

    Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Holzinger, K. (2001). Negotiations in public policy making: Exogenous barriers to successful

    dispute resolution. Journal of Public Policy 21(1): 7196.

    Holzinger, K. (2001a). Verhandeln statt Argumentieren oder verhandeln durch Argumen-

    tieren? Eine empirische Analyse auf der Basis der Sprechakttheorie. Politische Viertel-

    jahresschrift 42(3): 414446.

    Huber, E., Rueschemeyer, D. & Stephens, J.D. (1997). The paradoxes of contemporary

    democracy: Formal, participatory and social dimensions. Comparative Politics 29(3):

    323342.

    Hunold, C. (2000). Corporatism, pluralism and democracy: Toward a deliberative theory of

    bureaucratic accountability. Governance 14(2): 151167.

    Hunold, C. & Young, I.M. (1998). Justice, democracy and hazardous siting. Political Studies46: 8295.

    Innes, J.E. & Booher, D.E. (2003). Collaborative policy making: Governance through

    dialogue. In M.A. Haajer & H. Wagenaar (eds), Deliberative policy analysis:

    Understanding governance in network society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    468 yannis papadopoulos & philippe warin

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    25/28

    Jobert, B. & Muller, P. (1987). LEtat en action. Politiques publiques et corporatismes. Paris:

    Presses universitaires de France.

    Joerges, C. & Neyer, J. (1997). Transforming strategic interaction into deliberative problem-

    solving: European comitology in the foodstuffs sector.Journal of European Public Policy

    4(4): 609625.Joss, S. (ed.) (1999). Special issue on public participation in science and technology. Science

    and Public Policy 26(5).

    Joss, S. & Durant, J. (eds) (1995). Public participation in science: The role of consensus

    conferences in Europe. London: Science Museum.

    Jouve, B. & Gagnon, A.G. (2005). Dmocratie et mtropoles: nouveaux enjeux, nouveaux

    dfis. Grenoble: Presses Universitaires de Grenoble.

    Keohane, R.O. (2002). Governance in a partially globalized world. In D. Held & A. McGrew

    (eds), Governing globalization. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Khan, U. (ed.) (1999). Participation beyond the ballot box: European case studies in state-

    citizen dialogue. London: UCL Press.Kjaer, A.-M. (2004). Governance. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Kohler-Koch, B. (2000). Framing: The bottleneck of constructing legitimate institutions.

    Journal of European Public Policy 7(4): 513531.

    Kooiman, J. (1996). Research and theory about new public services management: Review

    and agenda for the future. International Journal of Public Sector Management 9(5/6):

    722.

    Kooiman, J. (2003). Governing as governance. London: Sage.

    Kuebler, D. (1999). Beyond nimbyism: Urban conflict resolution in Swiss drug policies. In

    U. Khan (ed.), Participation beyond the ballot box: European case studies in state-citizen

    dialogue. London: UCL Press.Lehmbruch, G. (1977). Liberal corporatism and party government. Comparative Political

    Studies 10(1): 91126.

    Lehmbruch, G. (1999). Verhandlungsdemokratie, Entscheidungsblockaden und Arenenver-

    flechtung. In W. Merkel & A. Busch (eds), Demokratie in Ost und West. Fr Klaus von

    Beyme. Frankfurt-am-Main: Suhrkamp.

    Linder, W. (1994). Swiss democracy: Possible solutions to conflict in multicultural societies.

    New York: St Martins Press.

    Lowndes, V., Pratchett, L. & Stoker, G. (2001). Trends in public participation. Part 2:

    Citizens perspectives. Public Administration 79(2): 445455.

    Macedo, S. (ed.) (1999). Deliberative politics: Essays on democracy and disagreement.

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Majone, G. (1996). Regulating Europe. London: Routledge.

    Majone, G. (2000). Temporal consistency and policy credibility: Why democracies need

    non-majoritarian institutions. In J. Theys (ed.), The environment in the 21st century.

    Vol. I: The issues. Paris: Germes.

    Manin, B. (1985). Volont gnrale ou dlibration? Esquisse dune thorie de la dlibra-

    tion politique. Le dbat33: 7293.

    Manin, B. (1987). On legitimacy and deliberation. Political Theory 15: 338368.

    Manin,B. (2002). (interview with) Lide de dmocratie dlibrative dans la science politiquecontemporaine. Introduction, gnalogie et lments critiques. Politix 15(57): 3755.

    Mansbridge, J. (1983). Beyond adversary democracy. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Mansbridge, J. (2003). Practice-thought-practice. In A. Fung & E.O. Wright (eds), Deepening

    democracy. London/New York: Verso.

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 469

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    26/28

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    27/28

    Putnam, R.D. (2000). Bowling alone: The collapse and revival of American community. New

    York/London: Simon & Schuster.

    Rehmann-Sutter, C., Vatter, A. & Seiler, H. (1998). Partizipative Risikopolitik. Opladen:

    Westdeutscher Verlag.

    Renn, O. et al. (1995). Fairness and competence in citizen participation: Evaluating models forenvironmental discourse. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Rhodes, R.A.W. (1997). Understanding governance. Buckingham: Open University

    Press.

    Rhodes, R.A.W. (2000). The governance narrative: Key findings and lessons from the

    ESRCs Whitehall programme. Public Administration 78(2): 345363.

    Sanders, L. (1997). Against deliberation. Political Theory 25: 347376.

    Savas, E.S. (2002). Competition and choice in New York City social services. Public Admin-

    istration Review 62(1): 8291.

    Saward, M. (ed.) (2000). Democratic innovation: Deliberation, representation and association.

    London/New York: Routledge.Saward, M. (2003). At the Edge of Political Theory: Political Community and Deliberative

    Democracy. Paper presented at the EpsNet Political Scientists in the New Europe

    conference, Paris, June.

    Saward, M. (2003a). Enacting democracy. Political Studies 51(1): 161179.

    Scharpf, F.W. (1970). Demokratietheorie zwischen Utopie und Anpassung. Konstanz:

    Universittsverlag.

    Scharpf, F.W. (1991). Political institutions, decision styles and policy choices. In R.M. Czada

    & A. Windhoff-Hritier (eds), Political Choice. Frankfurt-am-Main/Boulder, CO:

    Campus/Westview Press.

    Scharpf, F.W. (1999). Governing in Europe: Effective and democratic? Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.

    Schmitter, P.C. & Streeck, W. (1999). The Organization of Business Interests: Studying the

    Associative Action of Business in Advanced Industrial Societies. Discussion paper 99/1.

    Max-Planck-Institut fr Gesellschaftsforschung, Kln.

    Shapiro, I. (2002). Optimal deliberation? Journal of Political Philosophy 10(2): 196

    211.

    Shon, D. (1983). The reflective practitioner. New York: Basic Books.

    Sintomer, Y. (2005). Les jurys citoyens berlinois et le triage au sort: un nouveau modle de

    dmocratie participative? In M.-H. Bacqu et al. (eds), Gestion de proximit et

    dmocratie participative. Paris: La dcouverte.

    Smith, G. (2000). Toward deliberative institutions. In M. Saward (ed.), Democratic innova-

    tion: Deliberation, representation and association. London/New York: Routledge.

    Smith, G. (2005). Beyond the ballot: 57 democratic innovations from around the world.

    London: Power Inquiry.

    Smith, G. & Wales, C. (2000). Citizens juries and deliberative democracy. Political Studies

    48: 5165.

    Taiclet, A.-F. (2006). Governance, expertise and competitive politics. The case of territorial

    development policies in France. In A. Benz & Y. Papadopoulos (eds), Governance and

    democracy. London: Routledge.Van Eeten, M. (2001). The challenge ahead for deliberative democracy: A reply to Weale.

    Science and Public Policy 28(6): 423426.

    Verba, S., Nie, N.H. & Kim, J.O. (1978). A seven-nation comparison: Participation and

    political equality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    are innonative procedures in policy making democratic and effective? 471

    2007 The Author(s)

    Journal compilation 2007 (European Consortium for Political Research)

  • 8/8/2019 European Journal 2007 1

    28/28

    Vig, N.J. & Paschen, H. (eds) (2000). Parliaments and technology: The development of

    technology assessment in Europe. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Waelti, S., Kuebler, D. & Papadopoulos, Y. (2004). How democratic is governance? Lessons

    from Swiss drug policy. Governance 17(1): 83113.

    Walzer, M. (1999). Deliberation, and what else? In S. Macedo (ed.), Deliberative politics:Essays on democracy and disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Warin, P. & La Branche, S. (2005). La concertation du public par la recherche. Une tude

    rtrospective des productions scientifiques. Rapport pour le ministre franais de

    lEcologie et du Dveloppement durable. Grenoble: CERAT/IEP.

    Warren, M. (2002). Del