24

Click here to load reader

Emotional Intelligence Paper

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

En desacuerdo de la inteligencia emocional

Citation preview

Page 1: Emotional Intelligence Paper

Why Emotional Intelligence Is an Invalid Concept

by Edwin A. LockeUniversity of Maryland

1

Page 2: Emotional Intelligence Paper

2

Page 3: Emotional Intelligence Paper

Abstract

In this paper I argue that the concept of emotional intelligence (EI) in invalid both

because it is not a form of intelligence and because it is defined so broadly and

inclusively that it has no intelligible meaning. I distinguish the so called concept of

emotional intelligence from actual intelligence and from rationality. I identify the actual

relation between reason and emotion. I reveal the fundamental inadequacy of the concept

of EI when applied to leadership. Finally, I suggest some alternatives to the EI concept.

3

Page 4: Emotional Intelligence Paper

Why Emotional Intelligence Is an Invalid Concept

The concept of intelligence refers to one’s ability to form and grasp concepts,

especially higher level or more abstract concepts. The observations on which the concept

of intelligence is formed are that some people are simply able to “get” things better than

others, that is, they are able to make connections, see implications, reason deductively

and inductively, grasp complexity, understand the meaning of ideas, etc. better than other

people. Motivation obviously plays a role in understanding concepts and can partly

compensate for low ability, but even highly motivated people differ in intellectual ability.

Those who are better able to grasp higher level concepts are better able to handle

complex tasks and jobs.

Intelligence must be clearly distinguished from rationality. Whereas intelligence

refers to one’s capacity to grasp abstractions, rationality refers to how one actually uses

one’s mind. A rational individual takes facts seriously and uses thinking and logic to

reach conclusions. A person can be very intelligent and yet very irrational (cf. many

modern philosophers; Ghate & Locke, 2003). For example, a person’s thinking may be

dominated by emotions, and they may not distinguish between what they feel and what

they can demonstrate to be true.

The concept of emotional intelligence (EI) was introduced by Salovey and Mayer

(1990), although related ideas such as “social intelligence” had been introduced by earlier

writers—originally by E.L. Thorndike. Salovey and Mayer (1990, p. 189) defined

emotional intelligence as, “the ability to monitor one’s own and others’ feelings and

emotions, to discriminate among them and to use this information to guide one’s thinking

4

Page 5: Emotional Intelligence Paper

and actions.” (Note: definitions of EI are constantly changing, an issue I will return to

later).There are several problems with this definition. First, the ability to monitor one’s

emotions does not require any special degree or type of intelligence. Monitoring one’s

emotions is basically a matter of where one chooses to focus one’s attention, outwards at

the external world or inward at the contents and processes of one’s own consciousness.

(This claim obviously implies that people have volitional control over focusing their

minds. For a detailed discussion and defense of claim that people possess volition or free

will, see Binswanger, 1991, and Peikoff, 1991.) Focusing inwards involves introspection.

Similarly, the ability to read the emotions of others is not necessarily an issue of

intelligence. It could simply be a matter of paying attention to others and being aware of

one’s own emotions so that one can empathize with others. For example, if one is

unaware, due to defensiveness, that one can feel fear, one will not be able to empathize

with fear in others.

Second, discriminating between emotions is a learned skill just as is detecting a

given emotion. A highly intelligent person may be better able to make very subtle

distinctions between similar emotions (e.g., jealousy and envy), but, for basic emotions

(e.g., love, anger, fear, desire), it just a matter of focusing inwards so as to develop one’s

introspective skill.

Third, whether one uses one’s knowledge in everyday action is not an issue of

intelligence per se. Many factors may come into play here. Among them are rationality

(vs. emotionalism), being in (vs. out of) focus, integrity (including courage in the face of

opposition), and the nature of one’s purpose. In sum, the definition of EI indicates that it

5

Page 6: Emotional Intelligence Paper

is really some combination of assorted habits, skills and/or choices rather than an issue of

intelligence.

It is simply arbitrary to attach the word intelligence to assorted habits or skills, as

Howard Gardner and EI advocates do, on the alleged grounds that there are multiple

types of intelligences. This extension of the term simply destroys the meaning of the

concept—which, in fact, is the hidden agenda of the advocates of multiple intelligences.

The ultimate motive is egalitarianism: redefining what it means to be intelligent so that

everyone will, in some from, be equal in intelligence to everyone else. The agenda here is

not scientific but political. However, arbitrary redefinitions do not change reality. Some

people actually are more intelligent, in terms of their ability to grasp concepts, than

others, but this ability is not necessarily reflected in every skill that people choose to

develop. If one wants to group a set of related phenomena into a single concept, there

must be a conceptually identified, common element among them. Otherwise, the concept

has no clear meaning.

As another case in point, consider how Salovey and Mayer, in the same article

cited above, (1990, p. 190) expand their conceptualization of emotional intelligence. It is

said to include: the appraisal and expression of emotions in the self, both verbal and non-

verbal; the appraisal and identification of emotions in others through non-verbal

identification and empathy; the regulation of emotions in oneself and in others; and the

utilization of emotions so as to engage in flexible planning, creative thinking, direction of

attention and motivation.

Observe that the concept of EI has now become so broad and the components so

variegated that no one concept could possible encompass or integrate all of them no

6

Page 7: Emotional Intelligence Paper

matter what the concept was called; it is no longer even an intelligible concept. What is

the common or integrating element in a concept that includes: introspection about

emotions, emotional expression, non-verbal communication with others, empathy, self-

regulation, planning, creative thinking and the direction of attention? There is none.

Following Salovey and Mayer, Daniel Goleman (1994) popularized the concept

of EI. According to Goleman, EI involves: self-motivation and persistence; skill at

introspection; delay of gratification; self-control of impulses, moods and emotions;

empathy; and social skills (the ability to make friends). These elements overlap

considerably with those of Salovey and Mayer and are equally un-integratible by means

of a single concept. Most of the actions involved actually require the use of reason.

To add to the confusion, in another article, Mayer (1999, p. 50) defines emotional

intelligence as, “the capacity to reason with emotion in four areas: to perceive emotion, to

integrate it in thought, to understand it and to manage it.” The fundamental problem here

is that one cannot “reason with emotion.” This is a contradiction in terms. Reason and

emotion are two very different cognitive processes, and they perform very different

psychological functions. To reason means to observe reality starting with the material

provided by the senses, to integrate, without contradiction, sensory material into concepts

and concepts into principles. Reason is the means of gaining and validating one’s

knowledge. It is a volitional process guided by the conscious mind.

In contrast, emotions entail an automatic process based on subconsciously held

knowledge and values. Emotions reflect one’s stored beliefs about objects, people or

situations and one’s subconscious appraisal of them based on one’s values. Emotions are

the form in which one experiences automatized value judgments (Peikoff, 1991). Every

7

Page 8: Emotional Intelligence Paper

emotion reflects a specific type of value judgment. For example, fear is the automatic

response to the judgment of a physical threat. Anger is the response to the judgment that

a wrong has been done to you or valued others. Joy is the result of having achieved some

important value. Desire results from appraising some object that one does not possess or

some person who one does not yet have a relationship with as a positive value.

Because emotions are automatic and based on subconsciously stored beliefs and

values, they cannot be assumed to be valid assessments of reality. One’s beliefs might be

wrong; one’s values might be irrational. Emotions—automatic productions of the

subconscious mind-- are not tools of knowledge. The psychological function of emotions

is not to know the world but to make automatic evaluations and motivate action.

Emotions contain, as part of the experience, felt action tendencies. Positive emotions

entail the felt tendency to approach, possess or retain the appraised object; negative

emotions entail the felt tendency to flee, harm or destroy the appraised object. This does

not mean, however, that emotions have to be acted on. Through the power of reason we

can decide whether action in a given case is appropriate or not, and if appropriate, what

action is most suitable given the total situation.

One cannot, therefore, “reason with emotion;” one can only reason about it. It is

through reason that one identifies what emotion one is experiencing, discovers the beliefs

and values that gave rise to it, and decides what action, if any, to take on the face of it. It

is also through reason, which, as noted earlier, is an active, volitional process, that one

determines whether the beliefs behind an emotion are valid and if the values that underlie

it are rational. Reason also enables one to re-program the subconscious so that the

automatized appraisals (beliefs, values) that give rise to specific emotions are changed.

8

Page 9: Emotional Intelligence Paper

Further, reason is used to identify defense mechanisms which may distort or prevent one

from experiencing emotions, and thus stultify their motivating power.

Reason is also the key to self-regulation, not only of one’s emotions in the sense

described above, but also of one’s life in general. Regulating one’s life requires being

purposeful, which means setting long range goals and identifying plans which will enable

one to achieve them.. This process is not divorced from emotions, since one has to

identify what one wants (e.g., in one’s career, in romance) before setting a goal to pursue

it, but reason must be used to identify one’s desires and insure that they are rational if one

is to achieve one’s long range goals. In short, reason, the volitional, active part of one’s

mind, has to be in charge or one is left at the mercy of the emotions of the moment.

Some EI advocates might agree with all this and argue that EI, despite the

definitions usually given, really means being intelligent about emotions, that is,

recognizing their nature and proper function, their relationship to reason, and the need for

introspection. If this is what EI advocates mean by their concept, then what they are

actually referring to is not another form or type of intelligence but intelligence (the ability

to grasp abstractions) applied to a particular life domain: emotions. Intelligence, of

course, can be applied to any of thousands of life domains, but it does not follow that

there are thousands of types of intelligences. If we want to talk about how well a person

has mastered a certain domain, we already have a word for it: skill.

There is one more aspect to the EI story. In a later book, Primal Leadership,

Goleman, Boyatzis and McKee (2002) take EI theory a step further, into the realm of

leadership. Effective leadership traits which they claim to be based on EI include:

o Objective self-assessment

9

Page 10: Emotional Intelligence Paper

o Self-confidence and self-esteem

o Moral character (e.g., honesty and integrity)

o Adaptability and flexibility

o Achievement motivation

o Initiative and self-efficacy

o Organizational awareness (e.g., of organizational politics)

o Customer service

o The use of persuasion tactics

o Developing the ability of followers

o Initiating change

o Conflict management

o Team building

o The use of humor

Goleman et al. (2002) also argue that EI includes the use any or all of the six

following leadership styles:

o Visionary

o Coaching

o Affiliative

o Democratic

o Pacesetting

o Commanding

The question one must ask here is, given that leadership based on EI allegedly

10

Page 11: Emotional Intelligence Paper

encompasses such a long list of characteristics that people have associated with effective

leadership, what does EI not include? One thing is missing from the list: actual

intelligence!

In addition to making the concept of EI-leadership preposterously all-

encompassing, Goleman et al. (2002, p. ix) seriously misconstrue what organizational

leadership involves. They claim that “The fundamental task of leaders is to create good

feelings in those they lead.” This is simply not true. The function of organizations is to

attain goals; in the case of private organizations the goal is long-term profitability.

Organizations, other than psychotherapy clinics, are not in the “feel good” business.

Employee morale is important, but as a means to an end not as an end in itself divorced

from effectiveness.

It ironic that Goleman et al’s EI approach to leadership, despite its long list of

elements, omits any discussion of the intellectual aspects of leadership—aspects which

are critical to organizational success, including business success. These aspects require

the leaders of profit-making organizations to focus not inwards but outwards, at the

business environment. For example, does the leader know or understand:

Where the company should be heading?

The role of the different corporate functions?

The big picture? (Is there an integrating vision?)

How to fit the different parts and processes of the organization

together?

The strategic and technological environments?

How to attain a competitive advantage?

11

Page 12: Emotional Intelligence Paper

How to achieve cash flow?

How to prioritize?

How to balance the short term with the long term?

How to judge talent when hiring and promoting?

How to build a culture?

How to formulate and enforce core values?

Note that performing these very complex tasks requires, among other qualities,

actual intelligence. Making oneself or other people feel good will not substitute for

intellectual deficiencies. Good leadership requires consistent rational thinking by a mind

that is able to grasp and integrate all the facts needed to make the business succeed.

Michael Dell (1999, p. 206) makes an important observation regarding the

relation of emotions and knowledge,

there are countless successful companies that are thriving now despite the fact that

they started with little more than passion and a good idea. There are also many

that failed, for the very same reason. The difference is that the thriving companies

gathered the knowledge that gave them a substantial edge over their competition,

which they used to improve their execution….those that didn’t simply didn’t

make it.

Leadership is not primarily about making people feel good; it’s about knowing

what you are doing and knowing what to do.

Conclusion

Despite the insuperable problems with the various definitions of emotional;

intelligence, there is no denying the importance of one element of EI in human life:

12

Page 13: Emotional Intelligence Paper

introspection. Introspection is a very important human skill; it involves identifying the

contents and processes of one’s own mind. It is only through introspection that one can

monitor such things one’s degree of focus, one’s defensive reactions and one’s emotional

responses and their causes. Such monitoring has important implications for self-esteem

and mental health.

Given their emphasis on introspection, it is ironic that advocates of EI show

virtually no understanding of the actual nature of emotions. For example, while granting

that emotions entail impulses to action, Goleman’ s (1995), discussion of their causes is

confined almost entirely to neurophysiology, especially brain structure. But psychology

cannot be reduced to neurophysiology (Bandura, 1997); ideas do not have the same

attributes as neurons. Especially unfortunate—and mistaken (see Peikoff, 1991)-- is his

claim that, like a Frankenstein monster, we have an innate mind-body dichotomy, two

clashing brains, one rational and one emotional. This is reminiscent of Freud’s arbitrary

division of the personality into opposing parts (id, ego and superego)—a notion which

originated with Plato.

What is the error here? If EI advocates actually used introspection themselves,

they would observe that emotions, as noted earlier, are the product of subconscious ideas

—stored knowledge about the objects and automatic value appraisals based on that

knowledge. Thus there is no inherent clash between reason and emotion (Peikoff, 1991).

As noted, it is through reason that we are able to acquire the knowledge and the values

which cause our emotions. It is through reason that we can identify and, through

reprogramming, change our emotions. It is through reason that we have the power to

decide whether and how to act in the face of emotions. Emotions obviously have a

13

Page 14: Emotional Intelligence Paper

neurophysiological aspect, but brain structure does not determine the content of our

knowledge nor of our values. Nor does it determine whether and how we use our reason,

since reasoning is a volitional process (Binswanger, 1991).

EI’s extension into the field of leadership is even more unfortunate. By asserting

that leadership is an emotional process, Goleman denigrates the very critical role played

by rational thinking and actual intelligence in the leadership process. Given all the add-

ons to the concept proposed by Goleman et al (2002), any associations between

leadership effectives and an EI scale that included these add-ons would be meaningless.

What, then, are we to conclude about EI?

1. The definition of the concept is constantly changing;

2. Most definitions are so all-inclusive as to make the concept unintelligible.

3. One definition (e.g., reasoning with emotion) involves a contradiction.

4. There is no such thing as actual emotional intelligence, although intelligence can be

applied to emotions as well as to other life domains.

A more productive approach to the EI concept might be to replace it with the

concept of introspective skill. (This would be a prerequisite to emotional self-regulation).

Alternatively, it might be asked whether EI could be relabeled and redefined as a

personality trait. Possibly, providing it was (re)defined intelligibly and that it was

differentiated from skills and from traits that have already been identified (e.g., empathy).

However, it is not at all clear at this point what such a trait would be called.

Ayn Rand (1975, p. 77) stated that, “Definitions are the guardians of rationality,

the first line of defense against the chaos of mental disintegration.” With respect to the

14

Page 15: Emotional Intelligence Paper

concept of EI, not to mention many other concept in psychology and management

(Locke, 2003), we are more in need of rational guardians that ever.

15

Page 16: Emotional Intelligence Paper

References

Bandura, A. (1997) Self-efficacy: The exercise of control. New York: Freeman.

Binswanger (1991) Volition as cognitive self-regulation. Organizational Behavior &

Human Decision Processes, 50, 154-178.

Dell, M. (1999) Direct from Dell. New York: Harper Business.

Ghate, O. & Locke, E. (2003) Objectivism: The proper alternative to postmodernism.

In E. Locke (Ed.) Postmodernism and management: Pros, cons and the

alternative. Research in the Sociology of Organizations, Vol. 12, Amsterdam, JAI

(Elsevier Science Ltd.)

Goleman, D. (1995) Emotional intelligence. New York: Bantam.

Goleman, D., Boyatzis, R. & McKee, A. (2002) Primal leadership. Boston: Harvard

Business School Press.

Locke, E. (2003) Good definitions: The epistemological foundation of scientific

progress. In J. Greenberg (Ed.) Organizational behavior: The state of the science.

Mahwah, NJ: L. Erlbaum.

Mayer, J. (1999) Emotional intelligence: popular or scientific psychology? APA Monitor,

September, p. 50.

Peikoff, L. (1991) Objectivism: The philosophy of Ayn Rand. New York: Dutton.

Rand, A, (1975) The romantic manifesto. New York: Signet.

Salovey, P. & Mayer, J. (1990) Emotional intelligence. Imagination, Cognition and

Personality, 9, 185-211.

16

Page 17: Emotional Intelligence Paper

17