105
Bare coordination: a new case for cross- linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

Bare coordination: a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

  • Upload
    tevin

  • View
    18

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Bare coordination: a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting. Recoordinating bare coordination. Bert Le Bruyn & Henri ë tte de Swart. The phenomenon of bare coordination. Context - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

Bare coordination: a new case for cross-linguistic

availability of covert type-shifting

Page 2: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

Recoordinating bare coordination

Bert Le Bruyn & Henriëtte de Swart

Page 3: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

3

Spoon was

The phenomenon of bare coordination

I saw cats dogsand I saw

Context

We had to set the table for the queen. We arranged one crystal goblet, one silver spoon, two antique gold forks and two platinum knives.

Forks and knives were equally dirty

indefinite interpretation

definite interpretation

Plurals

Singulars

was set to the right of the plate* set to the right of the plate*Goblet spoon wereand only definite interpretation

Heycock & Zamparelli (2003)

??? There were goblet and spoon on the table.

Page 5: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

5

The phenomenon of bare coordination

Why is it bare singulars cannot occur bare whereas coordinated bare singulars can ?

When and why do bare coordinated nouns get a definite reading?

Page 6: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

6

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and

Roadmap

Page 7: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

7

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and

Roadmap

Page 9: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

9

New facts: English

We had to set the table for the queen. We arranged one crystal goblet, one silver spoon, two antique gold forks and two platinum knives. Goblet and spoon were set on the right of the plate.(Heycock & Zamparelli 2003)

We had to set the table for the queen. We arranged one crystal goblet, one silver spoon, two antique gold forks and two platinum knives. Forks and knives were equally dirty. (Heycock & Zamparelli 2003)

He had pad and pencil to picture the whole event.

There were forks and knives on the table.(Heycock & Zamparelli 2003)

Page 10: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

10

Recap

Basic dataCoordination lifts all semantic constraints on the absence of articles.

Page 11: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

11

Can you replicate the data for your language?

Page 12: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

12

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and• Surprise Bonus

Roadmap

Page 13: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

13

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and• Surprise Bonus

Roadmap

Page 14: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

14

Roodenburg (2004)

The analysis in a nutshell

Premise 1: Bare Coordinated NPs are plural.

Conclusion: Bare coordinated NPs are allowed in argument position.

Premise 2: Bare Plural NPs are allowed in argument position.

> Cat and dog were fighting.

Page 15: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

15

Roodenburg (2004)

The analysis in a nutshell

As for the definite readings: they’re akin to functional readings of bare plurals (Condoravdi 1994)

> Ghosts haunted the campus. Students were aware of the danger.

Page 16: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

16

Roodenburg (2004)

Problem

Roodenburg predicts bare coordination always to behave on a par with bare plural.

> Ghosts haunted the campus and we had to warn the students, the faculty and the rest of the staff. ??It turned out though that students were already aware of the danger. > Ghosts haunted the campus and we had to warn the students, the faculty and the rest of the staff. It turned out though that students and faculty were already aware of the danger.

Page 17: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

17

Heycock & Zamparelli (2003)

The analysis in a nutshell

Focus on deriving the definite reading of bare coordinated nominals.

Proposal: allow for N-to-D raising of the coordinated phrase.

DP

CoordP

NP1 and NP2

Page 18: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

18

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and

Roadmap

Page 19: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

19

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and

Roadmap

Page 20: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

20

Our analysis in a nutshell

coordinatednot coordinated

bare singulars

bare plurals

indefinite definite indefinite definite

> Classic blocking account:

indefinite bare singulars are blocked bydefinite bare singulars are blocked bydefinite bare plurals are blocked by the definite plural article

the definite singular articlethe indefinite singular article

Page 21: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

21

Our analysis in a nutshell

coordinatednot coordinated

bare singulars

bare plurals

indefinite definite indefinite definite

> Not so classic blocking account:

A, thesing and theplural don’t apply at the coordination level.As a consequence they cannot be taken to block indefinite or definite readings of coordinated bare nominals.

Page 22: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

22

Our analysis in a nutshell

A, thesing and theplural don’t apply at the coordination level.

>Indirect evidence

un homme et une femme (amale man and afemale woman) 1760000

un homme et femme (amale man and woman) 696

une femme et une fille (afemale woman and afemale girl) 885

une femme et fille (afemale woman and girl) 15

les hommes et les femmes (the men and the women) 3030000

les hommes et femmes (the men and women) 361000yahoo.fr 11/11/2010

Generalization:

Strong preference for repetition of the determiner; Suggests that the repetition of the determiner is the default; Suggests that the cases in which there is no repetition involve elided Ds.

Page 23: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

23

Our analysis in a nutshell

A, thesing and theplural don’t apply at the coordination level.

>Direct evidence

Dog and cat were fighting. > bare coordination can trigger plural agreement

> there is a level of syntactic representation at which CoordPs have to have plurality specified (see also de Vries 1992)

> If Ds were to apply to CoordPs we would predict CoordPs to be able to take a plural article, even if both conjuncts are singular.

> This is however not the case.

*Dog and cat was fighting.

Page 24: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

24

Our analysis in a nutshell

les hommes et les femmes the men and the women 3030000

les hommes et femmes the men and women 361000

les homme et femme the man and woman 99

les hommes et les garçons the men and the boys 2570

les hommes et garçons the men and boys 175

les homme et garçon the man and boy 1

les femmes et les filles the women and the girls 164000

les femmes et filles the women and girls 16000

les femme et fille the woman and girl 18

yahoo.fr 11/11/2010

Page 25: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

25

Recap

Basic dataCoordination lifts all semantic constraints on the absence of articles.

Basic insightDeterminers don’t apply at the coordination level.

ImplementationClassic blocking ...

Page 26: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

26

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and• Surprise Bonus

Roadmap

Page 27: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

27

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and• Surprise Bonus

Roadmap

Page 28: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

28

From ‘informal’ blocking to OTDP

NumP

CoordP

AND

NumP

NP

N

NumP

NP

N

DP DP

N-domain

CoordP-domain

N.B. Coordination can apply at the DP, NumP or NP-level.

N N

Page 29: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

29

From ‘informal’ blocking to OT

a. FdrMark discourse referents

b. FplMark reference to a group

For each type of functional projection we have a faithfulness constraint.

DP

NumP

c. FdefMark definiteness

We add an extra one for D projections.

DP

For the two domains we add a markedness constraint.

d. *FunctNDon’t mark functional structure in the N-domain

e. *FunctCoordPDon’t mark functional structure in the CoordP-domain.

N-dom

CoordP-dom

Page 30: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

30

From ‘informal’ blocking to OT

a. FdrMark discourse referents

b. FplMark reference to a group

For French and English the following ranking holds:

c. FdefMark definiteness

e. *FunctCoordPDon’t mark functional structure in the CoordP-domain.

d. *FunctNDon’t mark functional structure in the N-domain.

Page 31: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

31

From ‘informal’ blocking to OT

Depending on the level at which coordination applies the ranking derives the following possibilities:

the cats and the dogsDP level coordination

cats and dogsNumP level coordination

cat and dogNP level coordination

Testable illegal structures:

I saw *(a) cat.Bare singular arguments

several cat and dogDs applying at CoordP

Untestable (?) illegal structures:

I saw cat and dogs (?)(meaning I saw cats and dogs)

Number at CoordP

Page 32: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

32

Recap

Basic dataCoordination lifts all semantic constraints on the absence of articles.

Basic insightDeterminers don’t apply at the coordination level.

ImplementationClassic blocking ... and its formalization in OT.

Page 33: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

33

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and

Roadmap

Page 34: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

34

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and

Roadmap

Page 35: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

35

The semantics of coordination

We assume the basic semantics of coordination at the level of sets is that of set intersection.

X Y

Bare coordination never has this basic semantics.

X and Y

> Bride and groom were extremely happy.

There was an extremely happy person who was both bride and groom.

Page 36: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

36

The semantics of coordination

Two types of coordination:

> coordination with ‘joint’ readings

> coordination with ‘split’ readings

Bare coordination always concerns coordination with ‘split’ readings.

Our challenge will be to derive split readings without giving up the basic intuition of coordination being an instance of set intersection.

Page 37: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

37

The semantics of coordination

How to go about this?

> Enrichment of and

> First enrichment: turn and into a ‘matchmaker’

PQ ( )PQ x E E x( ) ( )

> Based on a proposal by Yoad Winter (p.c.)

Page 38: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

38

The semantics of coordination

bride groom

( , )

( , )

( , )

( , )

( , )

( , )

Page 39: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

39

The semantics of coordination

( , )

( , )

( , )

( , )

( , )

QxE ExP

Page 40: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

40

The semantics of coordination

> Enrichment of and

> First enrichment: turn and into a ‘matchmaker’

PQ ( )PQ x E E x( ) ( )

> Second enrichment: add a function that turns (singular) couples into plural individuals.

> Based on a proposal by Yoad Winter (p.c.)

PQ ( )PQ x E E x( ) ( )RtoI

Relations to Individuals

RtoI(R) = {xy : R(x,y)}

How to go about this?

Page 41: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

41

The semantics of coordination

bride and groom

Page 42: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

42

The semantics of coordinationbride and groom

> Bride and groom were extremely happy.

> the unique plural individual consisting of a bride and groom was extremely happy

> extremely_happy( )

Page 43: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

43

Recap

Basic dataCoordination lifts all semantic constraints on the absence of articles.

Basic insightDeterminers don’t apply at the coordination level.

ImplementationClassic blocking ... and its formalization in OT.

The semantics of bare coordinationEnriched version of an intersective semantics.

Page 44: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

44

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and

Roadmap

Page 45: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

45

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and• Surprise Bonus

Roadmap

shortcut to conclusion

Page 46: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

46

Why cat and dog is ‘definite’ by default

coordinatednot coordinated

bare singulars

bare plurals

indefinite definite indefinite definite

coordinatednot coordinated

bare singulars

bare plurals

indefinite definite indefinite definite

Page 47: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

47

Cat and dog were fighting.

> Implicature of uniqueness

If there had been more cats and dogs, we could have told you so.

Given that we did not tell you, you can assume that there was only one cat and one dog.

> The effect of this implicature is almost indistinguishable from the contribution of the definite article.

Even though our semantic account predicts both a definite and an indefinite reading, pragmatically the indefinite reading is so close to the definite reading that one gets the impression there’s only a definite reading.

Why cat and dog is ‘definite’ by default

Page 48: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

48

Predictions

... coordinated bare plurals should not have any preference for definite readings.

... the preference for definite interpretations should be cancelable.

Given that the implicature depends on the nouns being singular...

Given that we assume the default definite interpretation is an implicature...

> This is arguably what we find (see Heycock & Zamparelli).

> This is what we have demonstrated for existential contexts.

Why cat and dog is ‘definite’ by default

Page 49: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

49

More predictions

... the definiteness effect should not only be found for coordinated nouns but also for uncoordinated singular nouns in languages that have a singular/plural distinction but no articles

Given that the implicature arises because of the competition between bare singulars and plurals...

> Languages like Hindi and Russian have indeed been argued to only allow for definite readings for bare singulars, despite their acceptability in existential environments (see Dayal 2004).

Why cat and dog is ‘definite’ by default

Page 50: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

50

More predictions

... the definiteness effect should not only be found for coordinated nouns but also for uncoordinated singular nouns in languages that have a singular/plural distinction but no articles

... uncoordinated plural nouns in these languages should not show any preference for definite readings

Given that the implicature arises because of the competition between bare singulars and plurals...

> Languages like Hindi and Russian have indeed been argued to only allow for definite readings for bare singulars, despite their acceptability in existential environments (see Dayal 2004, Geist 2010).

> Uncoordinated bare plurals in Hindi and Russian have indeed been argued to allow both definite and indefinite readings (see Dayal 2004).

Why cat and dog is ‘definite’ by default

Page 51: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

51

One more prediction

... there should be no definiteness effect in Chinese comparable to the one in Hindi and Russian

Given that the implicature arises because of the competition between bare singulars and plurals...

> Bare nominals in Chinese have indeed been argued to freely allow both for a definite and an indefinite reading (see Yang 2001).

N.B.

This implicature account can be formulated both under the analysis of the singular/plural contrast of Farkas & de Swart (2010) and the one in the tradition of Krifka (1989) (see a.o. Sauerland et al. 2005).

Why cat and dog is ‘definite’ by default

Page 52: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

52

• New facts• Previous analyses• Our analysis in a nutshell• Our analysis in OT• The semantics of and• Surprise Bonus

Roadmap

Page 53: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

53

The phenomenon of bare coordination

Why is it bare singulars cannot occur bare whereas coordinated bare singulars can ?

When and why do bare coordinated nouns get a definite reading?

> Articles don’t apply at the coordination level

> No blocking of bare coordinated forms

> Semantically, definite/indefinite readings are available through type-shifting > Pragmatically, bare singulars prefer ‘definite’ readings

Page 54: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

54

Current work

How to account for cases like the following:

We hinted at a covert D in front of woman but this has been challenged in the literature.

this man and woman

Page 55: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

55

References

Dayal, 2004, ‘Number marking and (in)definiteness in kind terms’, Linguistics and Philosophy 27, 393-450.

Farkas & de Swart, 2010, “The semantics and pragmatics of plurals”, Semantics and Pragmatics 3.

Geist, 2010, “Indefinite NPs without indefinite articles”, presentation at SUB 2010.

Heycock & Zamparelli, 2003, “Coordinated bare definites”, Linguistic Inquiry 34, 443-469.

Heycock & Zamparelli, 2005, “Friends and colleagues”, Natural Language Semantics 13, 201-270.

Krifka, 1989, “Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics”, in: Bartsch, van Benthem & van Emde Boas (eds.), Semantics and contextual expression, Foris.

Roodenburg, 2004, Pour une approche scalaire de la déficience nominale, Ph.D. Dissertation, Universiteit van Amsterdam.

Sauerland, Anderssen & Yatsushiro, 2005, “The plural is semantically unmarked”, in: Kepser & Reis (eds.), Linguistic evidence, de Gruyter.

Yang, 2001, Common nouns, classifiers, and quantification in Chinese, Ph.D. Dissertation, Rutgers University.

Zwarts, 2009, Bare constructions in Dutch, Ms., Utrecht University.

Page 56: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

Writing abstracts

Page 57: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

How semanticists derive narrow scope

Page 58: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

58

Carlson

Come1Come2Not

x[come(x)]ykx[R(x,yk)&come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t> / St-St shorthand!

Page 59: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

59

Shorthand convention

In principle negation is of type <t,t>.

The <<e,t>,<e,t>> variant can be obtained as follow:

come(k)

S<e,t> -S come(k)

-come(k)

x-come(x)

function application

lambda abstraction

In these slides, the notation x(-come(x)) obtained through negation of the type <<e,t>,<e,t>> is shorthand for the above process. back

Page 60: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

60

Carlson

Come1Come2NotSome childrenChildren

Some children didn’t come.

x[come(x)]ykx[R(x,yk)&come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t> / St-St P<e,t>x[children(x)&P<e,t>(x)]childrenk

P<e,t>x[children(x)&P<e,t>(x)]<<e,t>,t>

x[come(x)]<e,t>

P<e,t>-P<e,t> / St-St

<<e,t>,<e,t>> <t,t>

(1) x[come(x)]P<e,t>x[children(x)&P<e,t>(x)]x[children(x)&come(x)]St-St -

(2) P<e,t>-P<e,t> x[come(x)] x[-come(x)]P<e,t>x[children(x)&P<e,t>(x)]x[children(x)&-come(x)]

shorthand!

Page 61: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

61

Chierchia

Come1NotSome childrenChildren

Children didn’t come.

e

x[come(x)]childrenk

x[come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t> / St-St P<e,t>x[children(x)&P<e,t>(x)]childrenk

<e,t>

x[come(x)] childrenkcome(childrenk)St-St-come(childrenk)

=-(come(childrenk))=-(x[R(x,childrenk)&come(x)])=-x[R(x,childrenk)&come(x)]

Page 62: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

62

Van Geenhoven

Come1NotSome childrenChildren

Children didn’t come.

<e,t>

x[come(x)]x[children(x)]

x[come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t> / St-St P<e,t>x[children(x)&P<e,t>(x)]x[children(x)]

<e,t>

x[come(x)]x[children(x)]

x[come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t>x[-come(x)] x[children(x)]

= P-x[come(x)&P(x)] x[children(x)]

= -x[come(x)&children(x)]

?

Page 63: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

63

Carlson

Come1Come2NotSome childrenChildren

Children didn’t come.

<<e,t>,t>

x[come(x)]<e,t>

P<e,t>-P<e,t> / St-St

<<e,t>,<e,t>> <t,t>

(1)(2)

childrenk

x[come(x)]ykx[R(x,yk)&come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t> / St-St P<e,t>x[children(x)&P<e,t>(x)]childrenk

ykx[R(x,yk)&come(x)]<e,t>

x[come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t>

(3)(4)

P<e,t>-P<e,t> ykx[R(x,yk)&come(x)]

x[-come(x)]

yk - x[R(x,yk)&come(x)]

childrenk

childrenk

-come(childrenk)

-x[R(x,childrenk)&come(x)]

x[come(x)]

ykx[R(x,yk)&come(x)]

childrenk

childrenk

come(childrenk)

x[R(x,childrenk)&come(x)]

St-St

St-St

-come(childrenk)

-x[R(x,childrenk)&come(x)]

Page 64: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

64

Krifka

Come1NotSome childrenChildren

Children didn’t come.

<e,t>

x[come(x)]x[children(x)]

x[come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t> / St-St P<e,t>x[children(x)&P<e,t>(x)]x[children(x)]

<e,t>

x[come(x)]x[children(x)]

x[come(x)]P<e,t>-P<e,t>x[-come(x)] x[children(x)]

= -come(x[children(x)])

= -(come(x[children(x)]))= -x[children(x)&come(x)]

not allowed in standard Montague grammar!!!

Page 65: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

65

Conclusion

> Narrow scope is always accounted for by local type-shifting and doesn’t presuppose that bare nominals always refer to kinds.

Carlson builds type-shifting into predicates.

Van Geenhoven applies local type-shifting to predicates.

Krifka applies local type-shifting to nouns.

Chierchia applies local type-shifting to nouns with a small detour via kinds.

> General constraint on covert type-shifting: apply it as locally as possible.

Page 66: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

The empirical validity of a locality constraint on type-

shifting

Page 67: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

67

Do bare nouns take wide scope?

YES!NO!

Min QueThe rest of the world

If they do, there is no reason to assume a locality constraint on type-shifting...

The answer...

English (Carlson), Spanish (Espinal and McNally 2010 and references therein), Hungarian (Farkas and de Swart 2003), Russian (Geist 2010), Albanian (Kalluli 2001), Hebrew (Doron 2003), Hindi (Dayal 2003, 2004), Mandarin Chinese (Yang 2001, Rullmann & You 2006), Indonesian (Chung 2000, Sato 2008), Javanese (Sato 2008), Turkish (Bliss 2003), Brazilian Portuguese (Schmitt & Munn 1999)

Page 68: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

68

How to go about testing scope?

> A first attempt

Every boy read a book.

a. There is a book that every boy read.

b. Every boy is such that he read a book.

Why is this not a good format for test items?

wide

narrow

Because every situation that makes a. true will also make b. true.

Page 69: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

69

How to go about testing scope?

> A better attempt

John didn’t read a (single) book.

a. There is a book that John didn’t read.

b. John read no book.

Why is this a better format for test items?

wide

narrow

Because a. can be true in situations in which b. is not true.

Page 70: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

70

A small classroom experimentDeze diagnose heeft ons doen inzien waarom hij sommige dwangideeën heeft, zoals altijd de eerste willen zijn (op de trap, in bad, aan tafel...) of woedebuien (omdat hij dingen niet begrijpt) of irrationele angsten (zoals steeds denken dat er bijen rond zoemen, terwijl het soms maar een grasmaaier is). Hoe ouder hij wordt, hij is nu bijna acht jaar, hoe duidelijker het autisme wordt.

Ik vind het absoluut niet leuk dat hij moet huilen vanwege mij. En dat is wel een aantal keren op een dag, omdat hij dingen niet mag of dat hij juist iets moet (naar bed gaan bijvoorbeeld). Ik weet dat het er bij hoort, maar leuk is anders. Nu kan ik er weer even tegen.

omdat hij dingen niet begrijpt

because he things not understand

omdat hij dingen niet mag

because he things not may

Does this necessarily mean that he doesn’t understand anything?

Does this necessarily mean that he’s not allowed to do anything?

Page 71: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

The set-up of the English experiment

Page 72: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

72

Setting-up the bare nominal test items

A.B.

A.B.

This last sentence is truth-conditionally only compatible with a wide scope reading of colleagues.

Task: judge the naturalness of the last utterance with respect to the rest of the dialogue on a scale from 0 to 5.

Rationale: subjects should not accept a continuation in which Flynn contradicts himself.

Page 73: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

73

Further design of the experiment

An experiment that would only look at the acceptability of bare nominal items would be meaningless.

Why?Because we wouldn’t know what the numbers meant.

Our baseline

Given that we were testing whether bare nominals could scope above negation, we needed an item that could not.

> Negative Polarity Items

Page 74: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

74

An example of an NPI test item

Page 75: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

75

Further design of the experiment

Experiments also need control items and fillers.

Why?

Control items are used to check whether people are actually sensitive to the phenomenon one is testing.

Our control items > Singular indefinites

Filler items are used to try to distract subjects in such a way that they don’t discover what the experiment is really about.

Our fillers > See example

Page 76: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

76

An example of a singular indefinite

Page 77: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

77

Examples of filler items

Page 78: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

78

Further design of the experiment

> Overview of the number of items:

2 NPI items2 Singular indefinite items3 Bare plural items5 Fillers

> Participants and procedure:

Questionnaire was put online. Included a number of questions that would allow us to weed out non-native speakers. Total number of relevant questionnaires: 63.

Page 79: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

Results of the English experiment

Page 80: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

80

Results: Means and SD

Page 81: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

81

Results: Means and SD

Page 82: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

82

Results: statistics

There’s a (significant) difference between the NPI items and the BP items.

There’s a (significant) difference between the BP items and the SI items.

There’s a (significant) difference between BP1 and BP2. /

Paired t-tests

Page 83: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

Conclusion of the English experiment

Page 84: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

84

Do bare nouns take wide scope?

There is ground to assume that bare nouns can take wide scope.

> This means that the general narrow scope behaviour cannot be derived solely by forcing covert type-shifting to apply locally.

> Covert type-shifting turns out to be less constrained than might seem at first sight.

Page 85: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

Questions/discussion

Page 86: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

86

General comment

Page 87: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

87

Content objection 1

Page 88: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

88

Content objection 2

Page 89: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

For those interested in contributing to the discussion

Page 90: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

90

An alternative clever way of testing

> Ionin 2010

There is a reviewer that is such that every teenager watched every movie he recommended.Every teenager is such that he watched every movie that was recommended by a reviewer.

> Remaining problem: Which item could serve as a baseline?

Page 91: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

A syntactic interludium

Page 92: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

92

Boskovic (2005)

He saw expensive cars.

*Expensive he saw cars. (English)

Expensive he saw cars. (Serbo-Croatian)

Some preliminary facts

Page 93: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

93

Boskovic (2005)

You like friends of Peter.

[Who] do you like friends of. (Eng)

[Who] do you like friends of. (SC)

Some preliminary facts

Page 94: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

94

Boskovic (2005)

Serbo-Croatian doesn’t have covert Ds whereas English does.

How does this explain the facts?

Why is this relevant for us?

the generalization

Page 95: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

95

Boskovic (2005)

PIC

Phase Impenetrability Condition:

“only the Spec of a phase is accessible for movement outside the phase”

explaining the facts

Page 96: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

96

Boskovic (2005)

XP

Spec X’

X XP

Spec X’

X XP

Spec X’

X Comp

DP

XP

Spec X’

X NP

Spec X’

X

Spec X’

X Comp

DP

XP

explaining the facts

NP

Page 97: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

97

Boskovic (2005)

Anti-Locality hypothesis

“movement shouldn’t be too short, it should at least cross a full phrasal boundary”

explaining the facts

Page 98: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

98

Boskovic (2005)

DP

Spec D’

D NP

Adjunct NP

explaining the facts

N Compl

NP

DP

Page 99: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

99

Boskovic (2005)

Serbo-Croatian doesn’t have covert Ds whereas English does.

explaining the facts

DP

Spec D’

NP

expensive NP

cars Compl

expensive NP

cars Compl

En

gli

sh

Ser

bo

-Cro

atia

n

NP

DP

Expensive he saw cars.

1. PIC

2. Anti-Loc

1. PIC

2. Anti-LocXP

NP

( )

Page 100: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

100

Boskovic (2005)

Serbo-Croatian doesn’t have covert Ds whereas English does.

explaining the facts

Spec D’

friends of John friends of John

En

gli

sh

Ser

bo

-Cro

atia

nNP

DP

Who do you like friends of.

1. PIC

2. Anti-Loc

1. PIC

2. Anti-LocXP

NP

( )

Page 101: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

101

Boskovic (2005)

If Boskovic is right there is no a priori reason for arguments to have a D projection.

This goes against Longobardi who assumes argumenthood requires the presence of a (covert or overt) D.

More in line with a type-shifting approach that does more in the semantics and less in the syntax.

relevance

Page 102: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

102

Boskovic (2005)

If you’re interested in exploring this line further, you can visit Boskovic’s website (download section). He extends the ideas developed above to a great number of languages and a great deal of different constructions.

http://web2.uconn.edu/boskovic/

remark

Page 103: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

103

Borer (2005)

Wants to pursue an alternative to type-shifting.

(i) I bought cookies.(ii) John bought ?(a) cookie.

both –s and a are countability markers; without them cookie would get a mass reading

(iii) Wo mai le quqi (Mandarin) I buy LE cookie(iv) Wo mai le yi ge quqi (Mandarin) I buy LE one CL cookie

Page 104: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

104

Borer (2005)

syntax of a (count) indefinite on its existential reading:

[DPe [#Pa e [CLa e [NPgirl]]]]

Indefinites like a in English do double duty: they function as classifiers and counters.

They don’t necessarily do triple duty though: the existential force associated with them on their existential reading comes from existential closure over the variables in the C-command domain of the verb.

No need for type-shifting!

the enterprise

Page 105: Bare coordination:  a new case for cross-linguistic availability of covert type-shifting

105

Borer (2005)

If you want to explore this line of thinking further, read Borer (2005) and make sure to complement it with Krifka (2004).

In name only ‘Bare NPs: Kind-referring, Indefinites, Both or Neither?’