2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    1/28

    Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2001. 52:1–26Copyright c 2001 by Annual Reviews. All rights reserved

    SOCIAL COGNITIVE THEORY : An AgenticPerspective

    Albert Bandura Department of Psychology, Stanford University, Stanford, California 94305-2131;e-mail: [email protected]

    Key Words biosocial coevolution, collective efcacy, emergent properties,human agency, self-efcacy

    Abstract The capacity to exercise control over the nature and quality of one’slife is the essence of humanness. Human agency is characterized by a number of core features that operate through phenomenal and functional consciousness. Theseinclude the temporal extension of agency through intentionality and forethought, self-regulation by self-reactive inuence, and self-reectiveness about one’s capabilities,quality of functioning, and the meaning and purpose of one’s life pursuits. Personalagency operates within a broad network of sociostructural inuences. In these agentictransactions, people are producers as well as products of social systems. Social cogni-tive theory distinguishes among three modes of agency: direct personal agency, proxyagency that relies on others to act on one’s behest to secure desired outcomes, andcollective agency exercised through socially coordinative and interdependent effort.Growing transnational embeddedness and interdependence are placing a premium oncollective efcacy to exercise control over personal destinies and national life.

    CONTENTS

    INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2PARADIGM SHIFTS IN PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORIZING . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2PHYSICALISTIC THEORY OF HUMAN AGENCY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4CORE FEATURES OF HUMAN AGENCY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6

    Intentionality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6Forethought . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7Self-Reactiveness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8Self-Reectiveness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10

    AGENTIC MANAGEMENT OF FORTUITY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11MODES OF HUMAN AGENCY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13UNDERMINERS OF COLLECTIVE EFFICACY

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    2/28

    2 BANDURA

    INTRODUCTION

    To be an agent is to intentionally make thingshappen by one’s actions. Agencyem-

    bodies the endowments, belief systems, self-regulatory capabilities and distributedstructures and functions through which personal inuence exercised, rather thanresiding as a discrete entity in a particular place. The core features of agency en-able people to play a part in their self-development, adaptation, and self-renewalwith changing times. Before presenting the agentic perspective of social cognitivetheory, the paradigm shifts that the eld of psychology has undergone in its shorthistory warrant a brief discussion. In these theoretical transformations, the coremetaphors have changed but for the most part, the theories grant humans little, if any, agentic capabilities.

    PARADIGM SHIFTS IN PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORIZING

    Much of theearly psychological theorizing was foundedon behavioristic principlesthat embraced an input-output model linked by an internal conduit that makesbehavior possible but exerts no inuence of its own on behavior. In this view,human behavior was shaped and controlled automatically and mechanically byenvironmental stimuli. This line of theorizing was eventually put out of vogue by

    the advent of the computer, which likened the mind to a biological calculator. Thismodel lled the internal conduit with a lot of representational and computationaloperations created by smart and inventive thinkers.

    If computers can perform cognitive operations that solve problems, regula-tive thought could no longer be denied to humans. The input-output model wassupplanted by an input-linear throughput-output model. The mind as digital com-puter became the conceptual model for the times. Although the mindless organismbecame a more cognitive one, it was still devoid of consciousness and agentic capa-bilities. For decades, the reigning computer metaphor of human functioning was a

    linear computational system in which information is fed through a central proces-sor that cranks out solutions according to preordained rules. The architecture of thelinear computer at the time dictated the conceptual model of human functioning.

    The linear model was, in turn, supplanted by more dynamically organizedcomputational models that perform multiple operations simultaneously and inter-actively to mimic better how the human brain works. In this model, environmentalinput activates a multifaceted dynamic throughput that produces the output. Thesedynamic models include multilevel neural networks with intentional functionslodged in a subpersonal executive network operating without any consciousness

    via lower subsystems. Sensory organs deliver up information to a neural network acting as the mental machinery that does the construing, planning, motivating, and

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    3/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 3

    the purposive use of information and self-regulative means to make desired thingshappen.

    Consciousness is the very substance of mental life that not only makes life

    personally manageable but worth living. A functional consciousness involvespurposive accessing and deliberative processing of information for selecting, con-structing, regulating, and evaluating courses of action. This is achieved throughintentional mobilization and productive use of semantic and pragmatic representa-tions of activities, goals, and other future events. In his discerning book on expe-rienced cognition, Carlson (1997) underscores the central role that consciousnessplays in the cognitive regulation of action and the ow of mental events. Therehave been some attempts to reduce consciousness to an epiphenomenal by-productof activities at the subpersonal level, to an executive subsystem in the informa-

    tion processing machinery, or to an attentional aspect of information processing.Like the legendary ponderous elephant that goes unnoticed, in these subpersonalaccounts of consciousness there is no experiencing person conceiving of endsand acting purposefully to attain them. However, these reductive accounts remainconceptually problematic because they omit prime features of humanness suchas subjectivity, deliberative self-guidance, and reective self-reactiveness. Forreasons to be given shortly, consciousness cannot be reduced to a nonfunctionalby-product of the outputof a mental process realized mechanically at nonconsciouslower levels. Why would an epiphenomenal consciousness that can do nothing

    evolve and endure as a reigning psychic environment in people’s lives? Without aphenomenal and functional consciousness people are essentially higher-level au-tomatons undergoing actions devoid of any subjectivity or conscious control. Nordo such beings possess a meaningful phenomenal life or a continuing self-identityderived from how they live their life and reect upon it.

    Green & Vervaeke (1996) observed that originally many connectionists andcomputationalists regarded their conceptual models as approximations of cogni-tive activities. More recently, however, somehave become eliminative materialists,likening cognitive factors to the phlogiston of yesteryear. In this view, people do

    not act on beliefs, goals, aspirations, and expectations. Rather, activation of theirnetwork structure at a subpersonal level makes them do things. In a critique of eliminativism, Greenwood (1992) notes that cognitions are contentful psycho-logical factors whose meaning does not depend on the explanatory propositionsin which they gure. Phlogiston neither had any evidential basis nor explana-tory or predictive value. In contrast, cognitive factors do quite well in predictinghuman behavior and guiding effective interventions. To make their way success-fully through a complex world full of challenges and hazards, people have to makegood judgments about their capabilities, anticipate the probable effects of different

    events and courses of action, size up sociostructural opportunities and constraints,and regulate their behavior accordingly. These belief systems are a working model

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    4/28

    4 BANDURA

    and of demonstrated functional value may be translatable and modeled in anothertheoretical language but not eliminatable (Rottschaefer 1985, 1991).

    PHYSICALISTIC THEORY OF HUMAN AGENCY

    As has already been noted, people are not just onlooking hosts of internal mecha-nisms orchestrated by environmental events. They are agents of experiences ratherthan simply undergoers of experiences. The sensory, motor, and cerebral systemsare tools people use to accomplish the tasks and goals that give meaning, direction,and satisfaction to their lives (Bandura 1997, Harr´ e & Gillet 1994).

    Research on brain development underscores the inuential role that agentic

    action plays in shaping theneuronal and functional structure of thebrain (Diamond1988, Kolb & Whishaw 1998). It is not just exposure to stimulation, but agenticaction in exploring, manipulating, and inuencing the environment that counts.By regulating their motivation and activities, people produce the experiences thatform the functional neurobiological substrate of symbolic, social, psychomotor,and other skills. The nature of these experiences is, of course, heavily dependenton the types of social and physical environments people select and construct.An agentic perspective fosters lines of research that provide new insights intothe social construction of the functional structure of the human brain (Eisenberg

    1995). This is a realm of inquiry in which psychology can make fundamentalunique contributions to the biopsychosocial understanding of human development,adaptation, and change.

    Social cognitive theory subscribes to a model of emergent interactive agency(Bandura 1986, 1999a). Thoughts are not disembodied, immaterial entities thatexist apart from neural events. Cognitive processes are emergent brain activitiesthat exert determinative inuence. Emergent properties differ qualitatively fromtheir constituent elements and therefore are not reducible to them. To use Bunge’s(1977) analogy, the unique emergent properties of water, such as uidity, viscosity,

    and transparency are not simply the aggregate properties of its microcomponentsof oxygen and hydrogen. Through their interactive effects they are transformedinto new phenomena.

    One must distinguish between the physical basis of thought and its deliberativeconstruction and functional use. The human mind is generative, creative, proac-tive, and reective, not just reactive. The dignied burial of the dualistic Descartesforces us to address the formidable explanatory challenge for a physicalistic the-ory of human agency and a nondualistic cognitivism. How do people operate asthinkers of the thoughts that exert determinative inuence on their actions? What

    are the functional circuitries of forethought, planful proaction, aspiration, self-appraisal, and self-reection? Even more important, how are they intentionally

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    5/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 5

    can designedly conceive unique events and different novel courses of action andchoose to execute one of them. Under the indenite prompt to concoct somethingnew, for example, one can deliberatively construct a whimsically novel scenario

    of a graceful hippopotamus attired in a chartreuse tuxedo hang gliding over lunarcraters while singing the mad scene from the opera Lucia di Lammermoor . In-tentionality and agency raise the fundamental question of how people bring aboutactivities over which they command personal control that activate the subpersonalneurophysiological events for realizing particular intentions and aspirations. Thus,in acting on the well-grounded belief that exercise enhances health, individualsget themselves to perform physical activities that produce health promotive bio-logical events without observing or knowing how the activated events work at thesubpersonal level. The health outcome is the product of both agent causality and

    event causality, operating at different phases of the sequence.Our psychological discipline is proceeding down two major divergent routes.

    One line of theorizing seeks to clarify the basic mechanisms governing humanfunctioning. This line of inquiry centers heavily on microanalyses of the innerworkings of the mind in processing, representing, retrieving, and using the codedinformation to manage various task demands, and locating where the brain activityfor these events occurs. These cognitive processes are generally studied disembod-ied from interpersonal life, purposeful pursuits, and self-reectiveness. People aresentient, purposivebeings. Faced with prescribed task demands, they actmindfully

    to make desired things happen rather than simply undergo happenings in whichsituational forces activate their subpersonal structures that generate solutions. Inexperimental situations, participants try to gure out what is wanted of them;they construct hypotheses and reectively test their adequacy by evaluating theresults of their actions; they set personal goals and otherwise motivate themselvesto perform in ways that please or impress others or bring self-satisfaction; whenthey run into trouble they engage in self-enabling or self-debilitating self-talk;if they construe their failures as presenting surmountable challenges they redoubletheir efforts, but they drive themselves to despondency if they read their failures

    as indicants of personal deciencies; if they believe they are being exploited, co-erced, disrespected, or manipulated, they respond apathetically, oppositionally,or hostilely. These motivational and other self-regulative factors that govern themanner and level of personal engagement in prescribed activities are simply takenfor granted in cognitive science rather than included in causal structures (Carlson1997).

    The second line of theorizing centers on the macroanalytic workings of so-cially situated factors in human development, adaptation, and change. Within thistheoretical framework, human functioning is analyzed as socially interdependent,

    richly contextualized, and conditionally orchestrated within the dynamics of var-ious societal subsystems and their complex interplay. The mechanisms linking

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    6/28

    6 BANDURA

    In the paths of inuence, sociostructural inuences operate through psychologicalmechanisms to produce behavioral effects. We shall return later to this issue andto the bidirectionality of inuence between social structure and personal agency.

    CORE FEATURES OF HUMAN AGENCY

    The core features of personal agency address the issue of what it means to behuman. The main agentic features are discussed in the sections that follow.

    Intentionality Agency refers to acts done intentionally. For example, a person who smashed

    a vase in an antique shop upon being tripped by another shopper would not beconsidered the agent of the event. Human transactions, of course, involve situa-tional inducements, but they do not operate as determinate forces. Individuals canchoose to behave accommodatively or, through the exercise of self-inuence, tobehave otherwise. An intention is a representation of a future course of action tobe performed. It is not simply an expectation or prediction of future actions but aproactive commitment to bringing them about. Intentions and actions are differentaspects of a functional relation separated in time. It is, therefore, meaningful tospeak of intentions grounded in self-motivators affecting the likelihood of actions

    at a future point in time.Planning agency can be used to produce different outcomes. Outcomes are

    not the characteristics of agentive acts; they are the consequences of them. AsDavidson (1971) explains, actions intended to serve a certain purpose can causequite different things to happen. He cites the example of the melancholic Hamlet,who intentionally stabbed the man behind a tapestry believing it to be the king,only to discover, much to his horror, that he had killed Polonius. The killing of the hidden person was intentional, but the wrong victim was done in. Some of the actions performed in the belief that they will bring desired outcomes actually

    produce outcomes that were neither intended nor wanted. For example, it is notuncommon for individuals to contribute to their own misery through intentionaltransgressive acts spawned by gross miscalculation of consequences. Some socialpolicies and practices originally designed with well-meaning intent turn out badbecause their harmful effects were unforeseen. In short, the power to originateactions for given purposes is the key feature of personal agency. Whether the ex-ercise of that agency has benecial or detrimental effects, or produces unintendedconsequences, is another matter.

    Intentions center on plans of action. Future-directed plans are rarely speci-

    ed in full detail at the outset. It would require omniscience to anticipate everysituational detail. Moreover, turning visualized futurities into reality requires

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    7/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 7

    rened or even reconsidered in the face of new information during execution of an intention. We shall see shortly, however, that realization of forward look-ing plans requires more than an intentional state because it is not causally suf-

    cient by itself. Other self-regulatory aspects of agency enter into the successfulimplementation of intentions. To add a further functional dimension to inten-tion, most human pursuits involve other participating agents. Such joint activi-ties require commitment to a shared intention and coordination of interdependentplans of action. The challenge in collaborative activities is to meld diverse self-interests in the service of common goals and intentions collectively pursued inconcert.

    ForethoughtThe temporal extension of agency goes beyond forward-directed planning. Thefuture time perspective manifests itself in many different ways. People set goalsfor themselves, anticipate the likely consequences of prospective actions, andselect and create courses of action likely to produce desired outcomes and avoiddetrimental ones (Bandura 1991b, Feather 1982, Locke & Latham 1990). Throughthe exercise of forethought, people motivate themselves and guide their actions inanticipation of future events. When projected over a long time course on mattersof value, a forethoughtful perspective provides direction, coherence, and meaning

    to one’s life. As people progress in their life course they continue to plan ahead,reorder their priorities, and structure their lives accordingly.

    Future events cannot, of course, be causes of current motivation and actionbecause they have no actual existence. However, by being represented cognitivelyin the present, foreseeable future events are converted into current motivators andregulators of behavior. In this form of anticipatory self-guidance, behavior ismotivated and directed by projected goals and anticipated outcomes rather thanbeing pulled by an unrealized future state.

    People construct outcome expectations from observed conditional relations be-

    tween environmental events in the world around them, and the outcomes givenactions produce (Bandura 1986). The ability to bring anticipated outcomes to bearon current activities promotes foresightful behavior. It enables people to tran-scend the dictates of their immediate environment and to shape and regulate thepresent to t a desired future. In regulating their behavior by outcome expecta-tions, people adopt courses of action that are likely to produce positive outcomesand generally discard those that bring unrewarding or punishing outcomes. How-ever, anticipated material and social outcomes are not the only kind of incentivesthat inuence human behavior, as a crude functionalism would suggest. If actions

    were performed only on behalf of anticipated external rewards and punishments,people would behave like weather vanes, constantly shifting direction to con-

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    8/28

    8 BANDURA

    self-evaluative outcomes, which may augment or override the inuence of externaloutcomes.

    Self-ReactivenessAn agent has to be not only a planner and forethinker, but a motivator and self-regulator as well. Having adopted an intention and an action plan, one cannotsimply sit back and wait for the appropriate performances to appear. Agencythus involves not only the deliberative ability to make choices and action plans,but the ability to give shape to appropriate courses of action and to motivate andregulate their execution. Thismultifaceted self-directedness operates through self-regulatory processes that link thought to action. The self-regulation of motivation,

    affect, and action is governed by a set of self-referent subfunctions. These includeself-monitoring, performance self-guidance via personal standards, and correctiveself-reactions (Bandura 1986, 1991b).

    Monitoring one’s pattern of behavior and the cognitive and environmental con-ditions under which it occurs is the rst step toward doing something to affectit. Actions give rise to self-reactive inuence through performance comparisonwith personal goals and standards. Goals, rooted in a value system and a sense of personal identity, invest activities with meaning and purpose. Goals motivate byenlisting self-evaluative engagement in activities rather than directly. By making

    self-evaluation conditional on matching personal standards, people give directionto their pursuits and create self-incentives to sustain their efforts for goal attain-ment. They do things that give them self-satisfaction and a sense of pride andself-worth, and refrain from behaving in ways that give rise to self-dissatisfaction,self-devaluation, and self-censure.

    Goals do not automatically activate the self-inuences that govern motivationand action. Evaluative self-engagement through goal setting is affected by thecharacteristics of goals, namely, their specicity, level of challenge and tempo-ral proximity. General goals are too indenite and noncommitting to serve as

    guides and incentives. Strong interest and engrossment in activities is sparkedby challenging goals. The self-regulative effectiveness of goals depends greatlyon how far into the future they are projected. Proximal subgoals mobilize self-inuences and direct what one does in the here and now. Distal goals alone setthe general course of pursuits but are too far removed in time to provide effectiveincentives and guides for present action, given inviting competing activities athand. Progress toward valued futures is best achieved by hierarchically structuredgoal systems combining distal aspirations with proximal self-guidance. Goals em-bodying self-engaging properties serve as powerful motivators of action (Bandura

    1991b, Locke & Latham 1990).Moral agency forms an important part of self-directedness. Psychological the-

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    9/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 9

    through self-regulatory mechanisms, which include moral judgment of the right-ness or wrongness of conduct evaluated against personal standards and situationalcircumstances, and self-sanctions by which moral agency is exercised (Bandura

    1991a).In competency development and aspirational pursuits, the personal standards of

    merit are progressively raised as knowledge and competencies are expanded andchallenges are met. In social and moral conduct, the self-regulatory standards aremore stable. People do not change from week to week what they regard as rightor wrong or good or bad. After people adopt a standard of morality, their negativeself-sanctions for actions that violate their personal standards, and their positiveself-sanctions for conduct faithful to their moral standards serve as the regulatoryinuences (Bandura 1991b). The capacity for self-sanctions gives meaning to

    moral agency. The anticipatory evaluative self-reactions provide the motivationalas well as the cognitive regulators of moral conduct. Self-sanctions keep conductin line with personal standards. Individuals with a strong communal ethic will actto further the welfare of others even at costs to their self-interest. In the face of situational pressures to behave inhumanely, people can choose to behave other-wise by exerting counteracting self-inuence. It is not uncommon for individualsto invest their self-worth so strongly in certain convictions that they will submitto harsh and punitive treatment rather than cede to what they regard as unjust orimmoral.

    The exercise of moral agency has dual aspects—inhibitive and proactive(Bandura 1999b). The inhibitive form is manifested in the power to refrain frombehaving inhumanely. The proactive form of morality is expressed in the powerto behave humanely.

    Moral standards do not function as xed internal regulators of conduct, how-ever. Self-regulatory mechanisms do not operate unless they are enlisted in givenactivities. There are many psychosocial maneuvers by which moral self-reactionscan be selectively disengaged from inhumane conduct (Bandura 1991b). Severalof these mechanisms of moral disengagement center on the cognitive reconstrual

    of the conduct itself. This is achieved by making harmful conduct personally andsocially acceptable by portraying it as serving socially worthy or moral purposes,masking it in sanitizing euphemistic language, and creating exonerating compar-ison with worse inhumanities. Other mechanisms reduce the sense of personalagency for harmful conduct through diffusion and displacement of responsibility.Moral self-sanctions are also weakened or disengaged at the outcome locus of the control process by ignoring, minimizing, or disputing the injurious effects of one’s conduct. The nal set of practices disengage restraining self-sanctions bydehumanizing the victims, attributing bestial qualities to them, and blaming them

    for bringing the suffering on themselves. High moral disengagers experience lowguilt over harmful conduct, are less prosocial, and are more prone to vengeful

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    10/28

    10 BANDURA

    Self-ReectivenessPeople are not only agents of action but self-examiners of their own functioning.The metacognitive capability to reect upon oneself and the adequacy of one’sthoughts and actions is another distinctly core human feature of agency. Throughreective self-consciousness, people evaluate their motivation, values, and themeaning of their life pursuits. It is at this higher level of self-reectiveness thatindividualsaddress conicts in motivational inducements and choose to act in favorof one over another. Verication of the soundness of one’s thinking also reliesheavily on self-reective means (Bandura 1986). In this metacognitive activity,people judge the correctness of their predictive and operative thinking againstthe outcomes of their actions, the effects that other people’s actions produce,

    what others believe, deductions from established knowledge and what necessarilyfollows from it.Among the mechanisms of personal agency, none is more central or pervasive

    than people’s beliefs in their capability to exercise some measure of control overtheir own functioning and over environmental events (Bandura 1997). Efcacybeliefs are the foundation of human agency. Unless people believe they can pro-duce desired results and forestall detrimental ones by their actions, they have littleincentive to act or to persevere in the face of difculties. Whatever other factorsmay operate as guides and motivators, they are rooted in the core belief that one

    has the power to produce effects by one’s actions. Meta-analyses attest to theinuential role played by efcacy beliefs in human functioning (Holden 1991,Holden et al 1990, Multon et al 1991, Stajkovic & Luthans 1998).

    Perceived self-efcacy occupies a pivotal role in the causal structure of socialcognitive theory because efcacy beliefs affect adaptation and change not only intheir own right, but through their impact on other determinants (Bandura 1997,Maddux 1995; Schwarzer 1992). Such beliefs inuence whether people think pes-simistically or optimistically and in ways that are self-enhancing or self-hindering.Efcacy beliefs play a central role in the self-regulation of motivation through goal

    challenges and outcome expectations. It is partly on the basis of efcacy beliefsthat people choose what challenges to undertake, how much effort to expend in theendeavor, how long to persevere in the face of obstacles and failures, and whetherfailures are motivating or demoralizing. The likelihood that people will act on theoutcomes they expect prospective performances to produce depends on their be-liefs about whether or not they can produce those performances. A strong sense of coping efcacy reduces vulnerability to stress and depression in taxing situationsand strengthens resiliency to adversity.

    Efcacy beliefs also play a key role in shaping thecourses lives take by inuenc-

    ing the types of activities and environments people choose to get into. Any factorthat inuences choice behavior can profoundly affect the direction of personalde elopment This is beca se the social in ences operating in selected en i

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    11/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 11

    choosing and shaping their environments, people can have a hand in what theybecome.

    The rapid pace of informational, social, and technological change is placing

    a premium on personal efcacy for self-development and self-renewal through-out the life course. In the past, students’ educational development was largelydetermined by the schools to which they were assigned. Nowadays, the Internetprovides vast opportunities for students to control their own learning. They nowhave the best libraries, museums, laboratories, and instructors at their ngertips,unrestricted by time and place. Good self-regulators expand their knowledge andcognitive competencies; poor self-regulators fall behind (Zimmerman 1990).

    Self-regulation is also becoming a key factor in occupational life. In the past,employees learned a given trade and performed it much the same way and in the

    same organization throughout their lifetime. With the fast pace of change, knowl-edge and technical skills are quickly outmoded unless they are updated to t thenew technologies. In the modern workplace, workers have to take charge of theirself-development for a variety of positions and careers over the full course of theirworklife. They have to cultivate multiple competencies to meet the ever-changingoccupational demands and roles. Collective agentic adaptability applies at theorganizational level as well as the workforce level. Organizations have to be fastlearners and continuously innovative to survive and prosper under rapidly chang-ing technologies and global marketplaces. They face the paradox of preparing for

    change at the height of success. Slow changers become big losers.Health illustrates self-regulation in another important sphere of life. In recent

    years, there has been a major change in the conception of health from a diseasemodel to a health model. Human health is heavily inuenced by lifestyle habitsand environmental conditions. This enables people to exercise some measureof control over their health status. Indeed, through self-management of healthhabits people reduce major health risks and live healthier and more productivelives (Bandura 1997). If the huge health benets of these few lifestyle habits wereput into a pill, it would be declared a spectacular breakthrough in the eld of

    medicine.

    AGENTIC MANAGEMENT OF FORTUITY

    There is much that people do designedly to exercise some measure of control overtheir self-development and life circumstances, but there is also a lot of fortuity inthe courses lives take. Indeed, some of the most important determinants of lifepaths occur through the most trivial of circumstances. People areoften inaugurated

    into new developmental trajectories, marital partnerships, occupational careers, oruntoward life paths through fortuitous circumstances. Consider the inuence of

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    12/28

    12 BANDURA

    happening eventuates in a marriage, geographic relocation, and a shift in careertrajectories, none of which would have occurred if the original ight had not beengrounded by a sudden storm (Krantz 1998). A book editor enters a lecture hall as

    it was rapidly lling up, for a talk on the “Psychology of Chance Encounters andLife Paths.” He seizes an empty chair near the entrance. Some months later, hemarries the woman he happened to sit next to. With only a momentary change inentry, seating constellations would have altered, and their lives would have takenquite different courses. A marital partnership was formed fortuitously at a talk devoted to fortuitous determinants of life paths (Bandura 1982)!

    A fortuitous event in socially mediated happenstances is dened as an unin-tendedmeetingof persons unfamiliar with each other. Although theseparatechainsof events in a chance encounter have their own determinants, their intersection oc-

    curs fortuitously rather than by design (Nagel 1961). It is not that a fortuitouseventis uncaused but, rather, there is a lot of randomness to the determining conditionsof its intersection. Of the myriad fortuitous elements encountered in everyday life,many of them touch people only lightly, others leave more lasting effects, andstill others thrust people into new life trajectories. The power of most fortuitousinuences lies not so much in the properties of the events themselves, but in theconstellation of transactional inuences they set in motion (Bandura 1982, 1998).On the personal side, people’s attributes, belief systems, interests, and compe-tencies inuence whether or not a given chance encounter gets converted into a

    lasting relationship. On the social side, the impact of fortuitous encounters partlydepends on the holding and molding power of the social milieus into which peopleare fortuitously inaugurated.

    Fortuity does not mean uncontrollability of its effects. There are ways peoplecan capitalize on the fortuitous character of life. They can make chance happen bypursuingan active life that increases the level and type of fortuitousencounters theywill experience. Chance favors the inquisitive and venturesome who go places, dothings, and explore new activities (Austin 1978). People also make chance work for them by cultivating their interests, enabling self-beliefs and competencies.

    These personal resources enable them to make the most of opportunities that ariseunexpectedly from time to time. Pasteur (1854) put it well when he noted that“chance favors only the prepared mind.” Self-development gives people a greaterhand in shaping their destiny in the life paths they travel. These various proactiveactivities illustrate the agentic management of fortuity.

    Fortuitous factors receive little notice in causal analyses of developmental tra- jectories, but they gure prominently in prescriptions for realizing valued futuresand safeguarding against detrimental ones (Bandura 1995, 1997; Hamburg 1992;Masten et al 1990; Rutter 1990). On the self-development side, the efforts center

    on cultivatingpersonal resources that enable individuals to exploit promising fortu-ities. On the safeguarding side, individuals are helped to expand the self-regulative

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    13/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 13

    MODES OF HUMAN AGENCY

    Theorizing andresearch on human agency hasbeen essentially conned to personal

    agency exercised individually. However, this is not the only way in which peoplebring their inuence to bear on events that affect how they live their lives. Socialcognitive theory distinguishes among three different modes of human agency:personal, proxy, and collective.

    The preceding analyses centered on the nature of direct personal agency andthe cognitive, motivational, affective, and choice processes through which it isexercised to produce given effects. In many spheres of functioning, people do nothave direct control over the social conditions and institutional practices that affecttheir everyday lives. Under these circumstances, they seek their well-being, secu-

    rity, and valued outcomes through the exercise of proxy agency. In this sociallymediated mode of agency, people try by one means or another to get those whohave access to resources or expertise or who wield inuence and power to act attheir behest to secure the outcomes they desire. No one has the time, energy, andresources to master every realm of everyday life. Successful functioning neces-sarily involves a blend of reliance on proxy agency in some areas of functioningto free time and effort to manage directly other aspects of one’s life (Baltes 1996,Brandtst ädter 1992). For example, children turn to parents, marital partners tospouses, and citizens to their legislative representatives to act for them. Proxy

    agency relies heavily on perceived social efcacy for enlisting the mediativeefforts of others.

    People also turn to proxycontrol in areas in which they can exert direct inuencewhen they have not developed the means to do so, they believe others can do itbetter, or they do not want to saddle themselves with the burdensome aspects thatdirect control entails. Personal control is neither an inherent drive nor universallydesired, as is commonly claimed. There is an onerous side to direct personalcontrol that can dull the appetite for it. The exercise of effective control requiresmastery of knowledge and skills attainable only through long hours of arduouswork. Moreover, maintaining prociency under the ever-changing conditions of life demands continued investment of time, effort, and resources in self-renewal.

    In addition to the hard work of continual self-development, the exercise of per-sonal control often carries heavy responsibilities, stressors, and risks. People arenot especially eager to shoulder the burdens of responsibility. All too often, theysurrender control to intermediaries in activities over which they can commanddirect inuence. They do so to free themselves of the performance demands andonerous responsibilities that personal control entails. Proxy agency can be used inways that promote self-development or impede the cultivation of personal compe-tencies. In the latter case, part of the price of proxy agency is a vulnerable securitythat rests on the competence, power, and favors of others.

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    14/28

    14 BANDURA

    Social cognitive theory extends the conception of human agency to collectiveagency (Bandura 1997). People’s shared belief in their collective power to pro-duce desired results is a key ingredient of collective agency. Group attainments are

    the product not only of the shared intentions, knowledge, and skills of its members,but also of the interactive, coordinated, and synergistic dynamics of their transac-tions. Because the collective performance of a social system involves transactionaldynamics, perceived collective efcacy is an emergent group-level property, notsimply the sum of the efcacy beliefs of individual members. However, there isno emergent entity that operates independently of the beliefs and actions of theindividuals who make up a social system. It is people acting conjointly on a sharedbelief, nota disembodied groupmind that is doing the cognizing, aspiring, motivat-ing, and regulating. Beliefs of collective efcacy serve functions similar to those

    of personal efcacy beliefs and operate through similar processes (Bandura 1997).Evidence from diverse lines of research attests to the impact of perceived col-

    lective efcacy on group functioning (Bandura 2000). Some of these studies haveassessed the effects of perceived collective efcacy instilled experimentally to dif-ferential levels. Other studies have examined the effects of naturally developedbeliefs of collective efcacy on the functioning of diverse social systems, includingeducational systems, business organizations, athletic teams, combat teams, urbanneighborhoods, and political action groups. The ndings taken as a whole showthat the stronger the perceived collective efcacy, the higher the groups’ aspirations

    and motivational investment in their undertakings, the stronger their staying powerin the face of impediments and setbacks, the higher their morale and resilience tostressors, and the greater their performance accomplishments.

    Theorizing about human agencyandcollectivities is replete with contentious du-alisms that social cognitive theory rejects. These dualities include personal agencyversus social structure, self-centered agency versus communality, and individu-alism verses collectivism. The agency-sociostructural duality pits psychologicaltheories and sociostructural theories as rival conceptions of human behavior or asrepresenting different levels and temporal proximity of causation. Human func-

    tioning is rooted in social systems. Therefore, personal agency operates within abroad network of sociostructural inuences. For the most part, social structuresrepresent authorized systems of rules, social practices, and sanctions designed toregulate human affairs. These sociostructural functions are carried out by humanbeings occupying authorized roles (Giddens 1984).

    Within the rule structures of social systems, there is a lot of personal varia-tion in their interpretation, enforcement, adoption, circumvention, and even activeopposition (Burns & Dietz 2000). These transactions do not involve a duality be-tween a reied social structure disembodied from people and personal agency,

    but a dynamic interplay between individuals and those who preside over theinstitutionalized operations of social systems. Social cognitive theory explains

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    15/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 15

    all operate as interacting determinants that inuence one another bidirectionally.The environment is not a monolithic entity. Social cognitive theory distinguishesbetween three types of environmental structures (Bandura 1997). They include the

    imposed environment, selected environment, and constructed environment. Thesedifferent environmental structures represent gradations of changeability requiringthe exercise of differing scope and focus of personal agency.

    In social cognitive theory, sociostructural factors operate through psychologicalmechanisms of the self system to produce behavioral effects. Thus, for example,economic conditions, socioeconomic status, and educational and family struc-tures affect behavior largely through their impact on people’s aspirations, sense of efcacy, personal standards, affective states, and other self-regulatory inuences,rather than directly (Baldwin et al 1989; Bandura 1993; Bandura et al 1996a,

    2000a; Elder & Ardelt 1992). Nor can sociostructural and psychological deter-minants be dichotomized neatly into remote and proximate inuences. Poverty,indexed as low socioeconomic status, is not a matter of multilayered or distal cau-sation. Lacking the money to provide for the subsistence of one’s family impingespervasively on everyday life in a very proximal way. Multicausality involves code-termination of behavior by different sources of inuence, not causal dependenciesbetween levels.

    The self system is not merely a conduit for sociostructural inuences. Althoughthe self is socially constituted, by exercising self-inuence human agents operate

    generatively and proactively, not just reactively, to shape the character of their so-cial systems. In these agentic transactions, people are producers aswell as productsof social systems. Personal agency and social structure operate interdependently.Social structures are created by human activity, and sociostructural practices, inturn, impose constraints and provide enabling resources and opportunity structuresfor personal development and functioning.

    Another disputable duality inappropriately equates self-efcacy with self-centered individualism feeding selshness, and then pits it against communalattachments and civic responsibility. A sense of efcacy does not necessarily

    exalt the self or spawn an individualistic lifestyle, identity, or morality that slightscollective welfare. Through unwavering exercise of commanding self-efcacy,Gandhi mobilized a massive collective force that brought about major sociopo-litical changes. He lived ascetically, not self-indulgently. If belief in the powerto produce results is put in the service of relational goals and benecial socialpurposes, it fosters a communal life rather than eroding it. Indeed, developmentalstudies show that a high sense of efcacy promotes a prosocial orientation charac-terized by cooperativeness, helpfulness, and sharing, with a vested interest in eachother’s welfare (Bandura et al 1996a, Bandura et al 1999, 2000b).

    Another dualistic antithesis inappropriately equates self-efcacy with individ-ualism and pits it against collectivism at a cultural level (Schooler 1990). Cultures

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    16/28

    16 BANDURA

    individualistic and collectivistic sociocultural systems come in a variety of forms(Kim et al 1994). There is substantial generational and socioeconomic hetero-geneity in communality among individuals in different cultural systems, and even

    greater intraindividual variation across social relationships with family members,friends, and colleagues (Matsumoto et al 1996). Moreover, people express theircultural orientations conditionally rather than invariantly, behaving communallyunder some incentive structures and individualistically under others (Yamagishi1988). Bicultural contrasts, in which individuals from a single collectivistic localeare compared on global indices to individuals from a single individualistic one,can spawn a lot of misleading generalizations.

    Ifpeople are to pool their resources and work together successfully, the membersof a group have to perform their roles and coordinated activities with a high sense

    of efcacy. One cannot achieve an efcacious collectivity with members whoapproach life consumed by nagging self-doubts about their ability to succeed andtheir staying power in the face of difculties. Personal efcacy is valued, notbecause of reverence for individualism, but because a strong sense of efcacy isvital for successful functioning regardless of whether it is achieved individually orby group members working together. Indeed, a strong sense of personal efcacy tomanage one’s life circumstances and to have a hand in effecting societal changescontributes substantially to perceived collective efcacy (Fern´ andez-Ballesteroset al 2000).

    Cross-cultural research attests to the general functional value of efcacy beliefs.Perceived personal efcacy contributes to productive functioning by members of collectivistic cultures just as it does to functioning by people raised in individ-ualistic cultures (Earley 1993, 1994). However, cultural embeddedness shapesthe ways in which efcacy beliefs are developed, the purposes to which they areput, and the sociostructural arrangements through which they are best exercised.People from individualistic cultures feel most efcacious and perform best underan individually oriented system, whereas those from collectivistic cultures judgethemselves most efcacious and work most productively under a group-oriented

    system. A low sense of coping efcacy is as stressful in collectivisitic cultures asin individualistic ones (Matsui & Onglatco 1991).

    There are collectivists in individualistic cultures and individualists in collec-tivistic cultures. Regardless of cultural background, people achieve the greatestpersonal efcacy and productivity when their psychological orientation is congru-ent with the structure of the social system (Earley 1994). Both at the societal andindividual level of analysis, a strong perceived efcacy fosters high group effortand performance attainments.

    Cultures are no longer insular. Transnational interdependencies and global eco-

    nomic forces are weakening social and cultural normative systems, restructuringnational economies and shaping the political and social life of societies (Keohane

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    17/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 17

    what happens economically and politically in one part of the world can affect thewelfare of vast populations elsewhere. Moreover, advanced telecommunicationstechnologies are disseminating ideas, values and styles of behavior transnationally

    at an unprecedented rate. The symbolic environment feeding off communicationsatellites is altering national cultures and homogenizing collective consciousness.With further development of the cyberworld, people will be even more heavily em-bedded in global symbolic environments. In addition, mass migrations of peopleare changing cultural landscapes. This growing ethnic diversity accords functionalvalue to bicultural efcacy to navigate the demands of both one’s ethnic subcultureand that of the larger society.

    These new realities call for broadening the scope of cross-cultural analysesbeyond the focus on the social forces operating within the boundaries of given so-

    cieties to the forces impinging upon them from abroad. With growing internationalembeddedness and interdependence of societies, and enmeshment in the Internetsymbolic culture, the issues of interest center on how national and global forces in-teract to shape the nature of cultural life. As globalization reaches ever deeper intopeople’s lives, a strong sense of collective efcacy to make transnational systemswork for them becomes critical to furthering their common interests.

    UNDERMINERS OF COLLECTIVE EFFICACY

    IN CHANGING SOCIETIESThe revolutionary advances in electronic technologies have transformed the na-ture, reach, and loci of human inuence. These new social realities provide vastopportunities for people to bring their inuence to bear on their personal devel-opment and to shape their social future. However, many of the contemporaryconditions of life undermine the development and maintenance of collective ef-cacy. Distal transnational inuences have wide-ranging consequential local effectson people’s lives. These transnational forces are hard to disentangle, let alone con-

    trol. They challenge the efcacy of governmental systems to exert a determininginuence on their own economic and national life. As the need for efcaciouscollective civic action grows, so does the sense of collective powerlessness. Un-der the new realities of growing transnational control, nation states increase theircontrolling leverage by merging into larger regional units such as the EuropeanUnion. However, these regional marriages do not come without a price. Paradox-ically, to gain international control, nations have to negotiate reciprocal pacts thatrequire some loss of national autonomy and changes in traditional ways of life(Keohane 1993).

    Everyday life is increasingly regulated by complex technologies that mostpeople neither understand nor believe they can do much to inuence. The very

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    18/28

    18 BANDURA

    sociostructural practices wield their inuence to maintain their vested interests.Long delays between action and noticeable results further discourage efforts atsocially signicant changes. In the metaphoric words of John Gardner, “Getting

    things done socially is no sport for the short-winded.”Social efforts to change lives for the better require merging diverse self-interests

    in support of common core values and goals. Recent years have witnessed growingsocial fragmentation into separate interest groups, each exing its own factionalefcacy. Pluralism is taking the form of militant factionalism. As a result, peopleare exercising greater factional inuence but achieving less collectively becauseof mutual immobilization. In addition, mass migration can further contribute tosocial fragmentation. Societies are thus becoming more diverse and harder to unitearound a national vision and purpose.

    The magnitude of human problems also undermines perceived efcacy to ndeffective solutions for them. Worldwide problems of growing magnitude instilla sense of paralysis that there is little people can do to reduce such problems.Global effects are the products of local actions. The strategy of “Think globally,act locally” is an effort to restore in people a sense of efcacy that they can make adifference. Macrosocialapplicationsof sociocognitive principles via the electronicmedia illustrate how small collective efforts can have substantial impact on suchurgent global problems as soaring population growth (Bandura 1997, Singhal &Rogers 1999).

    EMERGING PRIMACY OF HUMAN AGENCYIN BIOSOCIAL COEVOLUTION

    There is growing unease about progressive divestiture of different aspects of psy-chology to biology. Biological determinants of human behavior are being widelyheralded, and psychosocial dynamics are being downgraded for neurodynamics.It is feared that as we give away more and more psychology to disciplines lower

    down on the food chain, there will be no core psychological discipline left. Dis-ciplinary fragmentation, dispersion, and absorption in neuroscience, we are told,may be our discipline’s destiny. Contrary to the proclamations of the divestitiveoracles, psychology is the one discipline that uniquely encompasses the complexinterplay between intrapersonal, biological, interpersonal, and sociostructural de-terminants of human functioning. Psychology is, therefore, best suited to advanceunderstanding of the integrated biopsychosocial nature of humans and how theymanage and shape the everyday world around them. It is ironic that an integrativecore discipline, which deals with the whole person acting in and on environments,

    should consider fractionating and farming out subpersonal parts to other disci-plines. The eld of psychology should be articulating a broad vision of human

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    19/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 19

    events are brain activities, but physicality does not imply reduction of psychologyto biology. Knowing how the biological machinery works tells one little abouthow to orchestrate that machinery for diverse purposes. To use an analogy, the

    “psychosocial software” is not reducible to the “biological hardware.” Each isgoverned by its own set of principles that must be studied in their own right.

    Much of psychology is concerned with discovering principles about how tostructure environments to promote given psychosocial changes and levels of func-tioning. This exogenoussubject matter does nothave a counterpart in neurobiolog-ical theory and, hence, psychological laws are not derivable from it. For example,knowledge of the locality and brain circuitry subserving learning can say littleabout how best to devise conditions of learning in terms of level of abstractness,novelty, and challenge; how to provide incentives to get people to attend to, pro-

    cess, and organize relevant information; in what modes to present information; andwhether learning is better achieved independently, cooperatively, or competitively.The optimal conditions must be specied by psychological principles.

    Mapping the activation of the neuronal circuitry subserving Martin LutherKing’s “I Have a Dream” speech would tell us little about its powerful sociallyinspirational nature, the agentic deliberative effort that went into its creation, andthe civic-minded passion that energized its origination and public declaration. Norwill analyses at the molecular, cellular, and biochemical levels explain these agen-tic activities. There is little at the neuronal level that can tell us how to develop

    efcacious parents, teachers, executives, or social reformers.Psychological principles cannot violate the neurophysiological capabilities of

    the systems that subserve them. However, the psychological principles need to bepursued in their own right. Were one to embark on the slippery slope of reduc-tionism, the journey would traverse biology and chemistry and eventually end inatomic subparticles. Because of emergent properties across levels of complexity,neither the intermediate locales nor the nal stop in atomic subparticles supply thepsychological laws of human behavior.

    The biologizing of psychology, which lately has become highly fashionable,

    is also being promoted by uncritical adoption of one-sided evolutionism. Notto be outdone, the geneticization of human behavior is being promoted morefervently by psychological evolutionists than by biological evolutionists (Buss& Schmitt 1993, Bussey & Bandura 1999). In these analyses, human behavioris readily attributed to determinative ancestral programming and universalizedtraits. Biological evolutionists underscore the diversifying selection pressures foradaptiveness of different types of ecological milieus (Dobzhansky 1972, Fausto-Sterling 1992, Gould 1987). Socially constructed milieus differ markedly so nosingle mode of social adaptation ts all situations.

    Ancestral origin of bodily structures and biological potentialities and the deter-minants governing contemporary behavior and social practices are quite different

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    20/28

    20 BANDURA

    terms of partitioning behavioral variance into percent nature and percent nurture.This analytic dualism is mistaken for several reasons: It disregards the intricateinterdependence of nature and nurture. Moreover, socially constructed nurture has

    a hand in shaping human nature.Social cognitive theory acknowledges the inuential role of evolved factors

    in human adaptation and change, but it rejects one-sided evolutionism in whichevolved biology shapes behavior but the selection pressures of social and techno-logical innovations on biological evolution get ignored. In the bidirectional viewof evolutionary processes, environmental pressures fostered changes in biologi-cal structures and upright posture conducive to the development and use of tools.These endowments enabled an organism to manipulate, alter, and construct newenvironmental conditions. Environmental innovationsof increasing complexity, in

    turn, created new selection pressures for the evolution of cognitive capacities andspecialized biological systems for functional consciousness, thought, language,and symbolic communication.

    Human evolution provides bodily structures and biological potentialities, notbehavioral dictates. Psychosocial inuences operate through these biological re-sources to fashion adaptive forms of behavior. Having evolved, the advancedbiological capacities can be used to create diverse cultures—aggressive, pacic,egalitarian, or autocratic. Gould (1987) builds a strong case that biology sets con-straints that vary in nature, degree, and strength in different activity domains, but

    in most spheres of human functioning biology permits a broad range of culturalpossibilities. He argues cogently that evidence favors a potentialist view over adeterminist view. In this insightful analysis, the major explanatory battle is notbetween nature and nurture as commonly framed, but whether nature operates asa determinist or as a potentialist. For example, tall individuals have the potentialto become successful basketball players. But tallness does not ordain basketballpursuits. I seriously doubt that the genetic make-up of the Nazi Germans whocommitted unprecedented barbarity is really different from the genetic make-upof peaceful Swiss residing in the German canton of Switzerland. People possess

    the biological potential for aggression, but the answer to the cultural variation inaggressiveness lies more in ideology than in biology.

    Gould makes the further interesting point that biological determinism is oftenclothed in the language of interactionism to make it more palatable. The bidi-rectional biology-culture coevolution is acknowledged, but then evolved biologyis portrayed as the ruling force. The cultural side of this two-way causation, inwhich genetic make-up is shaped by the adaptational pressures of socially con-structed environments, receives little notice. Biological determinism is also oftenclothed in the language of changeability: The malleability of evolved dispositions

    is acknowledged, but determinative potency is then ascribed to them with cau-tion against efforts to change existing sociostructural arrangements and practices

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    21/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 21

    In Gould’s view (1987), biology has culture on a “loose leash,” whereas Wilsonargues that, biology has culture on a “tight leash.” How human nature is construeddetermines theextent to which obstructions to sociostructural changes aresought in

    genetic mismatch or in the counterforce of entrenched vested interests. Biologicaldeterminists favor the rule of nature, whereas biological potentialists, who regardhuman nature as permitting a range of possibilities, give greater weight to the ruleof distributed opportunities, privileges, and power. Thus, a biological deterministview highlights inherent constraints and limitations. A biological potentialist viewof human nature emphasizes human possibilities.

    There is much genetic homogeneity across cultures but vast diversity in be-lief systems and conduct. Given this variability, genetic coding that characterizeshumans underscores the power of the environment orchestrated through agentic

    action. Aggression, which is allegedly genetically programmed as a biologicaluniversal, is a good case in point. Wide intercultural diversity challenges the viewthat people are inherently aggressive. There are ghting cultures that breed aggres-sion by modeling it pervasively, attaching prestige to it and according it functionalvalue for gaining social status, material benets, and social control. There are alsopacic cultures in which interpersonal aggression is a rarity because it is devalued,rarely modeled, and has no functional value (Alland 1972; Bandura 1973, Sanday1981).

    Intracultural diversity also calls into question aggression as an innate human

    nature. The United States is a relatively violent society, but American Quakers,who are fully immersed in the culture, adopt pacism as a way of life. The thirdform of variability involves rapid transformation of warring societies into peacefulones. The Swiss used to be the main suppliers of mercenary ghters in Europe, butas they transformed into a pacic society their militaristic vestige is evident only inthe plumage of the Vatican guards. For ages the Vikings plundered other nations.After a prolonged war with Russiathat exhaustedSweden’s resources, thepopulousrose up and forced a constitutional change that prohibited kings from starting wars(Moerk 1995). This political act promptly transformed a ghting society into a

    peaceable one that has served as a mediator for peace among warring nations. Thisrapid cultural metamorphosis underscores the power of nurture. In cross-culturalcomparisons, Sweden ranks at the very bottom of all forms of violence.

    A biologically deterministic view has even thornier problems with the rapidpace of social change. People have changed little genetically over recent decades,but they have changed markedly through rapid cultural and technological evolutionin their beliefs, mores, social roles, and styles of behavior. Social systems andlifestyles are being altered by social means rather than by reliance on the slow, pro-tracted process of biological selection. As Dobzhansky (1972) puts it succinctly,

    the human species has been selected for learnability and plasticity of behavioradaptive to remarkably diverse habitats, not for behavioral xedness. The pace of

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    22/28

    22 BANDURA

    biologically limitless. The plasticity, which is intrinsic to the nature of humans,depends upon specialized neurophysiological structures and mechanisms that haveevolved over time. These advanced neural systems are specialized for channel-

    ing attention, detecting the causal structure of the outside world, transforming thatinformation into abstract representations, and integrating and using them for adap-tive purposes. These evolved information processing systems provide the capacityfor the very agentic characteristics that are distinctly human—generative symbol-ization, forethought, evaluative self-regulation, reective self-consciousness, andsymbolic communication.

    Neurophysiological systems have been shaped by evolutionary pressures, butpeople are not just reactive products of selection pressures. Other species areheavily innately programmed for stereotypic survival in a particular habitat. In

    contrast, human lifestyles are, in large part, experientially fashioned within bio-logical limits rather than come ready made. The exercise of agentic capabilities isa prime player in the human coevolution process. People are not only reactors toselection pressures, but they are producers of new ones at an increasingly dizzyingpace.

    Through agentic action, people devise ways of adapting exibly to remark-ably diverse geographic, climatic and social environments; they gure out ways tocircumvent physical and environmental constraints, redesign and construct envi-ronments to their liking, create styles of behavior that enable them to realize desired

    outcomes, and pass on the effective ones to others by social modeling and otherexperiential modes of inuence. By these inventive means, people improve theirodds in the tness survival game. Growth of knowledge is increasingly enhancinghuman power to control, transform, and create environments of increasing com-plexity and consequence. We build physical technologies that drastically alter howwe live our daily lives. We create mechanical devices that compensate immenselyfor our sensory and physical limitations. We develop medical and psychologicalmethods that enable us to exert some measure of control over our physical andpsychosocial lives. Through contraceptive ingenuity that disjoined sex from pro-

    creation, humans have outwitted and taken control over their evolved reproductivesystem. Carl Djerassi, who begot the birth control pill, predicts that further de-velopments in reproductive technologies will separate sex from fertilization bystoring eggs and injecting sperm in vitro for uteral reinsertion and childbearing ata time of one’s choosing (Levy 2000).

    Humans have created biotechnologies for replacing defective genes with modi-ed ones and for changing the genetic make-up of plants and animals by implantinggenes from different sources. In a budding biotechnology that is forging aheadin ways that bypass evolutionary genetic processes, we are now cloning clones

    and exploring methods that could alter the genetic codes of humans. As peopledevise ever more powerful technologies that enable them to fashion some aspects

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    23/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 23

    With further development of biotechnology, we face the prospect that moredirect social construction of human nature through genetic design of human be-ings for desired properties will increasingly command our attention and ethical

    concerns.What is technologically possible eventually gets applied. As previously noted,

    the genetic factors provide only potentialities, not the nished psychosocial at-tributes. However, there is no shortage of individuals with the resources and belief in genetic determinism to underwrite attempts at genetic engineering of humannature. The values to which we subscribe and the social systems we devise tooversee the uses to which our powerful technologies are put will play a vital rolein what we become and how we shape our destiny.

    ACKNOWLEDGMENTSPreparation of this chapter and some of the cited research was supported by grantsfrom the Grant Foundation, the Spencer Foundation, and the Jacobs Foundation.Some sections of this chapter include revised, updated and expanded material fromthe books, Social Foundations or Thought and Action: A Social Cognitive Theory ,Prentice-Hall 1986; Self-Efcacy: The Exercise of Control , Freeman 1997; and “ASocial Cognitive Theory of Personality” in Handbook of Personality , ed. L Pervin,O John (2nd ed.), Guilford.

    Visit the Annual Reviews home page at www.AnnualReviews.org

    LITERATURE CITED

    AllandA Jr. 1972. The Human Imperative .NewYork: Columbia Univ. Press

    Austin JH. 1978. Chase, Chance, and Creativ-ity: The Lucky Art of Novelty . New York:Columbia Univ. Press

    Baldwin C, Baldwin A, Sameroff A, Seifer R.1989. The role of family interaction in the prediction of adolescent competence . Pre-sented at Bienn. Meet. Soc. Res. Child Dev.,Kansas City, MO

    Baltes MM. 1996. The Many Faces of Depen-dency in Old Age . New York: CambridgeUniv. Press

    Bandura A. 1973. Aggression: A Social Learn-ingAnalysis . EnglewoodCliffs, NJ:Prentice-Hall

    Bandura A.1982.Thepsychologyofchanceen-

    Thought and Action: A Social CognitiveTheory . Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall

    Bandura A. 1991a. Social cognitive theory of moral thought and action. In Handbook of Moral Behavior and Development , ed. WMKurtines, JL Gewirtz, 1:45–103. Hillsdale,NJ: Erlbaum

    Bandura A. 1991b. Self-regulation of motiva-tion through anticipatory and self-reactivemechanisms. In Perspectives on Motiva-tion: Nebraska Symposium on Motivation ,ed. RA Dienstbier, 38:69–164. Lincoln:Univ. Nebraska Press

    Bandura A. 1993. Perceived self-efcacyin cognitive development and functioning. Educ. Psychol. 28:117–48

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    24/28

    24 BANDURA

    Bandura A. 1997. Self-Efcacy: The Exerciseof Control . New York: Freeman

    Bandura A. 1998. Exploration of fortuitous de-

    terminants of life paths. Psychol. Inq. 9:95–99Bandura A. 1999a. A social cognitive theory of

    personality. In Handbook of Personality , ed.L Pervin, O John, pp. 154–96. New York:Guilford. 2nd ed.

    Bandura A. 1999b. Moral disengagement in theperpetration of inhumanities. Pers. Soc. Psy-chol. Rev. (Special issue on Evil and Vio-lence ) 3:193–209

    Bandura A. 2000. Exercise of human agencythrough collective efcacy. Curr. Dir. Psy-chol. Sci. 9:75–78

    Bandura A, Barbaranelli C, Caprara GV, Pa-storelli C. 1996a. Multifaceted impact of self-efcacy beliefs on academic function-ing. Child Dev. 67:1206–22

    Bandura A, Barbaranelli C, Caprara GV, Pas-torelli C. 1996b. Mechanisms of moral dis-engagement in the exercise of moral agency. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 71:364–74

    Bandura A, Barbaranelli C, Caprara GV, Pa-storelli C. 2000a. Self-efcacy beliefs asshapers of children’s aspirations and careertrajectories. Child Dev. In press

    Bandura A, Barbaranelli C, Caprara GV, Pa-storelli C, Regalia C. 2000b. Sociocogni-tive Self-Regulatory Mechanisms GoverningTransgressive Behavior. J. Pers. Soc. Psy-chol. In press

    Bandura A, Pastorelli C, Barbaranelli C,Caprara GV. 1999. Self-efcacy pathways tochildhood depression. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol.76:258–69

    Brandtst ädter J. 1992. Personal control over de-velopment: implications of self-efcacy. InSelf-Efcacy: Thought Control of Action , ed.R Schwarzer, pp. 127–45. Washington, DC:Hemisphere

    Bratman ME. 1999. Faces of Intention: Se-lected Essays on Intention and Agency . NewYork: Cambridge Univ. Press

    Burns TR, Dietz T. 2000. Human agency andevolutionary processes: institutional dynam-ics and social revolution. In Agency in Social

    Theory , ed. B Wittrock. Thousand Oaks, CA:Sage. In pressBuss DM, Schmitt DP. 1993. Sexual strategies

    theory: an evolutionary perspective on hu-man mating. Psychol. Rev. 100:204–32

    Bussey K, Bandura A. 1999. Social cognitivetheory of gender development and differen-tiation. Psychol. Rev. 106:676–713

    Carlson RA. 1997. Experienced Cognition .Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum

    Davidson D. 1971. Agency. In Agent, Action,and Reason , ed. R Binkley, R Bronaugh, AMarras, pp. 3–37. Univ. Toronto Press

    Diamond MC. 1988. Enriching Heredity . NewYork: Free Press

    DobzhanskyT. 1972.Genetics andthe diversityof behavior. Am. Psychol. 27:523–30

    Earley PC. 1993. East meets West meetsMideast: Further explorations of collectivis-tic and individualistic work groups. Acad. Manage. J. 36:319–48

    EarleyPC.1994.Self orgroup? Cultural effectsof training on self-efcacy and performance. Admin. Sci. Q. 39:89–117

    Eisenberg L. 1995. The social constructionof the human brain. Am. J. Psychiatry152:1563–75

    ElderGH, ArdeltM.1992. Families Adaptingto Economic Pressure: Some Consequences for Parents and Adolescents . Presented at Soc.Res. Adolesc., Washington, DC

    Fausto-Sterling A. 1992. Myths of Gender: Bi-ological Theories About Women and Men .New York: Basic Books. 2nd ed.

    Feather NT, ed. 1982. Expectations and Ac-tions: Expectancy-Value Models in Psychol-ogy . Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum

    Fernández-Ballesteros R, Dı́ez-Nicol´ as J,Caprara GV, Barbaranelli C, Bandura A.2000. Structural Relation of Perceived Per-sonal Efcacy to Perceived Collective Ef-cacy . Submitted for publication

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    25/28

    AGENTIC PERSPECTIVE 25

    Cambridge: Polity/Berkeley: Univ. Calif.Press

    Gould SJ. 1987. An Urchin in the Storm . New

    York: NortonGreen CD, Vervaeke J. 1996. What kind of ex-planation, if any, is a connectionist net? InProblems of Theoretical Psychology , ed. CWTolman, F Cherry, R van Hezewijk, I Lubek,pp. 201–8. North York, Ont.: Captus

    Greenwood JD. 1992. Against eliminativematerialism: from folk psychology tovölkerpsychologie. Philos. Psychol. 5:349–67

    Hamburg DA. 1992. Today’s Children: Creat-ing a Future for a Generation in Crisis . NewYork: Times Books

    Harré R. 1983. Personal Being: A Theory for Individual Psychology . Oxford: Blackwell

    Harré R, Gillet G. 1994. The Discursive Mind .Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage

    Holden G. 1991. The relationship of self-efcacy appraisals to subsequent health-related outcomes: a meta-analysis. Soc.Work. Health Care 16:53–93

    Holden G, Moncher MS, Schinke SP, BarkerKM. 1990. Self-efcacy of children andadolescents: a meta-analysis. Psychol. Rep.66:1044–46

    Keohane RO. 1993. Sovereignty, interdepen-dence and international institutions. In Ideasand Ideals: Essays on Politics in Honor of Stanley Hoffman , ed. L Miller, M Smith, pp.91–107. Boulder, CO: Westview

    Keohane RO, Nye JS. 1977. Power and Inter-dependence: World Politics in Transition .Boston: Little, Brown

    Kim U, Triandis HC, Kˆaǧitçibasi C, Choi S,Yoon G, eds. 1994. Individualism and Col-lectivism: Theory, Method, and Applica-tions . Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage

    KolbB, Whishaw IQ. 1998.Brain plasticity andbehavior. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 49:43–64

    Krantz DL. 1998. Taming chance: social sci-ence and everyday narratives. Psychol. Inq.9:87–94

    Locke EA, Latham GP. 1990. A Theory of GoalSetting and Task Performance . EnglewoodCliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall

    Maddux JE. 1995. Self-efcacy, adaptation,and adjustment: Theory, research, and ap- plication. New York: Plenum

    Masten AS, Best KM, Garmezy N. 1990.Resilience and development: contributionsfrom the study of children who over-come adversity. Dev. Psychopathol. 2:425–44

    Matsui T, Onglatco ML. 1991. Instrumentality,expressiveness, andself-efcacyin career ac-

    tivities among Japanese working women. J.Vocat. Behav. 41:79–88

    Matsumoto D, Kudoh T, Takeuchi S. 1996.Changing patterns of individualism and col-lectivism in theUnited StatesandJapan. Cult.Psychol. 2:77–107

    Midgley M. 1978. Beast and Man: The Rootsof Human Nature . Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univ.Press

    Moerk EL. 1995. Acquisition and transmis-sion of pacist mentalities in Sweden. PeaceCon.: J. Peace Psychol. 1:291–307

    Multon KD, Brown SD, Lent RW. 1991. Re-lation of self-efcacy beliefs to academicoutcomes: a meta-analytic investigation. J.Couns. Psychol. 38:30–38

    Nagel E. 1961. The Structure of Science . NewYork: Harcourt, Brace and World

    Pasteur L. 1854. Inaugural lecture . Universityof Lille, France

    Rottschaefer WA. 1985. Evading conceptualself-annihilation: some implications of Al-bert Bandura’s theory of the self-system forthe status of psychology. New Ideas Psychol.2:223–30

    Rottschaefer WA. 1991. Some philosophi-cal implications of Bandura’s social cogni-tive theory of human agency. Am. Psychol.46:153–55

    Rutter M. 1990. Psychosocial resilience andprotective mechanisms. In Risk and Pro-tective Factors in the Development of Psy-

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    26/28

    26 BANDURA

    pp. 181–214. New York: Cambridge Univ.Press

    Sanday PR. 1981. The socio-cultural context of

    rape: a cross-cultural study. J. Soc. Issues37:5–27Schooler C. 1990. Individualism and the his-

    torical and social-structural determinants of people’s concerns over self-directedness andefcacy. In Self-Directedness: Cause and Effects Throughout the Life Course , ed. JRodin, C Schooler, KW Schaie, pp. 19–58.Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum

    Schwarzer R, ed. 1992. Self-Efcacy: Thought

    Control of Action . Washington, DC: Hemi-sphere

    Singhal A, Rogers EM. 1999. Entertainment- Education: A Communication Strategy for Social Change . Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum

    Sperry RW. 1993. The impact and promise

    of the cognitive revolution. Am. Psychol.48:878–85

    Stajkovic AD, Luthans F. 1998. Self-

    efcacy and work-related performance:a meta-analysis. Psychol. Bull. 124:240–61

    Wilson EO. 1998. Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge . New York: Knopf

    Yamagishi T. 1988. Theprovisionof a sanction-ing system in the United States and Japan.Soc. Psychol. Q. 51:265–71

    Zimbardo PG. 1995. The psychology of evil:a situationist perspective on recruiting good

    people to engage in anti-social acts. Res. Soc.Psychol. (Japn. J.) 11:125–33

    Zimmerman BJ. 1990. Self-regulating aca-demic learning and achievement: the emer-gence of a social cognitive perspective. Educ.Psychol. Rev. 2:173–201

    Accessprovidedby5.2.188.133on

    10/08/15.Forpersonaluseonly.

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    27/28

    Annual Review of Psychology Volume 52, 2001

    CONTENTS

    SOCIAL COGNITIVE THEORY: An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura 1

    NATURE AND OPERATION OF ATTITUDES, Icek Ajzen 27META-ANALYSIS: Recent Developments in Quantitative Methods forLiterature Reviews, R. Rosenthal, M. R. DiMatteo 59ADOLESCENT DEVELOPMENT, Laurence Steinberg, AmandaSheffield Morris 83THEORIES OF ASSOCIATIVE LEARNING IN ANIMALS, John M.Pearce, Mark E. Bouton 111ON HAPPINESS AND HUMAN POTENTIALS: A Review of Researchon Hedonic and Eudaimonic Well-Being, Richard M. Ryan, Edward L.

    Deci 141SENTENCE AND TEXT COMPREHENSION: Roles of LinguisticStructure, Charles Clifton Jr., Susan A. Duffy 167PERSONALITY, David C. Funder 197THINKING, Arthur B. Markman, Dedre Gentner 223CONSUMER RESEARCH: In Search of Identity, Itamar Simonson, ZivCarmon, Ravi Dhar, Aimee Drolet, Stephen M. Nowlis 249SLEEP-WAKE AS A BIOLOGICAL RHYTHM, P. Lavie 277STATISTICAL GRAPHICS: Mapping the Pathways of Science, HowardWainer, Paul F. Velleman 305THE DEVELOPMENT OF VISUAL ATTENTION IN INFANCY, JohnColombo 337PSYCHOLINGUISTICS: A Cross-Language Perspective, Elizabeth

    Bates, Antonella Devescovi, Beverly Wulfeck 369JOB BURNOUT, Christina Maslach, Wilmar B. Schaufeli, Michael P.

    Leiter 397OLFACTION, Richard L. Doty 423

    ACQUISITION OF INTELLECTUAL AND PERCEPTUAL-MOTORSKILLS, David A. Rosenbaum, Richard A. Carlson, Rick O. Gilmore

    453THE SCIENCE OF TRAINING: A Decade of Progress, Eduardo Salas,

    Janis A. Cannon-Bowers 471COMPARING PERSONAL TRAJECTORIES AND DRAWINGCAUSAL INFERENCES FROM LONGITUDINAL DATA, Stephen W.

    Raudenbush 501DISRESPECT AND THE EXPERIENCE OF INJUSTICE, Dale T.

    Miller 527HEALTH PSYCHOLOGY: Psychosocial and Biobehavioral Aspects of

    Chronic Disease Management, Neil Schneiderman, Michael H. Antoni,Patrice G. Saab, Gail Ironson 555DECISION TECHNOLOGY, W. Edwards, B. Fasolo 581EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY: Toward a Unifying Theory and aHybrid Science, Linnda R. Caporael 607ATTENTION AND PERFORMANCE, Harold Pashler, James C.

    Johnston, Eric Ruthruff 629

    PROBLEMS FOR JUDGMENT AND DECISION MAKING, R. Hastie653

  • 8/19/2019 2001_Social Cognitive Theory - An Agentic Perspective, Albert Bandura

    28/28

    EMPIRICALLY SUPPORTED PSYCHOLOGICAL INTERVENTIONS:Controversies and Evidence, Dianne L. Chambless, Thomas H. Ollendick 685