Transcript
Page 1: Unger's Defense of Skepticism

Unger's Defense of SkepticismAuthor(s): Gerald W. BarnesSource: Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the AnalyticTradition, Vol. 24, No. 2 (Mar., 1973), pp. 119-124Published by: SpringerStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4318771 .

Accessed: 24/06/2014 20:26

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical Studies: AnInternational Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 195.78.108.51 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 20:26:06 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Unger's Defense of Skepticism

GERALD W. BARNES

UNGER'S DEFENSE OF SKEPTICISM

(Received 6 January, 1972)

Peter Unger defends' the skeptical thesis that "in the case of every human being, there is hardly anything, if anything at all, which the person knows to be so" (p. 216). He attempts to show that the thesis "deserves, if not our acceptance, at least the suspension of our judgment" (ibid.). I shall argue that his defense appears to be unsound. If it is unsound, then it supplies no reason for hesitating to reject skepticism.

First let me outline Unger's case. It proceeds from his account of two notions: 'absolute term' and 'relative term' (pp. 202-207). Unger discus- ses mainly the absolute term 'flat' and the correlated relative terms 'bumpy' and 'curved'. Every absolute term has one or more relative terms correlated with it, in the sense that every absolute term can be defined, according to Unger, by means of some one or more relative terms:

To say that a surface is flat is to say that some things or properties which are matters of degree are not instanced in the surface to any degree at all. Thus, something which is flat is not at all bumpy, and not at all curved. Bumpiness and curvature are matters of degree (p. 203).

Every absolute term whatever, may be defined, at least partially, by means of certain relative terms. The defining conditions presented by means of the relative terms are negative ones; they say that what the realtive term purports to denote is not present at all, or in the least, where the absolute term correctly applies (p. 206).

Unger's defense of skepticism goes as follows. With regard to absolute terms other than those denoting something which "divides into discrete units" (p. 210), "fairly reasonable suppositions about the world make it somewhat doubtful that the terms properly apply" (ibid.). With regard to 'flat', for example, it would only be reasonable to assert that there exists a really flat surface if it were reasonable to assert of some surface that "there never is any surface which is flatter than it is" (p. 211). But we simply don't know enough to assert this reasonably of any surface so far observed, even one observed under the highest magnification so far at- tained.

Philosophical Studies 24 (1973) 119-124. All Rights Reserved Copyright C 1973 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

This content downloaded from 195.78.108.51 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 20:26:06 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Unger's Defense of Skepticism

120 GERALD W. BARNES

The term 'certain' is an absolute term. It can be defined in a variety of ways, by means of such relative terms as 'doubtful', 'uncertain', and 'confident' (p. 209). As with 'flat', so with 'certain': we are virtually never in a position reasonably to assert about anyone, concerning any proposi- tion he entertains, that "there never is anything of which he is more cer- tain" (p. 212), i.e., that what 'doubtful' denotes is "not present at all, or in the least" (p. 206) in him. In other words, one has no grounds for denying that there is nothing or next to nothing of which any person is ever certain. The reasonable course, says Unger, is to "suspend judgment on the matter" (p. 213).

Next Unger argues that knowing something logically requires being certain of it. This claim plus the earlier claim - that one cannot reason- ably deny that there is nothing or next to nothing of which any person is ever certain - yield the desired skeptical result: we cannot reasonably reject the proposition that everyone knows, at most, next to nothing.

Unger's defense of skepticism, outlined above, relies upon a premise to this effect: it is virtually never reasonable to assert that what 'doubtful' purports to denote is completely absent from a person's mind with respect to any proposition he entertains. I shall try to show that Unger leaves us without sufficient grounds for believing this premise. Thus, even if valid his defense of skepticism appears to be unsound.

It will be easier to see that this is so if we begin by considering 'bumpy', rather than 'doubtful'. If it is true of any surface, x, that is flat, then, according to Unger, what 'bumpy' denotes is "not present at all, or in the least" in x (p. 206). Suppose, now, that what 'bumpy' denotes were, roughly speaking, the property of being irregular to the naked eye. In that case, there would be many surfaces which, so far as the negative bumpi- ness requirement goes, qualify as flat, since there are many surfaces which are not "at all, or in the least", irregular to the naked eye. But it is essen- tial to Unger's argument, we have seen, that with regard to certain ab- solute terms, including 'flat', it be a matter of great doubt, at best, whether they ever apply to anything. Thus Unger cannot allow that 'bumpy' denotes the property of being irregular to the naked eye. Nor can 'curved' denote any property defined solely in terms of discriminations by the naked eye. For if 'bumpy' and 'curved' had these denotations, then by Unger's own account, it is plain that many surfaces are flat.

Assuming that no harm is done by speaking, with Unger, of properties

This content downloaded from 195.78.108.51 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 20:26:06 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: Unger's Defense of Skepticism

UNGER'S DEFENSE OF SKEPTICISM 121

as denoted (rather than connoted) by terms, the natural question here is, what shows what property a term denotes? One plausible reply is that in any given context the denoted property is the property which people generally use the term to denote in that context. Now if this reply is correct without qualification, then there are surely many contexts in which 'bumpy' has something like the denotation which Unger cannot allow. After all, if someone were to complain about having to play on a bumpy tennis court, when the only irregularities of its surface were ones discrim- inable only by means of an electron microscope, his complaint would be hard to make sense of. Or, if we're playing on a really bumpy tennis court, and I stoop down and, with the aid of a magnifying glass, remove a dust mote from it, it could only be as a joke that you would thank me for making the court less bumpy.

A similar point can be made about many other relative terms, including 'doubtful'. Imagine a non-philosopher, at dinnertime, hard at work trying to repair the oven so that dinner can be cooked. It would only be under quite unusual circumstances that one might suppose the man doubts that he is doing what he takes himself to be doing. Usually he would not doubt it at all, any more than he would doubt that 45 and 56 make 101, or that automobiles exist (Unger's examples). Only someone approaching the case philosophically would be prepared to suggest that the man is not certain of these things, i.e., to deny that "all [my emphasis] doubt is absent in that man's mind" (p. 208); people generally, including the man himself, would not be prepared to say these things.

Although Unger does not speak directly to the point just made, he does comment more generally on the trustworthiness of ordinary usage. It is possible, he argues (pp. 199-202), for what we ordinarily say about some things to be (unintendedly) false without its falsity having any practical consequences. More importantly, there is a way to demonstrate, in many cases, that what we ordinarily say is (unintendedly) false. Unger claims that there is a 'quite generally applicable" (p. 215) technique for discover- ing unnoticed implications of ordinary usage. It is a matter of "focusing on just those words most directly employed in expressing the concept whose conditions are our object of inquiry" (p. 214). Focusing is done "by suitably juxtaposing certain terms, like 'really' and 'actually', with the terms most in question" (p. 215); and, "more strikingly, we may em- phasize the terms in question" (ibid.).

This content downloaded from 195.78.108.51 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 20:26:06 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: Unger's Defense of Skepticism

122 GERALD W. BARNES

By this technique, "x is the son of y" becomes "x is (really) (actually) the son of y". Thus, speaking informally, there is no harm in saying, for example, that Nelson Rockefeller is the son of John D. Rockefeller, Jr. (Unger's example, pp. 215-16). But if one 'focuses' on what one is saying - "actually the son of John D. Rockefeller, Jr." - one comes to realize that one is saying something false, since there is more than one son of John D. Rockefeller, Jr., and hence nobody who is the son. Although one used "is the son" to denote the property of being (merely) a son, that use was a misuse.

Similarly, Unger might say, if we 'focus' on the supposition that the man fixing the oven is certain he is doing what he takes himself to be doing - is he really, actually certain? - we begin to hesitate. There begins to be a question whether he might not be more certain of his own existence for example. But then we cannot confidently say that the man is certain he is fixing the oven, for "as a matter of logical necessity, if someone is certain of something, then there never is anything of which he is more certain" (p. 212).

Unger seems to think that the property an expression denotes in a 'focused' context must be (more than nominally) the same property it denotes in some or all other contexts. Otherwise, what is the relevance of the fact that, for example, 'is the son' denotes being sole male offspring in a 'focused' context, a context which includes such features as heavy stress on "the', addition of another, highly charged, word ('really'), and the adoption of an intense philosophical/skeptical attitude toward the verbal performance under scrutiny? What was at issue was the denotation of 'is the son' in a context lacking all these features. But it is a commonplace that changes in the context of an expression's use (or, as some would say, changes in its use) can alter the expression's meaning, and it is at least plausible to suppose that meaning and denotation are closely related. Unger owes us some reason for thinking that his technique of 'focusing' reveals the property an expression denotes in non-'focused' contexts, be- fore we are obliged by what he says to retreat from the view suggested earlier, namely, the view that in any given context a term denotes the property which people generally use it to denote in that context. But Unger gives no such reason.

In the case of some terms - e.g., interestingly, in the case of 'bumpy' - certain facts may tempt us, nevertheless, to think that, properly used, the

This content downloaded from 195.78.108.51 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 20:26:06 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: Unger's Defense of Skepticism

UNGER'S DEFENSE OF SKEPTICISM 123

term must denote the same property in all contexts. If one observes ir- regularities in the surface of a polished stone through an electron micro- scope, one will find it difficult to deny that one is observing a property which is the same property one observes when, with unaided vision, one observes a bumpy tennis court. The two surfaces are obviously similar, in a way which is "immediately revealed in perception", so to speak. One could no more deny this, one feels, than deny that the chloroplasts in a plant cell seen through a microscope are the same color as an acre of grass, or deny that a spherical particle in the cell is the same shape (roughly) as the earth.

Thus it might be suggested that we cannot properly apply 'bumpy' - or at any rate, some such term - to the bumpy tennis court and withhold the same term from the (so-called) flat polished stone. To withhold it in the second instance (one might be tempted to say) would be to speak inac- curately in that it would be to deny a 'brute' feature of the world of which our own eyes can inform us. That we speak in a 'focused' context, or in a non-'focused' one, cannot by itself make a difference in how the things we speak about are, one might contend.

Even if this line of thought could be defended, however, it remains to ask whether one could take a similar line with 'doubtful'. One would have to show first that virtually always when any person entertained any pro- position, doubt about that proposition in that person's mind could be detected, by the person himself or by another, if a thorough attempt (perhaps using Unger's 'focusing') were made.

This would not be enough, however. On many ocasions - e.g., the man fixing the oven - doubt would be detected, if at all, only after a thorough attempt. One would have to show, second, that on virtually all these ocassions at least some measure of the detected doubt would be not mere- ly a result of the attempt at detection, that is, not merely, for example, doubt generated in response to expectations that doubt would be found.

To show these two things would obviously be very difficult, if it is even clear what could possibly settle the question regarding either. One im- portant thing is plain, however: the ubiquity of doubt independent of attempts to find it is not forced upon us as a feature of the world in the way in which (to some extent) the ubiquity of bumpiness may be. It remains accordingly obscure what reasons there might be to challenge the denotation with which people generally use the term 'doubtful'.

This content downloaded from 195.78.108.51 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 20:26:06 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: Unger's Defense of Skepticism

124 GERALD W. BARNES

This is not to deny that there are contexts (special scientific or philo- sophical ones, for example) in which the denotation of 'doubtful' is just the sort of property Unger claims it to be in all contexts, viz., a property whose absence (from the contexts in question) it is virtually impossible to establish. All I maintain against Unger is (1) that there is reason to think that in other, frequently occurring, contexts the denotation of 'doubtful' is not a property of that sort, and (2) that Unger supplies no reason to think otherwise.2

Trenton State College, Trenton, New Jersey

NOTES

1 In 'A Defense of Skepticism', Philosophical Review 80 (1971), 198-219. 2 I am grateful to Herb Heidelberger and Margaret Wilson for many helpful criticisms of earlier drafts of this paper.

This content downloaded from 195.78.108.51 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 20:26:06 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions


Recommended