20
  1 Airenti G., 2004. The development of the speaker's meaning. In: C. FlorŽn Serrano, C. Inchaurralde Besga, M.A.Ruiz Moneva, eds., Applied Linguistics Perspectives: Language Learning and specialized Discourse, Anubar, Zaragoza, 1-27 The development of the speaker's meaning Gabriella Airenti Centro di Scienza Cognitiva, Universitˆ di Torino, Via Po 14, 10123 Torino, Italy Abstract Pragmatics is a very diversified field where merely descriptive approaches stand side by side with attempts of theoretical conceptualization and formalization. What is generally ignored in this debate is that, since communication is a fundamental human capacity, cognitive plausibility must be a condition to make a theory acceptable. Moreover, as all human capacities develop from the birth on, the results of developmental studies have to be taken into account in the theoretical work. In particular, developmental studies can be useful to clarify three classical questions of the debate in pragmatics: the r elationship between language and communication, the very definition of communication, and the relationship between communication and action. In the paper I analyze these subjects and I propose an attempt to see communicative ability in its development. Key words: communication, development, theory of mind 1. Introduction Pragmatics is a very diversified field where merely descriptive approaches stand side by side with attempts of theoretical conceptualization and formalization. What is generally ignored in this debate is that, since communication is a fundamental human capacity, cognitive plausibility must be a condition to make a theory acceptable. Moreover, as all human capacities develop from the birth on, the results of developmental studies have to be taken into account in the theoretical work. Some developmental psychologists have tried to use concepts coming from pragmatics to better understand language acquisition. However, findings of developmental psychology have not influenced pragmatic theories. In my view this procedure has led to the acceptance of incorrect assumptions. In particular, developmental studies can be useful to clarify three classical questions of the debate in pragmatics: the relationship between language and communication, the very definition of communication, and the relationship between communication and action. In the following I shall analyze these subjects and I shall propose an attempt to see communicative ability in its development.

Zaragoza Libre

  • Upload
    mha2000

  • View
    214

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

pragmatics

Citation preview

  • 1

    Airenti G., 2004. The development of the speaker's meaning. In: C. Florn Serrano, C. Inchaurralde Besga, M.A.Ruiz Moneva, eds., Applied Linguistics Perspectives: Language Learning and specialized Discourse, Anubar, Zaragoza, 1-27

    The development of the speaker's meaning

    Gabriella Airenti

    Centro di Scienza Cognitiva, Universit di Torino, Via Po 14, 10123 Torino, Italy

    Abstract

    Pragmatics is a very diversified field where merely descriptive approaches stand side by

    side with attempts of theoretical conceptualization and formalization. What is generally

    ignored in this debate is that, since communication is a fundamental human capacity,

    cognitive plausibility must be a condition to make a theory acceptable. Moreover, as all

    human capacities develop from the birth on, the results of developmental studies have

    to be taken into account in the theoretical work. In particular, developmental studies can

    be useful to clarify three classical questions of the debate in pragmatics: the relationship

    between language and communication, the very definition of communication, and the

    relationship between communication and action. In the paper I analyze these subjects

    and I propose an attempt to see communicative ability in its development.

    Key words:

    communication, development, theory of mind

    1. Introduction

    Pragmatics is a very diversified field where merely descriptive approaches stand side by

    side with attempts of theoretical conceptualization and formalization. What is generally

    ignored in this debate is that, since communication is a fundamental human capacity,

    cognitive plausibility must be a condition to make a theory acceptable. Moreover, as all

    human capacities develop from the birth on, the results of developmental studies have

    to be taken into account in the theoretical work. Some developmental psychologists

    have tried to use concepts coming from pragmatics to better understand language

    acquisition. However, findings of developmental psychology have not influenced

    pragmatic theories. In my view this procedure has led to the acceptance of incorrect

    assumptions. In particular, developmental studies can be useful to clarify three classical

    questions of the debate in pragmatics: the relationship between language and

    communication, the very definition of communication, and the relationship between

    communication and action. In the following I shall analyze these subjects and I shall

    propose an attempt to see communicative ability in its development.

  • 2

    2. Language and communication

    In daily life situations we commonly find a communicative use of language. The

    analysis of particular cases where language is not used to communicate but simply as

    the expression of thought, or where pathology allows us to discover the possibility of

    mastering grammar when normal cognitive or communicative capacities are lacking has

    been used to confirm the theoretical autonomy of grammar pleaded by Chomsky in all

    his work (Blank, Gessner and Esposito 1979; Bellugi, Marks, Bihrle and Sabo 1988;

    Udwin and Yule 1991; Smith, Tsimpli and Ouhalla 1993). Actually, a number of cases

    have been studied where the opposite situation occurs: a grammatical impairment does

    not affect communicative capacities (Curtiss 1977). Moreover, infants are involved in

    interactions for at least a year before the first rudiments of language appear. Finally,

    adults communicate also by nonlinguistic means. Thus it is reasonable to pose the

    question: does a communicative capacity exist which develops independently of

    language and of other cognitive capacities? And in case of affirmative answer to the

    first question, how is this capacity structured?

    This formulation of the problem is not accepted by the supporters of universal

    grammar nor by scholars working on pragmatics. This is the conclusion that can be

    derived from the debate between Chomsky and Searle. Searle (1972) considers that the

    separation between language and communication is the major defect of Chomsky's

    theory in that it means to separate language from its main goal. Chomsky (1975) objects

    that language is the expression of thought. Language can be used appropriately without

    any goal of inducing an auditory, that can also be absent, to hold a given belief or to do

    a given action. Communication for Chomsky is only one function of language and not

    an essential one. Chomsky's remarks are very important from the psychological point of

    view in that they allow for the definition of a communicative function supported by

    cognitive structures separated from the ones responsible for language. Actually, there is

    no reason to assume that the cognitive faculties underlying communication are the same

    containing the rules of grammar. However, here is also the point where Chomsky has to

    be abandoned. In fact, to maintain the primacy of grammar Chomsky and his followers

    completely understate the role of communication. I would agree that the linguistic

    structure has no intrinsic communicative function. At the same time, one has to

    recognize that in real life language is mostly used to communicate. In fact, the very

    pathological cases where grammar is managed in the absence of pragmatic abilities

    show that deprived of these abilities, language is perceived as heavily defective, a kind

    of non mastered tool (Curtiss 1989).

    In pragmatics we find the symmetrical position. Primacy of pragmatics is derived

    from the consideration that language is prevalently used to communicate: this fact is

  • 3

    taken as the demonstration that the communicative function cannot be separated by the

    language structure. In particular, for speech act theorists speech acts, or to be more

    accurate, illocutionary acts, are primitive acts where the conventional aspect deriving

    from language and the cognitive aspect expressed by communicative intentions conflate

    in a single phenomenon (Austin 1962; Searle 1969).

    In the light of developmental data this debate can be seen differently. The main

    discovery made by cognitive psychologists studying infants is that before language

    acquisition children have a long history of interactions with others (Schaffer 1977;

    Bullowa 1979). The main question is if these initial interactions are instances of

    communicative behavior with two active partners, or if the appearance of

    communication is due to the attitude of the caregiver playing her role of attributing

    meanings to the infant. All the students who have focused on the interaction between

    infants and their caregivers (the mothers in the majority of cases) stress the fact that a

    very special interaction establishes whose features are particularly interesting: the

    participants develop a kind of proto-conversation where, in contexts which are typical

    of their relationship, the two partners alternate in the exchange of some simple gestures

    and sounds. The conventions of these exchanges are shared by the partners. The

    features which most researchers single out are the alternation and the form of dialogue.

    These features often lead to interpret first interactions as games or rituals, where the

    partners behave according to a stable frame which constitutes the basis for little

    variations. Trevarthen (1977) has stressed the main characteristic of first interactions

    defining them as interactions without object, a kind of implementation of

    intersubjectivity per se.

    The turning point toward different kinds of interactions is in general situated around

    the ninth month when there is an important improvement in child's motor abilities. The

    autonomy acquired by children in this period causes a break in the preceding form of

    communication. A new form of interaction appears where communication includes the

    external world as its proper object (Trevarthen and Hubley 1978). This is the phase

    where the transition between preverbal and verbal communication is situated. This

    conclusion is opposed by those developmental psychologists concerned to use the

    concept of communication as it has been defined by Grice (Gelman 1983; Shatz 1983).

    As the basic requirements for communication, i.e. intentional action and the possibility

    to model others' mental states, appear rather late in the development -in particular the

    second feature appears when language is already an elaborated tool- these authors

    conclude that no continuity has to be found between first interactions, which are not

    communicative, and successive linguistic communication. In this view communication

    is the result of the coupling of different abilities which is realized only in an advanced

    phase of language acquisition.

  • 4

    However, from the cognitive point of view, the fact that infants have structured

    interactions before language acquisition necessarily means that they have an ability to

    do so. Be the manifestation of this ability real communication or not, it is reasonable

    to consider that this capacity has to be involved in successive communication.

    Otherwise we should assume that there is a complete break between first interactions

    and successive instances of communication. It seems, on the contrary, that at least

    alternation, repetition, and slight variations on the basis of an established routine are

    features of first interactions that persist in communicative exchanges.

    Etnomethodologists who have studied conversation consider that turn-taking rules are

    the basic element of dialogue (Sacks, Schegloff and Jefferson 1974). So if we cannot

    prove that the first exchanges are instances of complete communication, and indeed we

    have good reasons to think that they are not, we must admit that they show elements of

    what will be later communicative behavior. These considerations added to the fact that

    even in the adult age actions can substitute for speech acts lead to the conclusion that

    communicative intentions and their linguistic expressions can be cognitively separated.

    Other considerations can be done on the role of speech acts. In the studies on

    language development some researchers maintain that the acquisition of language

    derives from the use of some prototypical speech acts done by children before language

    appears (Bruner 1975; Bates, Camaioni and Volterra 1976). These researches rely on

    the finding that a child is able to make a request, to take the main example, before being

    able to formulate it in a linguistic fashion. In these studies a fundamental role is given

    to the adult. It is the adult that through a long process of modeling leads the infant from

    the first cries manifesting an undifferentiated discontent to express her intentions in the

    form of speech acts (Bruner 1983a,b). This position has the merit of showing that

    language appears in a situation where a practice of interactions has already been

    established. But many questions remain unsolved. No detailed analysis is attempted of

    the relationship between the basic elements of communicative intention, which babies

    already possess in a very precocious phase, and the development of conversation

    abilities which result from a process of learning where the actual interaction with adults

    is fundamental. Moreover, the interpretation of speech acts, and in particular of indirect

    speech acts, is a problem even for theoretical pragmatics. Therefore, it seems doubtful

    that this concept, at least as it is defined by philosophers of language, can be used to

    clarify language acquisition. In fact, the introduction of the concept of speech act in

    developmental studies has played an interesting role. Developmental psychologists have

    found this concept useful to show that communicative intentions are present before

    speech and to establish a continuity between nonverbal and verbal communication. At

    the same time the linguistic connotations of this theory have in a way hidden the fact

    that there is more to first interactions than the sheer acquisition of what later will be

  • 5

    conventionalized in speech acts. Besides, the necessity to explain conventionalization

    has pushed toward the attribution of a preponderant role to adults. It is the adult who

    leads the child to express her intentions in the appropriate way, i.e. by the appropriate

    verbal speech act. In fact, from a cognitive point of view, the most interesting point is

    to analyze the capacity of newborns to participate in interactions in an active way. The

    adults teaching would be ineffective without the infants predisposition to respond.

    Another very interesting point which is not discussed by these authors is the

    interpretation of indirect speech acts. Data coming from the studies on children's

    interpretation of indirect speech show that indirect speech acts do not present special

    difficulties for children who have just acquired language (Shatz 1978). What constitutes

    the main difficulty for speech act theory is not perceived as such by children who

    currently react to indirect requests like to imperatives. This is another demonstration of

    the possibility to separate the communicative intention, which is correctly interpreted,

    from its linguistic form. Clearly, an adult and a child do not have the same

    interpretation of indirect speech acts. An adult does understand the real illocutionary

    force of the speech act but can also derive from the specific indirect which has been

    used, for instance, for a request, its degrees of kindness, strength, constrain, etc. The

    young child does not understand all the hints that the specific linguistic form can

    provide, but nevertheless understands its real force. This means, in my view, that the

    interpretation of the speech act is done on the basis of the available interactions. The

    typical adult/child interaction is one where the adult proposes something for the child to

    do and the child complies. Thus any situation of this kind is interpreted by the child as

    an imperative. On the contrary, the adult knows that the reference to an action to be

    done by herself can be part of different kinds of interactions and uses all the linguistic

    and extra linguistic indicators to choose the proper one.

    Developmental psychologists have discovered and described first interactions. Some

    of them have then chosen speech acts as the suitable theoretical tool to link their

    findings with pragmatics, i.e. linguistic studies. In fact, from the cognitive point of

    view, this choice has consequences which deserve consideration. Since speech acts are

    a merely linguistic device, the attention is focused on the linguistic aspect of

    interactions. The point is to explain the acquisition of verbal communication. In this

    perspective the function of first interactions is simply to prepare young children to

    language use. I think that the opposite path should be followed. The cognitive analysis

    of interactions occurring before the appearance of language should be used to explore

    the part of adult communicative interactions which is not depending on language. The

    very existence of this aspect shows that language and communication do not coincide. I

    would argue that this explains why speech acts are not a good model of communication

    and have the flaws which have been suggested by many authors. In fact both

  • 6

    Chomskyan theories denying the communicative function of language, and pragmatic

    theories, which link language and communication in an indissoluble way, paradoxically

    lead to the same understatement of nonlinguistic bases for communication. This has

    resulted in an unsatisfactory description of that cognitive ability which allows humans

    to perform communicative interactions whether linguistic or not.

    3. Cooperative action and communication

    In speech act theory the communicative function is included in linguistic expressions.

    Other authors in pragmatics consider instead communication as a form of cooperative

    rational action (Grice 1975,1978; Sperber and Wilson 1986a). Here the accent is put on

    the inferences allowing for the interpretation of communicative acts. In Airenti, Bara

    and Colombetti (1993a) we have argued that in communication a clear distinction is to

    be drawn between behavioral goals and conversational goals. Communication is the

    way humans have to share with others, at least in part, their private mental states using

    conventional rules of conversation. Behavioral goals when communicated are presented

    openly and can be negotiated. Rules of conversation are the modality normally used to

    this aim. This means that the goal of maintaining conversational cooperation is a

    permanent one, while behavioral cooperation has to be established each time and is not

    necessarily achieved. This is the case, for instance when we politely refuse a proposal

    we are not interested in. Let us consider a Gricean example which has been commented

    also by Sperber and Wilson (1986b):

    At a tea party:

    A: Mrs. X is an old bag

    a moment of appalled silence

    B: The weather has been quite delightful this summer, hasn't it?

    Grice's interpretation is that B's utterance evidently violates the maxim of relevance and

    that this intended violation leads to the interpretation that A's utterance has to be

    ignored as inappropriate to the situation, a social gaffe. This could implicate - writes

    Levinson (1983) - for instance that one of the lady's relations is nearby. The analysis of

    Sperber and Wilson is that no violation has been done. The principle of relevance,

    which is by definition valid, plus the fact that A's utterance has been ignored lead to the

    correct interpretation: B communicates that A's utterance is a blunder. The

    interpretation I suggest is different. With his/her utterance A intends to share with B a

    content of his/her mind, namely a judgment about Mrs. X. With his/her answer B

    communicates his/her refusal to share the judgment. The modality utilized by B is

    adequate to keep the conversation as correct as it can be in a situation like that, and it is

    interesting to note that to this aim the author of the example feels the necessity to insert

    before the answer a silence, i.e. a marker of dispreferred second. So conversational

  • 7

    cooperation is maintained while behavioral one is not. If we consider the exchange from

    the point of view of conversation all we can say is about a very limited part of A's real

    or pretended beliefs that s/he has decided to share with B. From this point of view A's

    private reasons to present his/her belief about Mrs. X (s/he could not hide it anymore,

    s/he wants to provoke B, s/he thought that B shared these feelings, etc.) or B's reasons

    to refuse (one of Mrs.X relations is nearby, s/he suspects A to test him/her, s/he really

    likes Mrs. X, etc.) are not interesting. On the contrary, these reasons are fundamental if

    we choose to see the exchange from the behavioral point of view. In fact, for A to

    understand the pragmatic meaning of B's utterance, B's private reasons are interesting.

    If, due to B's utterance, A acknowledges the presence of one of Mrs. X's relations

    nearby s/he will consider the whole episode as a regrettable accident. Unless s/he had

    pretended not to see Mrs. X's relation and in fact s/he had maneuvered to instigate B to

    say things which can disgrace him/her with Mrs. X. If A thinks to be in a powerful

    position with respect to B, his/her utterance could be a test of B's allegiance, and B's

    answer can be seen as a refusal to comply. We can imagine several more scenarios

    involving different partners' beliefs. The point I want to focus on here is that a

    pragmatic interpretation cannot be derived by general laws of action. In fact what is

    involved is what the partners want to do with each other and the conventional modality

    they use to do it. In Airenti, Bara and Colombetti (ibid.) we have argued that the

    knowledge used by the agents to interpret the behavioral aspects of communication

    comes in structures we have called behavior games. Behavior games are given as

    shared. Understanding the speaker's meaning of an utterance is to recover the link of a

    conventional linguistic expression with a shared behavior game. In this interpretation

    we maintain that communication is a kind of action. The point is that communication

    has its specific rules which are not the same that the agents use in cooperative action.

    Let us see now the problem from a developmental point of view. The analysis of the

    development from birth to the end of the second year, when we can say that the

    fundamental structure of language is acquired, shows a characteristic bifurcation.

    Language use begins rather late and the acquisition is very fast. On the contrary, the

    attempts of interaction start soon after birth and have a slow evolution in which

    subsequent child's acquisitions, like motor abilities and language itself, enter as tools

    capable to enhance the child's possibilities. As we have seen, the role of adults in the

    first interactions has often been stressed. The caregiver attributes a meaning to all the

    facial movements, minimal gestures, gazes, smiles, sounds of the baby, often repeating

    and interpreting them. This is certainly true. But what is also interesting from a

    cognitive point of view is that the child already in a very precocious phase can

    participate to these interactions in an active way. The partners establish then a series of

    routines well-known to both the participants. It is easy to show that we cannot consider

  • 8

    such a situation as communication in the Gricean sense. But at the same time one

    should note that two features are already present which lead us to perceive first

    interactions as a kind of dialogue: namely the alternation and sharedness of exchanges.

    Furthermore, these interactions appear well before the child becomes able to carry out

    an action in an autonomous way. The cognitive study of first interactions shows that the

    predisposition to sharedness is the very aspect that humans possess from the beginning,

    and from which more complex successive relationships are constructed. It can be noted

    that according to Premack and Premack (1994) who have studied infants after

    chimpanzees, the intention to share experience is what makes the difference between

    the two species. It has been shown that the child tries to get the other's attention on

    objects not only to make requests but also simply to share her excitement (Premack

    1990), and no comparable behavior has been reported in chimpanzees. On the same

    line, Butterworth (1991) proposes that agreement on the objects of shared experience be

    considered a protocommunicative prerequisite for comprehension. Thus if we focus on

    development we are not allowed to consider communication as derived from action.

    The child has from the beginning the capacity of sharing experience with others. This

    allows for the construction of the first interactive routines, behavior games in my

    terminology. A typical example of routine is the game of imitation. Some authors have

    attributed a great importance to imitation as a means for the baby to acquire knowledge

    of the other. In particular Melzoff and Moore (1977) have shown that imitation is a

    primary phenomenon starting immediately after birth. Newborns can and in fact do

    imitate tongue and lips protrusion. The authors use these data to formulate a theory

    where imitation, seen as an innate capacity, has the main function in the development of

    child's ability to acknowledge the similarity of the other (Melzoff and Moore 1993).

    What is interesting from our point of view is that this capacity is exploited both by the

    child and the mother to construct typical exchanges. We know that the caregivers

    frequently propose the game of imitation imitating themselves the child. In fact if we

    analyze imitation episodes in their context, we see that this is a way to exhibit

    interaction without requiring to refer to any external object. With the development the

    acquired capacities are included in the imitation sequences: manual movements

    between six and eight months, manipulation of toys between eight and ten months

    (Pawlby 1977). If we come back to the beautiful definition by Trevarthen of infants'

    interactions as "communication without object", we find on one side the baby who

    initially has only her predisposition to interact and on the other side the mother who

    proposes games which are rapidly acquired and become the background on which the

    baby constructs her relationship with the others. According again to Trevarthen, when

    motor abilities develop at about nine months, interactions dramatically change

    including in the relationships the external world and in particular objects which can be

  • 9

    manipulated, showed, asked for, etc. Thus, we can conclude that the phase when speech

    acts are formulated even in a nonverbal way is not the first stage of the development but

    the point where motor abilities, i.e. the possibility of performing intentional actions,

    meet with the already established capacity of participating in interactive games with

    others.

    4. Modeling the other and learning to participate in conversations

    A three-year-old child has acquired the capacity of speaking with a sufficiently rich

    vocabulary and following grammatical rules. But still her way of participating in

    communicative interactions is very different from the adults' one. Child's

    communication at this age differs in two ways from adult's one. First, the child is not

    able to detect and repair certain errors, to produce and understand ironic and deceptive

    utterances, to distinguish between deception and joke. Secondly, the child is unaware of

    the strategies which are normally considered typical of polite conversation. These two

    kinds of problems are very distant from each other but they rejoin in one point. They

    both are due to the lack of representational capacities of the child, still to be developed

    at this age. According to recent studies on the theory of mind the young child is not able

    to model higher order mental states, i.e. mental states on mental states (Perner and

    Wimmer 1985). Many experiments have been done and the results have been included

    by Perner (1991) in a general framework. Children do not acquire the concept of

    representation until they are four years of age. This acquisition allows them to

    understand that different individuals may entertain different representations of the same

    object. Already in Perner (1988) it was noted that this fact could be seen as a difficulty

    if we adopt for communication Grice's theory of nonnatural meaning (Grice 1957)

    where second-order beliefs are part of the definition. In fact also the beginning of the

    solution was offered by Perner. Normal communication is based on the transparence of

    intentions and beliefs. This enables young children to communicate. On the contrary,

    the development of higher-order mental states is necessary to understand errors and

    nonliteral uses of language. Actually, Gricean theory needs revisions both for formal

    reasons and in order to make it satisfactory from the cognitive point of view. In Airenti,

    Bara and Colombetti (1993a) we made a formal proposal which is in the line of

    Perner's intuition. Starting from Strawson (1964) Gricean definition of nonnatural

    meaning has been integrated and developed by several authors introducing more levels

    to rule out cases of noncommunicative transfer of information. This poses two more

    problems. On one side these are logical solutions with no psychological reality in that it

    is implausible also for an adult mind that the very fact of performing a communicative

    act implies a large number of calculations. Besides, it can be shown that no definition

    including a finite number of nested intentions is acceptable. For any nth-order intention

  • 10

    there is always the possibility that the intention n+1 is not verified making the

    interactive situation not fully overt. Our proposal has been to define the intention to

    communicate as a mental state S such that an actor entertaining S intends that the whole

    S is mutually recognized by the actor herself and her partner. This solution is

    compatible with the requirement to define a degree 0 of communication. My hypothesis

    is that this primitive mental state is part of infants cognitive endowment. It corresponds

    to a situation of complete sharedness which is the only possibility for a young child.

    When the concept of representation is developed, the acquisition that sharedness is not

    always verified allows for the production and comprehension of more complex

    communicative acts where sharedness is not verified in some point. Failure, irony,

    deception are very different cases of this kind whose peculiarities have been analyzed in

    Airenti, Bara and Colombetti (1993b).

    As we have seen at the beginning of this section, the other aspect where the

    communication of a young child differs from an adult's one is the management of

    conversation. Here a distinction has to be done between the organization of turn-taking

    and other strategies. In fact, as we have already seen, the respect of alternation seems to

    be the first feature of interactions that an infant acquires. For the other features of

    conversation we seem to have the opposite situation: children look highly incompetent.

    As Forster (1990) has noted, conversation skills are submitted to an explicit learning. A

    child who, as we have seen in Section 2, is perfectly able to understand an indirect

    speech act will not spontaneously use polite indirect forms unless taught to do so. In

    this we can see a link with the theory of mind again. In fact the great majority of

    conversation strategies are aimed at the mutual respect of face (Brown, Levinson 1987).

    This is the reason why, for instance, it is not suitable to introduce a topic according to

    the partners' goals abruptly but each topic has to be preceded by greetings and other

    polite formulas which start the interaction and that have to be repeated before the

    interaction can be interrupted (Schegloff and Sacks 1973). This is also the reason for

    the frequent choice of indirect formulas, the so-called indirect speech acts, the pre-

    sequences, the markers used to introduce dispreferred seconds, the hierarchy of

    preferences in repair, the important set of phenomena studied by the analysts of

    conversation (Schegloff, Jefferson and Sacks 1977; Schegloff 1988). The rule of

    mutually preserving face prescribes that the partners have a possibility of an honorable

    retreat at the conversation level, we could say, when their behavioral goals do not

    match. As said before conversational cooperation has to be achieved even when

    behavioral one is not. Brown and Levinson stress that preserving face is a universal

    phenomenon which constrains but does not determine the way it is performed in

    different cultures. What links conversational rules to the problem of representation is

    the fact that only the possibility to represent others' mental states makes it possible to

  • 11

    understand rules whose motivation is social and which are realized in a purely

    conventional way. Only when able to form an accurate model of the other the child will

    understand that an indirect request can be more effective than a direct one, that in some

    way language can affect others' feelings, that nobody likes refusals, etc. The possibility

    to deal with these facts in an effective way is the result of a long process of learning

    done by trial and error and with the constant assistance of the adults.

    In conclusion, the problem of what communication is is twofold. We have to define

    the minimal requirements for communication, and the definition we provide has to give

    account of the fact that infants are able to participate in communicative interactions

    very soon. There is no reason to assume that these basic principles change in adult life

    and in fact they guide an important part of normal behavior. But adults have one more

    capacity: they can model the others' minds. This means that communication can

    become a much more complex phenomenon where the conversation artifices are used

    both to convey and to interpret pragmatic meanings, adequate to the represented mental

    states.

    5. The development of the speaker's meaning

    In this section I shall propose to place the features of communication which have been

    discussed in the preceding part in a new framework. Actually, when we take the

    developmental point of view a number of pragmatic problems can be viewed in a

    different perspective: instead of an heterogeneous collection of phenomena we have a

    set of cognitive capacities which develop in time allowing for communicative

    exchanges of increasing elaboration.

    If we follow the first months of an infant the main feature which strikes us is her

    ability to share experience with other humans. This can be seen in the almost immediate

    synchronization that is achieved in the first common activities with the mother, feeding

    in particular. As the infant acquires a new ability (sounds emission, smile, etc.) she

    performs it toward the caregiver, the ability becomes an element of the interaction. This

    is true, as we have seen, also when no specific necessity is present. At this stage of

    development it seems difficult to see any possible derivation of this intention to share

    from more primitive mental states. Such a precocious ability can be explained only by

    postulating the existence of a primitive mental state. In Airenti, Bara and Colombetti

    (1993a) we have called it intentional communication and have given a formal definition

    of it. In a non formal way we can say that infants have the predisposition to share

    experience with others. Initially, this ability is exercised using the poor elements the

    baby has at her disposal: simple gestures, smile, vocalizations. But these poor tools are

    inserted in a frame of alternation which constructs interactions. These interactions

    become part of the experience of the child and constitute the basis for new interactions.

  • 12

    In theoretical terms, these interactions become part of the knowledge of the child in the

    form of games, i.e. structures describing stereotyped interactions. The relationship

    between the baby and the caregiver at the beginning is rather asymmetrical. It will be

    the caregiver who will propose games which can be played by them or who will qualify

    a gesture of the infant as communicative inserting it in a game. But the child manifests

    the capacity of participating in the games, implicitly understanding their rules: turn-

    taking, repetition, possible slight variations on the basis of an established routine which

    attributes meaning to single actions. I make the hypothesis that the capacity of

    interpreting others' communicative behavior on the basis of a game is innate, and that it

    constitutes with communicative intention human endowment for communication. If we

    define communication as manifesting the intention to share a behavior game -where

    understanding a communicative act means interpreting it within the frame of a behavior

    game- first interactions become cognitively interesting for two reasons. They can

    explain how the most simple examples of communication work and how the basis for

    pragmatic interpretation is constructed.

    To clarify this point of view, let us see an example. In (Airenti, Bara and Colombetti

    1993a) we have presented a number of rules for understanding the speaker's meaning.

    The rules are the formal way to express how a partner understands the speaker's

    meaning, where the speaker's meaning is expressed in terms of the relations of actions,

    linguistic or not, and mental states with games. These rules have been thought of as the

    complete set of possibilities an adult has to understand the speaker's meaning. My

    hypothesis is that these rules are progressively acquired by children. I shall not discuss

    here all the rules. I just want to show as at least one of them can apply also to infants.

    Let us examine the following rule:

    In the shared belief space, playing a move of a valid game counts by default as

    communicating the intention to play the game with the partner.

    This rule can be paraphrased in this way. If a partner acknowledges that an actor is

    overtly playing a move of a typical game of theirs, he will interpret this act as the

    intention to play the game. For example, if John and Susan normally eat biscuits when

    watching a movie together, the fact that after dinner Susan goes and fetches biscuits,

    will be interpreted by John as the proposal to play the 'movie game' - and he will react

    looking for a movie, or discussing a possible choice if he agrees with the proposal while

    he will explain that he is tired, he has work to do, he prefers to do something else, etc. if

    he doesn't. If we analyze first interactions we can see that also babies behave according

    to this rule. When mothers do some activity with their babies, at feeding and changing

    time for instance, or when mothers shift infants position, they are involved in

    interactions where the mothers have a complex repertoire of actions and babies respond

    with gestures, sounds, smiles, facial expressions, etc. Already when the baby is

  • 13

    two/three months old each pair develops typical modalities of interactions, games: the

    mother tickles the infant who smiles. The mother questions the infant who coos. So

    also in this case the baby identifies the other's action as connected to, part of a game. In

    fact observations of this kind have been done on eight-day-old babies (Chappel and

    Sanders 1979). Finally, evidence in favor of an actual engagement of the infant in the

    communicative games comes from studies, made in laboratory on ten-week-old

    children, aimed at studying the effects of perturbations of normal interactions (Tronick,

    Als and Adamson 1979). The mothers were instructed to slow down their rhythm with

    the babies or to interrupt exchanges remaining still-faced, or to show only their profile

    to the babies. In all these situations the infants adjusted their reactions appropriately to

    the actions of their partner. For instance, when the mother interrupted a communicative

    exchange with the baby and froze her expression, the baby tried all her repertoire of

    facial expressions and limb movements in an attempt to restore normal interaction. As

    stressed by the authors of these studies, the previous results show that the infants do not

    exhibit a rigid pattern of behavior into which the mothers fit themselves. On the

    contrary, babies are aware of the communicative situation and react accordingly. A

    major point distinguishing these interactions from adult ones is asymmetry. It is up to

    the caregiver to propose games which do not exceed the infants' capacities.

    When the abilities of the baby augment, and in particular motor abilities manifest,

    the real change is that the baby makes the world enter in her interactions and can

    propose games invented by herself: for instance she throws away an object expecting

    the mother to pick it up and give it back to her. What makes playing games in these

    situations different from the situations where adults are involved is again asymmetry.

    Conditions of validity of games are in general dictated by adults. The amusing game of

    throwing objects, for instance, cannot be done with breakable or heavy objects, it has to

    be stopped at lunch time, etc.

    In this phase we can say that at least two other rules for understanding the speaker's

    meaning are active.

    In the shared belief space, if the actor communicates that she intends to perform a

    move of a valid game, then by default she communicates that she intends to play the

    game with the partner.

    In the shared belief space, if the actor communicates that she intends to induce the

    partner perform a move of a valid game, then by default she communicates that she

    intends to play the game with the partner.

    In fact, if the caregiver says: "I am looking for the pail and the spade" or "Go, Tom, and

    fetch your pail and your spade", in both cases the child will understand that the

    caregiver is proposing to play the game to go out to a sand-pit.

  • 14

    The maturation of language in a sense is not a revolution, in that it does not change

    the fundamental structures of communication. All the same it offers a lot of new

    possibilities on the side of content. Games that can be played using only nonverbal

    items are limited in number. Moreover language speeds up the acquisition of new

    games and particularly their transmission. In fact what is characteristic of first

    interactions is that few people are involved. To construct games just performing actions

    requires a very intimate acquaintance. When two persons know each other very well a

    simple gesture performed by one can be understood by the other as the proposal of

    playing a certain game but the same gesture for a foreigner will be completely

    meaningless. In the first interactions this is the only actual possibility. Language allows

    for naming games and proposing them to a much larger set of persons.

    Up to this point what the child can do is a restricted set of operations. The richness is

    given by the number of games that can grow rapidly, but the procedure remains simple

    as simple is the model of the other which the child uses: people are influenced by

    communicative acts as doors are influenced by pressure. A very young child in case of

    failure just cries, both if a door does not open and when the mother does not give a

    desired object (Harding and Golinkoff 1979). Starting with the second year the child

    will try to repair the failure but again the strategies will not be different in the two

    cases: repetition of the act, repetition with some change, etc. (Golinkoff 1983). What

    makes communication possible for a child who is not able to deal with higher order

    mental states and to conceive the fact that different persons can hold different

    representations of situations and of others' mental states, is the attribution of sharedness.

    The ability to perform more refined communicative acts is due to the comprehension

    that sharedness is not always verified. But sharedness is still the assumption that is used

    in trivial exchanges even in adult life and which makes them not problematic. The

    derivation from sharedness of nested mental states is the way to cope with particularly

    critical situations as for instance when we need to know if someone wants to deceive us.

    The ability to produce realistic models of others is also a prerequisite to use the whole

    set of conversation rules.

    Conclusions

    My paper has started with the premise that no theory of language use can be done which

    is based only on adults communication. In fact communicating is a human activity and

    as such develops from birth to adult life. Taking into account development enlightens

    phenomena which are otherwise rather opaque. Interactions evolve before language is

    acquired and this fact has to be explained. Two possibilities are left. Either first

    interactions are communicative, and in this case we have to admit that communication

    develops separately from language, or we reserve the term communication for

  • 15

    linguistic interactions and we consider that in the first period of life children interact

    with others in a way which is not communicative, but in this case we have to explain

    what these interactions are. The reason to deny that first interactions are communicative

    derives from Gricean definition of communication. It involves higher order mental

    states which we are not allowed to attribute to infants. On the other hand, it seems

    sound to attribute to babies the capacity to deal with sharedness. A theory thus can be

    conceived where there is a continuity from first interactions to adults' ones. A theory

    where the starting point is the reciprocal attribution of sharedness, and the evolution is

    based on the successively developed ability to treat with higher order mental states.

    This explains both that communication is possible very soon and that first interactions

    are limited. Moreover, it explains the trivial character of an important part of adults'

    interactions (Airenti 2001).

    Intentional communication is a mental state and cannot be derived. Saying that

    communication is a form of action is a theoretical definition which is very useful in

    order to understand the social value of language but there is no demonstration that the

    intention to communicate is linked with the mental structures underlying action (Airenti

    1999). When a child indicates something to an adult in order to take possession of it,

    we say that she is doing a speech act. In fact this is not correct because what is specific

    of speech acts is their conventional form. What the child is doing in reality is to express

    a communicative intention regarding a given object. Something more can be said at

    this point on indirect speech acts. From the developmental point of view this concept

    looses its content. In fact, we have already seen that as regards comprehension children

    do not perceive any difference between indirect and direct forms. They understand the

    nonconventional form which is behind. As regards production, some forms are learned

    late (Gordon and Ervin-Tripp 1984). An explicit and repeated teaching is necessary to

    have a child acquire forms like: "Would you please give me..." or "I would like to

    have..." , etc. At the same time some indirect forms are among the first acquired speech

    acts: think of expressions like "I want chocolate". All these facts show that this concept

    is cognitively implausible.

    The speaker's meaning is the interpretation of a communicative act against the

    background of what the agents share about the relational context, the behavior game. In

    my view games are fit to explain both first nonverbal interactions as they are described

    in developmental literature and the mix of nonverbal and verbal interactions used in

    adult communication. The concept of behavior game seems useful to clarify the role to

    be attributed to cognitive and social aspects in communication. Communication is the

    product of individual minds who have at their disposal specific structures to represent

    interactions. This is the constraint on the set of all possible inferences that a

    communicative act in principle could admit. This constraint is active also in production

  • 16

    leading to exclude what is not part of the available games or of their admitted

    extensions. The fact that this is the content of an individual mind explains the

    possibility of errors.

    Conversation rules are the socially admitted way to exchange communicative

    intentions. They repose on two basic facts regarding interactions: the alternation and the

    preservation of face. The first aspect is one of the infants' first acquisitions and

    according to the necessities of the dialogical structure it will be specialized in turn-

    taking organization rules. The second aspect develops when the children have the

    possibility to represent themselves and to represent the others as individuals with

    possibly different representations. This is the minimal requirement for a child to

    understand that private intentions involving others have to be negotiated and that

    conversation strategies have a function in this process. The management of the

    techniques of conversation is the result of some years of learning. The slowness of the

    process is explained by the fact that even if the motivation is universal the

    implementation of conversation strategies is strictly conventional and culturally

    determined.

    Acknowledgements

    The research reported in this paper has been supported by the MURST (Italian Ministry

    for University and Scientific and Technological Research) for the year 1998.

    I thank Carlo Severi and Maurizio Tirassa for their helpful comments on the

    manuscript.

    References

    AIRENTI, GABRIELLA. 1999. Rational action and communication: differences in development.

    Proceedings of the European Conference on Cognitive Science, Siena: 219-223

    ---. 2001. Le rle des reprsentations dans le dveloppement de la capacit communicative. Intellectica

    1, 32: 155-183

    AIRENTI, GABRIELLA, BRUNO G. BARA and MARCO COLOMBETTI. 1993a. Conversation and

    behavior games in the pragmatics of dialogue. Cognitive Science 17: 197-256

    ---. 1993b. Failures, exploitations and deceits in communication. Journal of Pragmatics 20, 4: 303-

    326

    AUSTIN, JOHN L. 1962. How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    BATES, ELIZABETH, LUIGIA CAMAIONI and VIRGINIA VOLTERRA. 1976. Sensorimotor

    performatives. In Elizabeth Bates. (ed.). Language and context. New York: Academic Press: 49-71.

    BELLUGI, URSULA, SHELLY MARKS, AMY M. BIHRLE and HELENE SABO. 1988. Dissociation

    between language and cognitive functions in Williams Syndrome. In Dorothy Bishop and Kay

  • 17

    Mogford. (eds.). Language development in exceptional circumstances. London: Churchill

    Livingstone: 177-189

    BLANK, MARION, MYRON GESSNER and ANITA ESPOSITO. 1979. Language without

    communication: a case study. Journal of Child Language 6: 329-352

    BROWN, PENELOPE and STEPHEN C. LEVINSON. 1987. Politeness. Some universals in language

    usage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    BRUNER, JEROME S. 1975. The ontogenesis of speech acts. Journal of child language 2: 1-19

    ---. 1983a. Child's talk: learning to use language. New York: Norton

    ---. 1983b. The acquisition of pragmatic commitments. In: Roberta M. Golinkoff. (ed.). The transition

    from prelinguistic to linguistic communication, Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlsbaum: 27-42

    BULLOWA, MARGARET. (ed.). 1979. Before speech. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    BUTTERWORTH, GEORGE. 1991. The ontogeny and phylogeny of joint visual attention. In Andrew

    Whiten. (ed.). Natural theories of mind. Oxford: Basil Blackwell: 223-232

    CHAPPELL, P. F. and LOUIS W. SANDER. 1979. Mutual regulation of the neonatal-maternal

    interactive process: context for the origins of communication. In Margaret Bullowa. (ed.). Before

    speech. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 89-109

    CHOMSKY, NOAM. 1975. Reflections on language. New York: Pantheon Books

    CURTISS, SUSAN. 1977. Genie: A psycholinguistic study of a modern-day "wild child", New York:

    Academic Press

    ---. 1989. The independence and task-specificity of language. In Marc H. Bornstein and Jerome S.

    Bruner. (eds.). Interaction in human development. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum: 105-137

    FOSTER, SUSAN H. 1990. The communicative competence of young children. London: Longman

    GELMAN, ROCHEL. 1983. Reconsidering the transition from prelinguistic to linguistic

    communication. In Roberta M.Golinkoff. (ed.). The transition from prelinguistic to linguistic

    communication. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlsbaum: 275-279

    GOLINKOFF, ROBERTA M., 1983. The preverbal negotiation of failed messages: insights into the

    transition period. In Roberta M. Golinkoff. (ed.). The transition from prelinguistic to linguistic

    communication. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlsbaum: 57-78

    GORDON, D. and SUSAN ERVIN-TRIPP. 1984. The structure of children's requests. In Richard L.

    Schiefelbusch and Joanne Pickar. (eds.). The acquisition of communicative competence, Baltimore:

    University Park Press: 295-322

    GRICE, H. PAUL. 1957. Meaning. Philosophical Review 67: 377-388

    ---. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Peter Cole and Jerry L. Morgan. (eds.). Syntax and semantics 3:

    speech acts. New York: Academic Press: 41-58

    ---. 1978. Further notes on logic and conversation. In Peter Cole. (ed.). Syntax and semantics 9:

    Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press: 113-128

    HARDING, CAROL G. and ROBERTA M. GOLINKOFF. 1979. The origins of intentional

    vocalizations in prelinguistic infants. Child Development 50: 13-40

  • 18

    LEVINSON, STEPHEN C. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    MELZOFF, ANDREW N. and M.KEITH MOORE. 1977. Imitation of facial and manual gestures by

    human neonates. Science 198: 75-78

    ---. 1993. Why faces are special to infants. On connecting the attraction of faces and infants' ability for

    imitation and cross-modal processing. In Bndicte de Boysson-Bardies, Scania de Schonen, Peter

    Jusczyk, Peter MacNeilage and John Morton. (eds.). Developmental neurocognition: speech and face

    processing in the first year of life. Dordrecht: Kluwer

    PAWLBY, SUSAN J. 1977. Imitative interaction. In: H.Rudolph Schaffer. (ed.). Studies in mother-

    infant interaction, London: Academic Press: 203-224

    PERNER, JOSEF. 1988. Higher-order beliefs and intentions in children's understanding of social

    interaction. In Janet W. Astington, Paul L.Harris and David R.Olson. (eds.). Developing theories of

    mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 271-294

    ---. 1991. Understanding the representational mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press/Bradford

    PERNER, JOSEF and HEINZ WIMMER. 1985. "John thinks that Mary thinks that ...": attribution of

    second-order beliefs by 5- to 10-year old children Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 39:

    437-471

    PREMACK, DAVID. 1990. Words: what are they, and do animals have them?. Cognition 37: 197-212

    PREMACK, DAVID and ANN JAMES PREMACK. 1994. Why animals have neither culture nor

    history. In Tim Ingold. (ed.). Companion Encyclopedia of Anthropology. London: Routledge,

    SACKS, HARVEY, EMMANUEL A. SCHEGLOFF and GAIL JEFFERSON. 1974. A simplest

    systematics for the organization of turn-taking in conversation. Language 50: 696-735

    SCHAFFER, H.RUDOLPH. (ed.). 1977. Studies in Mother-Infant Interaction. London: Academic Press.

    SCHEGLOFF, EMMANUEL A.. 1988. Presequences and indirection: applying speech act theory to

    ordinary conversation. Journal of Pragmatics 12, 1: 55-62

    SCHEGLOFF, EMMANUEL A., GAIL JEFFERSON and HARVEY SACKS. 1977. The preference for

    self-correction in the organization of repair in conversation. Language 53: 361-382

    SCHEGLOFF, EMMANUEL A. and HARVEY SACKS. 1973. Opening up closings. Semiotica 7:

    289-327

    SEARLE, JOHN R. 1969. Speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    ---. 1972. Chomsky's revolution in linguistics. New York Review of Books June 2

    SHATZ, MARILYN. 1978. Children's comprehension of their mother's question-directives. Journal of

    Child Language 5: 39-46

    ---. 1983. On transition, continuity and coupling: an alternative approach to communicative

    development. In Roberta M.Golinkoff. (ed.). The transition from prelinguistic to linguistic

    communication. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlsbaum: 43-55

    SMITH, NEIL V., IANTHI-MARIA TSIMPLI and JAMAL OUHALLA. 1993. Learning the

    impossible: the acquisition of possible and impossible languages by a polyglot savant. Lingua 91:

    279-347

  • 19

    SPERBER, DAN and DEIRDRE WILSON. 1986a. Relevance. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University

    Press

    ---. 1986b. Inference and implicature. In Charles Travis. (ed.). Meaning and interpretation. Oxford:

    Blackwell: 45-75

    STRAWSON, PETER F. 1964. Intention and convention in speech acts. Philosophical Review 73: 439-

    460.

    TREVARTHEN, COLWYN. 1977. Descriptive analyses of infant communicative behaviour. In

    H.Rudolph Schaffer. (ed.). Studies in mother-infant interaction. London: Academic Press: 227-270

    TREVARTHEN, COLWYN and PENELOPE HUBLEY. 1978. Secondary intersubjectivity: confidence,

    confiding and acts of meaning in the first year. In Andrew Lock. (ed.). Action, gesture, and symbol:

    the emergence of language. London: Academic Press: 183-229

    TRONICK, EDWARD, HEIDELISE ALS and LAUREN ADAMSON. 1979. Structure of early face-to-

    face communicative interactions. In Margaret Bullowa. (ed.). Before speech. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press: 349-372

    UDWIN, ORLEE and WILLIAM YULE. 1991. A cognitive and behavioural phenotype in Williams

    Syndrome. Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology 2: 232-244