WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

  • Upload
    diana

  • View
    227

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    1/13

    Social Constructivism, Positivism, and Facilitated Communication

    Grover J. Whitehurst & Deanne A. Crone

    State University of New York at Stony Brook

    Running head: Social Constructivism, Positivism, and Facilitated Communication

    Published in The Journal of the Association of Persons with Severe

    Handicaps, 1994, 19, 191-195.

    Preparation of this article was supported by grants to G. J. Whitehurst from the Pew Charitable

    Trusts (91-01249-000), and the U.S. Administration for Children and Families (90CD095701 &

    90CD096201). Views expressed herein are the authors and have not been cleared by the grantors.

    Requests for reprints and inquiries can be addressed to G. J. Whitehurst, Department of Psychology,

    SUNY, Stony Brook, NY 11794-2500 (e-mail [email protected]) .

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    2/13

    Social Constructivism, Positivism, and Facilitated Communication

    Abstract

    Facilitated communication, a technique that is said to enhance the communicative abilities of

    individuals with severe language impairments, has engendered much controversy. Biklen and

    Duchan (1994) and Green and Shane (1994) present two sides of this controversy. Biklen and

    Duchan argue that from a constructivist's perspective, the primary issue is the underlying cultural

    presuppositions regarding mental retardation and science rather than the efficacy of facilitated

    communication. Green and Shane present research evidence challenging the efficacy of facilitated

    communication within a positivist's framework. We present a brief review of science as viewed

    through positivists' and constructivists' lenses. Using the framework of social constructivism

    adopted by Biklen and Duchan, we disagree with them on three points: 1) even though the process of

    constructing scientific knowledge is strongly affected by human social, emotional, and cognitive

    processes, it also involves matters of fact that cannot be ignored; 2) social constructivists' accounts

    of science can be accepted as descriptive without being prescriptive; 3) while we cannot prove that

    belief systems, including positivism and social constructivism, are true or false in the larger sense,

    belief systems have differential consequences for technological changes of the type that are valued by

    persons with severe impairments of communication.

    Page 1

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    3/13

    Facilitated communication is a procedure that is said to enhance the communicative abilities of

    persons with severe impairments in typical modes of oral or written language, particularly individuals

    diagnosed with autism or intellectual retardation. Typically, a communicatively normal adult, the

    facilitator, supports the wrist or arm of the person with the communicative deficiency as that person

    generates messages by selecting letters from a letter board or special typewriter. Advocates of

    facilitated communication have attributed remarkable improvements in the ability to communicate by

    people with severe communicative impairments to this procedure (e.g., Biklen, 1993; Crossley,

    1992).

    In a characteristic case report (Biklen, 1990), Jonothan, a 7-year-old described as autistic,

    incontinent, and without any history of expressive language, reportedly began typing messages in the

    first few minutes of exposure to facilitated communication: "Crossley managed to settle Jonothan on

    her sofa .... She typed 'JONOTHAN,' followed by 'MUM,' and then asked him for 'Dad.' He went

    straight to the D .... She typed 'JONATHAN,' whereupon he [with Crossley holding his hand] typed

    'JONOTHAN.' Crossley later checked the spelling with his mother. Jonothan had been correct" (p.

    294). In a later interaction, Jonothan reportedly typed a message about someone having sat on him

    and was asked by Biklen whether he meant that literally or metaphorically. "Jonothan [with

    Crossley holding his hand] responded by typing 'MET'" (p. 292).

    That literacy would emerge spontaneously in anyone and then be applied to abstract semantic

    distinctions such as "metaphorical" is remarkable. It is even more remarkable that such a

    phenomenon would occur with an otherwise low functioning 7-year-old. In normally developing

    children, the ability to understand grapheme-phoneme correspondences (e.g., that the word "Dad"

    starts with the /d/ sound which corresponds to the letter D) and the ability to translate that

    knowledge into print typically requires instruction at home and/or at school and proceeds along a

    Page 2

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    4/13

    regular and gradual course (Adams, 1990). The sudden emergence of these abilities in people

    labeled autistic or retarded would represent a critically important therapeutic breakthrough as well as

    a significant challenge to theories of autism, retardation, and literacy acquisition.

    The use of facilitated communication with communicatively impaired populations has

    burgeoned in the United States, perhaps due to the presentation of dramatic case histories by Biklen

    (1990), Crossley (1992) and others. Controversy over its meaning and effectiveness has gone hand

    in hand with its increased implementation. In an effort to present both sides of this controversy, the

    editors of this journal asked Biklen and Duchan (1994) and Green and Shane (1994) to respond to

    10 questions concerning facilitated communication, such as "Under what conditions ... might

    facilitated communication work and what evidence is available?" These authors were apt choices as

    Biklen has been the major advocate for facilitated communication in the United States, and Green

    has generated the largest body of research questioning its efficacy. We considered ourselves

    reasonable choices as commentators on their papers. Our basic research on the development of

    children's communication skills (e.g., Sonnenschein & Whitehurst, 1984) and our applied research on

    interventions for language delay (e.g., Whitehurst, et al., 1991; Whitehurst et al., 1994; Whitehurst &

    Fischel, 1994) is similar enough to the subject matter of facilitated communication to allow us a basis

    for evaluating competing claims. At the same time our work has never involved the severely

    impaired, nor do we know or have any connection with the principals in the controversy. Thus we

    looked forward to sorting through the answers to the questions posed by the editors with what we

    hoped would be both an absence of interfering bias and the perception of neutrality.

    As it turned out, Green and Shane hued closely to the task set by the editors, while Biklen and

    Duchan chose instead to argue that the editors' questions were invalid: "the controversy ... is not just

    about whether particular individuals are authoring their own messages, nor is it about whether the

    Page 3

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    5/13

    method is successful or not. It is not about what percentage of people can be proven competent, or

    about the percentage who have achieved or will achieve independent typing" (Biklen & Duchan,

    1994, p. 34-35). Questions such as these are said by Biklen and Duchan to reflect "a positivist

    perspective, implying that there are objective truths about facilitated communication that can be

    discovered through research studies" (p. 22). Biklen and Duchan take the position that they are

    practicing a different type of science, one incommensurate with questions concerning objective truths

    about facilitated communication. This type of science, called social constructivism (and conflated by

    Biklen and Duchan with other descriptors such as competence-based, phenomenological,

    experiential, ethnographic, and interpretivist), is said to lead to questions, methods, and answers that

    are different from those of positivists' science, and equally valid, e.g., "Our aim in this article is to

    provide convincing evidence to show that mental retardation does not exist as fact separate from

    interpretation ...." (p.2).

    Before detailing our disagreement with Biklen and Duchan's interpretation of social

    constructivism and its relevance for basic issues concerning facilitated communication, we note

    several points on which they and we are of like minds: 1) People with mental retardation should be

    treated with respect as individuals. 2) It is important to consider individuals' competencies as well as

    their deficiencies. 3) Labeling a person as retarded has repercussions on that person's life

    circumstances. 4) If an individual has the cognitive ability to communicate, but does not possess the

    necessary motoric skills, that person should be assisted by any valid means to express his/her

    thoughts and feelings. 5) Individuals involved in a discourse influence each other. 6) Data should be

    collected across time and under different circumstances for the same individual in order to produce

    an accurate assessment of that person's abilities and deficits. 7) It is interesting and important to

    determine how people with severe communicative impairments interpret their experience. 8) Data

    Page 4

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    6/13

    collected in natural circumstances can present a different view than data collected in highly controlled

    circumstances. 9) Ethnographic, qualitative research can be extremely useful in allowing scientists to

    formulate the intuitions and hypotheses that are a critical prerequisite to the most creative controlled

    research. 10) People without advanced degrees or special credentials can be trained to provide

    effective services for people with special needs.

    We have no particular bias regarding the efficacy or importance of facilitated communication.

    The research reviewed by Green and Shane seems to us to present a strong negative case for the

    general efficacy of the procedure, but we think the possibility of facilitated communication being

    useful in occasional specific cases is not entirely foreclosed and should be the topic of continued

    research. We do however have strong views about philosophy and research on social constructivism

    and its relevance to the evaluation of claims that are said to be scientific. Biklen and Duchan have

    used tenets of social constructivism to legitimize their claim that the utility and validity of facilitated

    communication need not be evaluated. They have attempted to refocus debate on the issue of the

    cultural presuppositions underlying mental retardation. We will attempt to place social

    constructivism in the context of the scientific enterprise and explain why Biklen and Duchan have

    misused it. In doing so we have been influenced by the work of our colleague, Stephen Cole

    (1992), who views the larger philosophical issue, of which social constructivism is one variant, as

    being able to account for consensus in science. That is, why do scientists come to agree that certain

    theories or claims of fact are justified and others are not?

    In the traditional positivists' view that is held by nearly all working scientists, science consists of

    claims about matters of fact. Scientists who wish to contribute to the body of knowledge that

    represents their discipline submit the results of their work to a process of peer review in which

    agreed upon criteria for publication are applied. These criteria consist of a set of clear rules for

    Page 5

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    7/13

    judging the procedural adequacy of the research and more fuzzy judgments regarding the work's

    importance. Given that the application of these criteria is subject to ordinary human frailties,

    mistakes are expected to occur. These include false claims of fact that are published, true claims of

    fact that are rejected, and the publication of work that is trivial. Mistakes at the level of publication

    are corrected by a second and more stringent evaluation occurring at the level of the audience of

    scientists to whom the published work should be relevant. The massive volume of published

    research in almost all fields of science is winnowed by the process of selective citation in subsequent

    research efforts. The net effect is cumulative science: The false or trivial research falls by the

    wayside, while the valid and important claims of fact become part of the enduring core.

    The last 50 years have witnessed a sustained attack on the positivists' view of science by

    philosophers and other critics. Though the arguments against positivism may vary, at the core of

    each is an appreciation of the degree to which science is a product of human cognitive, social, and

    emotional processes. The net effect is an acknowledgment that scientists, unlike Spock, are not

    perfectly rational beings. Instead they are involved and invested in a process of making meaning

    from their data and successes of their careers. At the least, this means that scientific theories and the

    degree of allegiance they engender are not completely dependent on observationally reliable facts.

    For instance, Lakatos (1970, p. 70) argued that observations (i.e., facts) in science are always theory

    laden:

    Galileo claimed that he could "observe" mountains on the moon and spots on the sun and

    that these "observations" refuted the time-honoured theory that celestial bodies are faultless crystal balls. But his "observations" were not "observational" in the sense of

    being observed by the -- unaided -- senses: Their reliability depended on the reliability of

    his telescope -- and of the optical theory of the telescope -- which was violently questioned

    by his contemporaries.

    In a similar vein, Kuhn (1962) held that science is not cumulative. New approaches are simply

    Page 6

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    8/13

    different rather than better than the ones they replace. In fact, according to Kuhn, objective truth

    plays no role in the evaluation of theories or paradigms. He notes that when Newton first published

    the inverse square law and his calculation from it of the predicted motion of the moon at perigee, the

    motion that could be observed with available methods was only half that predicted. Yet the theory

    was generally accepted during the 60 years that passed until the observational data caught up to it.

    In addition to philosophical writings, there is research that demonstrates the extent of

    irrationality in the scientific process. For example, a large and consistent body of work shows that

    consensus among reviewers of manuscripts submitted to prestigious journals or the National Science

    Foundation is relatively low (e.g., Whitehurst, 1984, Cole, Cole, & Simon, 1981). In one

    particularly revealing study, 12 already published research articles were resubmitted to the original

    journals a year or so later with fictitious authors and institutions, but otherwise unaltered (Peters &

    Ceci, 1982). Of the nine articles that were not detected as resubmissions by journal editors, eight

    were eventually rejected. In many cases the grounds given for rejection were described as "serious

    methodological flaws." As the argument goes, if science were a rational enterprise, firmly grounded

    in matters of fact, results such as these would be impossible.

    A final research and theoretical influence that has played a key role in the development of social

    constructivism is the theory of Piaget (1976, p. 13), who holds that objective knowledge structures

    "are the result of a construction and are not given in the objects, since they are dependent on action,

    nor in the subject, since the subject must learn how to coordinate his actions ..." This is the principal

    hypothesis of social constructivism, that learners construct their knowledge of the external world and

    this knowledge depends as much on learners' physical and mental actions as on the external world.

    Evidence supporting Piaget's position takes the form of demonstrating that individuals will fail to

    acquire certain specific concepts despite adequate teaching or exposure unless their general state of

    Page 7

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    9/13

    cognitive development allows those specific concepts to be assimilated. For instance, Lawson et al.

    (1991) demonstrated that skill at hypothetic-deductive reasoning rather than age predicted whether

    high school students could learn particular classification tasks that involved systematically testing

    alternative hypotheses about class membership.

    There are many problems with the types of evidence that have been presented in support of the

    contructivists' view. For instance, the low reliability in peer review may be an artifact of the

    statistical procedures that are applied to measure it (Whitehurst, 1984), and the claims of close links

    between Piagetian stages of development and the learning of specific tasks have been seriously

    challenged (Brainerd, 1978). However, suppose we accept the claims or implications of social

    constructivism that flow from the material we have briefly reviewed: 1) the history of science

    includes many instances in which ideas and theories have had far more influence on generating

    scientific consensus than have observable facts; 2) the history of science can as often be characterized

    as due to the theoretical equivalent of fad and fancy as to the relentless forward march of cumulative

    knowledge; 3) the procedures for judging the worth of contemporary research at the level of peer

    review are filled with caprice; and 4) the construction of human knowledge depends as much on

    actions of the learner as on the external world. Even so, does it follow that Biklen and Duchan, or

    indeed anybody who wishes to cloak their work in the mantle of science, can reasonably take the

    position that they need not address matters of fact because there are no objective truths that can be

    discovered through research? We think the answer is clearly no, for three reasons.

    First, the only thing that the empirical, philosophical, and historical analyses of social

    constructivists demonstrate, if taken at face value, is that human processes that are not grounded in

    matters of fact or the formal rules of science have a very significant impact on the products of

    science. However, such a demonstration does not exclude a separate or interacting role for reality,

    Page 8

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    10/13

    nature, or objective truth in the production of scientific consensus, either logically or empirically.

    Certainly in Piaget's theory, which is a touchstone of constructivists' thinking, knowledge emerges as

    a joint product of the learner and the object. Cole (1992, p. 25) describes the necessary role of

    empirical facts in science as follows:

    Even though in some 'ultimate' sense there may be no way to determine whether one

    paradigm is a better approximation to the 'real' laws of nature than another, the exclusion

    of nature and the empirical world from our model of how scientific knowledge grows

    makes it difficult to understand why some knowledge enters the core and most does not....

    [Consider HIV and AIDS.] If a vaccine is developed and all people who are given it do

    not become HIV positive, then we know that the vaccine works ..... If we consider the

    scientific goal the development of a vaccine for the virus that leads to AIDS, it becomes

    clear that a successful solution to that problem could not be socially constructed

    independent of the external world, that is, independent of the nature of the virus.

    Second, social constructivists' accounts of science can be accepted as descriptively accurate

    without being accepted as prescriptions for optimal science. Suppose an enterprising reporter

    uncovers evidence of widespread graft and corruption among local politicians. Do we then accept

    graft and corruption as part of the formal definition of local politics, or do we view these activities as

    inconsistent with the ideal of politics and attempt to reduce them? Likewise, if scientists are shown

    to make decisions based on an attempt to curry favor, advance their careers, and be associated with

    what is "hot," often in disregard of matters of fact, should we then make these behaviors criterial for

    science, perhaps replacing courses in research methodology for graduate students with courses on

    how to be obsequious to the big names in one's field?

    Third, though the rules of knowing that define positivists' science are clearly socially

    constructed (and in that sense are no different from the rites of a religious community or the

    principles of astrology), systems of belief are not without differential consequences. Hopi Indians

    Page 9

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    11/13

    performing a rain dance, communication facilitators supporting an impaired child's hand, and

    scientists with a p < .05 effect all believe they are effecting change and all possess an interpretive

    framework in which their behavior has meaning. We may not be able to determine which of these

    and other belief systems is true and which is false, and indeed, such questions may be meaningless.

    We can, however, conclude that the system of belief and practice that Biklen and Duchan label as

    positivists' science, much as it frequently diverges from its idealization, is differentially likely to

    produce technological progress. This includes the domain of communicative impairments. We can

    also conclude that people who call what they are doing science but who do not comport themselves

    in a manner that conforms to that system of belief and practice should expect to be treated like any

    infidel in the temple.

    Thus when Biklen and Duchan (1994, p. 34) say that the controversy is not "about whether the

    method is successful" in the face of a substantial body of evidence that it is not (Green & Shane,

    1994), and simultaneously describe what they are doing as science, they are at best misleading the

    consumers of facilitated communication, who we venture to guess are not spending the huge amount

    of time and effort they invest in facilitated communication based on their commitment to social

    constructivism, and who would certainly be surprised to learn that the world has no objective truths.

    Page 10

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    12/13

    References

    Adams, M.J. (1990). Beginning to read. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Biklen, D. (1990). Communication unbound: Autism and praxis. Harvard Educational Review,

    60, 291-313.

    Biklen, D. (1993). Communication unbound. New York: Teacher's College Press.

    Biklen, D. & Duchan, J.F. (1994). "I am intelligent": The social construction of mental

    retardation. The Journal of the Association for Persons with Severe Handicaps.

    Brainerd, C.J. (1978). The stage question in cognitive-developmental theory. Behavioral and

    Brain Science, 2, 173-213.

    Cole, S. (1992). Making science: Between nature and society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

    University Press.

    Cole, S., Cole, J., & Simon, G. (1981). Chance and consensus in peer review. Science, 214,

    881-886.

    Crossley, R. (1992). Getting the words out: Case studies in facilitated communication training.

    Topics in Language Disorders, 12, 29-45.

    Green, G. & Shane, H.C. (1994). Science, reason, and facilitated communication. The Journal

    of the Association for Persons with Severe Handicaps.

    Kuhn, D. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I.

    Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.) Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91-196).

    Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

    Lawson, A.E., McElrath, C.B., Burton, M.S., James, B.D., Doyle, R.P., Woodward, S.L.,

    Kellerman, L., & Snyder, J.D. (1991). Hypothetico-deductive reasoning skill and concept

    acquisition: Testing a constructivist hypothesis. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 28,

    Page 11

  • 8/14/2019 WhitehurstCrone - Social Constructivism

    13/13

    953-970.

    Peters, D.P. & Ceci, S.J. (1982). Peer-review practices of psychological journals: The fate of

    published articles, submitted again. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 5, 3-11.

    Piaget, J. (1976). The grasp of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Sonnenschein, S., and Whitehurst, G.J. (1984). Developing referential communication: A hierarchy

    of skills. Child Development, 55, 36-45.

    Whitehurst, G.J. (1984). Interrater agreement for journal manuscript reviews. American

    Psychologist, 39, 22-28.

    Whitehurst, G.J., Fischel, J.E., Lonigan, C.J., Valdez-Menchaca, M.C., Arnold, D.S., & Smith, M.

    (1991). Treatment of expressive language delay: If, when and how. Topics in Language

    Disorders, 11, 55-68.

    Whitehurst, G.J., Arnold, D.H., Epstein, J.N., Angell, A.L., Smith, M., & Fischel, J.E. (1994). A

    picture book reading intervention in daycare and home for children from low-income families.

    Developmental Psychology, 30,

    Whitehurst, G.J., & Fischel, J.E. (1994). Early developmental language delay: What, if anything,

    should the clinician do about it?Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 35, 613-648.

    Page 12