26
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Voting Methods First published Wed Aug 3, 2011 Think back to the last time you needed to make a decision as a member of a group. This may have been when you voted for your favorite political candidate during the last election. On a smaller scale, it may have been when you took part in a committee that needed to choose the best candidate for a job or a student to receive a special award. What method, or procedure, did the group use to make the final decision? Many interesting issues arise when we carefully examine our group decisionmaking processes. Consider a simple example of a group of friends deciding where to go for dinner. If everyone agrees on which restaurant is best, then it is obvious where to go. But how should the friends decide where to go if they have different opinions about which restaurant is best? Is there always a choice that is “fair” taking into account everyone's opinions? Or are there situations in which one person must be chosen to act as a “dictator” by making a unilateral decision? This article introduces and critically examines a number of different voting methods. The goal is not to provide a general overview of social choice theory or even a comprehensive account of voting theory. Rather, my objective is to highlight and discuss key results and issues that underlie phenomena that we observe when decision makers come together to make a collective decision. So, some topics will only briefly be mentioned, while others will not be discussed at all: Notable omissions include the extensive literature on the discursive dilemma (see List 2006, and references therein) and an overview of the work on voting power indices (Felsenthal and Machover 1998). To learn more about these topics, consult Nurmi (1998) and Saari (2001) for general introductions to voting theory and Brams and Fishburn (2002) and Saari (1995) for technical introductions and analysis of the vast literature. 1. The Problem: Who Should be Elected? 1.1 Notation 2. Examples of Voting Methods 3. Voting Paradoxes 3.1 Condorcet's Paradox 3.1.1 Electing the Condorcet Winner 3.2 Failures of Monotonicity 3.3 The Multiple Districts Paradox 3.4 The Multiple Elections Paradox 4. Topics in Voting Theory 4.1 Strategizing 4.2 Characterization Results 4.3 Voting to Track the Truth 5. Concluding Remarks: from Theory to Practice Bibliography Academic Tools Other Internet Resources Related Entries

Voting Methods (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Voting Methods (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Citation preview

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 1/26

    Stanford Encyclopedia of PhilosophyVotingMethodsFirstpublishedWedAug3,2011

    Thinkbacktothelasttimeyouneededtomakeadecisionasamemberofagroup.Thismayhavebeenwhenyouvotedforyourfavoritepoliticalcandidateduringthelastelection.Onasmallerscale,itmayhavebeenwhenyoutookpartinacommitteethatneededtochoosethebestcandidateforajoborastudenttoreceiveaspecialaward.Whatmethod,orprocedure,didthegroupusetomakethefinaldecision?Manyinterestingissuesarisewhenwecarefullyexamineourgroupdecisionmakingprocesses.Considerasimpleexampleofagroupoffriendsdecidingwheretogofordinner.Ifeveryoneagreesonwhichrestaurantisbest,thenitisobviouswheretogo.Buthowshouldthefriendsdecidewheretogoiftheyhavedifferentopinionsaboutwhichrestaurantisbest?Istherealwaysachoicethatisfairtakingintoaccounteveryone'sopinions?Oraretheresituationsinwhichonepersonmustbechosentoactasadictatorbymakingaunilateraldecision?

    Thisarticleintroducesandcriticallyexaminesanumberofdifferentvotingmethods.Thegoalisnottoprovideageneraloverviewofsocialchoicetheoryorevenacomprehensiveaccountofvotingtheory.Rather,myobjectiveistohighlightanddiscusskeyresultsandissuesthatunderliephenomenathatweobservewhendecisionmakerscometogethertomakeacollectivedecision.So,sometopicswillonlybrieflybementioned,whileotherswillnotbediscussedatall:Notableomissionsincludetheextensiveliteratureonthediscursivedilemma(seeList2006,andreferencestherein)andanoverviewoftheworkonvotingpowerindices(FelsenthalandMachover1998).Tolearnmoreaboutthesetopics,consultNurmi(1998)andSaari(2001)forgeneralintroductionstovotingtheoryandBramsandFishburn(2002)andSaari(1995)fortechnicalintroductionsandanalysisofthevastliterature.

    1.TheProblem:WhoShouldbeElected?1.1Notation

    2.ExamplesofVotingMethods3.VotingParadoxes

    3.1Condorcet'sParadox3.1.1ElectingtheCondorcetWinner

    3.2FailuresofMonotonicity3.3TheMultipleDistrictsParadox3.4TheMultipleElectionsParadox

    4.TopicsinVotingTheory4.1Strategizing4.2CharacterizationResults4.3VotingtoTracktheTruth

    5.ConcludingRemarks:fromTheorytoPracticeBibliographyAcademicToolsOtherInternetResourcesRelatedEntries

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 2/26

    1.TheProblem:WhoShouldbeElected?

    Thecentralquestionofthisarticleis:

    Givenagroupofpeoplefacedwithsomedecision,howshouldacentralauthoritycombinetheindividualopinionssoastobestreflectthewillofthegroup?

    Acompleteanalysisofthisquestionwouldincorporateanumberofdifferentissuesrangingfromcentraltopicsinpoliticalphilosophy(e.g.,howshouldwedefinethewillofthepeople?whatisademocracy?)tothepsychologyofdecisionmaking.Inthisarticle,Ifocusononeaspectofthisquestion:theformalanalysisofspecificvotingmethods(see,forexample,Riker1982Mackie2003,foramorecomprehensiveanalysisoftheabovequestion,incorporatingmanyoftheissuesraisedinthisarticle).

    Istartwithaconcreteexampletoillustratethetypeofanalysissurveyedinthisarticle.Supposethatthereisagroupof21people,orvoters,whoneedtomakeadecisionaboutwhichoffourcandidates,oroptions,shouldbeelected,orchosen.LetA,B,CandDdenotethefourdifferentcandidates.Thefirststepistodecidehowtorepresentthevoters'opinionsaboutthesetofcandidates.Manydifferentapproacheshavebeenexploredinthevotingtheoryliterature.Oneapproachistoassumethateachvoterhasanordinalpreferenceorderingoverthesetofcandidates,describingtherelativerankingsofthecandidates.Asecondapproachassumesthatvotersassigntoeachcandidateacardinalvaluedescribinghowmuchthatvoterprefersorvaluesthecandidate.Finally,onecandescribeanunderlyingspaceofissues,howmucheachvotercaresabouteachissueandthedegreetowhicheachcandidatessupportsthedifferentissues.Unlessotherwisestated,Ifollowmuchofthevotingtheoryliteratureandassumethatthevoters'opinionsaredescribedbylinearrankingsofthesetofcandidates(describingthevoters'ordinalpreferenceorderings).

    Forthisexample,assumethateachofthevotershasoneoffourpossiblerankingsofthecandidates.Theinformationabouttherankingsofeachvoterisgiveninthefollowingtable.

    #Voters

    3 5 7 6

    A A B C

    B C D B

    C B C D

    D D A A

    Readthetableasfollows:Eachcolumnrepresentsarankinginwhichcandidatesinlowerrowsarerankedlower.Thenumbersatthetopofeachcolumnindicatethenumberofvoterswiththatparticularranking.Supposethatyouareanoutsideobserverwithoutanyinterestintheoutcomeofthiselection.Whichofthecandidatesbestrepresentsthewillofthisgroup?Iftherewereonlytwocandidatestochoosefrom,thereisaveryintuitiveanswer:Thewinnershouldbethecandidateoroptionthatissupportedbymorethan50percentofthevoters(cf.thediscussionbelowaboutMay'sTheoreminSection4.2).However,iftherearemorethantwocandidates,asintheaboveexample,thestatementthecandidatethatissupportedbymorethan50percentofthevoterscanbeinterpretedindifferentways,leadingtodifferentideasaboutwhoshouldwintheelection.

    Onecandidatewho,atfirstsight,seemstobeagoodchoicetowintheelectioniscandidateA.Candidate

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 3/26

    Aisrankedfirstinmoreofthevoters'rankingsthananyothercandidate.(Aisrankedfirstbyeightvoters,BisrankedfirstbysevenCisrankedfirstbysixandDisnotrankedfirstbyanyofthevoters.)Thatis,morepeoplethinkthatAisbetterthananyothercandidate.

    Ofcourse,13peoplerankAlast,soamuchlargergroupofvoterswillbeunsatisfiedwiththeelectionofA.So,itseemsclearthatAshouldnotbeelected.NoneofthevotersrankDfirst,whichsuggeststhatDisalsonotagoodchoice.Thechoice,then,boilsdowntoBandC.Here,therearegoodargumentsforeachofBandCtobeelected.Thisechoesan18thcenturydebatebetweenthetwofoundingfathersofvotingtheory,JeanCharlesdeBorda(17331799)andM.J.A.N.deCaritat,MarquisdeCondorcet(17431794).Foraprecisehistoryofvotingtheoryasanacademicdiscipline,includingCondorcet'sandBorda'swritings,seeMcCleanandUrken(1995).IsketchtheintuitiveargumentsfortheelectionofBandCbelow.

    CandidateCshouldwin.Initially,thismightseemlikeanoddchoicesinceCreceivedthefewestnumberoffirstplacerankings(6).However,Cisastrongchoicebecausehebeatseveryothercandidateinaoneononeelection.Toseethis,weneedtoexaminehowthepopulationwouldvoteinthevarioustwowayelections:

    #Voters

    3 5 7 6

    A A B C

    B C D B

    C B C D

    D D A A

    #Voters

    3 5 7 6

    A A B C

    B C D B

    C B C D

    D D A A

    #Voters

    3 5 7 6

    A A B C

    B C D B

    C B C D

    D D A A

    13rankCaboveA8rankAaboveC

    11rankCaboveB10rankBaboveC

    15rankCaboveD7rankDaboveC

    TheideaisthatCshouldbedeclaredthewinnersincehebeatseveryothercandidateinoneononeelections.AcandidatewiththispropertyiscalledaCondorcetwinner.(WecansimilarlydefineaCondorcetloser.Infact,intheaboveexample,candidateAistheCondorcetlosersinceshelosestoeveryothercandidateinheadtoheadelections.)

    CandidateBshouldwin.ConsiderB'sperformanceinheadtoheadelections.

    #Voters

    3 5 7 6

    A A B C

    B C D B

    C B C D

    #Voters

    3 5 7 6

    A A B C

    B C D B

    C B C D

    #Voters

    3 5 7 6

    A A B C

    B C D B

    C B C D

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 4/26

    D D A A D D A A D D A A

    13rankBaboveA8rankAaboveB

    10rankBaboveC11rankCaboveB

    21rankBaboveD0rankDaboveB

    CandidateBperformsthesameasCinaheadtoheadelectionwithA,losestoCbyonlyonevoteandbeatsDinalandslide(everyoneprefersBoverD).Arguably,weshouldtakeintoaccountallofthesefactswhendeterminingwhoshouldrepresentthewillofthepeople.Borda'sideaistoassigneachcandidateascorethatreflectsallofthisinformation.BothCondorcetandBordasuggestcomparingcandidatesinoneononeelectionsinordertodeterminethewinner.WhileCondorcettallieshowmanyoftheheadtoheadraceseachcandidatewins,Bordasuggeststhatoneshouldlookatthemarginofvictoryorloss.AccordingtoBorda,eachcandidateshouldbeassignedascorerepresentinghowmuchsupportheorshehasamongtheelectorate.Onewaytocalculatethescoreforeachcandidateisasfollows(Iwillgiveanalternativemethod,whichiseasiertouse,inthenextsection):

    Areceives24points(8votesineachofthethreeheadtoheadraces)Breceives44points(13pointsinthecompetitionagainstA,plus10inthecompetitionagainstCplus21inthecompetitionagainstD)Creceives38points(13pointsinthecompetitionagainstA,plus11inthecompetitionagainstBplus14inthecompetitionagainstD)Dreceives20points(13pointsinthecompetitionagainstA,plus0inthecompetitionagainstBplus7inthecompetitionagainstC)

    Thecandidatewiththehighestscore(inthiscase,B)istheonewhoshouldbeelected.

    Theconclusionisthatinvotingsituationswithmorethantwocandidates,theremaynotalwaysbeoneobviouscandidatethatbestreflectsthewillofthepeople.Theremainderofthisentrywilldiscussdifferentmethods,orprocedures,thatcanbeusedtodeterminethewinnerofanelection.

    1.1Notation

    Inthisarticle,Iwillkeeptheformaldetailstoaminimumhowever,itisusefulatthispointtosettleonsometerminology.AssumethatthereisafinitesetofvotersVandafinitesetofcandidatesX.Iuselowercaselettersi,j,k,todenoteelementsofVanduppercaselettersA,B,C,todenoteelementsofX.Differentvotingmethodsrequiredifferenttypesofinformationfromthevotersasinput.Forexample,somemethodsaskvoterstoselectasinglecandidateorasetofcandidates,whileothermethodsaskvoterstolinearlyrankallofthecandidates.Theinputrequestedfromthevotersarecalledballots.Aprofileisasequenceofballots,onefromeachvoter.Thesecondcomponentofavotingprocedureisthemethodusedtocalculatethewinner,givenaprofileofballots.

    Asnotedabove,oneunderlyingassumptionisthatthevoters'actualdesiresaboutwhoshouldwintheelectionarerepresentedaslinearpreferencerelationsoverthesetofcandidates.GivenasetofcandidatesX,letL(X)denotethesetoflinearorderingsonX(thatis,relationsonXthatareirreflexive,transitive,andcomplete).Theseorderingsareintendedtorepresentthevoters'ordinalpreferencesabouttherelativerankingsofeachofthecandidates(seetheentryonpreferences,HanssonandGrneYanoff2009,foranextendeddiscussionofthesepropertiesandotherissuessurroundingformalmodelingpreferences).WeusePitodenotevoteri'spreferenceorderingoverX.Itisimportanttonotethattheseorderingsdonot

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 5/26

    reflectanycardinalinformation(forexample,theintensityofthepreferenceofonecandidateoveranother).Forinstance,supposethattherearethreecandidatesX={A,B,C}.Then,theassumptionisthatavoter'spreferencecanbeanyoneofthesixpossiblelinearorderingsoverX:

    Preference P1 P2 P3 P4 P5 P6

    A A B B C C

    B C A C A B

    C B C A B A

    #Voters n1 n2 n3 n4 n5 n6

    IcannowbemorepreciseaboutthedefinitionofaCondorcetwinner(loser).Thekeynotionhereisthemajorityrelation,whichistherankingofcandidatesintermsofhowtheyperforminoneononeelections.Formally,wewriteA>MB,providedthatmorevotersrankcandidateAabovecandidateBthantheotherwayaround(wewriteMifthereareties).So,ifthedistributionofpreferencesisgivenintheabovetable,wehave:

    A>MBjustincasen1+n2+n5>n3+n4+n6(otherwiseBMA)A>MCjustincasen1+n2+n3>n4+n5+n6(otherwiseCMA)B>MCjustincasen1+n3+n4>n2+n5+n6(otherwiseBMC)

    CandidateAiscalledtheCondorcetwinnerifAismaximalinthemajorityordering>M.TheCondorcetloseristhecandidatethatminimizesthisordering.

    Iconcludethissectionwithafewcommentsontherelationshipbetweentheballotsandthevoters'opinionsaboutthecandidates.Twoissuesareimportanttokeepinmind.First,theballotsofaparticularvotingmethodareintendedtoreflectsomeaspectofthevoters'opinionsaboutthedesirabilityofthedifferentcandidates.Sometypesofballotsareintendedtorepresentallorpartofthevoter'spreferenceordering,whileothertypesrepresentinformationthatcannotbeinferreddirectlyfromthevoter'sordinalpreferenceordering(forexample,bydescribinghowmuchavoterlikesaparticularcandidate).Second,itisimportanttobepreciseaboutthetypeofconsiderationsvoterstakeintoaccountwhenselectingaballot.Oneapproachistoassumethatvoterschoosesincerelybyselectingtheballotthatbestreflectstheirviewaboutthedesirabilityofthedifferentcandidates.Asecondapproachassumesthatthatvoterschoosestrategically.Inthiscase,avoterselectsaballotthatsheexpectstoleadtohermostdesiredoutcomegiventheinformationshehasabouthowtheothermembersofthegroupwillvote.Strategicvotingisanimportanttopicinvotingtheoryandsocialchoicetheory(seeTaylor2005,foradiscussionandpointerstotheliterature),butinthisarticle,unlessotherwisestated,Iassumethatvoterschoosesincerely.

    2.ExamplesofVotingMethods

    Avotingprocedureisawayofaggregatingtheindividual'spreferencesinordertocometoacollectivedecision.Aquicksurveyofelectionsheldindifferentdemocraticsocietiesthroughouttheworldrevealsawidevarietyofmethods.Inthissection,Idiscusssomeofthekeyproceduresthathavebeenanalyzedinthevotingtheoryliterature.Theseproceduresmaybeofinterestbecausetheyarewidelyused(e.g.,pluralityruleorpluralityrulewithrunoff)orbecausetheyareoftheoreticalinterest(e.g.,Dodgson's

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 6/26

    method).Idonotprovideacomprehensiveoverviewofthedifferentmethodsthathavebeendiscussedintheliterature(seeBramsandFishburn2002,forasystematicoverviewofdifferentvotingmethods).Rather,Ifocusonmethodsthateitherarefamiliarorhelpillustrateimportantideas.Istartwiththemostwidelyusedmethod:

    PluralityRule:Eachvoterselectsonecandidate(ornoneifvoterscanabstain),andthecandidate(s)withthemostvoteswin.So,theballotsaresimplythesetofcandidatesXand,givenvoteri'struepreferenceorderingPi,theuniquesincereballotforvoteriistop(Pi)(themaximalelementintheorderingPi).

    Pluralityruleisaverysimplemethodthatiswidelyuseddespiteitsmanyproblems.ThemostpervasiveproblemisthefactthatpluralityrulecanelectaCondorcetloser.Borda(1784)observedthisphenomenoninthe18thcentury.

    #Voters

    1 7 7 6

    A A B C

    B C C B

    C B A A

    CandidateAistheCondorcetloser(bothBandCbeatcandidateA,138)however,Aisthepluralityrulewinner.Infact,thepluralityranking(Aisfirstwitheightvotes,BissecondwithsevenvotesandCisthirdwithsixvotes)reversesthemajorityorderingC>MB>MA.Butthereareother(morebasic)reasonstocriticizepluralityrule.Forinstance,theverysimplepluralityballotsseverelylimitwhatthevoterscanexpressabouttheiropinionsofthecandidates.Rankedvotingproceduresaskformuchmoreinformationfromthevoter:theballotsarelinearorderingsofthecandidates.ThemostwellknownexampleofsuchaprocedureisBordaCount:

    BordaCount:Eachvoterprovidesalinearorderingofthecandidates.Eachcandidateisassignedascore(theBordascore)asfollows:Iftherearencandidates,given1pointstocandidatesrankedfirst,n2pointstocandidatesrankedsecond,,1pointtoacandidateranked2ndtolastand0pointstocandidatesrankedlast.So,theBordascoreofA,denotedBS(A),iscalculatedasfollows(where#UdenotesthenumberelementsinthesetU):

    BS(A) = (n1)#{i|iranksAfirst}+(n2)#{i|iranksAsecond}++1#{i|iranksAsecondtolast}+0#{i|iranksAlast}

    ThecandidatewiththehighestBordascorewins.

    RecalltheexamplediscussedintheintroductiontoSection1.WecancalculatetheBordascoreforeachofthecandidatesasfollows:

    BS(A)=38+20+10+013=24

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 7/26

    BS(B)=37+29+15+00=44BS(C)=36+25+110+00=38BS(D)=30+27+16+08=20

    BordaCountrequiresthevoterstocomeupwithalinearrankingofallthecandidates.Thiscanberatherdemandingwhentherearealargenumberofcandidates(asitcanbedifficultforvoterstomakedistinctionsbetweensomeofthemoreobscurecandidates).Asecondwaytomakeavotingmethodsensitivetomorethanthevoters'topchoiceistoholdmultistageelections.Thedifferentstagescancomeintheformofactualrunoffelectionsinwhichvotersareaskedtochoosefromareducedsetofcandidatesortheycanbebuiltintothewaythewinneriscalculatedbyaskingvoterstosubmitlinearorderingsoverthesetofallcandidates.Thefollowingarethemostwellknownexamplesofmultistagevotingmethods:

    PluralitywithRunoff:Startwithapluralityvotetodeterminethetoptwocandidates(ormoreifthereareties).Then,thereisarunoffbetweenthesecandidates,andthecandidatewiththemostvoteswins.Sometimes,arunoffcanbeavoidedifthetopcandidategetsasufficientlylargepercentageofthevotes(forexample,ifshegetsanabsolutemajority:morethan50percentofthevotes).

    Ratherthanfocusingonthetoptwocandidates,onecanalsoiterativelyremovethecandidate(s)withthefewestfirstplacevotes:

    TheHareRule:Theballotsarelinearordersoverthesetofcandidates.Repeatedlydeletethecandidateorcandidatesthatreceivethefewestfirstplacevotes,withtheremainingcandidate(s)declaredthewinner(orwinnersinthecaseofties).

    Ifthereareonlythreecandidates,thentheabovetwoproceduresarethesame(removingthecandidatewiththeleastnumberofvotesisthesameaskeepingthetoptwocandidates).Thefollowingexampleshowsthatthesetwoprocedurescanconflictwhentherearemorethanthreecandidates:

    #Voters

    7 5 4 3

    A B D C

    B C B D

    C D C A

    D A A B

    CandidateAisthepluralitywithrunoffwinner:CandidatesAandBarethetoptwocandidates,receivingsevenandfivevotes,respectively,inthefirstround.Intherunoffelection,thegroupsvotingforcandidatesCandDgivetheirsupporttocandidateBandA,respectively,withAwinning109.

    However,CandidateDwinswiththeHarerule:Inthefirstround,candidateCiseliminatedafterreceivingonlythreevotes.Butthenthisgroup'svotesaretransferredtoD,givinghersevenvotes.Thismeansthatinthesecondround,candidateBhasthefewestvotes(fivevotes)andsoiseliminated.AftertheeliminationofcandidateB,candidateDhasanabsolutemajoritywith12totalvotes(notethatinthisroundthegroupinthesecondcolumntransfersalltheirvotestoDsinceCwaseliminatedinanearlier

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 8/26

    round).

    OnefinalprocedureisCoombsrule,whichiterativelyremovesthecandidateswiththemostlastplacevotes.

    CoombsRule:Eachvotersubmitsalinearorderingoverthesetofcandidates.Candidateswhoarerankedlastbythemostvotersareiterativelyremoved.Thelastcandidate(s)toberemovedarethewinner(s).

    Intheaboveexample,candidateBwinstheelectionusingCoombsrule.Inthefirstround,A,withninelastplacevotes,iseliminated.ThenextcandidatetobeeliminatedisD,with12lastplacevotes.Finally,C,with16lastplacevotes,iseliminated.

    Thenexttypeofproceduresaskvoterstosubmitballotsthatrepresentinformationthatcannotbeinferreddirectlyfromtheirordinalpreferenceorderings.Thefirstexamplegivesvoterstheoptiontoeitherselectacandidatethattheywanttovotefor(asinpluralityrule)ortoselectacandidatethattheywanttovoteagainst.

    NegativeVoting:Eachvoterisallowedtochooseonecandidatetoeithervotefor(givingthecandidateonepoint)ortovoteagainst(givingthecandidate1points).Thewinner(s)is(are)thecandidate(s)withthehighestscore(s)(i.e.,themostpositivevotes).

    Negativevotingistantamounttoallowingthevoterstosupporteitherasinglecandidateorallbutonecandidate(takingapointawayfromacandidateCisequivalenttogivingonepointtoallcandidatesexceptC).Thatis,thevotersareaskedtochooseasetofcandidatesthattheysupport,wherethechoiceisbetweensetsconsistingofsinglecandidatesorsetsconsistingofallexceptonecandidate.Thenextproceduregeneralizesthisideabyallowingvoterstochooseanysubsetofcandidates:

    ApprovalVoting:Eachvoterselectsasubsetofthecandidates(wheretheemptysetmeansthevoterabstains)andthecandidate(s)withthemostvoteswins.

    ApprovalvotinghasbeenextensivelydiscussedbyStevenBramsandPeterFishburn(BramsandFishburn2007Brams2008).See,also,therecentcollectionofarticlesdevotedtoapprovalvoting(LaslierandSanver2010).

    Approvalvotingforcesvoterstothinkaboutthedecisionproblemdifferently:Theyareaskedtodeterminewhichcandidatestheyapproveofratherthandeterminingtherelativerankingofthecandidates.Thatis,thevoterisaskedwhichcandidatesareaboveacertainthresholdofacceptance.(SeeBramsandSanver2009,forexamplesofvotingproceduresthataskvoterstobothselectasetofofcandidatesthattheyapproveandto(linearly)rankthecandidates.)ThefinaltypeofproceduresIintroduceinthissectionallowvoterstoexpresstheirintensityofpreferenceamongthecandidates.

    CumulativeVoting:Eachvoterisaskedtodistributeafixednumberofpoints,sayten,amongthecandidatesinanywaytheyplease.Thecandidate(s)withthemostpointswinstheelection.

    ThisgeneralideawastakenfurtherinarecentproposalforanewmethodofvotingbyMichelBalinksiandRidaLaraki(2007).Thegeneralideaoftheirnewmethod(majoritarianjudgment)isthatvotersassigngradestoeachcandidatefromacommonlyacceptedgradinglanguage.Oncethegradesare

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 9/26

    assigned,eachcandidateisassignedhermediangrade.Thewinner(s)is(are)thecandidate(s)withthehighestmediangrade.Thedetailsofthisprocedurearebeyondthescopeofthisarticle,buttheycanbefoundalongwithaxiomaticcharacterizationsinBalinskiandLaraki(2010).

    Thissectionintroducedanumberofdifferentproceduresthatcanbeusedtomakeagroupdecision.Onestrikingfactisthatmanyofthedifferentproceduresgiveconflictingresultsonthesameinput.Thisraisesanimportantquestion:Howshouldwecomparethedifferentprocedures?Canwearguethatsomeproceduresarebetterthanothers?Thereareanumberofdifferentcriteriathatcanbeusedtocompareandcontrastdifferentvotingmethods:

    1. Pragmaticconcerns:Istheprocedureeasytouse?Isitlegaltouseaparticularvotingprocedureforanationalorlocalelection?Theimportanceofeaseofuseshouldnotbeunderestimated:Despiteitsmanyflaws,pluralityrule(arguablythesimplestvotingproceduretouseandunderstand)is,byfar,themostcommonlyusedmethod(cf.thediscussionbyLevinandNalebuff1995,p.19).

    2. Behavioralconsiderations:Dothedifferentproceduresreallyleadtodifferentoutcomesinpractice?Aninterestingstrandofresearch,behavorialsocialchoice,incorporatesempiricaldataaboutactualelectionsintothegeneraltheoryofvoting(ThisisdiscussedbrieflyinSection5.SeeRegenwetteretal.2006,foranextensivediscussion).

    3. Informationrequiredfromthevoters:Whattypeofinformationdotheballotsconvey?Whilerankedprocedures(e.g.,BordaCount)requirethevotertocompareallofthecandidates,itisoftenusefultoaskthevoterstoreportsomethingabouttheintensitiesoftheirpreferencesoverthecandidates.Ofcourse,thereisatradeoff:Limitingwhatvoterscanexpressabouttheiropinionsofthecandidatesoftenmakesaproceduremucheasiertouseandunderstand.

    4. Axiomaticcharacterizationresultsandvotingparadoxes:Muchoftheworkinvotingtheoryhasfocusedoncomparingandcontrastingvotingproceduresintermsofabstractprinciplesthattheysatisfy.Thegoalistocharacterizethedifferentvotingproceduresintermsofnormativeprinciplesofgroupdecisionmaking.SeeSections3and5.2fordiscussions.

    3.VotingParadoxes

    Inthissection,Iintroduceanddiscussanumberofvotingparadoxesi.e.,anomaliesthathighlightproblemswithdifferentmethods.SeeSaari(1995,2001)andNurmi(1999)forpenetratinganalysesthatexplaintheunderlyingmathematicsbehindthedifferentvotingparadoxes.

    3.1Condorcet'sParadox

    Averycommonassumptionisthatarationalpreferenceorderingmustbetransitive(i.e.,ifAispreferredtoB,andBispreferredtoC,thenAmustbepreferredtoC.Seetheentryonpreferences(HanssonandGrneYanoff2009)foranextendeddiscussionoftherationalebehindthisassumption).Indeed,ifavoter'spreferenceorderingisnottransitive,allowingforcycles(A>B>C>A),thenthereisnocandidatethatthevotercanbesaidtoactuallysupport(foreachcandidate,thereisanothercandidatethatthevoterprefers).Suchvotershavecontradictoryopinionsaboutthecandidatesand,arguably,shouldbeignoredoreliminatedbyanyvotingsystem.Manyauthorsarguethatsuchvoterswithcyclicpreferenceorderingshaveinconsistentopinionsaboutthecandidatesandshouldbeignoredbyanyvotingprocedures(inparticular,Condorcetforcefullyarguedthispoint).AkeyobservationofCondorcet(whichhasbecomeknownasCondorcet'sParadox)isthatevenifeachvoter'spreferenceorderingistransitive,themajorityorderingmaynotbetransitive.

    Condorcet'soriginalexamplewasmorecomplicated,butthefollowingsituationwiththreevotersand

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 10/26

    threecandidatesillustratesthephenomenon:

    #Voters

    1 1 1

    A C B

    B A C

    C B A

    Notethatwehave:

    CandidateAbeatscandidateB21inaoneononeelection.CandidateBbeatscandidateC21inaoneononeelection.CandidateCbeatscandidateA21inaoneononeelection.

    Thus,wehaveamajoritycycleA>MB>MC>MA,andsothereisnoCondorcetwinner.Oneinterpretationisthat,althougheachoftheindividualvotershasarationalpreferenceordering,thegroup'spreferenceordering(definedasthemajorityordering)isnotrational.Thissimple,butfundamentalobservationhasbeenextensivelystudied(seeGehrlein2006,foranoverviewoftheliterature).

    3.1.1ElectingtheCondorcetWinner

    Condorcet'sParadoxshowsthattheremaynotalwaysbeaCondorcetwinnerinanelection.However,onenaturalrequirementforavotingruleisthatifthereisaCondorcetwinner,thenthatcandidateshouldbeelected.VotingproceduresthatsatisfythispropertyarecalledCondorcetconsistent.ManyoftheproceduresintroducedabovearenotCondorcetconsistent.IalreadypresentedanexampleshowingthatpluralityruleisnotCondorcetconsistent(infact,pluralityrulemayevenelecttheCondorcetloser).

    TheexamplefromSection1showsthatBordaCountisnotCondorcetconsistent.Infact,thisisaninstanceofageneralphenomenonthatFishburn(1974)calledCondorcet'sotherparadox.Considerthefollowingvotingsituationwith81votersandthreecandidatesfromCondorcet(1785).

    #Voters

    30 1 29 10 10 1

    A A B B C C

    B C A C A B

    C B C A B A

    ThemajorityorderingisA>MB>MC,soAistheCondorcetwinner.UsingtheBordarule,wehave:

    BS(A)=231+139+011=101BS(B)=239+131+011=109BS(C)=211+111+059=33

    So,candidateBistheBordawinner.Condorcetpointedoutsomethingmore:Theonlywaytoelect

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 11/26

    candidateAusinganyscoringmethodistoassignmorepointstocandidatesrankedsecondthantocandidatesrankedfirst.Ascoringmethod,whichgeneralizestheBordascore,isdefinedbyfirstfixinganondecreasingsequenceofrealnumberss0s1sn1withs0Score(B),wemusthave231+v39>239+v31,whichimpliesthatv>2.But,ofcourse,itiscounterintuitivetogivemorepointsforbeingrankedsecondthanforbeingrankedfirst.PeterFishburngeneralizedthisexampleasfollows:

    Theorem(Fishburn1974).Forallm3,thereissomevotingsituationwithaCondorcetwinnersuchthateveryweightedscoringrulewillhaveatleastm2candidateswithagreaterscorethantheCondorcetwinner.

    So,noscoringruleisCondorcetconsistent,butwhataboutothermethods?ThefollowingexamplefromStevenBrams(2008,Chapter3)showsthattherearesituationsinwhichnofixedvotingrulecanelectaCondorcetwinner.Afixedvotingrule(orkApprovalVoting)isamethodbywhichthevoterschooseapredeterminednumberofcandidates.Forexample,pluralityisavoteforonefixedrule.Considerthefollowingvotingsituationwithfivevotersandfourcandidates:

    #Voters

    2 2 1

    A B C

    D D A

    B A B

    C C D

    CandidateAistheuniqueCondorcetwinner(themajorityorderingsisA>MB>MD>MC),butnofixedrulevotingprocedurewillguaranteethatAiselected.

    Usingvotefor1(pluralityrule),candidatesAandBaretiedforthewin.Usingvotefor2,candidateDiselected.Usingvotefor3,candidatesAandBaretiedforthewin.

    Ofcourse,approvalvotingmayelectcandidateA(forexample,ifeveryoneapprovesofAandallcandidatestheyrankhigherthanA).Infact,Brams(2008,Chapter2)provesthatifthereisauniqueCondorcetwinner,thenthatcandidatemaybeelectedunderapprovalvoting(assumingthatallvotersvotesincerely:seeBrams2008,Chapter2,foradiscussion).Notethatapprovalvotingmayalsoelectothercandidates(perhapseventheCondorcetloser).

    AnumberofvotingproceduresweredevisedspecificallytoguaranteethataCondorcetwinnerwillbe

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 12/26

    elected,ifoneexists.IdiscussfourexamplestogiveaflavorofhowsuchCondorcetconsistentprocedureswork.(SeeBramsandFishburn2002,andTaylor2005formoreexamples.)

    CondorcetRule:Eachvotersubmitsalinearorderingoverallthecandidates.IfthereisaCondorcetwinner,thenthatcandidatewinstheelection.Otherwise,allcandidatestieforthewin.

    Copeland'sRule:Eachvotersubmitsalinearorderingoverallthecandidates.AwinlossrecordforcandidateBiscalculatedasfollows:

    WL(B)=#{C|B>MC}#{C|C>MB}

    TheCopelandwinneristhecandidatethatmaximizesWL.

    ThenextmethodwasproposedbyCharlesDodgson(betterknownbythepseudonymLewisCarroll).Interestingly,thisisanexampleofaprocedureinwhichitiscomputationallydifficulttocomputethewinner(thatis,theproblemofcalculatingthewinnerisNPcomplete).SeeBartdholdietal.(1989)foradiscussion.

    Dodgson'sMethod:Eachvotersubmitsalinearorderingoverallthecandidates.Foreachcandidate,determinethefewestnumberofpairwiseswapsneededtomakethatcandidatetheCondorcetwinner.Thecandidate(s)withthefewestswapsis(are)declaredthewinner(s).

    Black'sProcedure:Eachvotersubmitsalinearorderingoverallthecandidates.IfthereisaCondorcetwinner,thenthatcandidateisthewinner.Otherwise,letthewinnersbetheBordaCountwinners.

    Theseprocedures(andtheotherCondorcetconsistentprocedures)guaranteethataCondorcetwinner,ifoneexists,willbeelected.But,shouldaCondorcetwinnerbeelected?TherearestrongintuitionsthataCondorcetwinner(ifoneexists)isthecandidatethatbestreflectsthewillofthevotersandthatthereissomethingamisswithavotingprocedurethatdoesnotalwayselectsuchacandidate.However,thereareargumentsagainsttheseintuitions.ThemostpersuasiveargumentcomesfromtheworkofDonaldSaari(1995,2001).Considerthefollowingexampleof81voters(thisexamplewasoriginallydiscussedbyCondorcet).

    #Voters

    30 1 29 10 10 1

    A A B B C C

    B C A C A B

    C B C A B A

    ThisisanotherexamplethatshowsthatBorda'smethodneednotelecttheCondorcetwinner.Themajorityorderingis

    A>MB>MC,

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 13/26

    whiletherankinggivenbytheBordascoreis

    B>BordaA>BordaC.

    However,thereisanargumentthatcandidateBisthebestchoiceforthiselectorate.Saari'scentralobservationistonotethatthe81voterscanbedividedintothreegroups:

    #Voters

    10 10 10

    A B C

    B C A

    C A B

    #Voters

    1 1 1

    A C B

    C B A

    B A C

    #Voters

    20 28

    A B

    B A

    C C

    Group1 Group2 Group3

    Groups1and2constitutemajoritycycleswiththevotersevenlydistributedamongthethreepossibleorderings.Thatis,thesegroupsformaperfectsymmetryamongthelinearorderings.So,withineachofthesegroups,thevoters'opinionscanceleachotherouttherefore,thedecisionshoulddependonlyonthevotersingroup3.Ingroup3,candidateBistheclearwinner.

    3.2FailuresofMonotonicity

    Avotingprocedureismonotonicprovidedthatmovingupintherankingsdoesnotadverselyaffectacandidate'schancestowinanelection.Thispropertycapturestheintuitionthatreceivingmoresupportfromthevotersisalwaysbetterforacandidate.Forexample,itiseasytoseethatpluralityruleismonotonic:Themorevotesacandidatereceives,thebetterchancethecandidatehastowin.Surprisingly,therearevotingmethodsthatdonotsatisfythisnaturalproperty.Themostwellknownexampleispluralitywithrunoff.Considerthetwotablesbelow.Notethattheonlydifferencebetweenthetwotablesisthepreferenceorderingsofthefourthgroupofvoters.ThisgroupoftwovotersranksBaboveAaboveCinthetableontheleftandswapsBandAinthetableontheright(so,AisnowtheirtoprankedcandidateBisrankedsecondandCisstillrankedthird).

    #Voters

    6 5 4 2

    A C B B

    B A C A

    C B A C

    #Voters

    6 5 4 2

    A C B A

    B A C B

    C B A C

    CandidateAisthepluralitywithrunoffwinner CandidateCisthepluralitywithrunoffwinner

    Intheelectionontheleft,candidateC,withfivevotes,iseliminatedinthefirstround.Then,C'svotesarealltransferredtocandidateA,givingheratotalof11towintheelection.However,intheelectionontheright,evenaftermovingupintherankingsofthefourthgroup(Aisnowrankedfirstbythisgroup),candidateAdoesnotwinthiselection.Infact,bytryingtogivemoresupporttothewinneroftheelectionontheleft,ratherthansolidifyingA'swin,thelastgroup'sleastpreferredcandidateendedup

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 14/26

    winningtheelection!Intheelectionontheright,ratherthanCbeingeliminatedinthefirstround,itiscandidateB,withonlyfourvotes,whoiseliminated.OnceBiseliminated,candidateCbeatscandidateA(CreceivesninevoteswhileAreceiveseight).

    Theaboveexampleissurprisingsinceitsuggeststhat,whenusingpluralitywithrunoff,itmaynotalwaysbebeneficialforacandidatetoreceiveextravotesinthefirstround.AsecondexampleofafailureofmontonicityisthenoshowparadoxofFishburnandBrams(1983),asthefollowingexampleillustrates.Supposethattherearethreecandidates,andthepopulationisdividedintothefollowinggroups:

    #Voters

    417 82 143 357 285 324

    A A B B C C

    B C A C A B

    C B C A B A

    Inthefirstround,candidateCwinstheelectionwith609votes(butthisisnotanabsolutemajority)candidateBreceives500votesandcandidateAreceives499votes.Thus,candidateAiseliminatedinthefirstround.Inthesecondround,417votesaretransferredtocandidateBand82votesaretransferredtocandidateC.Thus,candidateBwinstheelectionwith917votes(candidateCreceivesatotalof691votes).Now,supposethattherearetwovoterswiththerankingA>B>Cwhodidnottakepartintheaboveelection.ThesetwovotersrankAfirst,andso,theycertainlywouldpreferthattheirsupportforcandidateAbetakenintoaccount.But,considerwhathappenswhenthesetwovotersareaddedtothepopulation:

    #Voters

    419 82 143 357 285 324

    A A B B C C

    B C A C A B

    C B C A B A

    Inthiselection,candidateCstillwinsthefirstroundwith609votes,butcandidateBiseliminatedsinceAnowreceives501voteswhileBreceivesonly500votes.ButthismeansthatcandidateCwinstheelection(Creceives966votesandAreceives644votes).So,byshowinguptotheelection,thesetwoextravotersactuallycausedtheirleastpreferredcandidatetowin!

    3.3MultipleDistrictsParadox

    Supposethatapopulationisdividedintodistricts.Ifacandidatewinseachofthedistricts,onewouldexpectthatcandidatetowintheelectionovertheentirepopulationofvoters.Thisiscertainlytrueforpluralityvote:Ifacandidateisrankedfirstbyamajorityofthevotersinineachofthedistricts,thenthatcandidatewillalsoberankedfirstbyamajorityofvotersovertheentirepopulation.Interestingly,though,thisisnottrueforpluralityrulewithrunoff,asthefollowingexamplefromFishburnandBrams(1983)shows.

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 15/26

    District1

    #Voters

    160 0 143 0 0 285

    A A B B C C

    B C A C A B

    C B C A B A

    District2

    #Voters

    257 82 0 357 285 39

    A A B B C C

    B C A C A B

    C B C A B A

    CandidateAwinsbothdistricts:

    District1:Thereareatotalof588votersinthisdistrict.CandidateBreceivesthefewestfirstplacevotes,andsoiseliminatedinthefirstround.Inthesecondround,candidateAisnowthepluralitywinnerwith303totalvotes.

    District2:Thereareatotalof1020votersinthisdistrict.CandidateCreceivesthefewestfirstplacevotes(324),andsoiseliminatedinthefirstround.Inthesecondround,285votesaretransferredtocandidateAand39aretransferredtocandidateC.Inthesecondround,CandidateAisthepluralitywinnerwith644votes.

    However,notethatifyoucombinethetwodistricts,thenCandidateBisthewinner(thecombineddistrictsgiveustheexamplediscussedaboveinSection3.2).

    ThisparadoxisanexampleofamoregeneralphenomenonknownasSimpson'sParadox(MalinasandBigelow2009).SeeSaari(2001,Section4.2)foradiscussionofSimpson'sParadoxinthecontextofvotingtheory.

    3.4TheMultipleElectionsParadox

    Thisparadox,firstintroducedbyBrams,KilgourandZwicker(1998),hasasomewhatdifferentstructurefromtheparadoxesdiscussedabove.Votersaretakingpartinareferendum,wheretheyareaskedtheiropiniondirectlyaboutvariouspropositions.So,votersmustselecteitheryes(Y)orno(N)foreachproposition.Supposethatthereare13voterswhocastthefollowingvotesforthreepropositions(sovoterscancastoneofeightpossiblevotes):

    Propositions YYY YYN YNY YNN NYY NYN NNY NNN

    #Votes 1 1 1 3 1 3 3 0

    Whenthevotesaretalliedforeachpropositionseparately,theoutcomeisNforeachproposition(Nwins76forallthreepropositions).Puttingthisinformationtogether,thismeansthatNNNistheoutcomeofthiselection.However,thereisnosupportforthisoutcomeinthispopulationofvoters.

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 16/26

    AsimilarissueisraisedbyAnscombe'sparadox(Anscombe1976),inwhich:

    Itispossibleforamajorityofvoterstobeonthelosingsideofamajorityofissues.

    Thisphenomenonisillustratedbythefollowingexamplewithfivevotersvotingonthreedifferentissues(thevoterseithervoteryesornoonthedifferentissues).

    Issue1 Issue2 Issue3

    Voter1 yes yes no

    Voter2 no no no

    Voter3 no yes yes

    Voter4 yes no yes

    Voter5 yes no yes

    Majority yes no yes

    However,amajorityofthevoters(voters1,2and3)donotsupportthemajorityoutcomeonamajorityoftheissues(notethatvoter1doesnotsupportthemajorityoutcomeonissues2and3voter2doesnotsupportthemajorityoutcomeonissues1and3andvoter3doesnotsupportthemajorityoutcomeonissues1and2)!

    Theissueismoreinterestingwhenthevotersdonotvotedirectlyontheissues,butoncandidatesthattakepositionsonthedifferentissues.SupposetherearetwocandidatesAandBwhotakethefollowingpositionsonthethreeissues:

    Issue1 Issue2 Issue3

    CandidateA yes no yes

    CandidateB no yes no

    CandidateAtakesthemajorityposition,agreeingwithamajorityofthevotersoneachissue,andcandidateBtakestheopposite,minorityposition.Underthenaturalassumptionthatvoterswillvoteforthecandidatewhoagreeswiththeirpositiononamajorityoftheissues,candidateBwillwintheelection(eachofthevoters1,2and3agreewithBontwoofthethreeissues,soBwinstheelection32)!ThisversionoftheparadoxisknownasOstrogorski'sParadox(Ostrogorski1902).(SeeKelly1989RaeandDaudt1976Wagner1983,1984andSaari2001,Section4.6foranalysesofthisparadoxandPigozzi2005,forrelationshipstojudgmentaggregationliterature.)

    4.TopicsinVotingTheory

    4.1Strategizing

    Inthediscussionabove,Ihaveassumedthatvotersselectballotssincerely.Thatis,thevotersaresimplytryingtocommunicatetheiropinionsaboutthecandidatesundertheconstraintsofthechosenvotingmethod.However,inmanycontexts,voterswouldratherchoosestrategically.OneneedonlylooktorecentU.S.electionstoseeconcreteexamplesofstrategicvoting.Themostoftencitedexampleisthe

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 17/26

    2000U.S.election:ManyvoterswhorankedthirdpartycandidateRalphNaderfirstvotedfortheirsecondchoice(typicallyAlGore).Adetailedoverviewoftheliteratureonstrategicvotingisbeyondthescopeofthisarticle(seeTaylor2005foradiscussionandpointertotherelevantliteraturealsoseePoundstone2008foranentertainingandinformativediscussionoftheoccurrenceofthisphenomnoninmanyactualelections).Iwillexplainthemainissues,focusingonspecificvotingrules.

    Ingeneral,therearetwogeneraltypesofmanipulationthatcanbestudiedinthecontextofvoting.Thefirstismanipulationbyachairmanoroutsidepartythathastheauthoritytosettheagendaorselectthevotingmethodthatwillbeused.So,theoutcomeofanelectionisnotmanipulatedfromwithinbyunhappyvoters,but,rather,itiscontrolledbyanoutsideauthorityfigure.Toillustratethistypeofcontrol,considerapopulationwiththreevoterswhosepreferencesoverfourcandidatesaregiveninthetablebelow:

    #Voters

    1 1 1

    B A C

    D B A

    C D B

    A C D

    NotethateveryonepreferscandidateBovercandidateD.Nonetheless,achairmancanasktherightquestionssothatcandidateDendsupbeingelected.Thechairmanproceedsasfollows:First,askthevotersiftheyprefercandidateAorcandidateB.SincethevoterspreferAtoBbyamarginoftwotoone,thechairmandeclaresthatcandidateBisnolongerintherunning.ThechairmanthenasksvoterstochoosebetweencandidateAandcandidateC.CandidateCwinsthiselection21,socandidateAisremoved.Finally,inthelastroundthechairmanasksvoterstochoosebetweencandidateCandcandidateD.CandidateDwinsthiselection21andisdeclaredthewinner.

    Asecondtypeofmanipulationfocusesonhowthevotersthemselvescanmanipulatetheoutcomeofanelectionbymisrepresentingtheirpreferences.Considerthefollowingtwosevenvoter,threecandidateelectionscenarios:

    #Voters

    3 3 1

    A B C

    B A A

    C C B

    #Voters

    3 3 1

    A B C

    B C A

    C A B

    ElectionScenario1 ElectionScenario2

    Theonlydifferencebetweenthetwoscenariosisthatthemiddlegroupofvotersswappedtheirorderingoftheirbottomrankedcandidates(AandC).Inthefirstelectionscenario,candidateAistheBordacountwinner.However,inthesecondelectionscenario,candidateBistheBordacountwinner.So,ifweassumethatscenario1representsthetruepreferencesoftheelectorate,itisintheinterestofthemiddlegrouptomisrepresenttheirpreferenceandrankCsecond,followedbyA,sincetheoutcomewillresultin

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 18/26

    theirmostpreferredcandidate(B)beingelected.ThisisaninstanceofageneralresultknownastheGibbardSatterthwaiteTheorem(Gibbard1973Satterthwaite1975):Undernaturalassumptions,thereisnovotingmethodthatguaranteesthatvoterswillchoosetheirballotssincerely(foraprecisestatementofthistheoremandanextensiveanalysis,seeTaylor2005).

    Thereisagrowingliteraturethatcharacterizesvotingmethodsintermsofhowcomputationallycomplextheyaretomanipulate.Adiscussionofthisliteratureisbeyondthescopeofthisarticlehowever,IreferthereadertoBartholdietal.(1989)Conitzeretal.(2007)FaliszewskiandProcaccia(2010)andFaliszewskietal.(2010)foranintroductionandpointerstotherelevantliterature.

    4.2CharacterizationResults

    Muchoftheliteratureonvotingtheory(and,moregenerally,socialchoicetheory)isfocusedonsocalledaxiomaticcharacterizationresults.Themaingoalhereistocharacterizedifferentvotingmethodsintermsofabstractnormativeprinciplesofcollectivedecisionmaking.So,theaxiomsdiscussedinthisliteratureareintendedtodescribepropertiesthatagroupdecisionmethodshouldsatisfy.Itisworthpointingoutthatthisisdifferentfromthewayamathematicianorlogicianusesthewordaxiom:Tomathematiciansorlogicians,axiomsarebasicprinciplesthatamathematicaltheoryorlogicalsystemdosatisfy.Thatis,axiomsarebeingusedinadescriptivesense.(SeeEndriss2011,foraninterestingdiscussionofcharacterizationresultsfromalogician'spointofview.)

    Iwillnotattempttoprovideageneraloverviewofaxiomaticcharacterizationsinsocialchoicetheoryhere(seeGaertner2006,foranintroductiontothisvastliterature).Rather,Iinformallydiscussafewkeyaxiomsandresultsandhowtheyrelatetothevotingmethodsandparadoxesdiscussedabove.Istartwiththreecoreproperties.

    Anonymity:Thenamesofthevotersdonotmatter:Iftwovoterschangevotes,thentheoutcomeoftheelectionisunaffected.Neutrality:Thenamesofthecandidates,oroptions,donotmatter:Iftwocandidatesareexchangedineveryranking,thentheoutcomeoftheelectionchangesaccordingly.UniversalDomain:Thevotersarefreetohaveanyopinionaboutthecandidates.Inotherwords,nopreferenceorderingoverthecandidatescanbeignoredbyavotingmethod.Formally,thismeansthatvotingmethodsmustbetotalfunctionsonthespaceofallprofiles(recallthataprofileisasequenceofballots,onefromeachvoter.Here,Iamassuming,asistypicalforthisliterature,thattheballotsarethelinearorderingsoverthesetofcandidates).

    Thesepropertiesensurethattheoutcomeofanelectiondependsonlyonthevoters'opinions,withallthevotersbeingtreatedequally.Otherpropertiesareintendedtoruleoutsomeoftheparadoxesandanomaliesdiscussedabove.Insection4.1,thereisanexampleofasituationinwhichacandidateiselected,eventhoughallthevoterspreferadifferentcandidate.Thenextprinciplerulesoutsuchsituations:

    Unanimity:IfcandidateAispreferredtocandidateBbyallvoters,thencandidateBshouldnotwintheelection.

    Section3.2discussedexamplesinwhichcandidatesenduplosinganelectionasaresultofmoresupportfromsomeofthevoters.Intuitively,avotingprocedureismonotonicifmovingupintherankings(allelsebeingequal)shouldnotcauseacandidatetolosetheelection.Therearemanywaystomakethisprecise.Thefollowingstrongversion(calledPositiveResponsivenessintheliterature)isusedtocharacterizemajorityrulewhenthereareonlytwocandidates:

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 19/26

    PositiveResponsiveness:IfcandidateAistiedforthewinandmovesupintherankings,thencandidateAistheuniquewinner.

    Icannowstateourfirstcharacterizationresult.Notethatinalloftheexamplesabove,itiscrucialthattherearethreeormorecandidates(forexample,Condorcet'sparadoxdependscriticallyontherebeginthreeormorecandidates).Infact,whenthereareonlytwocandidates,oroptions,thenmajorityrule(choosetheoptionwiththemostvotes)canbesingledoutasbest:

    Theorem(May1952).Asocialdecisionmethodforchoosingbetweentwocandidatessatisfiesneutrality,anonymityandpositiveresponsivenessifandonlyifthemethodismajorityrule.

    SeeMay(1952)foraprecisestatementofthistheoremandAsanandSanver(2002),Maskin(1995),andWoeginger(2003)forgeneralizationsandalternativecharacterizationsofmajorityrule.Withmorethantwocandidates,themostimportantresultisKenArrow'scelebratedimpossibilitytheorem(1963).Arrowshowedthatthereisnosocialwelfarefunction(asocialchoicefunctionmapsthevoters'linearpreferenceorderingstoasinglesocialpreferenceordering)satisfyinguniversaldomain,unanimity,nondictatorship(thesocialorderingisdefinedtobetheorderingofasingleindividual)andthefollowingkeyproperty:

    IndependenceofIrrelevantAlternatives:Thesocialranking(higher,lower,orindifferent)oftwocandidatesAandBdependsonlyontherelativerankingsofAandBforeachindividual.

    Thismeansthatifthevoters'rankingsoftwocandidatesAandBarethesameintwodifferentelectionscenarios,thenthesocialrankingsofAandBmustbethesame.Thisisaverystrongpropertythathasbeenextensivelycriticized(seeGaertner2006,forpointerstotherelevantliterature).ItisbeyondthescopeofthisarticletogointodetailabouttheproofandtheramificationsofArrow'stheorem,butInotethatmanyofthevotingmethodswehavediscusseddonotsatisfytheaboveproperty.AstrikingexampleofavotingmethodthatdoesnotsatisfyindependenceofirrelevantalternativesisBordacount.Considerthefollowingtwoelectionscenarios:

    #Voters

    3 2 2

    A B C

    B C A

    C A B

    #Voters

    3 2 2

    A B C

    B C X

    C X A

    X A B

    ElectionScenario1 ElectionScenario2

    NoticethattherelativerankingsofcandidatesA,BandCarethesameinbothelectionscenarios.Inthesecondscenario,anew(undesirable)candidateisadded(i.e.,anirrelevantalternative).TherankingofthecandidatesaccordingtotheirBordascoreinscenario1putsAfirstwitheightpoints,BsecondwithsevenpointsandClastwithsixpoints.WithcandidateXintheelection(scenario2),thisrankingisreversed:CandidateCisfirstwith13voterscandidateBissecondwith12pointscandidateAisthirdwith11pointsandcandidateXislastwithsixpoints.So,eventhoughtherelativerankingsofcandidatesA,BandCdonotdifferinthetwoscenarios,thepresenceofcandidateXreversestheBordarankings.

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 20/26

    Finally,Idiscusscharacterizationsofallscoringrules(anymethodthatcalculatesascorebasedonweightsgiventodifferentcandidatesaccordingtowheretheyfallintherankingseeSection3.1.1foradefinition)andApprovalvoting.Onedefiningpropertyofthesemethodsisthattheydonotsufferfromthemultipledistrictsparadox.

    Reinforcement:SupposethatN1andN2aredisjointsetsofvotersfacingthesamesetofcandidates.Further,supposethatW1isthesetofwinnersforthepopulationN1,andW2isthesetofwinnersforthepopulationN2.Ifthereisatleastonecandidatethatwinsbothelections,thenthewinner(s)fortheentirepopulation(includingvotersfrombothN1andN2)isW1W2.

    Thereinforcementpropertyexplicitlyrulesoutmultipledistrictsparadoxes(so,candidatesthatwinallsubelectionsareguaranteedtowinthefullelection).Inordertocharacterizeallscoringrules,oneadditionaltechnicalpropertyisneeded:

    Continuity:SupposethatagroupofvotersN1electsacandidateAandadisjointgroupofvotersN2electsadifferentcandidateB.ThentheremustbesomenumbermsuchthatthepopulationconsistingofthesubgroupN2togetherwithmcopiesofN1willelectA.

    Wethenhave:

    Theorem(Young1975).Asocialdecisionmethodsatisfiesanonymity,neutrality,reinforcementandcontinuityifandonlyifthemethodisascoringrule.

    ThisresultwasgeneralizedbyMyerson(1995)bydroppingtherequirementthatvotershavelinearpreferences.AdditionalaxiomshavebeensuggestedthatsingleoutBordacountamongallscoringmethods(Young1974NitzanandRubinstein1981).Infact,SaarihasarguedthatanyfaultorparadoxadmittedbyBorda'smethodalsomustbeadmittedbyallotherpositionalvotingmethods(Saari1989,pg.454).Forexample,itisoftenremarkedthatBordacount(andallscoringrules)canbeeasilymanipulatedbythevoters.Saari(1995,Section5.3.1)showsthatamongallscoresrulesBordacountistheleastsusceptibletomanipulation(inthesensethatithasthefewestprofileswhereasmallpercentageofvoterscanmanipulatetheoutcome).

    IconcludethisbriefdiscussionofcharacterizationresultswithFishburn'scharacterizationofapprovalvoting(seeXu2010,foranoverviewofthedifferentcharacterizationsofapprovalvoting).

    Theorem(Fishburn1978).Asocialdecisionmethodisapprovalvotingifandonlyifthemethodsatisfiesanonymity,neutrality,reinforcementandthefollowingtechnicalproperty:

    Ifthereareexactlytwovoterswhoapproveofdisjointsetsofcandidates,thenthemethodsselectsaswinnersallthecandidateschosenbythetwovoters(i.e.,theunionoftheballotschosenbythevoters).

    4.3VotingtoTracktheTruth

    Thevotingmethodsdiscussedabovehavebeenjudgedonproceduralgrounds.ThisproceduralistapproachtocollectivedecisionmakingisdefinedbyColemanandFerejohn(1986,p.7)asonethatidentifiesasetofidealswithwhichanycollectivedecisionmakingprocedureoughttocomply.[A]processofcollectivedecisionmakingwouldbemoreorlessjustifiabledependingontheextenttowhich

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 21/26

    itsatisfiesthem.Theauthorsaddthatadistinguishingfeatureofproceduralismisthatwhatjustifiesa[collective]decisionmakingprocedureisstrictlyanecessarypropertyoftheprocedureoneentailedbythedefinitionoftheprocedurealone.Indeed,thecharacterizationtheoremsdiscussedintheprevioussectioncanbeviewedasanimplementationofthisidea(cf.Riker1982).Thegeneralviewistoanalyzevotingmethodsintermsoffairnesscriteriathatensurethatagivenmethodissensitivetoallofthevoters'opinionsintherightway.

    However,onemaynotbeinterestedonlyinwhetheracollectivedecisionwasarrivedatintherightway,butinwhetherornotthecollectivedecisioniscorrect.ThisepistemicapproachtovotingisnicelyexplainedbyJoshuaCohen(1986):

    Anepistemicinterpretationofvotinghasthreemainelements:(1)anindependentstandardofcorrectdecisionsthatis,anaccountofjusticeorofthecommongoodthatisindependentofcurrentconsensusandtheoutcomeofvotes(2)acognitiveaccountofvotingthatis,theviewthatvotingexpressesbeliefsaboutwhatthecorrectpoliciesareaccordingtotheindependentstandard,notpersonalpreferencesforpoliciesand(3)anaccountofdecisionmakingasaprocessoftheadjustmentofbeliefs,adjustmentsthatareundertakeninpartinlightoftheevidenceaboutthecorrectanswerthatisprovidedbythebeliefsofothers.(p.34)

    Underthisinterpretationofvoting,agivenmethodisjudgedonhowwellittracksthetruthofsomeobjectivefact(thetruthofwhichisindependentofthemethodbeingused).Acomprehensivecomparisonofthesetwoapproachestovotingtouchesonanumberofissuessurroundingthejustificationofdemocracy(cf.Christiano2008)however,Iwillnotfocusonthesebroaderissueshere.Instead,Ibrieflydiscussananalysisofmajorityrulethattakesthisepistemicapproach.

    ThemostwellknownanalysiscomesfromthewritingsofCondorcet(1785).Thefollowingtheorem,whichisattributedtoCondorcetandwasfirstprovedformallybyLaplace,showsthatifthereareonlytwooptions,thenmajorityruleis,infact,thebestprocedurefromanepistemicpointofview.Thisisinterestingbecauseitalsoshowsthataproceduralistanalysisandanepistemicanalysisbothsingleoutmajorityrulesasthebestvotingmethodwhenthereareonlytwocandidates.

    Assumethattherearenvotersthathavetodecidebetweentwoalternatives.Exactlyoneofthesealternativesis(objectively)correctorbetter.Thetypicalexamplehereisajurydecidingwhetherornotadefendantisguilty.ThetwoassumptionsoftheCondorcetjurytheoremare:

    Independence:Thevoters'opinionsareprobabilisticallyindependent(so,theprobabilitythattwoormorevotersarecorrectistheproductoftheprobabilitythateachindividualvoteriscorrect).VoterCompetence:Theprobabilitythatavotermakestherightdecisionisgreaterthan1/2,andthisprobabilityisthesameforallvoters.

    SeeDietrich(2008)foracriticaldiscussionofthesetwoassumptions.Theclassictheoremis:

    CondorcetJuryTheorem.SupposethatIndependenceandVoterCompetencearebothsatisfied.Then,asthegroupsizeincreases,theprobabilitythatthemajoritychoosesthecorrectoptionincreasesandconvergestocertainty.

    SeeNitzan(2010)foramodernexpositionofthistheorem.Forageneralizationofthistheorembeyondtwocandidates,seeYoung(1995)andListandGoodin(2001).ConitzerandSandholm(2005)taketheseideasfurtherbyclassifyingdifferentvotingmethodsaccordingtowhetherornotthemethodscanbe

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 22/26

    viewedasamaximumlikelihoodestimator(foranoisemodel).

    5.ConcludingRemarks:fromTheorytoPractice

    Aswithanymathematicalanalysisofsocialphenomena,questionsaboundaboutthereallifeimplicationsofthetheoreticalanalysisofthevotingmethodsgivenabove.Themaindifficultyiswhetherthevotingparadoxesaresimplyfeaturesoftheformalframeworkusedtorepresentanelectionscenarioorformalizationsofreallifephenomena.Thisraisesanumberofsubtleissuesaboutthescopeofmathematicalmodelinginthesocialsciences,manyofwhichfalloutsidethescopeofthisarticle.Iconcludewithabriefdiscussionoftwoquestionsthatshedsomelightonhowoneshouldinterprettheaboveanalysis.

    HowlikelyisaCondorcetParadoxoranyoftheothervotingparadoxes?Therearetwowaystoapproachthisquestion.Thefirstistocalculatetheprobabilitythatamajoritycyclewilloccurinanelectionscenario.Thereisasizableliteraturedevotedtoanalyticallyderivingtheprobabilityofamajoritycycleoccurringinelectionscenariosofvaryingsizes(seeGehrlein2006,andRegenwetteretal.2006,foroverviewsofthisliterature).Thecalculationsdependonassumptionsaboutthedistributionofpreferenceorderingsamongthevoters.Onedistributionthatistypicallyusedisthesocalledimpartialculture,whereeachpreferenceorderingispossibleandoccurswithequalprobability.Forexample,iftherearethreecandidates,anditisassumedthatthevoters'preferencesarerepresentedbylinearorderings,theneachlinearorderingcanoccurwithprobability1/6.Underthisassumption,theprobabilityofamajoritycycleoccurringhasbeencalculated(seeGehrlein2006,fordetails).Riker(1982,p.122)hasatableoftherelevantcalculations.Twoobservationsaboutthisdata:First,asthenumberofcandidatesandvotersincreases,theprobabilityofamajoritycyclesincreasestocertainty.Second,forafixednumberofcandidates,theprobabilityofamajoritycyclestillincreases,thoughnotnecessarilytocertainty(thenumberofvotersistheindependentvariablehere).Forexample,iftherearefivecandidatesandsevenvoters,thentheprobabilityofamajoritycycleis21.5percent.Thisprobabilityincreasesto25.1percentasthenumberofvotersincreasestoinfinity(keepingthenumberofcandidatesfixed)andto100percentasthenumberofcandidatesincreasestoinfinity(keepingthenumberofvotersfixed).Primafacie,thisresultsuggeststhatweshouldexpecttoseeinstancesoftheCondorcetandrelatedparadoxesinlargeelections.Ofcourse,thisinterpretationtakesitforgrantedthattheimpartialcultureisarealisticassumption.Manyauthorshavenotedthattheimpartialcultureisasignificantidealizationthatalmostcertainlydoesnotoccurinreallifeelections.Tsetlinetal.(2003)goevenfurtherarguingthattheimpartialcultureisaworstcasescenariointhesensethatanydeviationresultsinlowerprobabilitiesofamajoritycycle(seeRegenwetteretal.2006,foracompletediscussionofthisissue).

    Asecondwaytoarguethattheabovetheoreticalobservationsarerobustistofindsupportingempiricalevidence.Forinstance,isthereevidencethatmajoritycycleshaveoccurredinactualelections?WhileRiker(1982)offersanumberofintriguingexamples,themostcomprehensiveanalysisoftheempiricalevidenceformajoritycyclesisprovidedbyMackie(2003,especiallyChapters14and15).Theconclusionisthat,instrikingcontrasttotheprobabilisticanalysisreferencedabove,majoritycyclestypicallyhavenotoccurredinactualelections.However,thisliteraturehasnotreachedaconsensusaboutthisissue(cf.Riker1982):Theproblemisthattheavailabledatatypicallydoesnotincludevoters'opinionsaboutallpairwisecomparisonofcandidates,whichisneededtodetermineifthereisamajoritycycle.So,thisinformationmustbeinferred(forexample,byusingstatisticalmethods)fromthegivendata.

    Howdothedifferentvotingmethodscompareinactualelections?Inthisarticle,Ihaveanalyzedvotingmethodsunderhighlyidealizedassumptions.But,intheend,weareinterestedinaverypracticalquestion:Whichmethodshouldagivensocietyadopt?Ofcourse,anyanswertothisquestionwill

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 23/26

    dependonmanyfactorsthatgobeyondtheabstractanalysisgivenabove.Aninterestinglineofresearchfocusesonincorporatingempiricalevidenceintothegeneraltheoryofvoting.Evidencecancomeintheformofacomputersimulation,adetailedanalysisofaparticularvotingmethodinreallifeelections(forexample,seeBrams2008,Chapter1,whichanalyzesApprovalvotinginpractice),orasinsituexperimentsinwhichvotersareaskedtofillinadditionalballotsduringanactualelection(Laslier2010,2011).

    However,themoststrikingresultsherecanbefoundintheworkofMichaelRegenwetterandhicolleagues.Theyhaveanalyzeddatasetsfromavarietyofelections,showingthatmanyoftheusualvotingmethodsthatareconsideredirreconcilable(e.g.,plurality,BordacountandmethodsthatchoosetheCondorcetwinner)are,infact,inperfectagreement.Thissuggeststhatthetheoreticalliteraturemaypromoteoverlypessimisticviewsaboutthelikelihoodofconsensusamongconsensusmethods(Regenwetteretal.2009,p.840).SeeRegenwetteretal.2006foranintroductiontothemethodsusedintheseanalysesand(Regenwetteretal.2009)forthecurrentstateoftheart.

    Bibliography

    Anscombe,G.E.M.,1976,OnFrustrationoftheMajoritybyFulfillmentoftheMajority'sWill,Analysis,36(4):161168.

    Arrow,K.,1963,SocialChoiceandIndividualValues,NewHaven:YaleUniversityPress,2ndedition.Asan,G.andR.Sanver,2002,AnotherCharacterizationoftheMajorityRule,EconomicsLetters,

    75(3):409413.Balinski,M.andR.Laraki,2007,Atheoryofmeasuring,electingandranking,Proceedingofthe

    NationalAcademyofSciences,104(21):87208725.,2010,MajorityJudgement:Measuring,RankingandElecting,Boston:MITPress.BartholdiIII,J.J.,C.A.Tovey,andM.A.Trick,1989,TheComputationalDifficultyofManipulatingan

    Election,SocialChoiceandWelfare,6(3):227241.,1989,Votingschemesforwhichitcanbedifficulttotellwhowontheelection,SocialChoiceand

    Welfare,6(2):157165.Borda,J.C.de,1784,MmoiresurleslectionsauscrutinparM.deBordainMmoiresde

    l'AcadmieRoyaledesSciencesanne1781,Paris:l'ImprimerieRoyale,pp.657665TranslatedinMcCleanandUrken1995,pp.8389.

    Brams,S.,2008,MathematicsandDemocracy,Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress.Brams,S.andP.Fishburn,2007(2ndEdition),ApprovalVoting,NewYork:Springer.,2002,VotingProcedures,inHandbookofSocialChoiceandWelfare,K.J.Arrow,A.K.Sen,and

    K.Suzumura(eds.),Amsterdam:Elsevier,pp.173236.Brams,S.,D.M.KilgourD.M.,andW.Zwicker,1998,Theparadoxofmultipleelections,Social

    ChoiceandWelfare,15(2):211236.Brams,S.andSanver,M.R.,VotingSystemsThatCombineApprovalandPreference,inThe

    MathematicsofPreference,Choice,andOrder:EssaysinHonorofPeterC.Fishburn,S.Brams,W.Gehrlein,andF.Roberts(eds.),Berlin:Springer,pp.215237.

    Christiano,T.,Democracy,TheStanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy(Fall2008Edition),EdwardN.Zalta(ed.),URL=.

    Cohen,J.,1986,Anepistemicconceptionofdemocracy,Ethics,97(1):2638.Coleman,J.andJ.Ferejohn,1986,Democracyandsocialchoice,Ethics,97(1):625.Condorcet,M.J.A.N.deC.,Marquede,1785,Essaisurl'applicationdel'analyselaprobabilitides

    dcisionsrendueslapluralitdesvoix,Paris:l'ImprimerieRoyaleTranslatedinMcleanandUrken1995,pp.91113.

    Conitzer,V.,T.Sandholm,andJ.Lang,2007,WhenareElectionswithFewCandidatesHardtoManipulate?,JournaloftheACM,54(3):Article14.

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 24/26

    Conitzer,V.andT.Sandholm,2005,CommonVotingRulesasMaximumLikelihoodEstimatorsinProceedingsofthe21stAnnualConferenceonUncertaintyinArtificialIntelligence(UAI05),pp.145152.

    Daudt,H.andD.W.Rae,1976,TheOstrogorskiparadox:apeculiarityofcompoundmajoritydecision,EuropeanJournalofPoliticalResearch,4(4):391399.

    Dietrich,F.,2008,ThepremisesofCondorcet'sjurytheoremarenotsimultaneouslyjustified,EpistemeaJournalofSocialEpistemology,5(1):5673.

    Dowding,K.andM.VanHees,2007,InPraiseofManipulation,BritishJournalofPoliticalScience,38(1):115.

    Endriss,U.,2011,LogicandSocialChoiceTheory,inLogicandPhilosophyToday,J.vanBenthemandA.Gupta(eds.),London:CollegePublications.

    Faliszewski,P.andA.Procaccia,2010,AI'sWaronManipulation:AreWeWinning?,AIMagazine,31(4):5364.

    Faliszewski,P.,E.Hemaspaandra,andL.Hemaspaandra,2010,Usingcomplexitytoprotectelections,CommunicationsoftheACM,53(11):7482.

    Felsenthal,D.andM.Machover,1998,TheMeasurementofVotingPower:TheoryandPractice,ProblemsandParadoxes,CheltenhamGlos:EdwardElgarPublishing.

    Fishburn,P.andS.Brams,1983,ParadoxesofPreferentialVoting,MathematicsMagazine,56(4):207214.

    Fishburn,P.,1974,ParadoxesofVoting,AmericanPoliticalScienceReview,68(2):537546.,1978,AxiomsforApprovalVoting:DirectProof,JournalofEconomicTheory,19(1):180185.Gaertner,W.,2006,APrimerinSocialChoiceTheory,Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.Gehrlein,W.,2006,Condorcet'sParadox,Berlin:Springer.Gibbard,A.,1973,Manipulationofvotingschemes:Ageneralresult,Econometrica,41(4):587601.Hansson,S.O.andGrneYanoff,T.,Preferences,TheStanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy(Spring

    2009Edition),EdwardN.Zalta(ed.),URL=.

    Kelly,J.S.,1989,TheOstrogorski'sparadox,SocialChoiceandWelfare,6(1):7176.Laslier,J.F.,2011,LessonsfrominsituexperimentsduringFrenchelections,inInSituand

    LaboratoryExperimentsonElectoralLawReform:FrenchPresidentialElections,B.Dolez,B.GrofmanandA.Laurent(eds.),Berlin:Springer,pp.91104.

    ,2010,LaboratoryexperimentsaboutapprovalvotinginHandbookofApprovalVoting,J.F.LaslierandR.Sanver(eds.),Berlin:Springer,pp.339356.

    Laslier,J.F.andR.Sanver(eds.),2010,HandbookonApprovalVoting,Series:StudiesinChoiceandWelfare,Berlin:Springer.

    Levin,J.andB.Naelbuff,1995,Anintroductiontovotecountingschemes,JournalofEconomicPerspectives,9(1):326.

    List,C.,2006,TheDiscursiveDilemmaandPublicReason,Ethics,116(2):362402.List,C.andR.Goodin,2001,EpistemicDemocracy:GeneralizingtheCondorcetJuryTheorem,

    JournalofPoliticalPhilosophy,9(3):277306.Mackie,G.,2003,DemocracyDefended,Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.Malinas,G.andJ.Bigelow,Simpson'sParadox,TheStanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy(Fall2009

    Edition),EdwardN.Zalta(ed.),URL=.

    Maskin,E.,1995,Majorityrule,socialwelfarefunctionsandgameforms,inChoice,WelfareandDevelopment:AFestschriftinHonourofAmartyaK.Sen,K.Basu,P.Pattanaik,K.Suzumura(eds.),Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,pp.100109.

    May,K.,1952,Asetofindependentnecessaryandsufficientconditionsforsimplymajoritydecision,Econometrica,20(4):680684.

    McClean,I.andA.Urken(eds.),1995,ClassicsofSocialChoice,AnnArbor:TheUniversityof

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 25/26

    MichiganPress.Myerson,R.,1995,Axiomaticderivationofscoringruleswithouttheorderingassumption,Social

    ChoiceandWelfare,12(1):5974.Nitzan,S.,2010,CollectivePreferenceandChoice,Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.Nitzan,S.andA.Rubinstein,1981,AfurthercharacterizationofBordarankingmethod,Public

    Choice,36(1):153158.Nurmi,H.,1987,ComparingVotingSystems,Dordrecht:D.Reidel.,1999,VotingParadoxesandHowtoDealwithThem,Berlin:SpringerVerlag.,2010,VotingTheory,ineDemocracy:AGroupDecisionandNegotiationPerspective,D.R.

    InsuaandS.French(eds.),Berlin:Springer,pp.101124.Ostorogorski,M.,1902,DemocracyandtheOrganizationofPoliticalParties,London:Macmillan.Pigozzi,G.,2005,Twoaggregationparadoxesinsocialdecisionmaking:theOstrogorskiparadoxand

    thediscursivedilemma,Episteme:AJournalofSocialEpistemology,2(2):3342.Poundstone,W.,2008,GamingtheVote:WhyElectionsaren'tFair(andWhatWeCanDoAboutIt),

    NewYork:HillandWangPress.Regenwetter,M.,B.Grofman,A.A.J.Marley,A.A.J.andI.Tsetlin,2006,BehavioralSocialChoice:

    ProbabilisticModels,StatisticalInference,andApplications,Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

    Regenwetter,M.,B.Grofman,A.Popova,W.Messner,C.DavisStober,andD.Cavagnaro,2009,BehaviouralSocialChoice:AStatusReport,PhilosophicalTransactionsoftheRoyalSocietyB,364(1518):833843.

    Riker,W.,1982,LiberalismagainstPopulism:AConfrontationbetweentheTheoryofDemocracyandtheTheoryofSocialChoice,SanFrancisco:W.H.Freeman&Co.

    Saari,D.,1989,Adictionaryofvotingparadoxes,JournalofEconomicTheory,48(2):443475.,1995,BasicGeometryofVoting,Berlin:Springer.,2001,DecisionsandElections:ExplainingtheUnexpected,Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity

    Press.,2000,MathematicalStructureofVotingParadoxes:II.PositionalVoting,EconomicTheory,

    15(1):55102.Satterthwaite,M.,1975,StrategyproofnessandArrow'sconditions:Existenceandcorrespondence

    theoremsforvotingproceduresandsocialwelfarefunctions,JournalofEconomicTheory,10(2):198217.

    Taylor,A.,2005,SocialChoiceandtheMathematicsofManipulation,Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

    Tsetlin,I.,M.Regenwetter,andB.Grofman,2003,Theimpartialculturemaximizestheprobabilityofmajoritycycles,SocialChoiceandWelfare,21(3):387398.

    Wagner,C.,1983,Anscombe'sParadoxandtheRuleofThreeFourths,TheoryandDecision,15(3):303308.

    ,1984,AvoidingAnscombe'sParadox,TheoryandDecision,Volume16(3):233238.Woeginger,G.,2003,Anewcharacterizationofthemajorityrule,EconomicLetters,81(1):8994.Young,H.P.,1995,OptimalVotingRules,JournalofEconomicPerspectives,9(1):5164.,1975,SocialChoiceScoringFunctions,SIAMJournalofAppliedMathematics,28(4):824838.

    AcademicTools

    Howtocitethisentry.PreviewthePDFversionofthisentryattheFriendsoftheSEPSociety.LookupthisentrytopicattheIndianaPhilosophyOntologyProject(InPhO).

  • 2/6/2015 VotingMethods(StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/votingmethods/ 26/26

    EnhancedbibliographyforthisentryatPhilPapers,withlinkstoitsdatabase.

    OtherInternetResources

    ThreevideoscreatedbyDonaldSaariforthe2008MathematicsAwarenessMonthwhichhadthethememathematicsofvoting:

    1. MathematicsofVoting2. CreatingVotingParadoxes3. WhatCausesVotingParadoxes

    RelatedEntriesdemocracy|preferences|socialchoicetheory

    Acknowledgments

    IwouldliketothankUlleEndriss,UriNodelman,RohitParikh,EdwardZaltaandtwoanonymousrefereesformanyvaluablecommentsthatgreatlyimprovedthereadabilityandcontentofthisarticle.ThisarticlewaswrittenwhiletheauthorwasgenerouslysupportedbyanNWOVidigrant016.094.345.

    Copyright2011byEricPacuit

    OpenaccesstotheSEPismadepossiblebyaworldwidefundinginitiative.PleaseReadHowYouCanHelpKeeptheEncyclopediaFree

    TheSEPwouldliketocongratulatetheNationalEndowmentfortheHumanitiesonits50thanniversaryandexpressourindebtednessforthefivegenerousgrantsitawardedourprojectfrom1997to2007.

    ReaderswhohavebenefitedfromtheSEPareencouragedtoexaminetheNEHsanniversarypageand,ifinspiredtodoso,[email protected].

    TheStanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophyiscopyright2014byTheMetaphysicsResearchLab,CenterfortheStudyofLanguageandInformation(CSLI),StanfordUniversity

    LibraryofCongressCatalogData:ISSN10955054