Trust' in Hobbes's Political Though

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

no

Citation preview

  • Trust in Hobbess Political Thought

    Trust is not usually considered a Hobbesian concept, which is odd since trust is central to the technical definition of a covenant, namely a contract in which the parties are trusted to perform in future. The key to understanding Hobbess concept of trust is to be found in his account of conquestsovereignty by acquisitionwhich is a heavily revised adaptation of the Roman justification for the enslavement of war captives. Hobbes introduces a distinction between servants, who are trusted with liberty, and imprisoned slaves. The relationship of servant and master comes down to trusting one other to carry out their part and monitoring the others performance (i.e., in game theoretic terms, it is an assurance game or stag hunt). The relationship involves an ongoing exchange of benefitsof protection in exchange for service and obedience; and shows how, for Hobbes, life and liberty are connected goods. Brought to understanding the hypothetical model of sovereignty by institution, a trust interpretation explains the compatibility of consent and de facto authority in Hobbess political theory. The salience of his account of servitude (versus slavery and freedom) to discussions by Quentin Skinner and Philip Pettit of neo-republican liberty is considered in the conclusion.

    Deborah Baumgold Department of Political Science

    University of Oregon Eugene, OR 97403-1284 [email protected]

    Prepared for delivery at the 2012 Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association Convention, August 30-September 2, 2012

  • 1

    Wheres no trust, there can be no Contract. --Thomas Hobbes, De Cive, 8.3

    Trust is commonly thought to be a Lockean concept and not a Hobbesian one.1 But the

    estimation would be revised if we paid more attention to Hobbess account of sovereignty by

    acquisition, the realistic corollary to the hypothetical tale of sovereignty by institution. On

    its face, sovereignty by acquisition involves an odd, implausible consent argument: those

    conquered in warwhether individuals or countrieslegitimize the victors authority via

    consent. Doesnt their lack of choice preclude anything resembling genuine consent? Hobbess

    answer hardly improves the argument. It seems that consent is signified by a choice on the part

    of the victor whether or not to allow the conquered to go free. Every one that is taken in the

    War, and hath his life spard him, is not supposd to have Contracted with his Lord; for every

    one is not trusted with so much of his naturall liberty, as to be able, if he desird it, either to flie

    away, or quit his service, or contrive any mischief to his Lord.2 It appears that it is the victor

    who decides whether their relationship is or is not consensual!

    But this dismissive interpretive construction is not the last word. More kindly

    interpreters, notably Kinch Hoekstra, have given a sympathetic reading to Hobbess account of

    consent in the conquest situation. Addressing the textual question of whether the principle of a

    mutuall Relation between Protection and Obedience is a novelty of Leviathan,3 Hoekstra

    argues it was a consistent feature of the theory from the beginning. Hobbes was always both a

    consent theorist and a de facto theorist of authority. If tacit and attributed consent count as

    1 The title of this essay makes reference to John Dunns classic Trust in the Politics of John Locke in Rethinking Modern Political Theory: Essays 1979-1983 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 34-54. My thanks to Leonard Feldman and Burke Hendrix for their comments on an earlier draft of this essay. 2 Thomas Hobbes, De Cive: The English Version entitled in the first edition Philosophicall Rudiments Concerning Government and Society, ed. Howard Warrender (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), 8.2, p. 118. 3 Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. C. B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth: Penguin, Pelican, 1968), A Review and Conclusion, p. 728.

  • 2

    consent, then he may be considered a thoroughgoing consent theorist. If they do not, then he is,

    after all, a de facto theorist of authority of a particular kind."4 Hoekstra saves Hobbes by

    substituting consent for agency as the core issue in the story of conquest and consent: the

    identification of the victor as the active agent fades into the background in favor of a notion of

    Hobbesian tacit consent.

    The general thrust of Hoekstras interpretation is, I believe, correct. My purpose here is

    to extend it by unpacking the ideas that he runs together under the term tacit consent. In so

    doing, it will become apparent that the substance of what Hoekstra labels tacit consent is

    actually a particular understanding of trust. This understanding, we will see, both explains

    away the problematic agency issue and, per Hoekstra, links conquest with the institution

    covenant. Thus to paraphrase: I argue that Hobbes is a thoroughgoing consent theorist by

    virtue of an idea of trust that underlies both contract models.

    Hobbess idea of trust grew out of the neoRoman account of slavery which the English

    inherited via Brackton and Coke and which Hobbes adapted for his own political and

    philosophical purposes.5 My interpretation begins here: with the justification of slavery in the

    sixth-century codification of Roman law, the Digest of Justinian, and Hobbess adaptations of it.

    The root idea that he took over and elaborated was the rationalization that slavery involves an

    exchange of benefits between master and servant. In the Digest, this is explicitly contrasted with

    the Aristotelian view that some humans may have a slaves nature: Slavery is an institution of

    4 Kinch Hoekstra, The De Facto Turn in Hobbess Political Philosophy, in Leviathan After 350 Years, ed. by Tom Sorell and Luc Foisneau (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004), p. 69; see also p. 46. 5 Henry of Bratton, De Legibus Et Consuetudinibus Angli (Bracton on the Laws and Customs of England), trans. Samuel E. Thorne (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Law School Library; Bracton Online, 1968-1977). Edward Coke, The First Part of the Institutes of the Laws of England, Liberty Library of Constitutional Classics (http://www.constitution.org/coke/coke.htm), Lib 2, Ch. 11, Sect. 172, p. 116.

  • 3

    the jus gentium, whereby someone is against nature made subject to the ownership of another.6

    Against this background, I turn, in the second section, to the main subject: how Hobbes

    transformed a neoRoman view of service into an account of trust in which, crucially, life and

    liberty are seen as connected goods. The final sections take up the political significance of the

    account, which played out in Hobbess definition of the political covenant and, in an

    idiosyncratic explanation of great immediacy in the Civil War, the nature of political servitude

    and freedom. In recent years, Quentin Skinner and Philip Pettit have made the last a subject of

    note in discussions of republican thinking about freedom. Disagreeing with the views of both,

    I offer an alternative take on Hobbess message concerning the freedom of subjects.

    War Captivity: Hobbess NeoRoman Reasoning

    From the start, Hobbes imported the Roman rationalization of slavery into his political

    theory. Even in The Elements of Law, though, he also criticized their failure to conceptualize

    alternative outcomes to war captivity:7

    when a servant taken in the wars, is kept bound in natural bonds, as chains, and

    the like, or in prison; there hath passed no covenant from the servant to his

    master . . . This kind of servant is that which ordinarily and without passion, is

    called a SLAVE. The Romans had no such distinct name, but comprehended all

    under the name of servus; whereof such as they loved and durst trust, were

    6 Theodor Mommsen, ed., The Digest of Justinian, trans. Alan Watson (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1985) vol. I, 5.4, p. 15 (emphasis mine). I discuss the Digests rationalization of slavery and its English reception in Slavery Discourse before the Restoration: The Barbary coast, Justinians Digest, and Hobbess political theory, History of European Ideas, 36 (2010): 412-18. 7 It is conceivable that Hobbes drew on Bodin for the distinction. The Republique, whose defense of absolutism is paraphrased in the Elements, distinguishes in somewhat similar fashion between slaves who are and are not trusted with liberty (Jean Bodin, The Six Bookes of a Commonweale, trans. R. Knolles and ed. Kenneth Douglas McRae, reprint of 1606 ed. [Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1962], V.6, p. 627).

  • 4

    suffered to go at liberty . . . the rest were kept chained, or otherwise restrained

    with natural impediments to their resistance.8

    The subsequent versions develop the point into a full-fledged distinction between servants, who

    are allowed freedom, and slaves, who are not: after such Covenant made, the Vanquished is a

    SERVANT, and not before: for by the word Servant . . . is not meant a Captive, which is kept in

    prison, or bonds, . . . for such men, (commonly called Slaves,) have no obligation at all. A

    servant, Leviathan further explains, is a captive that being taken, hath corporall liberty

    allowed him; and upon promise not to run away, nor to do violence to his Master, is trusted by

    him.9 Invoking the authority of the Greeks, Hobbes inserted a digression about the distinction

    into a chapter on dmonology (Part IV, chapter 45). The Greeks, he explains, had distinct

    names for the roles:

    those that are absolutely in the power of their Masters, as Slaves taken in war,

    and their Issue, whose bodies are not in their own power, (their lives depending

    on the Will of their Masters, in such manner as to forfeit them upon the least

    disobedience,) and that are bought and sold as Beasts, were called , that is

    properly, Slaves, and their Service, .: The other, which is of those that

    serve (for hire, or in hope of benefit from their Masters) voluntarily; are called

    ; that is, Domestique Servants; to whose service the Masters have no further

    8 Thomas Hobbes, The Elements of Law Natural and Politic, ed. J. C. A. Gaskin (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), 22.3, p. 127. 9 Hobbes, Leviathan, 20, p. 255. De Cives version of the passage added a feudal parallel: these serve . . . within prisons or bound within irons; and therefore they were called not by the common name of servant only, but by the peculiar name of slave; even as now at this day, un serviteur, and an serf or un esclave have diverse significations. Edward Cokes 1628 Institutes had assimilated feudal relationships to the Roman schema, by distinguishing villeinage in which the tenant is a bondman from villeinage in which the person is free, and the tenure servile (The First Part of the Institutes of the Laws of England, Liberty Library of Constitutional Classics [http://www.constitution.org/coke/coke.htm], Lib 2, Ch. 11, Sect. 172, p. 116).

  • 5

    right, than is contained in the Covenants made betwixt them.10

    Nor is the distinction merely linguistic, but entails a crucial revision to the Roman

    defense of slavery. By failing to distinguish the roles, they had over-generalized the rationale of

    an exchange of benefits. In the case of servants, Hobbes concurs that their service is justified by

    their lives having been spared:

    If a man taken Prisoner in the Wars, or overcome; . . . (to avoid Death) promises

    the Conquerour, or the stronger Party, his Service, i.e. to do all whatsoever he

    shall command him; in which Contract the good which the vanquisht, or inferior,

    in strength doth receive, is the grant of his life, which by the Right of War in the

    naturall state of men he might have deprivd him of; but the good which he

    promises, is his service and obedience.11

    The equivalent political case enjoys the same defense. 12 DESPOTICALL dominion is acquired

    to the Victor, when the Vanquished, to avoyd the present stroke of death, covenanteth . . . that

    so long as his life, and the liberty of his body is allowed him, the Victor shall have the use

    thereof, at his pleasure.13

    However, the situation is crucially different with respect to imprisoned slaves. In the

    passage regarding the Greek roots of the role distinction, notice that Hobbes explains: slaves

    bodies are not in their own power, (their lives depending on the Will of their Masters, in such

    manner as to forfeit them upon the least disobedience). In other words, slaves do not receive

    the benefit which the Romans had ascribed to the institution because they may be killed by their

    10 Leviathan, 45, pp. 667-68. Tying the subject back to religious worship, he concludes with the observation that Scripture uses the two terms promiscuously because we are both slaves of God and, in

    worshipping him, his servants. 11 Hobbes, De Cive, 8.1, p. 117. 12 Hobbes, De Cive, 8.1, p. 117: for to be a King, is nothing else but to have Dominion over many Persons. 13 Hobbes, Leviathan, 20, p. 255. In the Review and Conclusion (p. 721), conquest is defined as the Acquiring of the Right of Soveraignty by Victory. Which Right, is acquired, in the people Submission, by which they contract with the Victor, promising Obedience, for Life and Liberty."

  • 6

    masters at any time: a slave is a Captive, which is kept in prison, or bonds, till the owner of

    him that took him, or bought him of one that did, shall consider what to do with him; he that

    hath Quarter, hath not his life given, but deferred till farther deliberation; For it is not an

    yeelding on condition of life, but to discretion.14 The specter of death is never-ending for them.

    Being kept in chains, they remain as vulnerable to their masters as they were on the battlefield.

    Thus, lurking behind the seemingly simplistic distinction between free servants and

    imprisoned slaves is a less-than-simplistic concept of life as a good. The good is not simply to

    be alive (as might be read into Hobbess assumption of an innate drive for self-preservation),

    but rather consists in being securely alive; this, in turn, is crucially bound up with being trusted

    with liberty. Free servants and imprisoned slaves are both alive, but life is truly a benefit only

    for those who are trusted with freedom.

    Thus, the root proposition is that the benefit of life is receivedand therefore defined

    by being trusted with freedom. Life and liberty are connected goods because, to Hobbess

    mind, liberty signifies security and imprisonment, vulnerability. Then onely is [a captives] life

    in security, and his service due, when the Victor hath trusted him with his corporall liberty. A

    captives voluntary surrender will have this outcome only if it is accompanied by a promise of

    life from the victor, since surrender, in and of itself, obliges not the Victor longer, than in his

    own discretion hee shall think fit.15 We might say that the fact of being alive is morally

    insignificant in the case of the imprisoned: liberty is a necessary condition for living to qualify

    as a benefit or good.

    This is obviously an existential, not a factual, proposition. Being secure means having

    some control over ones life. Recall Leviathans explanation that slaves bodies are not in their

    14 Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 255 (emphasis mine) and p. 256. 15 Hobbes, Leviathan, 20, p. 256.

  • 7

    own power because their lives depend on their masters will. The benefits exchanged in the

    model of sovereignty by acquisitionbenefits which are summarized in the

    conceptualization of free servants versus imprisoned slavesare service and obedience in

    return for liberty, connoting control over ones body and a secure life.

    Trust

    It follows why trust and contract are Hobbess third and crucial additions to the Roman

    account. Whereas the Digest describes an immediate exchange that rationalizes an enduring

    relationship, Hobbesian servitude is born of a promiseon both sidesabout future behavior.

    The upshot of the tie between liberty and life (properly understood) is to make this

    necessarily a contract story, a compact being defined as the promise of him who is trusted;16

    and more specifically, a covenant story, covenants being pacts in which one or both parties are

    trusted to perform in the future.17 The benefit of life, in the case of servants, comes down to

    being able to count on not being mortally assaulted by their masters; entrusting servants with

    liberty means, for masters, counting on their service and counting on them not to flee or attack.

    Thus Hobbess more complicated account has an additional moral dimension that was

    absent from the Roman original. Where that went no further than rationalizing slavery, Hobbes

    adds to the rationalization of servitude a further account of the duties of both parties. This

    dimension is dramatized in the observation that naturall liberty puts a servant in a position to

    be able, if he desird it, either to flie away, or quit his service, or contrive any mischief to his

    16 Hobbes, De Cive, 8.3, p. 118. 17 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, 14, p. 193. The parallel passage in The Elements of Law reads (15.9, p 84): In all contracts where there is trust, the promise of him that is trusted, is called a COVENANT. . . . Promises therefore, upon consideration of reciprocal benefit, are covenants and signs of the will, or last act of deliberation, whereby the liberty of performing, or not performing, is taken away, and consequently are obligatory.

  • 8

    Lord. Servants are in a position to be able to kill their masters, but are obliged not to do so,

    whereas slaves, who are permitted to do so, have a hard time of it due to imprisonment. Duty

    replaces chains.18

    The force of the moral story, from another angle, is to raise and resolve the problem of

    temporality. Why, it might be queried of the Digest, does a single, one-time exchange of life for

    service rationalize a perpetual relationship? It is commonly thought that Locke was the first of

    the contract thinkers to address this question; he answered it, as we know, with a concept of

    tacit consent, referring to the use of benefits in the present.19 Trust is the less well-known

    Hobbesian equivalent. By framing the Roman rationale of exchanging benefits into a covenant

    about future behavior, Hobbes accomplished the same end as Lockean tacit consent:

    justifying duty over time, in the absence of repetitive explicit promising.

    But trust and tacit consent are different concepts.20 The former, as explicitly defined by

    Hobbes, pertains to a reciprocal moral relationship, whereas the latter, Lockean concept works

    by broadening the definition of consent to extend beyond explicit promising. When two parties

    trust one another, it means they have assured one another about a future exchange of some

    good which the other values. This coincides, as a descriptor of action, with the familiar notion

    of people trusting one another to do their part. Furthermore, Hobbes has a different concept of

    trust from the Lockean one. Whereas Hobbesian trust refers to reliance on others to carry out

    their part in joint action, Locke associates trust with holding others accountable to standards.

    Although less well-known, might the Hobbesian idea not be, in fact, a more common-sense

    18 Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 256: For Slaves that work in Prisons, or Fetters, do it not of duty, but to avoyd the cruelty of their task-masters. 19 John Locke, Second Treatise, in Two Treatises of Government, rev. ed. (New York: New American Library/Mentor, 1965), 119-122, pp. 392-94. 20 This is not to deny that Hobbes has a concept of tacit consent. It is clear he does: despotical dominion is acquired through a covenant either in expresse words, or by other sufficient signes of the Will (Leviathan, 20, p. 255). My argument concerns the moral core of Hobbesian contractarianism.

  • 9

    view of trust that more famous alternative? In game-theoretic terms, Hobbess idea

    corresponds to an assurance gamethis being one in which everyones first choice is

    cooperation, assuming the confidence that others will also cooperate. Within this situation,

    failing to do ones fair share becomes reprehensible.21

    The reciprocity of the trust relationship resolves the apparent problem of agency in the

    model of sovereignty by acquisition. Despite stressing the masters agency in trusting

    servants with liberty, it is the case conceptually (at least) that servants have an independent role

    in the relationship. In a full account of the creation of the relationship, Hobbes is careful to note

    the servants part: If a Subject be taken prisoner in war; or his person, or his means of life be

    within the Guards of the enemy, and hath his life and corporall Libertie given him, on condition

    to be Subject to the Victor, he hath Libertie to accept the condition; and having accepted it, is the

    subject of him that took him; because he had no other way to preserve himselfe.22 Acceptance

    of liberty might be stretched to connote acceptance of the duties of servitude. But this is a

    stretch and it is hard to see that, on the battlefield, accepting servitude as the price of life is a

    genuine choice, rather than being simplyas the Romans had saidan obvious benefit.

    The reciprocity of the contractual relationship resides, more fundamentally, in the

    obverse, negative dimension. The key question is not Do servants have a genuine choice in

    accepting the relationship? but, rather, Whose action may vitiate the relationship? The

    answer is that neither party may end it unilaterally: masters are not supposed to assault

    servants (i.e., treat them as slaves) and servants are not supposed to assault or flee masters (i.e.,

    21 Andrew Levine, Engaging Political Philosophy (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2002), p. 40. For the interpretation that Hobbess game is actually an assurance game (or stag hunt), see also Edwin Curly,

    Introduction to Hobbes Leviathan, in Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994), p. xxviii; Brian Skyrms, The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 4-6; Jean Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), esp. pp. 67-68; Philip Pettit, Made with Words: Hobbes on Language, Mind, and Politics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008), pp. 111-114. 22 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, 21, pp. 272-73.

  • 10

    act as slaves are permitted to do). In effect, Hobbess thinking shifts the moral locus of the

    argument away from the creation moment to the continuing trust relationship between

    independent actors. At the moment of captivity, the vanquished are at the mercy of the victors;

    subsequently, masters and servants are at one anothers mercy, so to speak. Only the others

    failure to carry out their part can vitiate the contractual relationship. Curiously, however, this

    implication is not spelled out in regard to the household relationship. Where it is spelled out, of

    course, is in the political analogy. The mutuall Relation between Protection and Obedience

    means, precisely, that subjects obligations depend upon their lives being protected by the

    sovereign. The Obligation of Subjects to the Soveraign, is understood to last as long, and no

    longer, than the power lasteth, by which he is able to protect them.23 In which case, the

    situation resembles that of slaves, whose vulnerability precludes obligation.

    The upshot is that we can see that Hobbess concept of trust is less demanding than is

    often thought. In game-theoretic interpretations, it is usually taken for granted that iteration is

    crucial to the Hobbesian solution to the assurance game. Granted, his reply to the Fool makes

    covenant-keeping depend upon iteration, which matters because it supports a forecast of future

    behavior.24 But the model of sovereignty by acquisition lays out a different idea of trust:

    rather than forecasting the future, trusting others involves monitoring whether they are doing

    their part.25 Nothing so vague as reasonable suspicion undoes cooperation;26 it is undone by

    identifiable failure with regard to an on-going exchange of benefits.

    23 Hobbes, Leviathan, 21, p. 272. The passage continues: Soveraignty . . . hath in it, from the very institution, many seeds of a naturall mortality. 24 Skyrms, Stag Hunt, p. 4. 25 For a discussion of the monitoring problem, see Levine, Engaging Political Philosophy, pp. 29ff. 26 Cf. Hampton, Hobbes and Social Contract Tradition, p. 68.

  • 11

    Political Covenants

    Trust unites the creation models of sovereignty by acquisition and sovereignty by

    institution, because it is basic to the salient kind of contract. A covenant is a contract in

    which one or both parties are trusted to performto deliver the Thing contracted for on his

    partin future. In situations in which both parties contract now, to performe hereafter: . . .

    he that is to performe in time to come, being trusted, his performance is called Keeping of

    Promise, or Faith; and the fayling of performance (if it be voluntary) Violation of Faith.27 Beyond

    the obvious point that a covenant creates an on-going relationship, the nuanced account of trust

    provided by the acquisition model aids understanding the other covenant story, sovereignty by

    institution.

    It brings to the fore the essential sense in which the institution covenant comes down to

    the exchange of obedience and service for protection. Notice that Leviathans key covenant

    passage describes the compact in precisely this way:

    The only way to erect such a Common Power, as may be able to defend them

    from the invasion of Forraigners, and the injuries of one another, and thereby to

    secure them in such sort, as that by their owne industrie, and by the fruites of the

    Earth, they may nourish themselves and live contentedly; is, to conferre all their

    power and strength upon one Man, or upon one Assembly of men.28

    The exchange principle carries over into particular applications, including discussions of the

    limits of subjection and the need for absolutism. An exiled subject is released from subjection

    27 Hobbes, Leviathan, 14, p. 193. 28 Hobbes, Leviathan, 17, p. 227. The passage continues: the Essence of the Common-wealth . . . (to define it,) is One Person, of whose Acts a great Multitude, by mutuall Covenants one with another, have made themselves every one the Author, to the end he may use the strength and means of them all, as he shall think expedient, for their Peace and Common Defence. The same formulation appears in the covenant passages in the earlier versions: Elements, 19.7-8, pp. 106-7; De Cive, 5.9, p. 89.

  • 12

    forasmuch as being out of the protection of the sovereignty that expelled him, he hath no

    means of subsisting but from himself. I.e., absent the benefit of protection, there had been no

    necessity that any man should enter into voluntary subjection, as they do in commonwealths.29

    Furthermore, protection requires absolute government: but grant then that thou hadst given

    him a power which were not absolute, but so much onely as sufficd to defend thee from the

    injuries of others, which, if thou wilt be safe, is necessary for thee to give; are not all the same

    things to be feared?30

    Therefore, it is a false dilemma to worry about whether Hobbes is a consent theorist or a

    theorist of de facto power: false because the Hobbesian political covenant is definedin the

    institution model like that of acquisitionby an on-going exchange of goods (benefits) that

    justifies de facto authority. Hoekstra is correct that the principle of the mutual relation of

    protection and obedience pervades Hobbess theory (although I disagree with his account of the

    nature of the connection).31

    This is not to say, however, that the exchange rationale fits comfortably in all Hobbess

    creation stories. Although the initial version of the institution covenant involves different

    parties than the acquisition story, the rationale fits readily into that version. Versus the mutual

    compact of conqueror and vanquished, the original non-resistance covenant is made by

    incipient subjects only; the incipient sovereign is not party to it.32 However, the nature of the

    compact itself is independent of the identity of the parties. Consider De Cive on the limits of

    29 Hobbes, Elements, 21.14, p. 125. 30 Hobbes, De Cive, 6.13, annotation to second edition, p. 99 (emphasis omitted). The passage carries over into Leviathans well-known comparison of the dangers of tyranny versus civil war (18, pp. 238-39). 31 Hoekstra, De Facto Turn, p. 39, and p. 72: The difficulty of how Hobbes can endorse both consent theory and the de facto theory of authority . . . can be resolved conceptually, via an understanding of tacit and attributed consent. Hoekstra criticizes an earlier work of mine that argues for Hobbess growing

    need, over the Civil War decade, to introduce historical facts into the theory (When Hobbes Needed

    History, in Hobbes and History, ed. G. A. J. Rogers and Tom Sorell [London: Routledge, 2000], pp. 25-43). I continue to see that as part of the story, but have come to regard it as less significant. 32 Hobbes, Leviathan, 17, p. 227; and 18, p. 230.

  • 13

    subjection. Hobbes begins by reiterating the terms of the non-resistance covenant: We have

    seen how Subjects, nature dictating, have obligd themselves by mutuall Compacts to obey the

    Supreme Power. As he continues, it is clear that the fact the sovereign is not a party to the

    compact doesnt alter the exchange logic. Subjects obligations end if and when the sovereign

    can no longer carry out his part of the bargain.

    If the Kingdome fall into the power of the enemy, so as there can no more

    opposition be made against them, we must understand that he, who before had

    the Supreme Authority, hath now lost it: For when the Subjects have done their

    full indeavour to prevent their falling into the enemies hands, they have fulfilld

    those Contracts of obedience which they made each with other.33

    Accurately, then, the Hobbesian social contract originally was a covenant in which incipient

    subjects promised to trust one another to serve and obey, for the indefinite future, that body

    whom they had nominated as sovereign. In return, they trust that they will receive on-going

    protection. It is inconsequential whether or not the sovereign actually makes a promise; even

    when the sovereign does not, the political covenant is defined by the trust that he will do his

    part, as they will do theirs.

    When Hobbes added an alternative, authorization account in Leviathan, he neglected,

    however, to consider its incompatibility with the exchange rationale. Authorization effectively

    undoes the limits which are built into an exchange contract. It substitutes identification, which

    is seemingly permanent, for impermanent, though indefinite, trust. The new image has the

    sovereign standing in for subjects, who are instructed to see themselves as the author of his

    actions; where the earlier account had described a relationship between parties with different

    goals, who agree to exchange goods in order to achieve them. The contrast appears plainly in a

    33 Hobbes, De Cive, 7.18, p. 116 (emphasis mine).

  • 14

    Leviathan discussion of the servant/master relationship. By this new account, a servant

    holdeth his life of his Master, by the covenant of obedience; that is, of owning, and authorising

    whatsoever the Master shall do. Should the servant be harmed rather than protected by the

    master, the moral relationship does not end. To the contrary, the servant, being author of the

    masters actions, is author of the harms: in case the Master, if he refuse, kill him, or cast him

    into bonds, or otherwise punish him for his disobedience, he is himselfe the author of the same;

    and cannot accuse him of injury.34 Hobbes faced a conceptual problem: how to strengthen the

    tie between ruler and ruled35 and also maintain exchange of benefits and trust as fundamental

    political principles? But it couldnt be done. Whereas contract versus de facto authority is a false

    dilemma, these two versions of the institution modelauthorization and identification versus

    exchange of benefits and trustare genuinely incompatible.

    Still, there is one further issue to which the false dilemma directs attention: Does the

    contract play an independent role in Hobbesian logic? Since the covenant is defined by an

    exchange of benefits of indefinite duration, does the theory reduce to an exchange story (in

    either a utilitarian or a conventional version)?36 Once again, it is helpful to return to Hobbess

    adaptation of the Roman rationalization of slavery, specifically his introduction of the

    distinction between servitude (based on covenant) and slavery (not). What the covenant

    accomplishes is the definition of the roles of master and servant and the responsibilities

    associated with each. The point of using a covenant to do this is to specify with some precision

    what constitutes agreement upon and acceptance of the roles; the duration of the roles; and,

    34 Hobbes, Leviathan, 20, p. 256. 35 See Hobbes, De Cive, 6.20, p. 105, where Hobbes explains that the idea of a direct tie between each subject and sovereign is needed to refute the false opinion that a parliamentary majority has the authority to remove the sovereign. 36 A classic of neo-utilitarian interpretation is John Plamenatz, Man and Society (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1963), vol. 1, ch. 4. Hampton, Hobbes and Social Contract, offers an assurance game version of a self-interested agreement (pp. 142-43).

  • 15

    therefore, what would end them. The roles are inaugurated when, with mutual agreement,

    captive servants are let out of their chains; they last indefinitely, until the other party fails to

    carry out his part. Thus the independent weight of the covenant lies not so much in giving

    subjects an additional motive for political obedience as in specifying what dominion and

    subjection precisely entail, and why.

    Political Servitude

    Subjects in a commonwealth are . . . nothing more than the slaves or servants of the sovereign. -- Philip Pettit, Made with Words37

    In the recent wave of literature on freedom and subjection, Hobbess revisionist distinction

    between servants and slaves is down-played and the concept of servitude, narrowly defined, is

    under-appreciated. Interpretive work on Hobbess negative concept of libertyby, most

    notably, Philip Pettit and Quentin Skinnerconcentrates on the neoRoman dichotomy of slave

    versus free-man and neglects Hobbess additional distinction between servants and slaves.

    Both interpreters regard these as merely varieties of subjection: two modes of slavery (Pettit)

    or two species of servant (Skinner).38 As the alternative phrasings indicate, though, they

    interpret Hobbesian liberty differently and therefore arrive at opposing characterizations of his

    political message. Defining freedom as non-domination, Pettit assimilates subjects to slaves

    inasmuch as both are deprived of their freedom of decision; and this leads him to conclude that

    Hobbes accepted the republican charge that subjects of absolute government are not free.39 By

    stressing the physical liberty of subjects, Skinner sees Leviathan as an effort, rather, to refute

    republicans on their own ground: being free of external constraint, subjects of absolute

    37 Pettit, Made with Words: Hobbes on Language, Mind, and Politics, p. 139. 38 Pettit, Made with Words, p. 135; Quentin Skinner, Hobbes and Republican Liberty, p. 43. 39 Pettit, Made with Words, pp. 138-39.

  • 16

    government as just as free as subjects of a republic.40

    Although they draw opposite ideological morals, both interpretations nonetheless focus

    on the original Roman opposition of slavery and freedom. Curiously, however, their

    descriptions of the condition of Hobbesian subjects actually correspond to his narrow,

    revisionist definition of servitude. Pettit uses a negative frame: Those who live under a

    commonwealth may be free-men in the sense of . . . retaining corporal freedombut they are

    not free-men in the intuitive sense of not being anyones servant or subject.41 I.e., subjects are

    the political equivalents of un-imprisoned servants. Hobbes and Republican Liberty concludes in

    the same vein, indeed with specific mention of the exchange covenant between conqueror and

    conquered. Skinner frames the point with specific reference to Leviathans defense of the Rump:

    it deserves to be obeyed in conscience as a fully lawful power because [t]hose who have

    accepted its protection, thereby receiving from it their lives and bodily liberty, may be said to

    have consented by sufficient signs to be its subjects.42 English subjects continue to trade

    obedience for protection, just as household slaves do, despite the change in regimes.

    In fact, Hobbes freely admitted the essential similarity of political subjects to household

    servants, especially in definitional discussions of the concept free man in The Elements of Law

    and De Cive. In the original version, the accent is on their shared servitude: The subjection of

    them who institute a commonwealth amongst themselves, is no less absolute, than the

    subjection of servants. They differ only inasmuch as a FREEMAN enjoys a state of better

    hope than a servant: A freeman therefore may expect employments of honour, rather than a

    servant. And this is all that can be understood by the liberty of the subject. For in all other

    40 E.g., Skinner, Hobbes and Republican Liberty, pp. 208-10. Skinner gives a developmental account of Hobbess thinking regarding liberty. I follow Hoekstra in emphasizing the consistency of his account of

    conquest through the theorys several versions (De Facto Turn, esp. p. 71). 41 Pettit, Made With Words, p. 139. 42 Skinner, Hobbes and Republican Liberty, p. 207, see pp. 198-208.

  • 17

    senses, liberty is the state of him that is not subject.43

    De Cive accents the positive: their shared physical liberty (in which sense all servants

    and subjects are free, who are not fettered and imprisoned). Still, Hobbess point remains that

    privileges are all that distinguish free subjects from servants.

    But this priviledge free subjects and sonnes of a family have above servants, (in

    every government, and family, where servants are) that they may both undergoe

    the more honourable offices of the City or family, and also enjoy a larger

    possession of things superfluous. And herein layes the difference between a free

    subject, and a servant, that he is FREE indeed, who serves his City onely; but a

    SERVANT is he who also serves his fellow subject: all other liberty is an exemption

    from the Laws of the City, and proper only to those that bear rule.

    Seemingly in an attempt to dress up subjection, he appends an exaggerated version of the

    exchange of benefits rationalization of servitude. Far from being oppressed, servants are

    governed and sustained. A servant shouldnt complain about a lack of liberty, unlesse he

    count it a misery to be restrained from hurting himselfe, and to receive that life, (which by

    warre, or misfortune, or through his own idlenesse was forfeited) together with all manner of

    sustenance, and all things necessary to the conservation of health, on this condition only, that he

    will be ruld.44

    Leviathan continues to accentuate subjects liberty. As Skinner has emphasized, the work

    gives a negative definition of a FREE-MAN (he, that in those things, which by his strength and

    43 Hobbes, Elements, 23.9, pp. 132-33. Here, in an aberrant suggestion that is nowhere repeated, Hobbes associates servitude with conquest and subjection with uncompelled dominion. 44 Hobbes, De Cive, 9.9, pp. 125-26.

  • 18

    wit he is able to do, is not hindred to doe what he has a will to45) and includes a new chapter on the

    liberty of subjects (21). The key issue in his debate with Pettit is the question of whether civil

    laws count as impediments to action.46 However, with regard to political relationships rather

    than philosophical conceptualization, there is nothing to debate. Hobbes opens chapter 21 of

    Leviathan (Of the Liberty of Subjects) with philosophical arguments that had been worked out

    in his debate with Bramhall in the mid-40s.47 But he quickly turns to the main subject: laws as

    artificial chains. In relation to these Bonds onlymaking reference to Artificiall Chains,

    called Civill Lawesit is, that I am to speak now, of the Liberty of Subjects.48 This liberty

    comes down, he goes on to explain, to the silence of the law and the inalienable natural right of

    self-defense.49 Neither was a new point, although inalienable right does not play out, as one

    might imagine, in a ban on military service;50 and the point about the silence of the law had

    appeared previously in support of rulers liberties. (In the earlier texts, he had explained that,

    aside from the privileges which free subjects enjoy over servants, all other liberty is an

    exemption from the Lawes of the City, and proper only to those that bear Rule.51) Although

    slanted thus in a novel direction, chapter 21 of Leviathan is fully consistent with the accounts of

    servitude and subjection in the earlier versions.

    Throughout, Hobbess message was that the English were not political slaves to the

    45 Hobbes, Leviathan, 21, p. 262. This definition was introduced in De Cive, 9.9, p. 125: LIBERTY, that we may define it, is nothing else but an absence of the lets, and hindrances of motion. 46 Pettit distinguishes two sorts of obstructions to action, contractual (including civil law) and corporal (Made with Words, pp. 135, 138, 153). Skinner distinguishes these are arbitrary versus external: Hobbes made room for both, he argues, in De Cive but, crucially, dropped the former in Leviathan (Hobbes and Republican Liberty, pp. 113-15, 127-28). 47 Skinner, Hobbes and Republican Liberty, pp. 129-31. 48 Hobbes, Leviathan, 21, pp. 263-64. 49 The application of this inalienable right to the case of military service is not, however, straightforward; see my Subjects and Soldiers: Hobbes on Military Service." History of Political Thought 4 (1983): 43-64. 50 I discussed the complexities of Hobbess account of military service in Subjects and Soldiers: Hobbes on Military Service." History of Political Thought 4 (1983): 43-64. 51 Hobbes, De Cive, 9.9, p. 126. See Elements, 23.9, p. 133, and 27.3, p. 164. This carries over in a margin note in chapter 21: The Liberty which writers praise, is the Liberty of Soveraigns; not of Private men (p. 266).

  • 19

    Stuarts. Nor should they desire political freedom in the (republican) sense of self-government,

    for that would quickly transform into civil war.52 Perhaps he had gone too far in De Cive in

    claiming that a government such as the Stuarts governed and sustained them. Still, his

    account of the political covenant established that the Stuarts provided a real good and showed

    that, until that government failed, subjects were therefore obliged to support it.

    In 21st-century jargon, the servant-subjects task was to monitor their assurance game

    with Charles I or, later, the Rump. The assurance covenant told them precisely how the game

    could legitimately be ended, and how not. Should the ruler(s) fail to play their part, subjects

    would be absolved of their part; but so long as rulers protected them, they were obliged to serve

    and obey. The precision of Hobbess accountof an exchange of benefits of indefinite

    duration--makes his political covenant not so different, in the end, from the Lockean

    accountability contract. The latter carefully spells out the contractual terms by which rulers are

    to be held to account: their role is to provide indifferent authority and to protect individuals

    lives, liberties, and estates.53 Should they fail to do so, they have contravened their role and

    subjects may rebel. Much as Hobbesian subjects are never licensed to rebel (which would be an

    illicit unilateral violation of the covenant), Hobbesian rulers are nonetheless accountable to

    provide specific goods, just as Lockean rulers are. Hobbess specification of the good is much

    shorter and he abjures rebellion. But trusting government to play its part is as much a

    Hobbesian sentiment as it is a Lockean one.

    52 Hobbes, De Cive, 6.13, annotation to second edition, p. 99: for if men could rule themselves, every man by his own command, that is to say, could they live according to the Lawes of Nature, there would be no need at all of a City, nor of a common coercive power (emphasis omitted). 53 Locke, Second Treatise, 226, p. 464.

  • Copyright of Conference Papers -- American Political Science Association is the property ofAmerican Political Science Association and its content may not be copied or emailed tomultiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission.However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.