59
HOW TO PROBE EXPLETIVES Jun Abe Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009 1-3-1 Tsuchitoi, Aoba-ku, Sendai 980-8511 JAPAN [email protected] TEL&FAX: 81-22-721-3239

Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

  • Upload
    vomien

  • View
    216

  • Download
    1

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

HOW TO PROBE EXPLETIVES

Jun Abe

Tohoku Gakuin University

January 2009

1-3-1 Tsuchitoi, Aoba-ku, Sendai

980-8511 JAPAN

[email protected]

TEL&FAX: 81-22-721-3239

Page 2: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

1

HOW TO PROBE EXPLETIVES

Abstract. This article aims to argue for the Move-approach to expletive constructions,

according to which expletives satisfy the EPP by moving to a designated position rather

than by being simply externally merged into it. In particular, it defends Sato’s (2008)

analysis of the there-construction under Chomsky’s (2008) probe-goal system, which

crucially assumes that the expletive and its associate make a constituent underlyingly

and that the associate carries partitive Case which needs to be checked in accordance

with the probe-goal mechanism. It is demonstrated that this analysis is both

conceptually and empirically superior to any known version of the External

Merge-approach to such a construction. Further, I propose a revision of Sato’s system

according to which expletives are characterized differently from other ordinary DPs in

terms of formal features: they carry unvalued -features. This makes it possible to

accommodate cases in which expletives appear to be involved in default agreement due

to the intervention effects induced by the experiencer phrases of raising predicates.

Key Words: expletives, partitive Case, default agreement

1. Introduction

It is no doubt that the investigation of how expletive constructions are derived has given

a significant impact on existing movement theories at various stages of the development

of generative grammar. The reason for this is that most cases of the expletive

constructions have corresponding movement cases that involve raising of DPs to the

Page 3: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

2

positions occupied by expletives. Thus, such an instance of the English

there-construction as (1a), for example, has the corresponding raising case shown in

(1b).

(1) a. There is someone in the garden.

b. Someone is in the garden.

The standard claim with such a pair of sentences is that they share an underlying

structure such as (2) below and that (1a) is derived from this structure by inserting there

in the subject position indicated by e, whereas (1b) is derived from it by moving

someone to that position.

(2) [ e is someone in the garden]

Since the advent of Case theory originally proposed by Vergnaud and extensively

developed by Chomsky (1981), it has been a central issue how the associate of there

(i.e., someone in (1a)) obtains Case. Concretely, given that in the derivation of (1b),

someone raises to the subject position to obtain nominative Case, it raises the question

how someone in (1a) obtains Case. Relating to this issue is the peculiar agreement

pattern observed with such a construction. As witnessed by comparing (1a) with the

following example, the matrix T agrees not with its subject there but rather with its

associate.

(3) There are some men in the garden.

Obviously, this raises the question how it is possible to establish an agreement relation

between T and the associate of there, given that the latter does not occupy the normal

position with which T agrees. These are basic issues of expletive constructions that

Page 4: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

3

have been tackled since the LGB era.

Since Chomsky (1986) proposed a LF movement theory of the there-construction,

according to which the associate of there undergoes LF movement to the position

occupied by there, he has taken a consistent stance in approaching these issues; that is,

he takes it that there has no direct relevance for the way its associate obtains Case from

and agrees with T. Rather, there is taken as just a place holder for subject position to

satisfy the Extended Projection Principle (henceforth, EPP). This basic idea is carried

over to the most recent system of feature checking theory under the Minimalist Program,

often called probe-goal system (cf. Chomsky (2000)), in which T probes with respect to

its -set and finds the associate of there as a goal, checking the -set against that of the

latter, and also the nominative Case of the associate is checked by T as a reflex, and

finally there is inserted into the Spec-TP to satisfy the EPP feature.

This article aims to argue against this position and to support the following

claims:

(4) a. Expletives and their associates form constituents underlyingly, following Sabel

(2000), Hornstein and Witkos (2003) and Sato (2008), among others.

b. Expletives have unvalued -features that may or may not be valued by their

associates.

Under this alternative system, such a there-construction as (1a) does not share with the

corresponding raising case (1b) the underlying structure given (2), but rather has

roughly the following underlying structure:

(5) [ e is [there someone] in the garden]

Page 5: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

4

(1a) is derived from this structure by raising there to the subject position marked by e,

in much the same way as (1b) is derived from (2) by raising someone. Nonetheless,

there are two crucial differences between the two cases: (i) the associate of there

receives Case other than nominative and (ii) even though there is directly involved in

checking the -features of T, the features it bears originally are unvalued, as indicated in

(4b). I argue that this approach to expletive constructions, which is named as

Move-approach in contrast with the standardly assumed External Merge-approach, is

superior to the latter in both conceptual and empirical considerations. Especially, I

demonstrate, along the lines of Sato’s (2008) approach, that it fits neatly into

Chomsky’s (2008) probe-goal system and that it properly captures the core data of

expletive constructions that have been extensively discussed in the minimalist literature.

Furthermore, I argue that the apparent empirical problems that will be raised against the

Move-approach with respect to the intervention effects caused by experiencer phrases in

the seem-type construction are naturally solved by attributing the unvalued status to the

-features of expletives, as characterized in (4b).

The paper is organized as follows: Section 2 outlines Sato’s (2008) analysis of

the there-construction under Chomsky’s (2008) probe-goal system and provides further

arguments for this analysis. Moreover, I try to extend Sato’s analysis to the expletive

it-construction, pointing out that the Move-approach is better off than the External

Merge-approach in this extended domain as well. Section 3 raises empirical problems

against the Move-approach with respect to different agreement patterns shown between

the cases involving the expletive there and the corresponding raising cases in the

Page 6: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

5

seem-type construction with an experiencer phrase. In Section 4, I provide solutions to

these problems, making crucial use of the unvalued status of the -features of expletives,

which makes it possible for them to be involved in default agreement. Further, I

provide a consequence of this revised Move-approach concerning the there-construction

embedded in the ECM, which contrasts with that involving a raising predicate in the

availability of default agreement.

2. Arguments for the Move-Approach to the There-Construction

2.1 An Outline of Sato’s (2008) Analysis

As a starting point, I first outline Sato’s (2008) analysis of the there-construction, which

instantiates the Move-approach to this construction under Chomsky’s (2008) probe-goal

system.

One of the conceptual problems Sato raises against the External Merge-analysis

of the there-construction is concerned with the singularity of the way the expletive there

is involved in the probe-goal system. Typically, External Merge is related to a

D-structure property, i.e., building up structures for selectional relations, whereas Move

is involved in deriving surface structures from these basic structures through

feature-checking under the probe-goal system. Given this situation, the role the

expletive there plays in this system is peculiar in that it is involved in feature checking

by way of External Merge. Thus, consider how (1a) is derived under the probe-goal

system assumed by Chomsky (2000). The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence

Page 7: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

6

is given below:1

(6) [T [vP be [SC someone in the garden]]]

At this stage, T probes with respect to its -set and finds someone as its goal, checking

these features as well as the nominative Case feature of the latter. Then, the expletive

there is externally merged with the structure in (6) to satisfy the EPP feature of T.

Under this system, expletives are only elements that satisfy EPP features by way of

External Merge.2

This anomaly of expletives induces an undesirable complication to Chomsky’s

(2000) probe-goal system. Let us consider the derivation of the following example:

(7) There is likely to be someone in the garden.

Since Chomsky assumes that all types of T, whether they are finite or infinitival, carry

EPP-features, the embedded infinitival T in (7) needs an element to satisfy its EPP

feature, and in this case, the expletive there serves to this end. Hence, it is inserted

into the Spec of the embedded TP, as shown in (8a), and then is raised into the Spec of

the matrix TP to satisfy an EPP feature again, which gives rise to (8b):

(8) a. [TP there to [vP be [SC someone in the garden]]]

b. [TP there T [vP be [AP likely [TP t to [vP be [SC someone in the garden]]]]]]

This shows that the expletive there can undergo Move under Chomsky’s system of

1 In this structure, SC stands for small clause. In this paper, I will not be committed to

the exact structure of the small clause given in (6). 2 See Groat (1999) for a similar reasoning with respect to the singularity of the way

there satisfies the EPP, which leads him to adopt the Move-approach.

Page 8: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

7

feature checking, and this is exactly the cause of an undesirable complication.

Chomsky (2000) assumes that in the probe-goal system, a goal must be active to serve

as such and that in order to be active, it must carry an uninterpretive feature; this is

called Activation Condition. Thus, to guarantee that the expletive there can undergo

Move, which requires a preceding application of the operation Agree in terms of a

probe-goal relation, it needs to carry an uninterpretable feature. At the same time,

however, it must be defective, in contrast with other full-fledged DPs, in the sense that

it cannot enter an ordinary Agree relation with T. Notice that in (7), the matrix T

agrees not with there but rather with its associate someone, as is clear from the

comparison of (7) with the following example:

(9) There are likely to be some men in the garden.

To capture this fact, Chomsky proposes that the expletive there does not carry a full

-set but only carries an uninterpretable person feature (henceforth abbreviated as

[uPerson]). Thus, at the stage just before there undergoes Move to the matrix TP to

yield (8b), T probes with respect to its -set and hits there first as a goal, since the latter

is active and carries part of a full -set. This nonetheless does not lead to checking of

the -set of T due to the defective -features of there, which then allows T to probe

again. It then hits someone and its -set is properly checked against that borne by

someone, as well as the Case-feature of the latter as a reflex. This explains why T

agrees with the associate of there rather than there itself. Finally, as there has served

as a goal for T even though it does no establish an Agree relation, it undergoes Move to

the matrix Spec-TP to satisfy the EPP-feature of T.

Page 9: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

8

Though the characterization of there as carrying [uPerson] may work well in

deriving such a there-construction as (7) and (9) as well as accounting for the agreement

pattern observed in such a construction, it nonetheless causes an apparently unnecessary

complication in deriving a simple there-construction such as (1a), as pointed out by

Nomura (2004) and Richards and Biberauer (2005). Let us consider again (6),

repeated below, which represents the stage of derivation of (1a) just before there is

inserted.

(10) [T [vP be [SC someone in the garden]]]

As mentioned above, from this stage of derivation, there is inserted into the Spec-TP to

satisfy the EPP-feature of T. Note that there carries [uPerson] that needs to be

checked, which then forces there to act as a probe. Chomsky (2000) claims that this

uninterpretive feature is checked against the -set of T, but as pointed out correctly by

Richards and Biberauer (2005), the latter ought to be inactive, as its -set is already

checked, hence not being able to be involved in checking the [uPerson] of there.3 On

top of this, this checking is apparently unnecessary in deriving such a simple

there-construction as (1a) in a proper way, which then strongly suggests that the

[uPerson] that is attributed to there is just a technical artifact that is posited only to

3 A reviewer kindly reminds me of another significant problem to Chomsky’s (2000)

system, pointed out by Bo kovi (2007): under this system, nothing guarantees that

probing by there with respect to its [uPerson] feature cannot take place when it is

inserted into the Spec-TP at the stage given in (8a). If there established an Agree

relation with someone at this stage, it could not move to the matrix Spec-TP due to the

Activation Condition.

Page 10: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

9

capture the fact that there undergoes Move in the derivation of such a there-construction

as (7) and (9). This undesirable complication seems to occur due to the anomaly of

there as being involved in checking an EPP-feature by way of External Merge.

Sato (2008) also raises an empirical problem with the External Merge-approach to

the there-construction, which is concerned with one of the data regarding such a

construction that have attracted much attention under the Minimalist Program:

(11) a. There is likely to be someone in the garden. (=(7))

b. *There is likely someone to be in the garden.

Chomsky (2000) basically follows Chomsky (1995) in accounting for the

ungrammaticality of (11b) by the Merge-over-Move Principle, which dictates that

Merge must be chosen over Move at a given stage of derivation if both operations are

available. This principle is conceptually motivated by the economy consideration

according to which Move is a costly operation, contrary to External Merge, in that it

applies to a syntactic object that is already integrated into a structure. To see how this

principle works, let us consider the stage of derivation of (11a, b) where the embedded

infinitival T is merged with the following vP, as shown below:

(12) [to [vP be someone in the garden]]

At this stage, the EPP-feature of the infinitival T needs to be satisfied and two options

are available for this purpose: either externally merge there or move someone into the

Spec-TP. The Merge-over-Move principle dictates that the former option be chosen,

as shown below:

(13) [TP there to [vP be someone in the garden]] (= (8a))

Page 11: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

10

Then the derivation proceeds in the way indicated in (8), giving rise to sentence (11a).

Since the Merge-over-Move Principle forces there-insertion at the stage given in (12),

there is no legitimate way to produce sentence (11b), which could be derived if someone

was moved to the embedded Spec-TP at this stage.

Sato (2008) points out correctly that such an analysis in terms of the

Merge-over-Move Principle does not work any more under the current conception of

the Minimalist Program, since Move is now characterized as a cost-free operation.

Thus, Chomsky (2004) claims that Move (or Internal Merge according to his

terminology) is “an operation that is freely available,” and “accordingly, displacement is

not an ‘imperfection’ of language; its absence would be an imperfection.” (p. 8) Given

this conception of Move, the Merge-over-Move Principle will lose its basis in terms of

economy considerations, and hence we need a different account for the

ungrammaticality of such a case as (11b).4

In order to solve the problems pointed out above, Sato (2008) adopts a

Move-approach to the there-construction, such as the one proposed by Sabel (2000) and

Hornstein and Witkos (2003), in which the expletive there forms a constituent with its

associate underlyingly, as given below:

4 See Epstein and Seely (1999, 2006) and Bo kovi (2002, 2007) for additional

arguments against the Merge-over-Move Principle.

Page 12: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

11

(14) P

3

there the associate

[+ ][-Case] [+ ][-Case(Part)]

Sato does not commit herself to the identification of the category that constitutes there

and its associate (that is why she exploits P) nor to the internal structure of this

category. There carries interpretable -features and an uninterpretable Case-feature,

just like other ordinary DPs, and it shares the values of its -features with its associate,

as indicate by [+ ]. Even though Sato does not address the question of what internal

structure guarantees the fact that there and its associate share the values of -features,

her analysis will be quite compatible with Sabel (2000) and Hornstein and Witkos

(2003), who claim that their internal structure is something like the following:

(15) DP

3

D NP

1

there[+ ][-Case] the associate[+ ][-Case(Part)]

In this structure, the agreement relation between there and its associate is captured in

the structural relation of the D head to its NP complement, as is the case with French

articles such as le, la, les, for instance, as claimed by Hornstein and Witkos (2003).

The associate carries not only -features but also an uninterpretable Case-feature.

Page 13: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

12

Sato assumes, following Belletti (1988), that this Case-feature must be valued as

partitive due to the selectional requirement imposed by there upon its associate. This

captures so-called definiteness effects exhibited by the associate; that is, the fact that it

must be an indefinite.5 Notice that there and its associate act as independent nominal

elements in the sense that each carries its own - and Case-features. In this respect,

Sato’s analysis will be more accurately couched with the internal structure given in (15)

than with other alternatives under which there and its associate constitute a

subject-predicate relation.6 Furthermore, it will be argued in the next subsection that

the idea that there and its associate make a constituent underlyingly should be extended

to the pair of the expletive it and its associate clause, and that the reason why the latter

pair does not share -features unlike the former is attributed to the selectional relation of

5 See Chomsky (1995) and Bo kovi (2007) for a claim to the effect that the expletive

there carries a D-feature that requires NP as its associate at LF and hence the latter

needs to be an indefinite, on the assumption that definiteness resides in D.

A reviewer points out that since partitive Case has semantic import, it will not be

natural to assume that it is uninterpretable/unvalued. To resolve this inadequacy, we

may adopt Pesetsky and Torrego’s (2007) feature checking mechanism, according to

which formal features are characterized in terms of both interpretability and valuation.

Given this mechanism, it will not be unnatural to assume that the associate of there

carries an interpretable and unvalued Case feature, whose value is supplied as partitive

by a relevant verb. For expository purposes, I keep to outlining Sato’s (2008) original

mechanism in the text. See Sections 3 and 4 for relevant discussions regarding

interpretability and valuation. 6 See Hoekstra and Mulder (1990) and Moro (1997), among others, for the claim that

there is a predicate and its associate serves as its subject, and Williams (1994) and

Hazout (2004) for the opposite view.

Page 14: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

13

D to its complement CP; see (35). To the extent that the availability of -feature

sharing is naturally captured by the selectional relation of D to NP vs. CP, the internal

structure given in (15) will be more appropriate under Sato’s theory than the

subject-predicate structure, advocated by the scholars mentioned in fn. 6.

Belletti claims that “[b]ecause partitive is an inherent Case assigned by verbs, it

will typically be assigned to the direct object of both transitive and unaccusative verbs,”

(p. 3) which is clearly indicated by such a language as Finnish that has an overt

manifestation of partitive Case, as illustrated below:

(16) a. Hän pani kirjoja pöydälle.

he put bookpart, pl on the table

‘He put some books on the table.’

b. Helsingistä tulee kirjeitä.

from Helsinki comes letterpart, pl

‘There come some letters from Helsinki.’

c. *Miehiä on tavannut Pekan kadulla.

manpart, pl aux3sg met Pekkagen in the street

‘Some men met Peter in the street.’

The ungrammaticality of (16c) follows from the fact that partitive Case is not assigned

by T. Thus, the assumption that the associate of there must have its uninterpretable

Case feature valued as partitive serves to capture its limited distribution. For instance,

it accounts for the contrast in grammaticality between the sentences in (1a), (3), (7) and

(9) on the one hand and the following sentences on the other:

Page 15: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

14

(17) a. *There seem that a lot of people are intelligent.

b. *There seem to a lot of people that it is raining outside.

In these sentences, the associate of there, i.e., a lot of people appears in a position where

it is unable to get its uninterpretable Case feature valued as partitive, and hence the

derivations do not converge or if they do, they violate the selectional requirement

imposed by there upon its associate.

Sato assumes, along the lines of Lasnik’s (1995) theory of partitive Case, that this

Case is involved in the probe-goal system exactly in the same way as other structural

Cases. This assumption leads us to consider an idiosyncratic property of the

there-construction that appears to make partitive Case differ from other structural Cases

at least in a certain variety of languages, including English: the type of verbs which are

able to appear in this construction is limited to unaccusative verbs, including be, as

noted by Hoekstra and Mulder (1990):7

(18) a. There just may not exist a solution (to this problem).

b. There occurred a catastrophe (in that country).

(19) a. *There walked a man with a dog.

b. *There ate a man a pudding.

The grammaticality contrast between the sentences in (18) and those in (19) will be

7 The types of the expletive construction illustrated in (19) are in fact grammatical in

such languages as Dutch and Icelandic with the word orders indicated in the

ungrammatical English examples. The ungrammaticality of these examples has

nothing to do with their word orders but simply indicates that intransitives and

transitives are incompatible with the there-construction.

Page 16: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

15

accounted for if we stipulate that those verbs that are able to value the uninterpretable

Case feature of the associate of there as partitive are confined to unaccusative verbs.

Given Belletti’s (1988) claim that partitive Case is in principle assigned by any type of

verbs, however, it is desirable to dispense with this stipulation. I will demonstrate

directly how this can be done under Sato’s approach to the there-construction.

Given that partitive Case is valued by verbs, a question arises as to whether the vP

that is involved in checking this Case constitutes a strong phase, since the usual

assumption with this latter notion is that when v is involved not only in Case checking

but also in licensing an external argument, its maximal projection constitutes a strong

phase. Sato assumes that the answer is positive; that is, Case checking suffices for a

given vP to constitute a strong phase. This is crucial for the probe-goal system she

assumes in which the search domain of a probe is regulated by the

Phase-Impenetrability Condition (henceforth, PIC), as stated below:8

(20) Phase-Impenetrability Condition

In Phase with head H, the domain of H is not accessible to operations outside ,

only H and its edge are accessible to such operations. (Chomsky 2000, p. 108)

Thus, according to this condition, once a partitive Case is checked in vP, the domain of

v, namely VP, is not accessible to any operation at the next phase level.

8 Sato (2008) adopts the version of the PIC proposed by Chomsky (2000), but it would

not matter, as far as I can see, if she adopted the different version of the PIC assumed by

Chomsky (2001). This is because under the probe-goal system invented by Chomsky

(2008), which Sato adopts, only a phrase head is eligible for a probe, which neutralizes

a crucial difference between the two different versions of the PIC.

Page 17: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

16

Let us now see how there-constructions are derived under the probe-goal system

of Chomsky (2008) with the assumptions made by Sato (2008). To take (1a) for

illustration, the first stage where a phase head probes is the following:

(21) [v’ v* [V’ be [DP there someone] in the garden]]]

At this stage, be inherits -features from the phase head v* and probes for them. There

are two options that can serve as goals for this probing: there and someone. Sato

claims that in this situation, the associate someone should be chosen as a goal, since be

is able to provide a partitive Case as a reflex of the checking of -features.9 After this

Agree relation is established, someone is raised into the Spec of V. At the same time,

the expletive there is raised into the Spec of v* thanks to the edge feature of the latter;

otherwise, its Case feature would remain unvalued and hence the derivation would

crash.10 This completes the derivation of the lower v*P, as given below:11

9 Or the expletive there will not be an appropriate receiver of partitive Case, given that

it occupies the D head, as assumed in the structure given in (15), and that partitive Case

is provided only to NP. 10 A reviewer raises the question whether there prevents be from targeting the associate

as its goal because there is closer to be than its associate. There are at least two

possibilities to address this question. One is, as the reviewer suggests, to rely on the

notion of equidistance, so that there may not block be from targeting the associate

because both there and its associate are equidistant from the target. The other

possibility, which is more interesting under the probe-goal system assumed here, is to

exploit the notion of parallel operations in such a way that in one span of such

operations, their targets do no interfere in each other’s operations with respect to

minimality. Thus, in the v*-V level of operations given in the text, (22) is derived

from (21) at once, all operations involved taking place in parallel. Hence, there and its

Page 18: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

17

(22) [v*P therei [v*’ v*+be [VP someonej [V’ tbe [DP ti tj] in the garden]]]]

The next phase level that can undergo probing is the matrix C, as shown below:

(23) [C’ C [T’ Pres [v*P therei [v*’ v*+be [VP someonej [V’ tbe [DP ti tj] in the garden]]]]]]

At this stage, T inherits -features from the phase head C and probes for them. In this

case, there is the only candidate for a goal, since any element inside VP is not

accessible for this probing, according to the PIC. Then the checking of -features

between T and there leads to providing nominative Case feature to the latter as a reflex,

which establishes an Agree relation and brings there into the Spec of T. This

completes the derivation of sentence (1a), as shown below:

(24) [CP [TP therei [T’ Pres [v*P t’i [v*’ v*+be [VP someonej [V’ tbe [DP ti tj] in the garden]]]]]]]

Notice that since the expletive there shares the values of its -features with its associate,

the fact that the -features of there is checked with those of T results in the required

agreement pattern in which T agrees with the associate of there.

This way of deriving a there-construction is immune from the conceptual

problems pointed out above. For one thing, there is no singularity that applies only to

associate, which are both targets of separate operations, do not interfere in each other’s

operations. 11 In this derivation, be is raised into the above v*, as is the case with other main verbs.

Given that it behaves like an auxiliary with respect to SAI and the relative order with

not, etc., it should raise further into T when no other auxiliary occupies that position.

For an expository purpose, however, we will dispense with this further movement to T

in the representations given in the text, since nothing hinges on whether it really takes

place or not.

Page 19: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

18

the expletive there in the way the - and Case-features are checked in the present

probe-goal system: after an Agree relation is established between a probe and a goal in

terms of the - and Case-features, the goal itself or a phrase including it is pied-piped to

the Spec of the probe, irrespective of whether the targeted phrase is an ordinary DP or

the expletive there. Furthermore, there will arise no complication that has arisen under

the External Merge-approach when we consider a more complex case of the

there-construction. Let us consider the derivation of (7) under the present system.

The first stage at which a phase head has done probing is the same as that for (1a),

namely the one given in (22), repeated below:

(25) [v*P therei [v*’ v*+be [VP someonej [V’ tbe [DP ti tj] in the garden]]]]

The next phase level at which probing takes place is the matrix CP; the intermediate TP

is not a phase by definition nor the matrix vP due to its lack of Case checking. Thus

we reach the following stage:

(26) [C’ C [T’ Pres [vP [v’ v+be [AP likely [T’ to [v*P therei [v*’ v*+be [VP someonej [V’ tbe

[DP ti tj] in the garden]]]]]]]]]]

At this stage, T inherits -features from the phase head C and probes for them. In this

case again, there is the only candidate for a goal, since any element inside VP is not

accessible for this probing, according to the PIC, as indicated by striking out the

relevant part. Then the checking of -features between T and there leads to providing

nominative Case feature to the latter as a reflex, which establishes an Agree relation and

brings there into the Spec of T. Since the intermediate infinitival T has an EPP-feature,

the movement of there must be successive-cyclic, which leads to the final representation

Page 20: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

19

of sentence (7), as shown below:

(27) [CP [TP therei [T’ Pres [vP [v’ v+be [AP likely [TP t”i [T’ to [v*P t’i [v*’ v*+be [VP someonej

[V’ tbe [DP ti tj] in the garden]]]]]]]]]]]]

Notice that nothing special is required in deriving such a complex there-construction as

(7). This situation sharply contrasts with that found under the External

Merge-approach, in which positing a [uPerson] feature to capture the fact that there can

undergo Move in such a case as (7) leads to an unnecessary complication in such a

simple case as (1a), that is, the need for there to serve as a probe with respect to the

[uPerson] feature. On top of that, the present system dispenses with re-probing by T,

arguably a desired consequence, which is necessary under the External Merge-approach.

Recall that in deriving such a there-construction as (7) under the External

Merge-approach, the matrix T that probes for its -set first hits there as a goal, but that

due to the defective -features of there, T needs to probe again and hits someone as an

appropriate checker of the -set. This is apparently not an efficient way of checking

relevant features, and hence it would be better to dispense with it. Thus the present

system is advantageous in this respect as well.

As for the empirical problem pointed out above regarding the pair of

there-constructions given in (11), Sato (2008) claims that the ungrammatical case (11b)

is straightforwardly excluded under the present system. Let us consider again the

stage of derivation given in (26), which is shared by (11a) and (11b). In order to

derive sentence (11b) from this stage, someone needs to raise to the intermediate

Spec-TP, but as indicated by striking out the relevant part, the PIC prohibits it from

Page 21: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

20

doing so.12 Hence, there is no way of deriving (11b) under the present system.

Therefore, the ungrammaticality of this sentence follows automatically without any

further stipulation.

Let us finally address the question of how the present system derives the fact,

noted above, that only unaccusative verbs appear to be able to license the associate of

the there-construction. Let us first consider the case of the there-construction that

involves an intransitive verb. Suppose that the complex form consisting of there and

its associate occupies the subject position of such a verb, as schematized below:

(28) C [T’ T [v*P [DP there associate] v* [VP Vintr]]]

Given this structure, there is no way for the associate to obtain partitive Case, under the

assumption that it must be obtained by a verb. Hence, such a case is excluded for

exactly the same reason as the cases in (17).13 Let us next consider the case that

12 As a reviewer points out, raising of someone into the intermediate Spec-TP would

induce a minimality violation, since there is closer to that position than someone.

Furthermore, even if someone were able to raise somehow into the intermediate

Spec-TP, that would then block raising of there into the matrix Spec-TP due to a

minimality violation. See Groat (1999) for such an account under Chomsky’s (1995)

framework. Notice that neither account in terms of minimality will be maintained if

we adopt the second possibility suggested in fn. 10, according to which the targets of

parallel operations do not interfere in each other’s operations regarding minimality. In

that case, we need to rely on the PIC to exclude the derivation of (11b). 13 We have not considered the possibility that in (28), the expletive is involved in

checking of the -features of T and is raised into the Spec-TP, whereas the associate is

raised into the Spec-CP thanks to the edge feature of C, hence accessible to the next

v*-V phase level. I assume that the movement of the associate across the expletive is

Page 22: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

21

involves a transitive verb. Suppose that the complex form consisting of there and its

associate occupies the object position of such a verb, as schematized below:

(29) [v*P DP v* [VP Vtr [DP there associate]]]

Notice that we are assuming that any type of verbs can provide partitive Case in

principle. Hence, in (29), V and the associate can enter into an Agree relation,

checking both -and Case-features against each other, and then the associate raises into

the Spec-VP. After there raises into the Spec-v*P thanks to the edge feature of v*, we

reach the following stage of derivation:

(30) [C’ C [T’ T [v*P therei [v*P DP [v*’ v*+V [VP associatej [V’ tV [DP ti tj]]]]]]]]

At this stage, T necessarily picks up there as a goal, since the latter is the closest to T,

and hence the external argument DP is left unchecked, leading the derivation to crash.

This is why transitive verbs cannot be involved in the there-construction. As a result,

only unaccusative verbs can lead instances of the there-construction to convergent

derivations.

2.2 An Alternative of the External Merge-Approach

There is one competing alternative of the External Merge-approach, proposed by Abe

(1997) and Bo kovi (2002), which is worth considering here. Abe and Bo kovi

claim, contrary to Chomsky (2000), that no EPP requirement is imposed upon raising

infinitival clauses. Under this assumption, such an instance of the there-construction

banned by a general condition to be specified, and hence leave such a possibility out of

consideration.

Page 23: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

22

as (7) is derived without applying Move to there; in other words, by simply inserting

there into the matrix Spec-TP, as shown below:

(31) [TP there is likely [TP to be someone in the garden]]

Under this analysis, the ungrammaticality of (11b) immediately follows from the Last

Resort Principle, since to move someone to the intermediate Spec-TP would have no

triggering. On the other hand, Abe and Bo kovi claim that in such a raising case as

the following:

(32) Someone is likely to be in the garden.

someone undergoes successive-cyclic movement, passing through the intermediate

Spec-TP. They follow Chomsky (1993) in that successive-cyclic movement is not a

result of satisfying the EPP-features of intermediate TPs but rather follows from the

Shortest Move (henceforth, SM, which is phrased as Minimize Chain Links in Chomsky

and Lasnik (1993)), which dictates that each application of Move cannot pass a possible

landing site.

Though this alternative of the External Merge-approach has many interesting

empirical consequences other than providing a very neat explanation to the pair given in

(11) (see Section 3), it gives rise to a couple of both conceptual and empirical problems,

when couched under Chomsky’s (2008) probe-goal system. Let us begin with

conceptual problems. Abe (1997) and Bo kovi (2002) assume that the expletive there

is inserted by External Merge into a Case position to satisfy a Case requirement of a

head, i.e., the Inverse Case Filter. Given the assumption that intermediate infinitival

Ts do not carry any feature, including an EPP-feature, it follows that there does not

Page 24: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

23

move under the system invented by Abe and Bo kovi ; in this sense, their approach is

viewed as a more radical External Merge-approach than that advocated by Chomsky

(2000). For one thing, this system suffers the singularity of the expletive there in that

it is the only element that is involved in feature checking by way of External Merge.

Since Abe and Bo kovi assume that there carries a Case-feature, it will have to

function as a probe after it is externally merged into a given structure under the

probe-goal system. Thus, to take (1a), repeated below as (33) with a relevant structure,

for illustration,

(33) [TP there T [vP v+is someone in the garden]]

after there is externally merged into the Spec-TP, it should probe for its Case-feature

and finds T as its goal, checking this feature.14 A crucial question to raise here is how

the -features of T are checked. If we follow the way an Agree relation is established

under Chomsky’s (2008) probe-goal system, it will be most natural to claim that the

-features of T are valued as a reflex of Case-feature checking. However, this alone

does not capture the fact that in the there-construction, T agrees with the associate of

there. In order to capture this, we need some extra operation. We might say that

before there is inserted into the Spec-TP, T has already established an Agree relation

with its associate with respect to their -features. Since the Case-feature of the

14 One may notice that this way of feature checking is anomalous, given the standard

assumption that Agree precedes External Merge or Move. But in Section 3, I adopt the

claim, made by Goto (2008), that the EPP can be satisfied by Move before Agree takes

place in English. Hence, this anomaly carries over to our system.

Page 25: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

24

associate is taken care of by be, T will still have the ability of checking the Case-feature

of there. Though this works technically, it is not as efficient as the Move-approach

adopted here in that T establishes more than one Agree-relation, one involving

-features and the other involving Case-feature, which happens only when T has the

expletive there in its Spec position. This inefficiency has the same flavor as

re-probing necessary for Chomsky’s (2000) analysis of the there-construction.15

Let us now move on to empirical problems. It is well-known that there is

another type of expletives that do not induce agreement between T and their associates,

but rather are directly involved in an agreement with T. The expletive it in English is

such a case, as illustrated in the following paradigm:

(34) a. That he’ll resign and that he’ll stay in office seem at this point equally

possible.

b. *It seem at this point equally possible that he’ll resign and that he’ll stay in

office.

c. It seems at this point equally possible that he’ll resign and that he’ll stay in

office. (McCloskey 1991, p. 564-565)

(34a) shows that when that-clauses are conjoined in subject position, they exhibit a

plural agreement with T, as witnessed by the morphological form of seem. Under the

15 Another way of capturing the agreement pattern in question is to relate there and its

associate by way of covert movement; either by adjoining the associate to there, as in

Lasnik (1992, 1995) and Abe (1997) or the other way around, as in Bo kovi (1997).

Since such an option does not seem to fit well into Chomsky’s (2008) probe-goal

system, I will leave it aside.

Page 26: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

25

probe-goal system adopted here, this agreement fact will follow if we assume that the

conjoined that-clauses are base-generated after the adjective possible and that they have

[+plural] value for their number feature. Thus, when the matrix T probes for its

-features, it finds the conjoined that-clauses as its goal, hence its -features valued by

those of the latter.16 The contrast between (34b) and (34c), on the other hand, shows

that the presence of the expletive it in subject position forces a singular agreement with

T. How can the radical External Merge-approach account for this agreement pattern?

Nomura (2004) points out correctly that under the system in which the expletive it is

directly merged into Spec-TP, it is predicted that (34b) rather than (34c) should be

grammatical, since T searches for an element within its c-command domain, hence

choosing the conjoined that-clauses as its goal in exactly the same way as in (34a).

Thus, given that the Spec/head relation is no longer relevant for feature checking, any

version of External Merge-approach to expletive constructions will be confronted with

the problem of how to capture the fact that such an expletive as the English it exhibits

an agreement with T.17

16 Given the Activation Condition, the conjoined that-clauses must carry an

uninterpretable feature so as to undergo Move after an Agree relation is established

between them and T. I leave open exactly what uninterpretable feature is involved in

this checking. See Bo kovi (1995) for the claim that a clause optionally carries a

Case-feature and that when it undergo A-movement, it is required to carry this feature. 17 Bo kovi (1997) argues that (34b) does not necessarily show the agreement between

the expletive it and T, as McCloskey argues, but rather that this agreement pattern can

be taken as a result of the first conjunct agreement with the associate of it. The latter

agreement pattern is independently observed with the expletive there, as he provides a

Page 27: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

26

The Move-approach adopted here, on the other hand, is free from such a problem

if we make the natural assumption that the expletive it and its associated clause make a

constituent underlyingly, just like the there-construction. The expletive it crucially

differs, however, from the expletive there in that it does not share the values of its

-features with its associate. We can capture this fact by positing the underlying

structure of it and its associate as something like the following:18

relevant example such as the following:

(i) There is/*are a man and five women in the garden.

Though this analysis correctly captures the agreement pattern exhibited by (34b), it

raises a problem with that exhibited by (34a). Under the present probe-goal system, it

will be predicted that it should show a singular agreement for exactly the same reason as

(34b) does. Thus, a question still remains as to how to capture the whole agreement

pattern given in (34) under the External Merge-approach. I thank a reviewer for

bringing Bo kovi ’s (1997) analysis to my attention. 18 See Bo kovi ’s (1997) for the claim that “the associate of expletive it must be a

clause specified as [+tense],” (p. 90) which captures the fact that it can host infinitival

control clauses whereas it cannot host infinitives containing NP-traces, as illustrated

below:

(i) a. It was arranged [PRO to leave].

b. *Iti was believed [ti to be someone in the garden].

We might capture this fact on the assumption that only [+tense] infinitival clauses are

CPs and that the expletive it selects CP as its complement.

Page 28: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

27

(35) DP

3

D CP

1 it[+ ][-Case] the associate[+ ]

It is not unnatural to assume that unlike the D-N association, which induces -feature

sharing, the D-C association does not induce such an effect. As a result, the expletive

it has its own values of -features, namely third person singular. In deriving such a

sentence as (34c), the matrix T probes for -features and finds it as its goal. Notice

that the associate that-clause is invisible to such probing due to lack of uninterpretable

features. Then, the -features of T are checked against those of it and the latter obtains

nominative Case as a reflex. This correctly captures the fact that the expletive it agrees

with T.

Notice furthermore that this construction differs from the there-construction in

whether the associate carries a Case such as partitive. Recall that we have discussed

toward the end of the preceding subsection how the present system can derive the fact

that only unaccusative verbs can be involved in the there-construction. In this account,

partitive Case plays a crucial role: since this Case must be obtained by a verb, the

associate cannot function as the external argument of an intransitive verb (and a

transitive verb for that matter), and when the associate appears in the internal argument

of a transitive verb, partitive Case must be checked by this verb, which thus makes it

necessary for the expletive there to be checked by T and hence leaves the external

Page 29: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

28

argument unchecked. It is then predicted under the present system that there will be no

such restriction with respect to the type of verbs in the it-construction, and this is

apparently the case. Furthermore, it is predicted that the expletive it can not only be

checked by a finite T with nominative Case but also by a transitive verb with accusative

Case. That this is in fact the case is demonstrated in detail by Postal and Pullum

(1988); some examples that show that the expletive it can appear in object position are

reproduced below:

(36) a. I dislike it that he is so cruel.

b. I didn’t suspect it for a moment that you would fail.

c. I regret it very much that would could not hire Mosconi.

These facts thus lend support to the position according to which the there-construction

and the it-construction are treated on a par, that is, the expletives and their associates

form a constituent underlyingly, and the different distributions exhibited by the two

constructions are ascribed to the presence of partitive Case in the associate of there.

A second problem that will arise with the radical External Merge-approach has to

do with the following pair of sentences discussed by Lasnik (1995):

(37) a. There is likely to be a building demolished.

b. There is a building likely to be demolished.

In (37a), a building functions as the internal argument of demolished, and hence it must

have moved from the complement position of the verb to whatever position precedes it.

Lasnik claims that the movement is to Spec-Agro to check the partitive Case of a

building. Given this, it will be expected that (37b) is derived by moving a building

Page 30: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

29

from the complement position of demolished all the way to the surface position in a

successive-cyclic fashion, passing though the intermediate Spec-TP. However, this

expectation is not fulfilled, as witnessed by the fact that extraction of such an adjunct as

how is possible with (37a), but not with (37b):

(38) a. Howi is there likely to be [a building demolished ti]?

b.?*Howi is there a building likely to be [demolished ti]?

Lasnik asserts that if such a raising derivation as described just above were available to

(37b), then we would not expect that (38b) were ungrammatical, and hence that this

sentence should be analyzed differently. He suggests that it involves a reduced relative

clause that modifies the associate of there; that is, likely to be demolished is a reduced

relative modifying a building. (38b) is then explained as a violation of the complex

NP island condition.

Lasnik prevents the raising derivation in question for (37b) by assuming,

following Belletti (1988), that partitive Case is inherent. In (37a), the partitive Case of

a building is properly licensed, since its -role assigner, i.e., demolished, is covertly

raised into Agro to license it. In (37b), by contrast, the partitive Case of a building is

not properly licensed, since its licenser demolished is located too far down in the

structure to raise into the matrix Agro. Although the characterization of partitive Case

as inherent has an independent motivation, as convincingly demonstrated by Bellletti

(1988) with Italian cases, it is not at all obvious whether such a characterization has any

good motivation in English. Under the standard small clause analysis of

there-constructions involving be, a sentence such as (39a) below has roughly the

Page 31: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

30

underlying structure given in (39b):

(39) a. There will be a man available.

b. e will be [SC a man available]

In this case, the licenser of partitive Case for a man is be, which does not have any

-relation with this NP, whereas its -licenser is available. Thus, this apparently

contradicts with the claim that partitive Case is inherent. To solve this problem,

Lasnik (1995) claims that be here acts as a light verb which has no -role of its own and

hence that this allows the predicate of the complement clause of be to raise covertly into

the latter verb. Given the present framework of the probe-goal system invented by

Chomsky (2008), however, such a covert head movement will not be warranted.

Furthermore, it is not at all clear under this proposal how to deal with such a

there-construction in which the predicate of the associate of there constitutes PP, as

illustrated in (1a), whose underlying structure will be the following:

(40) e will be [SC someone in the garden]

In this case, it is rather obvious that someone and in the garden enters a

subject-predicate relation, but it is not at all obvious whether this relation is something

that has to be captured as a -relation. This leads further into the question of what

raises covertly into be in this case. Thus, I take it that these problems give us a good

motivation to look for a new explanation for why the raising derivation is impossible for

(37b). Notice that as far as I can see, the radical External Merge-approach will not

have anything to contribute to answering this question.

Under the Move-approach, on the other hand, we can offer a fairly natural

Page 32: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

31

explanation of how to prevent the raising derivation for (37b). There are actually two

such derivations we need to consider, depending upon which occurrence of be is

involved in checking partitive Case. Let us first consider the one in which the lower

be enters into an Agree relation with a building with respect to - and partitive

Case-features. This derivation is excluded for basically the same reason as (11b),

repeated below:

(41) *There is likely someone to be in the garden.

Recall that this sentence is ruled out because after someone enters into an Agree relation

with the lower be and then is moved to the embedded Spec-VP, the PIC makes it

invisible from the next higher phase level, so that it ought not to undergo further

movement. Accordingly, if a building in (37b) enters an Agree relation with the lower

be, then it should not undergo movement across the v*-V phase level in which the Agee

relation is established, due to the PIC. The more interesting derivation to consider is

the one in which the upper be is involved in checking partitive Case. Thus, the crucial

stage of this derivation is the following:

(42) [v*’ v* [VP be [AP likely [TP [T’ to [vP [v’ v+be [VP demolished [DP there a

building]]]]]]]]]

At this stage, the upper verb be, which inherits -features from v*, probes for these

features and then finds a building as its goal (here there cannot be a goal, either because

otherwise a building could not obtain partitive Case or because be will not be able to

value the Case-feature of the expletive on the assumption that partitive Case is assigned

only to NP; see fn. 9). After an Agree relation is established between be and a

Page 33: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

32

building, the latter phrase must undergo Move to the matrix Spec-VP. On the other

hand, there also needs to undergo Move to the matrix Spec-v*P to be visible from the

next higher phase level at which it needs to obtain nominative Case. If these

applications of Move were successful, then the derivation would converge, contrary to

our expectation. There is a natural way, however, to exclude such applications of

Move. The key point is that each application of Move must take place in a

successive-cyclic fashion passing through the intermediate Spec-TP. Suppose,

following Chomsky (1993), that successive-cyclic A-movement is forced by the SM, as

assumed by the radical External Merge-approach. The application of Move to a

building into the matrix VP is obviously an instance of A-movement, and hence is

required to pass through the intermediate Spec-TP in accordance with the SM. The

other application of Move, i.e., moving there into the matrix v*P is a little bit tricky, but

since the final destination of there is the matrix Spec-TP, it is natural to regard such

movement as an instance of A-movement as well, and hence it also needs to pass

through the intermediate Spec-TP. Then, given that these two applications of Move

take place in parallel under the probe-goal system of Chomsky (2008), we can attribute

the illegitimacy of such applications to a restriction to the effect that the intermediate

Spec-TP cannot be used by more than one element at a time.19 In this way, we can

19 Notice that this does not exclude the possibility of having multiple Specs in the

projection of a phase head such as v* and C, which could be obtained when the phase

head probes more than once. Hence, if the claim in the text is correct, it will be

predicted that multiple Specs are allowed only for phase heads. Whether this is the

right prediction or not needs further research, however. I thank a reviewer for pointing

Page 34: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

33

correctly exclude the raising derivations as illegitimate for (37b) under the

Move-approach, which then counts as a good advantage over the radical

External-Merge approach.20

3. Empirical Problems

I have argued that the Move-approach to the there-construction proposed by Sato

(2008) is both conceptually and empirically superior to the External Merge-approach

under the probe-goal system of Chomsky (2008). However, this approach is also not

free from any problem. In this section, I point out a couple of empirical problems with

this approach and provide a solution to them in the next section.

Bo kovi (2002) provides a fair amount of evidence for his claim that expletives

do not move. What he regards as “probably the strongest piece of evidence” (p. 196)

is provided by the experiencer blocking effect in French. Whereas English allows a

raising construction with an experiencer phrase, as shown below:

(43) John seems to Mary to be smart.

French does not allow such a construction, as illustrated below (the examples in (44)

and (45) are taken from Bo kovi (2002)):

out the importance of this consequence. 20 It is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss other variants of the Move-approach to

expletive constructions and to compare them with the one adopted here. See Bowers

(2002), Nomura (2003) and Richards and Biberauer (2005) for the claim that expletives

are base-generated in Spec-vP or Spec-VP and are moved to the above Spec-TP.

Page 35: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

34

(44) a. *Deux soldats semblent au général manquer ( tre manquants) la

two soldiers seem to-the general to-miss to-be missing at the

caserne.

barracks

‘Two soldiers seem to the general to be missing from the barracks.’

b. * Deux soldats semblent au général tre arrivés en ville.

two soldiers seem to-the general to-be arrived in town

‘Two soldiers seem to the general to have arrived in town.’

However, the counterparts of these sentences that involve expletives in the matrix

subject position are acceptable, as illustrated below:

(45) a. Il semble au général y avoir deux soldats manquants la caserne.

there seems to-the general to-have two soldiers missing at the barracks

‘There seem to the general to be two soldiers missing from the barracks.’

b. Il semble au général tre arrivés deux soldats en ville.

there seems to-the general to-be arrived two soldiers in town

‘There seem to the general to have arrived two soldiers in town.’

Bo kovi takes the grammaticality of these sentences involving the expletive il,

contrary to the corresponding raising sentences given in (44), as indicating that the

expletive does not undergo Move but rather is directly inserted into the matrix TP.

This evades a violation of relativized minimality that is induced by the intervening

experiencer phrase in such raising cases as in (44). On the other hand, the paradigm

presented in (44) and (45) is a challenging problem to the version of the Move-approach

Page 36: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

35

to the there-construction proposed by Sato (2008), according to which the cases

involving the expletive il, as presented in (45), ought to be ungrammatical due to a

violation of relativized minimality induced by the movement of the expletive across the

experiencer phrase.

A second problem with this version of the Move-approach is concerned with a

peculiar paradigm of agreement that emerges in the English sentences corresponding to

those given in (44) and (45). As noted above with example (43), English allows a

raising construction with an experiencer phrase and this construction exhibits the

normal pattern of agreement between the matrix subject and verb, as shown below:

(46) a. A man seems to Mary to be in the room.

b. Some men seem to Mary to be in the room.

In contrast with this pattern, when the expletive there is involved in this construction, an

unexpected pattern manifests itself, as pointed out by Boeckx (2000); compare the

sentences in (47) with those in (48):

(47) a. There seems to Mary to be a man in the room.

b. There seems/?*seem to Mary to be men in the room. (Boeckx 2000)

(48) a. There seems to be a man in the room.

b. There seem to be men in the room.

When an experiencer phrase is omitted, as in (48), the main verb agrees in number with

the associate of there, as expected. On the other hand, when an experiencer phrase

exists, as in (47), such a normal agreement pattern collapses and the main verb exhibits

its singular form, irrespective of whether the associate of there is singular or plural.

Page 37: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

36

Under the Move-approach to the there-construction, the contrast in agreement pattern

between the raising cases, illustrated in (46), and those involving the expletive there,

illustrated in (47), is unexpected, since both cases involve raising of a nomimal element

out of the embedded infinitival clause across the experiencer phrase. This calls for an

explanation.

Before moving on to providing a solution to these problems in the next section, I

present here Goto’s (2008) work to address the question of why English and French are

different regarding the availability of the raising construction with an experiencer

phrase, as shown in (43) and (44). First of all, Goto follows Chomsky (1995),

Bo kovi (2002) and others in that such French cases as in (44) are a violation of

relativized minimality; more precisely a violation of the Minimal Link Condition

(henceforth, MLC) in Chomsky’s terms. Thus, in both cases of (44), the matrix T

cannot probe into an element inside the embedded infinitival clause, since the

experiencer phrase is the closest to the probe, and hence the embedded subject cannot

be moved up to the matrix Spec-TP. Goto then considers how such an English

counterpart as (43) can evade a violation of the MLC. I summarize Goto’s proposals

as follows:

(49) a. Following Chomsky (2000), the EPP is a selectional requirement rather than a

feature to be checked.

b. The EPP can be satisfied by Move before Agree takes place in English.

c. Following Abe (2002), Probe is subject to the MLC while Move is subject to

the SM.

Page 38: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

37

Abe (2002) proposes that so-called movement involves two steps, i.e., Probe (or Select

in his terms) and Move, and that each operation is subject to a minimality condition, as

indicated in (49c). Thus, to take (50) below for illustration,

(50) John seems to be smart.

let us consider the stage of its derivation just before John undergoes movement:

(51) [C’ C [T’ T [vP v [VP seem [T’ to be John smart]]]]]

At this stage, the matrix T probes for its -features and hits John without violating the

MLC. After an Agree relation is established, John undergoes Move, which is subject

to the SM. Since the latter condition demands that Move not skip a possible landing

site, John undergoes successive-cyclic movement, passing through the intermediate

Spec-TP, thereby the derivation reaching the following stage:21

(52) [C’ C [TP Johni T [vP v [VP seem [TP ti’ to be ti smart]]]]]

Goto’s core proposal is given in (49b), which is flatly opposed to Chomsky’s (2000)

assumption that Move must take place after an Agree relation is established. He then

assumes that such an application of Move is subject to the SM, along the lines of Abe

(2002)’s minimality conditions.

Let us now consider how this mechanism properly generates such a raising case

as (43); the first stage where relevant operations take place in this case is the matrix C-T

21 This account of how Abe’s (2002) system of movement works misses the full

definition of “possible landing site”, which needs to be worked out, partly because his

system is not fully compatible with the present probe-goal system, especially regarding

whether the notion of phase plays a crucial role. For the present purpose, I simply

assume that Spec-TP counts as a possible landing site for so-called A-movement.

Page 39: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

38

level, as shown below:

(53) [C’ C [T’ T [vP v [VP seem to Mary [T’ to be John smart]]]]]

At this stage, John can move up to the matrix Spec-TP before Agree takes place and this

movement can take place successive-cyclically by making John pass through the

embedded Spec-TP, hence satisfying the SM; crucially, crossing the experiencer phrase

does not cause a SM violation, since it is not a possible landing site for the movement in

question. The derivation then proceeds to the following stage:

(54) [C’ C [TP Johni T [vP v [VP seem to Mary [TP ti’ to be ti smart]]]]]

Goto claims that at this stage, John probes for its uninterpretable Case-feature and finds

T as a value assigner of this feature, and further that it values the -features of T in

return. This completes the derivation of (43).22

In order to accommodate the ungrammaticality of such a French counterpart as in

(44) under Goto’s mechanism, it will be necessary to assume that the option given in

(49b) is unavailable for such a case. Then the ungrammaticality of the sentences given

in (44) immediately follows exactly in the way explained above, since the unavailability

of this option makes Agree a prerequisite for Move. Though Goto tries to derive the

availability of the option (49b) from a language parametrization, it will be more

22 See Bo kovi ’s (2007) for a similar mechanism of the way feature checking is

implemented, though it remains to be seen whether his whole system is in fact

compatible with the present probe-goal system; especially, his theory aims to address

such issues as the look-ahead problem of computation, the elimination of the EPP, the

Activation Condition and the Inverse Case Filter, which I am unable to discuss in this

paper.

Page 40: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

39

desirable, as a reviewer points out, to attribute it to an independently motivated lexical

parametrization. Here I suggest one possible way of doing so in terms of Pesetsky and

Torrego’s (2007) feature characterization. They assume that formal features are

characterized with both interpretability and valuation. While in most cases, these two

notions coincide in such a way that being interpretable entails being valued and being

uninterpretable entails being unvalued, I propose that this correlation breaks up in the

characterization of Case-feature in the following way:23

(55) a. English D-N Case-feature: uninterpretable, unvalued

b. French D-N Case feature: uninterpretable, valued

I speculate that the difference between English and French nominals with respect to

Case valuation may be attributed to the morphological property of “rich declension”;

i.e., those nominals which show rich declension have valued Case-features whereas

those which are poor in declension have unvalued Case-features. Given this

characterization, the availability of (49b) follows from Pesetsky and Torrego’s (2007)

assumption given below, which I assume in what follows:

(56) Only unvalued features can act as probes.

The derivation of such an English raising case as (43) given above in (53) and (54) still

holds with the feature characterization given in (55a). Crucially, John is able to act as

a probe for its Case-feature after it moves up to the matrix Spec-TP, thanks to its

23 See Bo kovi (2008) for the claim that gender-feature is characterized as

uninterpretable and yet valued, though the conceptual motivation for such a

characterization is different from the one given in the text.

Page 41: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

40

unvalued status. In French cases such as given in (44), on the other hand, the option

(49b) is unavailable since if we followed this option, the DP moved up to the matrix

subject position would have to be able to act as a probe, but it would not, due to lack of

any unvalued features. The remaining option is to make the matrix T probe into the

infinitival clause to hit the subject DP as its goal, but this inevitably violates the MLC

due to the presence of the experiencer phrase.

Goto (2008) also provides an account for Boeckx’s (2000) agreement paradigm

given in (47) under his mechanism, but he crucially assumes the External

Merge-approach to the there-construction: Since there is externally merged into the

matrix Spec-TP in such cases as in (47), the availability of the option given in (49b) is

irrelevant here. Thus, the matrix T cannot probe into the embedded infinitival clause

due to the intervention effect caused by the experiencer phrase, hence manifesting a

default value with respect to its -features. The same explanation would hold for the

grammaticality of the French counterparts of expletive constructions exemplified in (45),

but crucially under the External Merge-approach. In the next section, I provide a

solution to Boeckx’s (2000) agreement paradigm given in (47) as well as the

grammaticality of the French expletive constructions given in (45) under the

Move-approach advocated by Sato (2008).

4. A Revision of Sato’s (2008) Mechanism

In order to solve the problems raised above against the Move-approach, I examine how

expletives are characterized in terms of formal features, revising Sato’s (2008) original

Page 42: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

41

assumptions. She treats the expletive there on a par with other DPs in carrying

full-fledged Case- and -features. I oppose this characterization, rather following

Chomsky (2000) in that expletives should be characterized differently.

Let us first suppose, following Chomsky, that expletives simply lack

Case-features. This may be supported by the fact that they do not exhibit any case

declension, as far as I know, which is most notable with such an expletive as English

there that has a locative form in its origin. As for the -features of expletives, I

propose the following, adopting Pesetsky and Torrego’s (2007) characterization of

formal features:

(57) a. The expletive there carries uninterpretable and unvalued -features.

b. The values of the -features may be supplied by its associate.

Given that expletives lack semantic content, it is most natural to assume that the

-features of expletives are uninterpretable. Recall Sato’s assumption that the

expletive there shares the values of its -features with its associate. Departing from

this assumption, I assume that the -feature sharing is optional, as indicated in (57b).

Given the internal structure of the expletive there and its associate, as shown in (15),

which is repeated below,

(58) DP

3

D NP

1 there[+ ][-Case] the associate[+ ][-Case(Part)]

Page 43: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

42

this means that the D-N agreement is optional here, so that the value of the -features of

there can be [+ ] or [- ].24

Concentrating first on the case where the -features of the expletive there are

valued by those of its associate, so that it carries uninterpretable valued -features, note

that this new characterization of the expletive there in terms of formal features

nonetheless keeps Sato’s analysis of the there-construction almost intact, since the

uninterpretability of the -features serves to the same end as the uninterpretability of the

Case-feature borne by there in her original analysis, especially to satisfy the Activation

Condition.25 To take (1a) again for illustration, (21), reproduced below, represents the

first stage where a phase head probes:

24 See Hornstein and Witkos (2003) for relevant discussions. 25 This new characterization of there will nonetheless yield some theoretical

consequences that cannot be fleshed out in detail in the present paper, especially,

relating the issue of whether it should carry Case. For one thing, it argues against the

existence of the Inverse Case Filter, since under the present system, there is able to

check the relevant features of T and V (in ECM cases) even though it lacks Case-feature.

A reviewer has brought to my attention such a case that demonstrates that the expletive

there is subject to so-called Case adjacency ((i) is taken from Hazout (2004)):

(i) *For unexpectedly there to be a unicorn in the garden is unlikely.

In light of the present system of expletives, the apparent adjacency requirement holding

between for and there in (i) cannot be attributed to a requirement on Case checking per

se. Rather, it might be attributed to a constraint on the Agree relation established

between the complementizer for and its goal. Though this idea may be extendable to

such a case where an Agree relation is established in the v*-V phase level, it is not clear

whether such an adjacency requirement equally holds for the C-T phase level in a

tensed clause. I must leave this issue for future research.

Page 44: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

43

(59) [v’ v* [V’ be [ P there someone] in the garden]]]

At this stage, be inherits -features from the phase head v* and probes for them. They

are uninterpretable unvalued features. For this probing, the associate someone needs

to be chosen as a goal, since be is able to provide partitive Case as a reflex of the

checking of -features; if there were chosen as a goal, then there would be no way for

the associate to obtain partitive Case, or be will not be able to value the Case-feature of

the expletive, to begin with, on the assumption that partitive Case is assigned only to NP.

After someone and there are raised into the Spec of V and of v*, respectively, the

derivation reaches the next phase level, represented in (23), reproduced below:

(60) [C’ C [T’ Pres [v*P therei [v*’ v*+be [VP someonej [V’ tbe [ P ti tj] in the garden]]]]]]

At this stage, T inherits uninterpretble unvaluded -features from the phase head C and

probes for them. In this case, there is the only candidate for a goal, since any element

inside VP is not accessible for this probing, according to the PIC. As there carries

valued -features, it supplies those values to T, thereby establishing an Agree relation

and bringing there into the Spec of T, as shown in (24), reproduced below:

(61) [CP [TP therei [T’ Pres [v*P t’i [v*’ v*+be [VP someonej [V’ tbe [ P ti tj] in the garden]]]]]]]

Since the expletive there shares the values of its -features with its associate, the fact

that the -features of there have valued those of T results in the required agreement

pattern in which T agrees with the associate of there.

There is one crucial respect in which the characterization of there as carrying

uninterpretable valued -features differs from Sato’s original characterization: while in

the latter, there carries an unvalued feature, that is, one with respect to Case, it does not

Page 45: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

44

carry any such feature in the former. This is of great significance, given Pesetsky and

Torrego’s (2007) assumption regarding the eligibility of probing, given in (56),

reproduced below:

(62) Only unvalued features can act as probes.

Recall that under Goto’s (2008) approach, English raising cases have access to the

option given in (49b) but that once this option is chosen, the moved element must act as

a probe to check its unvalued/uninterpretable feature, as illustrated with the derivation

of (43) in (53)-(54). Thus, given (62), it follows that the expletive there, when it has

its -features valued by its associate, has no access to the option given in (49b), contrary

to normal DPs, since it does not have any unvalued feature, hence not acting as a probe.

This in turn leads us to consider how such there-constructions as in (47), repeated below,

are derived.

(63) a. There seems to Mary to be a man in the room.

b. There seems/?*seem to Mary to be men in the room.

Notice that unless we rely on the option given in (49b), as we did in deriving such

corresponding raising cases as given in (46), there is no way to derive these sentences

properly under the present assumptions. Notice also that the main verb seem in (63)

takes a third person singular form, arguably a default one, no matter whether the

associate of there is singular or plural. Thus, the correct derivations of (63a, b) should

capture this agreement pattern as well.

Schütze (1999) observes many cases of the there-construction in which T fails to

agree with a plural associate DP and instead manifests a singular form; some relevant

Page 46: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

45

examples are given below:

(64) There is/’s/are lots of cookies on the table.

(65) a. There appear/?appears to be cookies on the table.

b. There tend/?tends to be cookies on the table when Johnnie comes home.

For such cases, Schütze adopts the view that “I [=T] cannot enter any agreement

relationship at all in the presence of such subjects [as there] and therefore shows up as a

default form.” (p. 477) Following this idea, I propose that the default agreement

manifested in (64) and (65) is induced when the -features of there are not valued; to

put it in other words, I put forth the following:

(66) Default agreement occurs if two occurrences of unvalued -features establish an

Agree relation.

To illustrate how this works, let us consider the following schematic configuration:

(67) … T … … [ there associate] …

unvalued/uninterpretable unvalued/uninterpretable

Here T probes for the uninterpretable/unvalued -features that are inherited from the

above C and finds there as its goal, which also has uninterpretable/unvalued -features.

I am assuming that feature matching as a result of probing deprives the feature(s)

involved of the label [uninterpretable], so as not to violate Full Interpretation at the

interface, and that the two occurrences of unvalued -features remain unchanged after

an Agree relation is established between them. And thanks to this establishment, there

is raised into the Spec-TP. Finally, I assume that a last resort strategy of the following

sort for unvalued -features works just before the Transfer operation applies:

Page 47: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

46

(68) Unvalued -features may be supplied with default values that are specified in a

given language.

Since English has a third person singular form as default, the two occurrences of the

unvalued -features in T and there bear this form. This is what happens when T fails

to agree with a plural associate DP and instead manifests a singular form in some

instances of the there-construction.

Given the option (49b), we have another way of deriving those

there-constructions that involve default agreement. Suppose that in (67), the expletive

there undergoes Move before an Agree relation is established, as shown below:

(69) therei T … … [ ti associate] …

unvalued/uninterpretable unvalued/uninterpretable

Since there carries unvalued -features, it is able to function as a probe for these

features, and then finds T as its goal, establishing an Agree relation. Since this

matching of -features involves unvalued ones, this gives rise to default agreement,

according to (66). Given this option of derivation, we can not only provide proper

derivations to such sentences as in (63), repeated below, but also explain why they

exhibit default agreement.

(70) a. There seems to Mary to be a man in the room.

b. There seems/?*seem to Mary to be men in the room.

In order to derive these sentences properly, we need to rely on the option given in (49b),

since otherwise the matrix T could not probe into the embedded infinitival clause due to

the intervention effect caused by the experiencer phrase. Furthermore, the expletive

Page 48: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

47

there cannot share the values of -features with its associate in these cases, since if it

did, then it would not be able to act as a probe after it is raised into the matrix Spec-TP,

due to lack of unvalued features. Hence, the only way to rely on the option (49b) is to

keep the -features of there unvalued, so that it can properly act as a probe after it is

raised into the matrix Spec-TP. In this way, there establishes an Agree relation with

the matrix T in terms of unvalued -features, which are then supplied with default

values; hence the matrix verb takes the third person singular form, i.e., seems.

Much the same explanation holds for the cases of the French il-construction that

involve raising verbs, as illustrated in (45a, b), reproduced below, which are

grammatical, unlike the corresponding raising cases illustrated in (44):

(71) a. Il semble au général y avoir deux soldats manquants la caserne.

‘There seem to the general to be two soldiers missing from the barracks.’

b. Il semble au général tre arrivés deux soldats en ville.

‘There seem to the general to have arrived two soldiers in town.’

The French expletive il is more like the English expletive it rather than there in that it

always induces a third person singular form on the finite verb with which it enters into a

subject-predicate relation, even if its associate is plural, as illustrated below:

(72) a. Il a été mangé des pommes.

‘It has been eaten apples.’

b. Il est venu quelques hommes.

‘It has come some men.’ (Hoekstra and Mulder 1990, p. 47)

Given the present way of characterizing expletives in terms of formal features, it is most

Page 49: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

48

natural to hypothesize that the expletives il and it are minimally different from the

expletive there in that their -features are not valued by their associates.26 Thus, we

can classify expletives into at least two kinds in terms of the availability of this

valuation, as summarized below:

(73) a. Expletives carry uninterpretable and unvalued -features.

b. The values of the -features may or may not be supplied by their associates,

depending upon the inherent nature of the expletives.

According to this characterization, the expletives il and it differ from their pronominal

counterparts in that while the latter take the third person singular forms as a reflex of

their internal valued -features, the former happen to take the same form due to the

default agreement strategy stated in (68).27

With this much in background, the grammaticality of the French impersonal

constructions given in (71) immediately follows, given the above characterization of the

26 See the discussion around (35) for the expletive it and its that-clause associate. 27 Bo kovi (2002, 2007) observes that quasi-argument expletives show a blocking

effect caused by the experiencer phrase, as shown below:

(i)?*Il semble au général avoir plu.

there seems to-the general to-have rained

‘It seems to the general to have rained.’

He attributes the ungrammaticality of this sentence, contrary to such cases as in (71), to

the fact that “il is actually -marked by plu in (i).” Under the present theory of

expletives, this may be taken as indicating that the quasi-argument il has an

uninterpretable, valued Case-feature as well as interpretable, valued -features, just like

ordinary DPs in French.

Page 50: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

49

expletive il. In each case, il first undergoes Move to raise into the matrix Spec-TP.

Notice that this option is available to il, unlike other normal DPs in French, since it

carries unvalued -features. Then, it probes for its unvalued -features and finds the

matrix T as its goal. This feature matching makes the -features borne by the matrix T

and il both get rid of the label [uninterpretable] and establishes an Agree relation

between them. Since both elements have unvalued -features, the establishment of an

Agree relation between them makes these features obtain default values due to the

strategy stated in (68), thereby leading the derivation to converge.

The English expletive it shows the same property as the French il in relevant

respects. Consider (74a) below, whose rough underlying structure is given in (74b).

(74) a. It seems to Mary that John is honest.

b. e T seem to Mary [it [that John is honest]]

In (74b), the expletive it first moves to the matrix Spec-TP and then probes for its

unvalued -features and finds the matrix T as its goal. After these two elements have

established an Agree relation, the unvalued -features of the two elements are supplied

with default values. This completes the derivation with the correct outcome.

Finally, let us consider the case where the v*-V phase level probes and finds an

expletive as a goal to see whether any interesting result is obtained. Such a case is

instantiated in the ECM construction, as exemplified below:

(75) We proved there to be a thief among us.

Under the present assumptions, (75) has the following stage of derivation, at which the

matrix v*-V is to probe for -features:

Page 51: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

50

(76) [v*’ v* [V’ prove [T’ to [v*P therei [v*’ v*+be [VP a thiefj [V’ tbe [ ti tj] among us]]]]]]]

At this stage, the verb prove finds there as its goal and checks its

uninterpretable/unvalued -features against those of the expletive, whether the latter are

valued or not, establishing an Agree relation, and then there is raised into the

Spec-VP.28 After prove is raised into the above v*, we can derive the correct word

order.

With this much bearing in mind, let us consider cases of the ECM construction

that appear to induce intervention effects due to the presence of PP phrases between the

matrix verbs and the following infinitival clauses (the examples are cited from Takano

(1998)):

(77) a. *We proved to the authorities Smith to be the thief.

b. We proved Smith to the authorities to be the thief.

(78) a. *We proved to the authorities there to be a thief among us.

b. *We proved there to the authorities to be a thief among us.

The ungrammaticality of (77a) and (78a) will be immediately accounted for under the

present probe-goal system, according to which Smith and there must be raised into the

matrix Spec-VP, thereby resulting in preceding any phrase inside the VP; hence they

necessarily precede the PP to the authorities, as in (77b) and (78b). The

28 This implies that so-called “object raising” is obligatory in the ECM construction.

This is, however, incompatible with what Lasnik (1999) observes with a variety of

syntactic tests, which all lead to the conclusion that “object raising” is optional. See

Bo kovi (2002) for a reinterpretation of Lasnik’ relevant data in light of the obligatory

object shift analysis.

Page 52: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

51

grammaticality of (77b) is also immediately explained under the present assumptions,

exactly like such a raising case as (43) that involves an experiencer phrase. Given the

option stated in (49b), which states that Move can apply before Agree takes place in

English, Smith in (77b) can raise into the matrix Spec-VP without inducing an

intervention effect, since the relevant operation of Move is subject only to the SM. It

then probes for its uninterpretable/unvalued Case-feature and finds the matrix V as its

goal, obtaining the accusative value from the latter as well as checking its

uninterpretable/unvalued -features as a reflex. In this way, the derivation of (77b) is

led to converge.

The most interesting case is (78b). Adopting the External-Merge approach to

the there-construction, Takano (1998) accounts for the ungrammaticality of this

sentence as a violation of the MLC, since the matrix V cannot probe into the infinitival

clause to hit there as its goal due to the presence of the PP phrase. This account,

however, faces a problem with respect to the grammaticality of the sentences given in

(70), reproduced below:

(79) a. There seems to Mary to be a man in the room.

b. There seems/?*seem to Mary to be men in the room.

Takano would predict that these sentences were ungrammatical exactly for the same

reason as (78b) is, since the matrix T could not probe into the infinitival clause without

inducing a violation of the MLC. Under the present probe-goal system, on the other

hand, there is a natural way to exclude such a sentence as (78b). Recall that such cases

as in (79) are derived when there keeps its -features unvalued, so that it may act as a

Page 53: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

52

probe for these feature after it moves up to the matrix Spec-TP. Since the Agree

relation established between there and the matrix T involves only unvalued -features, it

induces default agreement. Suppose that the default value assignment stated in (68),

reproduced below, is not applicable to Vs but only to Ts and expletives.29

(80) Unvalued -features may be supplied with default values that are specified in a

given language.

Then the ungrammaticality of (78b) immediately follows, since the unavailability of this

default agreement forces the derivation of this sentence to take the option of the

-features of there being valued against those of its associate, which in turn makes the

option given in (49b) unavailable due to the condition on the eligibility of probe, stated

in (62). The only remaining way is to make the matrix V probe for its -features

before there is raised into the matrix Spec-TP and yet the presence of the PP phrase

prevents it from penetrating into the infinitival clause to hit there as its goal; hence the

ungrammaticality of (78b).

5. Conclusion

In this paper, I have defended the Move-approach to expletive constructions, based

upon the work by Sato (2008). Couched under the probe-goal system proposed by

29 A reviewer raises the very interesting question of whether the availability of default

agreement has anything to do with overt agreement, suggesting that there might be such

a correlation. This leads to the interesting prediction that default agreement should

occur in Vs in overt object agreement languages. I have not yet done enough research

to determine whether it is in fact borne out.

Page 54: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

53

Chomsky (2008), this approach has been shown to be superior both conceptually and

empirically to any known theory of the External Merge-approach to these constructions.

Conceptually, this approach makes the probe-goal system much simpler basically

because it treats expletives on a par with other normal DPs in the way they are involved

in checking relevant features, including satisfaction of the EPP. Empirically, it has

been demonstrated that this approach provides natural accounts for the core data

involving there and it-constructions in collaboration with the crucial ingredients of

Chomsky’s probe-goal system; especially, the PIC and the parallel operations operative

at one phase level.

Furthermore, I have attempted a refinement of Sato’s analysis of the

there-construction by proposing that expletives are characterized differently from other

ordinary DPs in terms of formal features: they carry uninterpretable and unvalued

-features. This enables us to solve some apparent problems with Sato’s original

theory. In particular, I have proposed that when the -features of there are kept

unvalued, it can establish an Agree relation with T after it moves up to its Spec position,

and that matching unvalued -features with other unvalued ones induces default

agreement. This takes care of the fact that those expletive constructions that involve

raising predicates do not induce intervention effects despite the presence of experiencer

phrases only when the matrix verbs manifest default agreement. Further, by making

the natural assumption that default agreement is possible only with T but not with V, I

have provided a plausible account to the ungrammaticality of such a case of the

there-construction that involves a PP phrase intervening between the matrix ECM verb

Page 55: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

54

and the associate of there in the infinitival clause.

Though I believe that this paper has provided enough evidence for the

Move-approach to expletive constructions, there still are several important points left

open; in particular, we need a more thorough examination on the internal structure of

the expletive-associate complex. Further, it will be necessary to compare the present

theory with another variety of the Move-approach according to which expletives are

base-generated separately from their associates. I hope that the present work

constitutes a good basis upon which these further issues can be properly dealt with.

References

ABE, J. 1997. What triggers successive-cyclic movement. In ‘Is the logic clear?’:

Papers in honor of Howard Lasnik, University of Connecticut Working Papers in

Linguistics 8, ed. J.S. Kim, S. Oku & S. Stjepanovi , 1-20. Cambridge, MA: MIT

Working Papers in Linguistics.

ABE, J. 2002. On the displacement property of language and minimality. Ms., Tohoku

Gakuin University, Sendai.

BELLETTI, A. 1988. Unaccusatives as Case assigners. Linguistic Inquiry 19: 1-34.

BOECKX, C. 2000. Quirky agreement. Studia Linguistica 54: 354-380.

BO KOVI , . 1995. Case properties of clauses and the Greed principle. Studia

Linguistica 49: 32-53.

BO KOVI , . 1997. The syntax of nonfinite complementation: An economy

approach. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Page 56: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

55

BO KOVI , . 2002. A-movement and the EPP. Syntax 5: 167-218.

BO KOVI , . 2007. On the locality and motivation of Move and Agree: An even

more minimal theory. Linguistic Inquiry 38: 589-644.

BO KOVI , . 2008. Unifying first and last conjunct agreement. Ms., University of

Connecticut, Storrs.

BOWERS, J. 2002. Transitivity. Linguistic Inquiry 33: 183-224.

CHOMSKY, N. 1981. Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris.

CHOMSKY, N. 1986. Knowledge of language: Its nature, origin, and use. New York:

Praeger.

CHOMSKY, N. 1993. A minimalist program for linguistic theory. In The view from

Building 20: Essays in linguistics in honor of Sylvain Bromberger, ed. K. Hale &

S.J. Keyser, 1-52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

CHOMSKY, N. 1995. Categories and transformations. In The Minimalist Program, N.

Chomsky, 219-394. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

CHOMSKY, N. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In Step by step: Essays on

minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik, ed. R. Martin, D. Michaels & J.

Uriagereka, 89-155. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

CHOMSKY, N. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. M.

Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

CHOMSKY, N. 2004. Beyond explanatory adequacy. In Structure and beyond: The

cartography of syntactic structures, Vol.3, ed. A. Belletti, 104-131. Oxford: Oxford

University Press.

Page 57: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

56

CHOMSKY, N. 2008. On phases. In Foundational issues in linguistic theory:

Essays in honor of Jean-Roger Vergnaud, ed. R. Freiden, C. Otero & M.L.

Zubizarreta, 133-166. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

CHOMSKY, N. & H. LASNIK. 1993. The theory of principles and parameters. In

Syntax: An International Handbook of Contemporary Research, ed. J. Jacobs, A.

von Stechow, W. Sternefeld, & T. Vennemann. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

EPSTEIN, S.D. & T.D. SEELY1999. Spec(ifying) the GF subject. Ms., University of

Michigan, Ann Arbor, & Eastern Michigan University, Ypsilanti.

EPSTEIN, S.D. & T.D. SEELY2006. Derivations in minimalism: Exploring the

elimination of A-chains and the EPP. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

GOTO, N. 2008. Interplay between Agree and Move. Ms., Tohoku Gakuin University,

Sendai.

GROAT, E.M. 1999. Raising the case of expletives. In Working minimalism, ed. S.D.

Epstein & N. Hornstein, 27-43. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

HAZOUT, I. 2004. The syntax of existential constructions. Linguistic Inquiry 35:

393-430.

HOEKSTRA, T. & R. MULDER. 1990. Unergatives as copular verbs: Locational and

existential predication. The Linguistic Review 7: 1-79.

HORNSTEIN, N. & J. WITKOS. 2003. Yet another approach to existential

constructions. In Grammar in focus: Festschrift for Christer Platzack, ed. L.O.

Delsing, C. Falk, G. Josefsson & H. Sigur sson. Lund University, Department of

Scandinavian.

Page 58: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

57

LASNIK, H. 1992. Case and expletives: Notes toward a parametric account. Linguistic

Inquiry 23: 381-405.

LASNIK, H. 1995. Case and expletives revisited: On Greed and other human failings.

Linguistic Inquiry 26: 615-633.

LASNIK, H. 1995. Chains of arguments. In Working minimalism, ed. S.D. Epstein &

N. Hornstein, 189-215. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

MCCLOSKEY, J. 1991. There, it and agreement. Linguistic Inquiry 22: 563-567.

MORO, A. 1997. The raising of predicates: Predicative noun phrases and the theory of

clause structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

NOMURA, M. 2004. Expletives Move! In Proceedings of the 32nd western conference

on linguistics Vol. 15, ed. B. Agbayani, V. Samiian & B.V. Tucker, 207-220.

Fresno, CA: California State University, Department of Linguistics.

PESETSKY, D. & E. TORREGO. 2007. The syntax of valuation and the interpretability

of features. In Phrasal and clausal architecture: Syntactic derivation and

interpretation, ed. S. Karimi, V. Samiian & W. Wilkins, 262-294. Amsterdam: John

Benjamins.

POSTAL, P.M. & G.K. PULLUM. 1988. Expletive noun phrases in subcategorized

positions. Linguistic Inquiry 19: 1988.

RICHARDS, M. & T. BIBERAUER. 2005. Explaining expl. In The function of

function words and functional categories, ed. M. den Dikken & C. Tortora,

115-153. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

SABEL, J. 2000. Expletives as features. In Proceedings of the 19th west coast

Page 59: Tohoku Gakuin University January 2009sacl/Expletives.pdf · These are basic issues of expletive constructions that . 3 ... The relevant stage of derivation of this sentence . 6 is

58

conference on formal linguistics, ed. R. Billerey & B.D. Lillehaugen, 411-424.

Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.

SATO, M. 2008. Where is there?: An approach to the expletive construction, Master’s

Thesis, Tohoku Gakuin University, Sendai.

SCH TZE, C.T. 1999. English expletive constructions are not infected. Linguistic

Inquiry 30: 467-484.

TAKANO, Y. 1998. Object shift and scrambling. Natural Language and Linguistic

Theory 16: 817-889.

WILLIAMS, E. 1994. Thematic structure in syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.