TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    1/21

    Swift's Knaves and Fools in the Tradition: Rhetoric versus Poetic in "A Tale of a Tub," SectionIXAuthor(s): John R. ClarkReviewed work(s):Source: Studies in Philology, Vol. 66, No. 5 (Oct., 1969), pp. 777-796Published by: University of North Carolina PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4173655.

    Accessed: 03/11/2011 10:26

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    University of North Carolina Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    Studies in Philology.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=uncpresshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4173655?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4173655?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=uncpress
  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    2/21

    Swift's

    Knaves and Fools in the

    Tradition:

    RhetoricVersus Poetic

    in A Tale

    of

    a Tub,

    Section

    IX

    By

    JoHN

    R. CLARR

    N essence,

    recent

    criticism

    of Swift's

    Tale of

    a

    Tub, promising

    and

    eventful

    as it

    has been, has

    too much

    emphasized ts author's

    1" tactics

    "

    and his

    "

    rhetoric."

    One would

    hardly wish to deny

    the presence

    of

    rhetoric

    n

    the workof

    art;

    for all men-artists among

    them-employ

    rhetoric

    upon

    every

    occasion:

    "all

    men make use,

    more or less, of [rhetoricand dialectic]; for to a certain extent all

    men

    attempt

    to discuss

    statements and to maintain

    them,

    to defend

    themselves

    and

    to

    attack others."

    Nonetheless,

    the

    work

    of

    art

    and

    the

    rhetorical

    tract differ

    considerably;

    where

    the

    rhetorician

    seeks

    to

    persuade

    an

    audience, concerning

    what it

    should

    think

    or how

    it

    should

    act,

    the

    artist "

    nothing

    affirmeth

    ";

    he is

    concemed with

    imitation, with

    the

    creation of

    a

    complete poetic whole,

    "

    a

    perfect

    pattern."

    This

    means,

    in

    effect,

    that rhetoric is

    a

    "useful,"

    while

    poetics

    is a "

    fine,"

    art.

    1

    See esp. John

    M.

    Bullitt, Jonathan

    Swift

    and

    the

    Anatomy of Satire (Cain

    bridge, Mass., 1953);

    Martin

    Price,

    Swift's

    Rhetorical

    Art

    (New Haven, 1953);

    William

    B.

    Ewald,

    Jr.,

    The

    Masks

    of

    Jonathan Swift (Oxford, 1954); Harold

    D.

    Kelling,

    "Reason

    in

    Madness:

    A Tale

    of

    a

    Tub," PMLA,

    LXIX

    (1954),

    I98-222;

    Ronald Paulson,

    Theme

    and Structure

    in

    Swift's

    Tale

    of

    a

    Tub

    (New Haven,

    I960);

    Charles

    Allen

    Beaumont, Swift's

    Classical

    Rhetoric

    (Athens, Ga.,

    I96I);

    Edward

    W.

    Rosenheim,

    Jr., Swift

    and the Satirist'sArt

    (Chicago,

    I963); and Jack

    G.

    Gilbert, Jonathan

    Swift:

    Romantic

    and

    Cynic

    Moralist

    (Austin,

    Texas, I966).

    'Aristotle,

    Rhetoric

    I.

    i.

    i,

    in

    Rhetoric.

    Poetics,

    trans. W.

    Rhys Roberts (New

    York, 1954),

    p. 19.

    'Sir Philip Sidney,

    The

    Defense of

    Poesy,

    ed. Albert

    S. Cook

    (New York,

    1890),

    pP- 35,

    19.

    777

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    3/21

    778 Swift'sKnavesand Fools in the Tradition

    Useful art,

    employing

    nature's own machinery,

    aids her in her effort to

    realize the

    ideal

    in the

    world

    aroundus, so far as

    man's

    practicalneeds are served

    by furthering

    this

    purpose. Fine art sets

    practical

    needs aside; it does

    not seek to affect

    the

    real

    world,

    to

    modify

    the

    actual. By

    mere imageryit reveals

    the

    ideal

    form

    at

    which

    nature

    aims

    in

    the highest sphere

    of organic existence,-in the

    region, namely,

    of

    human life.4

    Rhetoric is

    discursive;

    poetry,

    presentational.5For rhetoric s a

    means

    to creating

    "

    action

    "

    in the

    real world;

    whereas poetry is an

    end

    in

    itself, the creation of a complete and imitative "action"-not in the

    real

    world,

    but in the world of

    art.

    Thus,

    "rhetorical

    "

    explorations

    of

    the Tale of

    a

    Tub

    leave

    some-

    thing to be

    desired;

    and perhaps there

    is no better

    exemplar

    of the

    rhetorical

    critic'spractice than

    studies of that

    most rich

    and climactic

    portion of the Tale

    of

    a

    Tub,

    Section

    IX, the

    "

    Digression

    on Mad-

    ness."

    Since

    the critic

    of rhetoric

    believes that

    the satirist's

    primary

    concern

    is the

    persuasion,reassurance,or

    sustenance of his

    audience,

    he

    is

    too apt

    to

    conceive of the

    satirist'sbusiness

    as

    the

    manufacture

    and distributionof virtuous doctrine. Numbers of rhetoricalcritics

    have

    come

    to

    expect

    the

    satirist

    not

    only

    to

    censure

    folly and

    vice,

    but

    positively

    to inculcate virtue as

    well.

    With

    Middleton

    Murrv,

    they

    hold that

    "

    True satire

    implies

    the

    condemnaton

    of a

    society

    by

    reference to an ideal,"

    such

    an ideal

    normallyassumingthe

    form of

    social

    aspirations

    and codes-most

    often termed

    "reasonable stand-

    ards

    "

    or satiric "norms."

    Apparently

    such

    critics

    expect the refer-

    ence

    to such

    standards o

    be

    open, direct,

    intoned

    rhetorically n

    the

    identifiablefirst-person

    oice of

    the

    satirist

    himself; they assume

    that

    the "norms" or "positive standards" shall at the least stick out

    4 S.

    H.

    Butcher, Aristotle's

    Theory

    of

    Poetry

    and

    Fine

    Art, intro.

    John

    Gassner,

    4th ed.

    (New York,

    195

    ),

    p.

    I57.

    'These terms and a valuable discussion of

    them

    may

    be

    found in

    Susanne

    Langer,

    Philosophy

    n

    a

    New

    Key (New

    York, 1948),

    Chap.

    IV.

    6

    J.

    Middleton

    Murry,

    The

    Problem

    of

    Style

    (London, I960),

    p.

    59.

    'That satire

    appeals

    to some

    affirmative

    "norm"

    is an

    idea

    generally

    accepted.

    See, for

    instance, "A Discourse

    conceming the

    Original and

    Progress

    of

    Satire,"

    Essays

    of John

    Dryden,

    ed.

    W.

    P.

    Ker,

    2

    Vols.

    (New

    York,

    I96I),

    II, 104;

    Louis I.

    Bredvold,

    "A

    Note

    in

    Defence of

    Satire,"

    ELH,

    VII

    (1940),

    253-64;

    Leland

    Douglas

    Peterson,

    "The

    Satiric

    Norm

    of

    Jonathan Swift"

    (unpublished

    Ph. D. Diss., University of Minnesota,

    I962).

    Only most recently have critics

    begun

    to

    question the

    concept of satiric

    norms; see A.

    M.

    Tibbetts et

    al.,

    "Norms,

    Moral or

    Other,

    in

    Satire: A

    Symposium,"

    Satire

    Newsletter,

    II

    (Fall I964),

    2-25.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    4/21

    John R. Clark 779

    'round

    the edges

    of the

    satire, shall

    be something

    hard,

    chunky,

    and

    obvious,

    like a turkey-bone

    n the throat.

    Searching

    the

    Tale of a

    Tub

    for such standards

    has

    proved to

    be,

    for

    many a critic,

    a traumatic

    experience,

    for such

    standards

    are

    intransigently

    absent.

    It is just

    this

    elusiveness

    of standards

    n

    the

    Tale

    that has led

    critics frequently

    of late to

    accuse Swift

    of

    "

    betray-

    ing" or "trapping" his

    audience.8

    These claim

    that, rhetorically,

    Swift

    leads his audience to

    accept

    some clearcut

    prose statement

    of

    affirmatives,only

    to

    disappoint

    and shock

    his audience

    by shifting

    ground,

    and

    attacking

    even those

    positives

    he had

    appeared

    o sustain.

    As

    an

    instance

    of such critical findings,

    we might

    consider

    F. R.

    Leavis, who

    in his

    essay,

    "

    The

    Irony

    of Swift,"

    engages

    to compre-

    hend two

    lengthy

    and crucial paragraphs

    rom the

    Tale's Section

    IX.

    Leavis

    concludes

    that

    Swift

    in

    this

    passage

    deliberately

    betrays

    his

    readers,

    first

    coercing

    them to

    choose

    sides between Surface

    (Cre-

    dulity,

    delusion, happiness)

    and

    Depth (Curiosity,

    reason,

    virtuoso

    experimentation);

    for

    the most

    part

    leading

    readers

    to

    deplore

    Deptlh

    or

    Curiosity

    and to favor Surface

    or

    Credulity.

    Then,

    in

    a

    startling

    climax,

    Swift

    suddenly

    and

    willfully

    reverseshimself,

    admitting

    that

    those seeking

    after

    Depth

    are "knaves,"

    but now

    equally

    subverting

    admirers

    of

    Surface,resigning

    them

    to the

    category

    of " fools."

    Fools

    or

    Knaves:

    these

    are the choices.

    Which

    one is

    right?

    Leavis

    in-

    quires;

    and

    concludes

    that,

    for

    Swift,

    neither

    position

    is,

    and that

    therefore

    Swift's attitude

    is

    wholly

    "

    negative."

    9

    A considerable

    num-

    ber

    of critics

    have

    agreed

    with

    this

    reasoning,

    some

    of them

    going

    so

    far as

    to

    urge

    that Swift

    is actually

    the helpless

    neurotic, attracted

    by

    Credulity

    as well

    as

    by

    Curiosity,

    and evisceratedupon

    the horns

    of

    his dilemma.-l

    'Consult

    Milton

    Voigt,

    Swift

    and the

    Twentieth

    Century (Detroit,

    I964),

    p.

    150;

    the

    idea

    is developed

    at

    length

    by

    Henry

    W.

    Sams,

    " Swift's

    Satire

    of the Second

    Person,"

    ELH,

    XXVI

    (1959),

    36-44.

    9 F.

    R. Leavis,

    "The Irony

    of

    Swift,"

    Scrutiny,

    II

    (March

    I934), 374, 375.

    "

    Basil

    Wiley,

    The

    Eighteenth

    Century

    Background

    (Boston,

    I96I),

    p.

    Io6;

    M.

    C. Bradbrook

    nd

    M. G. Lloyd

    Thomas,

    Andrew

    Marvell (Cambridge,

    I940),

    pp. 114-7;

    J.

    C.

    Maxwell,

    "Demigods

    and

    Pickpockets:

    The Augustan

    Myth

    in

    Swift and Rousseau,"Scrutiny,XI

    (I942),

    34-9;

    D. S. Savage, "Swift," Western

    Review,

    XV

    (Autumn

    1950),

    25-36;

    John

    Lawlor,

    "Radical

    Satire

    and

    the Real-

    istic

    Novel,"

    Essays

    and

    Studies 1955,

    ed.

    D.

    M. Low (London,

    1955),

    pp. 58-

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    5/21

    780 Swift'sKnavesand Fools in the Tradition

    Yet there

    is no invincible

    necessity

    hat

    requiresus

    to discern

    n

    Section

    IX

    the

    thought-tormented

    oice of Swift,

    or the

    spectacle

    of the

    greatest

    satirist

    of the

    eighteenth

    century

    striving

    to instill

    doctrine

    but

    producing,

    nstead,

    a prostrate

    nd melancholy

    egativ-

    ism.

    The purpose

    of the

    present

    tudy

    is to examine

    he Tale of

    a

    Tub'sSection

    X

    aesthetically,

    reating

    he

    Tale

    centripetally

    s

    single

    and

    complete

    work

    of mimetic

    art.

    With

    Aristotle,

    we shall

    assume

    that the artist tandsapart romhis creation,hat the shapingof his

    fictional

    lotsubordinates

    o

    itselfthe

    operations

    f

    character,

    hought,

    diction,

    and the other

    elements

    of literary

    creation. And

    like

    Aristotle,

    we

    shall

    expect

    in fact

    that

    thought,

    diction, personae

    can only

    be

    comprehended

    n

    context,

    anonly be

    comprehended

    n terms

    of that

    plot

    or action

    which

    they serve

    to frame.

    In

    Section

    VIII,

    we will

    recall,

    he

    ostensible

    Modem

    persona

    ad

    deduced

    "

    system

    " of the

    sect of

    Modern

    Aeolists,

    ndhe

    concluded

    by assertinghat he had alwayscherished or this sect "a peculiar

    Honour."

    1 Section

    IX

    smoothly

    continues in this

    vein: the

    Modern

    urges

    hat

    such

    "

    honour

    "

    should

    not

    be

    palliated

    imply

    because

    he

    sect's

    ounder, ack,

    happened

    o be

    insane.

    Thus

    it

    is

    that Section

    IX

    proceeds

    quite

    simply

    as a

    defense of,

    a

    praiseof,

    Madness:

    delivered

    n the manner f the

    epideictic

    peech-

    that

    "

    ceremonial

    ratory

    f

    display,"

    s

    Aristotleerms it."2For,

    al-

    75;

    A.

    E.

    Dyson,

    " Swift:

    The

    Metamorphosis

    f

    Irony,"

    Essays

    and

    Studies

    z958,

    ed.

    Basil

    Willey

    (London,

    I959),

    pp. 53-67;

    David

    P.

    French,

    "Swift, Temple,

    and

    'A Digressionon Madness,'"TSLL, V (Spring

    I963),

    esp.

    49-5I;

    CurtisC. Smith,

    "Metaphor

    Structure

    n

    Swift's

    Tale

    of

    a

    Tub,"

    Thoth,

    V

    (Winter

    1964),

    esp.

    26.

    Oswald

    Johnson,

    "

    Swift

    and

    the

    Common

    Reader,"

    In

    Defense

    of Reading,

    ed.

    Reuben

    A.

    Brower

    and Richard

    Poirier

    (New

    York,

    I962),

    pp. 174-9I,

    extends

    the

    argument

    conceming

    Swift's

    "negativism

    "

    to nearly everything

    Swift

    wrote.

    Even

    the late

    Herbert

    Davis acknowledged

    Swift

    to

    be

    "

    a

    person

    of

    a

    hard-mouthed

    imagination,

    easily

    disposed

    to run

    away

    with him

    " in

    his satires

    (Stella,

    A

    Gentle-

    woman

    of the

    Eighteenth

    Century [New

    York,

    I942],

    p. 27;

    cf. p.

    38).

    11

    Jonathan

    Swift,

    A

    Tale

    of

    a

    Tub To

    which is

    added The Battle

    of

    the Books

    and

    the

    Mechanical

    Operation

    of

    the Spirit,

    edd.

    A. C.

    Guthkelch

    and

    D.

    Nichol

    Smith,

    znd

    ed. (Oxford,

    1958),

    p.

    I6i.

    Hereafter,

    all

    quotations

    from

    and

    refer-

    ences

    to

    specific

    passages

    in the

    Tale

    shall

    refer

    to

    this

    edition,

    page

    numbers

    being,

    included within parentheses, in the body of this paper.

    la Rhetoric

    I.

    3.

    I3

    58b.

    I2. That

    Swift

    was

    thoroughly

    familiar

    with

    traditional

    oratory

    s patently

    obvious;

    every

    schoolboy

    endured long years

    of

    such

    training

    (see

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    6/21

    John R. Clark

    78I

    though Swift may not be the overtrhetorician iven to oration,his

    Modem

    persona ertainly s: in SectionIX he simplycommences n

    encomium n praiseof Madness,particularlyiming o show, as such

    encomiasticoratorydoes, that Madness is "worthy of praise," s

    "noble s

    18

    and, in order o render uch honor, he Modem proceeds

    through he appropriatend traditionalratorical ivisions-exordium,

    narratio,

    partitio, argumentatio,peroratio.1'

    Here the Modern, ike Cicero's deal orator,"besideavoidingany

    suspicion

    f a

    displayof talent,"

    hoosesnot

    to be

    "

    the

    champion f

    [mere] expediency,"

    but rather the

    championof "integrity ; he

    "urges

    us

    on the

    path

    of moralworth

    . .

    [by collecting] xamples f

    our

    ancestors'

    chievementshat

    were

    glorious

    ven

    though nvolving

    danger,

    and

    . .

    .

    magnif[ies]

    he

    value of an

    undyingmemory

    widt

    posterity."

    15 His

    narratio r

    postulate implyurges

    hat

    "

    the

    greatest

    Actions

    hat have

    been

    performed

    n the World" are

    directlyowing

    to Madness

    I62).

    In

    his brief

    partitio,

    he announces hat his

    argu-

    mentatiowill producegreatexamples

    where Madness s

    responsible

    for

    (a)

    "The

    Establishment

    f

    New

    Empiresby Conquest," b)

    "

    The

    Advance

    and

    Progress f

    New Schemes n

    Philosophy,"

    nd

    (c)

    "

    the

    contriving,

    s

    well as the

    propagating f

    New

    Religions

    (I62).

    All of

    these

    "

    proofs

    " or

    "

    confirmationsmake he traditional

    appeals

    o the

    noble

    Ancestry

    f

    Madness

    and

    present

    a

    respectable

    Donald

    Leman

    Clark, John

    Milton at

    St. Paul's

    School:

    A

    Study of

    Ancient

    Rhetoric in

    English

    Renaissance

    Education [New

    York,

    1948],

    and

    Alice Stayert

    Brandenburg,

    "English

    Education and

    Neo-Classical

    Taste

    in the

    Eighteenth

    Cen-

    tury,"

    MLQ,VIII

    [I947],

    '74-93).

    That Swift

    also

    employed uch

    oratory

    to

    his

    own ends) in his satires s likewise apparent(see, for instance, CharlesAllen Beau-

    mont, "Swift's

    Classical

    Rhetoric in

    'A Modest Proposal,"'

    Georgia

    Review, XIV

    [Fall

    I960], 307-I7,

    and Lamarr

    Stephens,

    "'A

    Digression

    n Praise

    of Digressions'

    as a Classical

    Oration:

    Rhetorical

    Satire

    in Section

    VII of Swift's

    A Tale

    of

    a Tub,"

    Tulane

    Studies

    in English,

    XIII [I963],

    41-49).

    I owe

    a

    considerabledebt,

    in

    these pages

    treating

    of the Modem's

    oration,

    to the thorough

    study

    by

    Henry

    Knight

    Miller,

    "The Paradoxical

    Encomium

    with

    Special

    Reference

    to its Vogue

    in

    England,

    I6oo-I8oo,"

    MP,

    LIII (I956),

    145-78.

    8Aristotle, Rhetoric,

    pp.

    33,

    56-7.

    14

    Raymond

    L.

    Irwin,

    "

    The

    Classical

    Speech

    Divisions," QJS,

    XXV

    (April

    I939),

    2i2-3;

    these

    terms

    differ among

    various

    authors;

    I have

    largely

    relied upon

    Cicero's

    De oratoreII. lxxviii.

    3

    I

    5-lxxxi. 333.

    lS

    De oratoreII. lxxxii.

    334-5,

    in De Oratore,

    edd.,

    trans.

    E. W. Sutton

    and

    H.

    Rackham

    (Cambridge,

    Mass.,

    1948),

    I,

    451-2.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    7/21

    782 Swift's Knaves and Fools in the Tradition

    analysis

    of the

    Company Madness

    keeps: proofs, that is, which make

    the

    usual appeals to

    Genesis,

    Tradition, and Association.'6 The ora-

    tion advances

    regularly

    enough,

    the orator

    citing two examples under

    each of

    the three

    announced heads: Henry IV and

    Louis XIV; Epi-

    curus and

    Descartes;

    Jack

    of

    Leyden and (presumably)

    brother Jack,

    the

    founder

    of Aeolism. Thus

    far,

    the

    Modern persona is

    fulfilling

    those

    parts

    of his oration'stitle

    which

    promise

    to

    demonstrate

    "

    the

    Original" (Vapors) and "the

    Use'"

    (in Politics, Philosophy, Re-

    ligion)

    of Madness.

    In

    the crucial

    eighth and

    ninth

    paragraphs, he Modem proceeds

    further

    to demonstrate

    "

    the Use

    "

    of Madness:

    madness or

    delusion

    is

    in

    fact

    the

    only

    source

    of

    happiness;

    all

    mankind must make

    a

    choice between

    madness and a sort

    of

    cavilling

    curiosity; and even

    those who

    elect the latter come

    to

    discover their

    error

    (I73). He

    concludes

    this

    portion

    of his oration

    resoundingly,

    asserting that

    Madness

    is

    entirely superior

    to

    sanity,

    to

    reason,

    or

    to

    science.

    This

    is thatsuperiority f being a

    "

    fool "among"knaves."

    The

    "

    knave

    "

    in

    the case is a

    tricky

    and deceitful

    fellow simply

    because

    he is not "

    tranquil,"

    " serene,"

    and

    "peaceful

    ";

    his "curi-

    osity"

    leads

    him to uncover the

    ugly

    and

    the

    unpleasant,

    to

    the

    en-

    dorsement

    of

    "

    the

    Art

    of

    exposing

    weak

    Sides,

    and

    publishing

    In-

    firmities"

    (172),

    as

    well

    as

    "

    unmasking

    "

    (a practice

    never

    accepted

    as "fair

    usage"

    in

    art or in

    life

    [I731).

    From the

    perfectly regular

    viewpoint

    of the

    Modem,

    who

    is,

    after

    all, praising

    insanity,

    the

    "knave's"

    deceit

    consists

    wholly

    in

    his

    favoring

    unnatural

    explora-

    tion, in preferringexperiments

    and

    anatomies,

    n

    discoveringa world

    of flaws

    and

    imperfections.

    The

    "

    fool,"

    on the other

    hand

    (French,

    fou

    or

    fol)

    is

    the

    madman,

    or

    "natural

    ";

    he

    is,

    naturally enough,

    favored

    n an orationwhich

    is, quite devotedly,

    a

    praise

    and a

    defense

    of

    himself.

    The

    Modem

    persona, then, having logically

    demonstrated

    the

    1"

    Theodore

    Burgess,Epideictic

    Literature

    (Chicago,

    I902), esp. pp. 157-66, treats

    of the typical

    " Universal

    Lines

    of

    Argument

    "

    or

    "

    commonplaces

    an

    orator

    employs

    in

    praising

    a

    person; among

    them the

    general

    reference to

    genos,

    sub-

    divisions

    of

    which

    praise

    the

    subject'sprogonoi (ancestors), pateres (parents), his

    ethos

    (race), and

    anatrophe,

    the subject's Youth and Upbringing; in this last

    "

    place

    "

    are

    introduced

    the

    "

    companions

    "

    and " associates"

    of

    the

    subject's child-

    hood and youth.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    8/21

    John

    R. Clark

    783

    "Original

    and the

    "

    Use

    "

    of Madness,

    n

    the remainder

    f his ora-

    tion (and

    sounding

    ncreasingly

    ike the

    modem "projector")

    ub-

    sequently

    proposes

    he refinement

    f

    madness-its

    "Improvement

    n

    a Commonwealth."

    he

    national

    madare

    to be

    tumed

    loose

    from

    Bedlam,

    are to occupy

    he choice

    seats n society

    and

    secure

    hereins

    of government.

    In the contextof a

    verydeliberate

    raise

    of

    folly, which,

    in the

    course

    of its argument,

    andidly

    presents confirmation

    f foolishness

    and the consequent efutation f its oppositemember,knavery,t is

    difficult

    o understand

    ow

    the

    rhetorical

    riticcould

    havewondered

    which

    "

    side

    "-that of

    foolsor of knaves-couldpossibly

    be

    "

    correct."

    Nevertheless,

    t

    might

    still

    be

    objected

    hat one is wrong

    to isolate

    both

    "

    credulity

    and

    "

    curiosity

    from the life

    that

    adheres o

    the

    common orms."

    A reader,

    n

    other

    words,might insist

    that

    Swift

    sanctions

    "

    credulity

    which

    is

    synonymous

    ith

    shallow

    adherence

    to

    the "common

    orms

    "

    of

    the

    Anglican

    Church

    and

    of a genteel

    and questionablynlightened pperclass.Such a readerwouldargue

    that Swift

    in

    the

    Tale

    of

    a Tub

    exposes-often

    helplessly-this

    very

    credulous

    hallowness

    hat

    he would

    endorse;

    he

    reader

    mightfeel

    that

    this

    is

    so

    because

    Swift,

    no

    verybright

    thinker,

    had

    nothing

    better

    than

    "

    surfaces

    and "forms"

    to offer

    in the

    place

    of fanatic

    curiosity

    nd

    an

    indifferent

    cientific

    determinism.

    Our reply

    must

    be

    that Swift

    is not at

    all

    equivalent

    o

    his com-

    mitted

    persona;

    we

    shall

    discover

    hat

    Swift,

    unlike the

    Modern

    n

    Section

    IX

    who

    is

    devoted

    o

    credulity,

    tands

    broadly

    loof

    fromthe

    positions f eitherthe curiousor the credulousman.

    In Section

    IX,

    we

    will

    remember,

    he sane

    mind is

    distinctly

    separate

    rom

    credulity

    and

    curiosity.

    For the sane

    mind,

    "in

    its

    natural

    Position

    and

    State of

    Serenity"

    I71),

    chooses,

    elects to

    pass

    its

    life

    in

    adherence

    to the " common

    forms,"

    which

    are

    "

    the

    pattern

    of human

    leaming

    "-that

    is,

    the massive accumulation

    of

    value

    and

    experience

    that

    distinguishes

    the historical

    sense,

    and,

    indeed,

    that renders any

    sort

    of

    civilization

    possible.

    We

    cannot

    enough

    emphasize

    the idea of the mind's

    " natural"

    position,

    and

    the

    concept that such a mind "elects" or " chooses" such a pattern,per-

    mitting

    itself to

    be "instructed"

    by

    it.

    Such

    a mind

    is

    marked

    by

    decision

    and

    self-possession.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    9/21

    784 Swift's Knaves and Fools in the Traditiot

    In

    sharp contrast,

    credulous

    man and curious are equally

    emble-

    matic

    of an "unnatural"

    state; in both, the

    mind is overcome

    (this

    is its hamartia)

    by an ide'e

    fixe;

    in

    both "a Man's Fancy gets

    astride

    on

    his

    Reason"

    (17I), and such

    minds cease to retain self-possession,

    becoming,

    instead,

    themselves

    possessed.

    Throughout

    the Restora-

    tion

    and Age

    of Reason,

    Englishmen,

    mindful

    of

    the enthusiastic

    excesses

    of

    the Puritan Civil Wars,

    feared

    every

    expressionof

    "

    fancy

    "

    and

    "

    spirit

    "-feared

    any

    mind

    overthrown, nhabited

    by

    spirits

    and

    devils.

    It

    was commonplace

    n the

    period

    to

    wam

    against

    inspiration:

    "

    Beware

    what

    Spirit rages

    in

    your

    breast;/For

    ten

    inspir'd

    ten thou-

    sand

    are

    Possest."

    7

    Swift's

    credulous

    and curious

    men

    are

    so

    possessed.

    In the context

    of Section IX's wit, both the credulous

    man and the curious

    "

    conceive

    it in [their] Power, to

    reduce the Notions of all

    Mankind,

    exactlyto the same

    Length, and Breadth,and

    Height of [their]

    own

    "

    (i66). This conception

    is

    clearly

    not

    Swift's own;

    but

    it

    is the en-

    deavor of the

    credulous

    and the curious.

    They would

    both

    attempt

    to measure

    the world

    by

    themselves,

    "qui

    ratione

    sua

    disturbant

    moenia mundi

    ";

    8

    in

    this crazed

    undertaking they

    both

    appear to

    "choose

    "

    either tranquil Epicurean

    delusion

    or an

    ultimately un-

    satisfactory

    materialistic

    or virtuoso

    experimentalism.

    Yet in

    reality

    they are

    minds violently possessed-by

    vapors

    from

    we

    know

    not

    where,

    if

    you

    will-but

    possessed

    all the

    same, by

    the

    determination

    to

    measure

    the

    world

    by themselves;

    to

    abandon,

    that

    is, any

    aware-

    ness of

    "common

    forms" or

    of existence

    itself

    outside their

    own

    minds-forsaking

    God, religion, politics,

    tradition,

    and

    learning-,

    sub-

    stituting

    in their

    stead

    a monolithic reliance either

    upon

    their

    own

    Senses

    or

    upon

    their

    immediate

    privateImaginings.

    Such

    an

    ambition

    explains why,

    in Section

    IX,

    Swift's

    Modern

    persona,

    himself

    a

    veritable

    archetype

    of "

    Sufficiency,"

    9

    intends to

    "7Wentworth

    Dillon,

    Earl of

    Roscommon,

    "An

    Essay

    on

    Translated Verse"

    (i684), in Critical

    Essays

    of

    the

    Seventeenth

    Century,

    ed.

    J.

    E.

    Spingam (Bloom-

    ington, Ind.,

    1957),

    II,

    306.

    18

    Jonathan Swift, "Thoughts

    on

    Religion,"

    The

    Prose Works

    of Jonathan

    Swift,

    ed. Herbert Davis (Oxford,

    1939-68),

    IX,

    261.

    19 "

    Sufficiency,the worst compositionout of the pride and ignorance of man-

    kind,"

    was

    a favorite

    term

    of Sir William

    Temple's;

    see Sir

    William

    Temple's

    Essays

    on Ancient

    &

    Modern

    Learning

    and

    On

    Poetry,

    ed.

    J.

    E.

    Spingarn (Oxford,

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    10/21

    John R. Clark 785

    deducea

    System

    hat can so easilycontradict

    veryopinionsave his

    own; and why his System

    emphasizes t bottoma local and

    private

    "something

    ndividual n human Minds"

    (I62). It explainswhy

    "greatactions

    "

    (upon whichthe Modemexpends

    o muchtime) are

    repeatedly ttributed

    o the isolatedndividual-Henry

    V, LouisXIV,

    Epicurus,Cartesius,

    Wotton, Jack, and,

    to be sure, the Modern

    personahimself.

    For the Modem persona,

    mad and solitary

    n his

    garret,

    s concerned nly with

    the actionsand the ideas of

    "

    Single

    Men"

    (I62),

    single men concernedwith themselvesalone. Both

    credulousand curiousmen

    are

    withdrawn

    nto

    singularity-where

    they sleep, and dream,

    or

    engage

    n

    private

    occult

    study,poring

    over

    data

    amassed rom

    brief

    forays

    nto

    the

    external

    world,

    where

    they

    have obtained

    nformationsromvisions

    and

    anatomies.

    As

    Ian

    Watt

    has

    observed,

    ".

    .

    .

    from

    the

    Renaissance

    nwards,

    there was

    a

    growing

    tendency

    or individual

    experience

    o

    replace

    collectivetradition,"

    0

    culminating,

    as

    we

    know, in the victoryof

    romantic ingularity

    nd economic

    ndividualismn

    the

    nineteenth

    century. Nevertheless,Restorationand eighteenth-centurymen

    fought

    the

    good

    fight against

    his

    encroaching

    freedom

    ;

    and

    poets

    and practical

    men

    alike

    were

    repeatedly

    eminded hat

    they

    should

    "hate

    minuteness,

    and

    [be]

    afraid

    of

    singularity."'21

    Traditional

    Restoration

    riticism

    epeatedly

    arns

    against

    he

    private,

    he

    singular;

    these

    are

    equated

    with

    the

    perverse.

    In framing

    a

    Character

    for

    Tragedy,

    a Poet is not to leave

    his

    reason, and

    blindly

    abandon

    himself

    to follow

    fancy,

    for then his

    fancy might

    be

    monstrous,

    might

    be

    singular,

    and

    please

    no

    body'smaggot

    but

    his

    own;

    but

    reason is

    to be

    his

    guide, reason is common to all people, and can never carry him from what is

    Natural.22

    igog),

    esp.

    p. 3. Consult

    the discussion

    of sufficiency

    in Ronald

    Paulson,

    Theme

    and Structure

    n Swift's

    Tale of

    a

    Tub, esp. pp.

    92-3. Professor

    Paulson conceives

    of the dichotomy

    between credulity

    and

    curiosity

    exemplified

    n

    the

    conflict between

    the

    "

    Hack's

    "

    Gnostic

    Idealism and

    Swift's

    own Lockean Realism

    (p.

    I37).

    20The

    Rise

    of

    the

    Novel

    (Berkeley

    and

    Los

    Angeles,

    1957),

    p.

    6o.

    21

    Anthony Ashley Cooper,

    Third

    Earl

    of

    Shaftesbury,

    Characteristics

    of

    Men,

    Manners,

    Opinions, Times,

    Treatise

    II,

    " Sensus Communis:

    An

    Essay on the

    Freedom

    of Wit and Humour,"

    Pt.

    IV,

    sec.

    iii, quoted

    in

    Watt,

    Rise

    of the Novel,

    p. I6. Concerning

    the distrustof

    singularity

    in the

    Enlightenment,

    consult

    Scoat

    Elledge, "The Backgroundand Development in English Criticismof the Theories

    of Generality

    and

    Particularity,"

    PMLA,

    LXII

    (I947),

    147-82.

    8S

    Thomas Rymer,

    "The

    tragedies

    of the

    Last

    Age

    Consider'd

    and

    Examin'd

    by

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    11/21

    786 Swift's Knacves nd Fools in the Tradition

    Swift,

    unlike

    his modem credulous and curious men,

    participates n

    this tradition opposing

    entlhusiastic

    ancy and the private maggot.

    Moreover, there is decisive

    evidence that the

    "credulous" and

    curious

    "

    men are distinctly

    separate rom any view of Swift's own.

    This

    becomes clear when we examine the tradition of

    the seven-

    teenth-century

    Character. The "humour character,"

    with his singu-

    lar and

    pronouncedfoible, had been popular in English

    drama since

    the time

    of Jonson.2; He is descended from

    Menandrian comedy's

    highly

    conventionalizedcharacterizations, uch as those

    of the cun-

    ning slave, the

    kindly

    matron,

    the

    fawning parasite,the mniser

    mor,

    the

    miles

    gloriosus.24

    The humour characterhas

    of

    course,

    a still older life in

    tradition;

    in the

    Nicomnachean

    thics Aristotle

    explored at length a

    number of

    "settled

    dispositions"

    of mind that

    produced

    in men

    an

    excess

    or

    defect

    from some

    moral virtue. In

    treating

    of

    such

    error-ridden

    x-

    tremes,

    Aristotle

    rendered

    llustrative

    "

    characters such

    as the

    buffoon,

    the vain

    man,

    the

    profligate,

    the

    paltry man,

    the

    niggard.25

    In the

    work of

    Aristotle's

    disciple, Theophrastus,

    examples

    of

    excesses and

    defects

    of virtue

    are

    presented

    more

    "

    humourously,"

    more

    at

    length,

    in bolder

    colors.

    His

    portrayals

    of

    exemplary

    excesses and

    defects

    include

    such

    pairs

    of charactersas the

    Complaisant

    Man

    and the

    Surly,

    the Buffoon

    and

    the

    Boor,

    the aiazon

    and

    eiron,

    the

    coward

    and

    the

    bully.26

    the Practice

    of the

    Ancients

    and

    by

    the Common Sense of

    All

    Ages"

    (i678),

    Critical Essays of

    the Seventeenth

    Century, II,

    192.

    23

    The concept

    of

    the

    humours originates

    with Heraclitean

    metaphysics

    and

    Hippocratic medicine; by the principle of concordia discors, the world, like the

    individual, is

    bound

    in a

    delicate

    harmony

    that

    can

    be

    unbalanced

    when

    malaise

    leads to

    the

    predominance

    of some

    single

    humour.

    Jonson's

    more

    renowned eluci-

    dations

    of his

    conception

    of the humour character

    appear

    in

    Asper's eighth speech

    in the Prologue

    to

    Every

    Man

    Outt

    of

    His

    Humour

    (1598)

    and

    in Cash's definition,

    III.

    ii,

    in the

    revised

    Every

    Man

    In His Humour

    (16I2?).

    24

    In

    the Prologue

    to his

    Menandrian

    Heauton

    Timorumenon

    (lines 37-9),

    Terence

    lists

    a

    number

    of the

    prominent

    character-types:

    the

    "

    servus

    currens,

    iratus senex,

    edax

    parasitus, sycophanta

    autem

    inpudens,

    avarus leno." For a

    delineation

    of sixteen

    such

    character-types,

    consult Marvin

    T.

    Herrick, "Comic

    Theory

    in

    the Sixteenth

    Century,"

    Illinois

    Studies in

    Language

    and

    Literature,

    XXXIV

    (Urbana,

    1950),

    I47-73.

    25 The Nicomachean

    Ethics, ed.,

    trans.

    H.

    Rackham (Cambridge, Mass., 1947),

    pp.

    249; 227;

    I8I; 213; 20I-3.

    '2

    " The

    Characters

    of

    Theophrastus,"

    d.,

    trans.

    J.

    M.

    Edmonds,

    in

    The

    Char-

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    12/21

    John R. Clark 787

    As is well-known,

    Hall,

    Cornwallis,

    Earle,

    and Overbury

    recom-

    menced

    the

    tradition

    of such

    satiric

    character-writing,

    which

    con-

    tinues

    popular

    throughout

    the

    seventeenth

    century.27

    We soon

    discoverthat

    during

    this

    period no

    humourous

    affectation

    or excess

    was more

    popularly

    characterized

    han

    that

    "curiosity"

    in

    pedants,

    antiquaries,

    and

    similar

    Baconian

    collectors

    of a

    type

    ridiculed

    as

    long ago

    as in

    Lucian's

    "Ignorant

    Book-Collector"

    (Adversus

    In-

    doctum).

    Later in the

    seventeenth

    century,

    with the

    growth

    of the

    Royal Society and inductive science, this collectoris more specifically

    embodiedas

    a Sir

    Nicholas

    Gimcrack

    of Shadwell's

    play, as

    the

    "

    vir-

    tuoso,"

    who in

    his Will

    leaves

    to his associate

    his "rat's

    testicles,

    and

    Whale's pizzle,"

    and

    to his

    son his

    "monsters,

    both

    wet

    and

    dry.)

    28

    Caught

    in

    this

    rising

    tide,

    the curious

    virtuoso

    is

    laughed

    at

    for

    fully

    a

    century.

    Marston deals

    with several

    characters named

    "

    Curio

    ";

    Pope

    utilizes a

    "

    Curio

    ";

    and

    he

    is, properly,

    as

    Thomas

    Adams

    in his

    Character

    calls

    him,

    "The Curious Man":

    "If

    this

    Itching curiositie take him in the Cephalicaveine, and possesse the

    understandingpart,

    he

    mootes

    more

    questions

    in an houre then

    the

    seven

    Wise men

    could resolve

    in seven yeeres."

    His

    curiosity

    regu-

    larly

    exceeds

    any prudence

    or

    self-restraint:

    He

    hath

    a

    greater

    desire

    to

    know where

    Hell

    is,

    then

    to

    scape

    it.... For

    want

    of

    correcting

    the

    garden

    of his inventions,

    the weedes choke

    the herbes; and

    he

    suffers

    the skimme

    of his braine to boile into

    the broth.

    He is a

    dangerous

    Prog-

    nosticator,

    and

    propounds

    desperate

    riddles.

    Such

    a

    meddler,

    Adams

    adds,

    is

    driven

    to

    study

    mystical

    emblems,

    adores astrology,engages

    in

    Popish

    plots;

    for he

    is

    overpowered

    by

    acters

    of

    Theophrastus;

    Herodes,

    Cercidas,

    and

    the Greek

    Choliambic

    Poets

    (Cam-

    bridge,

    Mass.,

    1946),

    pp. 50-3,

    76-9; 68-71,

    48-51;

    98-103,

    40-3;

    104-9,

    52-7.

    27

    Consult

    Gwendolen

    Murphy,

    A

    Bibliography

    of

    English

    Character-Books,

    I6o8-1700

    (Oxford,

    1925).

    Excellent

    surveys

    of

    the

    growth

    of

    character-writings

    may

    be

    found

    in

    Anna Janney

    De

    Armond,

    "Some

    Aspects

    of

    Character-Writing

    in

    the

    Period

    of

    the

    Restoration,"

    Delaware Notes,

    XVI

    (I943),

    55-89,

    and

    m

    Edward

    Niles

    Hooker,

    "Humour

    in

    the Age

    of

    Pope,"

    HLQ,

    XI

    (1948),

    36I-85.

    28Joseph

    Addison,

    Tatler

    No.

    2I6,

    The

    Tatler,

    The

    Guardian

    (London,

    I852),

    I, 394.

    Consult

    Walter

    E.

    Houghton,

    Jr.,

    "The

    English

    Virtuoso

    in

    the

    Seven-

    teenth Century,"

    JHI,

    III

    (1942),

    51-73,

    I90-2.I9,

    and

    C. S.

    Duncan,

    "The

    Scientist

    as

    a Comic

    Type,"

    MP,

    XIV (I9I6),

    28I-I.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    13/21

    788 Swift's Knaves and Fools in the Tradition

    vapors, overcome

    by "humorem

    in

    cerebro,

    in corde tumorem,

    ru-

    morem

    n lingua."

    9

    On the

    other

    hand, the

    "

    credulous

    7

    man is equally

    popular n the

    "characters

    "

    of the tradition.

    He is the

    ironic

    ingenu or witless naif

    treated

    in Wireker's

    Speculum

    Stultorumn,

    Dedekind's

    Grobianus,

    Dekker's

    Guls Hornbook,

    Voltaire's

    Candide,

    and is

    represented

    by

    all

    those silly praisersof

    folly that can

    be traced back

    in one

    strand

    to the Middle

    Ages.30Alexander

    Barclay s

    severe with such

    "

    Foles

    of lyght

    credence";such

    a gull

    is

    lyght myndyd, and

    voyde

    of

    all prudence

    Whiche alway

    is wont,

    without aduysement

    To all

    vayne

    talys sone

    to

    gyue

    credence

    Aplyenge

    his

    ervs

    thereto.

    Barclay

    holds the

    credulous man precisely

    as guilty

    as the

    "talc

    berers

    ":

    "They

    ar as lewde

    that wyll

    the same byleue."

    31

    Furthermore,

    he Old

    Testament had made

    little or no

    distinction

    between

    the

    "

    fool

    "

    and the

    "

    knave,"both alike being sinners;

    2

    nor

    was

    such a

    distinction

    always

    mnaintained

    n the late Middle

    Ages

    and

    early

    Renaissance.3;

    Samuel

    Butler

    certainly

    transfixes

    ool

    and knave together

    in

    Hudibras:

    29

    Thomas

    Adams,

    "

    The

    Curious

    Man,"

    in A

    Cabinet of

    Characters,

    ed.

    Gwendolen

    Murphy

    (London, I925),

    pp.

    54-6.

    The

    "curious

    "

    man

    is a traditional

    character;

    Alexander

    Barclay

    treats,

    not only of

    the

    collecting

    "bok-fole,"

    and

    the

    fool addicted

    to

    Astronomy,

    but

    "

    Of

    ouer

    great

    and chargeable

    curyosyte

    of

    men

    "

    in general,

    who attempt

    "

    the hole worlde [to]

    take

    on

    theyr

    backe

    ";

    "

    Many

    of this

    sort wander

    and compass

    All

    studies,

    the wondrs of the worlde

    to se/

    With

    un-

    stabyll wynges fleynge from place to place" (Sebastian Brant, The Ship of Fools,

    trans.

    Alexander

    Barclay

    [1509],

    ed. J.

    H. Jamieson

    [London,

    1874],

    1,

    19-23;

    II,

    i8-22;

    I,

    129-32,

    176).

    In

    fact,

    '"curiosity"

    was considered

    in the Renaissance

    one

    of the gravest

    sins,

    and the cause

    of

    Adam's

    Fall

    (see

    Howard

    Schultz,

    Milton

    and

    Forbidden

    Knowledge

    [New

    York,

    I955],

    esp.

    pp. I-74).

    0

    Consult

    Barbara

    Swain,

    Fools

    and

    Folly

    During

    c

    lliddle

    Ages

    and

    the

    Renaissance

    (New

    York, 1932),

    esp.

    Ch.

    II, pp.

    10-26.

    "'Brant, Ship

    of Fools,

    II,

    2I4,

    215,

    lines

    1-4,

    21.

    82In Proverbs

    he

    Fool is

    a

    blabbererand lazy

    (9:13,

    I0:5,

    10:14,

    13:I6, 14:I5,

    I7:24, 19:

    1

    5

    ),

    but he

    is akin

    to

    the

    " talebearer "

    of

    I I: I

    3.

    Fools and knaves

    merge

    in

    I2:

    I5:

    "The way

    of a

    fool

    is

    right

    in his

    own

    eyes."

    Traditionally,

    fools

    and

    knaves

    are

    equally

    sinners,

    for ignorance

    is

    understood

    as criminal

    negligence.

    ss

    "

    The

    first

    thing

    to be remembered

    is that the words

    ' fool ' and '

    knave

    '

    were

    constantly coupled

    together,

    but not always

    in

    quite

    the same

    way;

    for

    sometimes

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    14/21

    John R. Clark 789

    Doubtless the pleasure is as great

    Of being

    cheated, as to cheat;

    As lookers-on eel most delight,

    That least perceive a juggler'sslight,

    And still

    the less they understand,

    The

    more th'

    admire his slight

    of hand."

    Bacon

    urgesprecisely his point:

    fool and knavealike are dangerous.

    The

    "

    foulest

    "

    "

    vice or diseaseof leaning," Bacon

    asserts,

    s

    that which doth destroy the essential form of knowledge, which is nothing

    but

    a

    representationof truth. . . .

    This vice therefore brancheth itself into

    two

    sorts; delight

    in

    deceiving, and aptness to

    be

    deceived; imposture and

    credulity;

    which, although they appear

    to

    be of

    a

    diversenature, the one seeming to

    proceed

    of

    cunning,

    and

    the other of simplicity, yet certainly they do for the most

    part

    concur: for

    as the verse noteth,

    Percontatorem

    ugito, nam garrulus dem est,

    an

    inquisitive

    man is

    a

    prattler, so

    upon

    the like reason a credulous

    man is a

    deceiver.8"

    Although

    he twin vices

    of

    curiosity nd credulitymight be

    akin,

    theyare nonethelesshe twinpoles,respectively, f excessanddefect

    borne to

    us

    from Aristotle's thical

    analysis.

    Unlike

    fool

    or

    knave,

    the

    wise,

    the

    prudent

    man

    sustainsa

    balance,a mean, that these

    others

    lack: "Un homme

    sage

    ni

    ne se

    laisse

    gouverner,

    ni

    ne

    cherche

    a gouvernor

    es

    autres: l

    veut

    que

    la

    raison

    gouverne

    eule,

    et

    toujours."

    6

    Thomas

    Hobbes,

    working

    with

    these

    commonplace deas,

    dis-

    tinguishes

    wo

    extremestates of

    mind, sensuality

    and

    fancifulness.

    On

    the one

    hand,

    he

    analyzes

    the

    extremity

    of

    "sensual

    man."

    "The appetiteof sensualor bodily delight"in such a man causes

    him

    to seek

    "

    pleasures

    f

    sense,

    which

    only please

    for the

    present,"

    leading

    him

    to

    ignore

    honor or future events and

    goals,

    until

    he

    they

    were

    treated

    as

    synonyms,

    sometimes

    emphasis

    was

    laid on

    the

    distinction

    between

    them"

    (Enid

    Welsford,

    The Fool:

    His

    Social and

    Literary

    History [New

    York, 1936], pp. 236-7).

    s4

    Hudibras

    II. iii.I-5.

    8B

    "The Advancement

    of

    Learning,"

    The Works

    of

    Francis

    Bacon, edd. James

    Spedding,

    Robert

    Leslie

    Ellis,

    and

    Douglas

    Denon Heath

    (Boston, I86I-4),

    VI,

    sz2.

    The

    Latin

    verse

    is from Horace

    (Ep.

    I. xviii.

    69).

    88

    [Jean de] La Bruy6re,Les Caracteresou Les Moeurs de ce Siecle suivis du

    discours

    a

    l'Academie

    et

    precedes

    de

    la

    Traduction

    de

    Theophraste,

    ed.

    G.

    Mon-

    gr6dien (Paris, ['9541),

    p.

    I32.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    15/21

    790

    Suift's Knavesand Foolsin the Tradition

    becomes

    ncreasinglyess

    diligent, ess curious, ess

    extensive,

    with

    drawing into himself with a

    totally inert lassitude common

    to

    many

    a

    psychotic.Such a state

    of withdrawal

    Hobbes calls "dulness."

    The

    contrary tate,

    Hobbesexplains, s revealedby the man wlho

    tums utterly

    outward n his

    interests,

    who literallyappears

    o

    take

    a

    flight away

    from

    himself.

    He reveals

    the

    quick ranging of mind . . .

    , which is joined with curiosity of

    comparing

    the things that come into the mind, one with another: in which comparison, a

    man delighteth himself either with

    finding

    unexpected similitude of things, other-

    wise much

    unlike, in which men place the

    excellency of fancy.

    In excess, such

    a mind

    betrays

    "

    mobility

    in the spirits

    "

    still

    further,

    that Hobbes

    designates

    levity."

    An

    example

    hereof

    is

    in them

    that

    in

    the midst of

    any

    serious

    discourse, havse

    their

    minds

    diverted

    to every little jest or witty

    observation;

    which maketh them

    depart

    from

    their discourseby a

    parenthesis,and

    from

    that parenthesis

    by

    another

    till at

    length

    they

    either

    lose themselves, or make

    their narration ike a dream,

    or

    some

    studied

    nonsense. The passions from whence

    this proceedeth, s curiosity,but

    with too much equality and indifference: for when all things make equal impres-

    sion and

    delight,

    they equally throngto

    be

    expressed.

    The final

    triumph f any humour haracter'sdee

    fixe,

    Hobbes

    under-

    standsas the

    mind's

    "principaldefect"-either a soaring

    light

    out-

    side

    the

    self

    or a dejectedsubmersion

    7ithin:

    "

    that

    wvhich

    men

    call

    mad.ness,

    which appearethto be

    nothing else but some imagina-

    tionz of some suchi

    predominlancy bove the rest, that we

    have no

    passionz

    but from

    it; and this conception is

    nothing else but

    excessive

    vain

    glory,

    or vain

    dejection."

    7

    For our purposes, he mostrevealingpresentationof the twin faults

    of

    "

    cuLriosity

    and

    "

    credulity"occurs n Samuel

    Butler's

    Characters

    of

    "

    The Credulous

    Man"

    and

    "

    The

    Curious

    Man."

    Butler's

    "

    curi-

    ous

    "

    man is

    unconcemedwith

    the

    utility

    of

    any

    goal,

    but rather

    seeks

    rarity,

    and

    "

    stores

    up

    Trifles."

    He

    admires subtleties

    above

    all

    Things,

    because

    the more subtle

    they are, the

    nearer

    they

    are

    to

    nothing;

    and values no Art

    but

    that which

    is

    spun

    so

    thin,

    that

    it is of no

    Use

    at all. He

    had

    ratherhave an iron Chain

    hung

    about the

    Neck of

    a

    s. Thomas Hobbes, "Human Nature, or the Fundamental Elements of Pol-icy

    (i 640), The

    English

    Works

    of Thomas Hobbes

    of Malmesbury,

    ed.

    Sir

    William

    Molesworth London,

    I

    839-45),

    IV,

    55-7. See also

    Leviathan

    I.

    xi.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    16/21

    John R. Clark

    791

    Flea, than

    an Alderman's

    of

    Gold,

    and Homer's

    fiads

    in

    a Nutshel

    than

    Alexander's

    Cabinet.

    . .

    . he so

    much

    affects Singularity,

    that

    rather

    than follow

    the Fashion, that

    is

    used by the

    rest of the

    World,

    he will

    wear dissenting

    Cloaths

    with odd fantastic

    Devices to

    distinguish himself

    from others,

    like Marks

    set upon

    Cattle.

    Such a curious

    man

    "

    is

    wonderfully

    taken with

    abstruse

    Knowledge,

    and had

    rather

    hand to

    Truth with

    a Pair

    of

    Tongs wrapt

    up in

    Mysteries

    and Flieroglyphics,

    han

    touch it

    with his hands,

    or see

    it

    plainly demonstrated o his Senses." He is dedicatedto "Study upon

    Things

    that

    are never

    to be known

    ";

    and his

    studies

    ultimately lead

    him

    to visionary

    pursuit

    of the

    "

    Philosopher's

    Stone

    and universal

    Medicine."

    8

    At the opposite

    extreme

    is

    Butler's

    "

    Credulous Man,"

    the super-

    gull

    who actually

    tempts

    others

    to

    deceive

    him.

    "

    He is

    the same

    thing

    to a

    lyar,

    as

    a thief

    is

    to a

    receiver,"

    and

    is,

    in

    fact,

    more

    blame-

    worthy

    than

    the

    liar,

    "for if

    it were not for

    easy

    believers,

    liars

    would be at

    a loss."

    Above

    all,

    he is

    tranquil

    in his

    ignorance:

    His

    faith is of

    a

    very strong

    constitution,

    that

    will swallow

    and

    digest

    anything,

    how

    crude, raw,

    and

    unwholesome

    so ever it be.

    . . . He finds most

    delight

    in

    believing

    strange

    things,

    and the

    stranger

    they are,

    the easier

    they pass

    with

    him;

    but

    never

    regards

    hose

    that are

    plain

    and

    feasible,

    for

    every

    man

    can believe

    such."'

    During

    the seventeenth century, jests

    and characters of

    such

    "credulous"

    and

    "

    curious"

    men

    were

    quite

    common;

    "

    and

    Swift

    knew

    well

    enough

    the traditionof humours

    and characters

    we

    have

    been

    exploring.4"

    Swift

    naturally

    understood

    the excess

    of

    curiosity

    38

    Samuel

    Butler,

    "

    A

    Curious

    Man,"

    Characters

    and

    Passages

    from

    Note-books,

    ed.

    A.

    R. Waller (Cambridge,

    I908), pp.

    66-7.

    39Butler,

    "A Credulous

    Man,"

    ibid.,

    pp.

    212-3.

    40

    Chester

    Noyes

    Greenough,

    A Bibliography

    of

    the

    Theophrastan

    Character

    with

    several

    Portrait

    Characters,

    ed.

    J.

    Milton

    French (Cambridge,

    Mass.,

    I947),

    lists

    characters

    of

    Curio

    and

    curiosity

    (pp. II,

    2I,

    26, 2I0,

    2I6, 227),

    and

    of

    Credulo

    and credulity

    (pp.

    95, 190,

    272).

    4' Swift

    himself

    records

    that

    he

    had

    read

    Theophrastus

    in

    I697 (Tale,

    pp.

    lvi-lvii).

    "

    The

    tradition

    of the Theophrastan

    character

    had

    for

    Swift's

    age

    defined

    moral

    types;

    the

    drama

    had

    created

    its

    humor

    characters

    and

    given

    them

    the

    further

    trappings

    of

    a social

    position

    " (Martin

    Price,

    Swift's

    Rhetorical

    Art,

    p.

    63).

    For Swift's own repeateduse of the satiric,ad hominem character,

    1710-1714,

    see

    Richard

    I. Cook,

    "

    Swift's

    Polemical

    Characters,"

    Discourse,

    VI

    (Winter

    I962-3),

    30-48.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    17/21

    792

    Swift'sKnavesand Foolsin the Tradition

    and

    the defect

    of credulity

    xactly

    as

    Aristotle

    ad understoodlhem-

    as defections

    rom

    Temperance

    ndintellectual

    Prudence.

    Surely,

    oo,

    the reader

    amiliar

    with

    the Tale

    of

    a

    Tub

    will

    have

    observed

    the

    similarity

    between

    Swift's digressive

    narrator

    and

    Hobbes'

    wondering,

    urious

    wit

    who

    loses

    himself

    within

    a series

    of

    parentheses.42

    he

    readerwill

    also

    have noted

    the similarity

    n

    sub-

    ject

    matter

    and language

    between

    Swift's

    Modern

    speaker

    and

    the

    curiousand credulous haractersf the tradition:he discussion f

    "the

    skime

    "

    of the

    curious

    man'sbrain,

    which tends

    to

    "

    boile

    into

    the

    broth";

    43

    their

    joint

    interest

    in

    "Homer's

    Iliads

    in a Nutshel

    ";

    44

    their

    proud

    penchant

    or asking

    "morequestions

    n

    an houre

    han

    the

    seven

    Wise

    men could

    resolve

    n

    sevenyeeres

    ;

    45

    their

    devotion

    o

    "

    Studyupon

    Things

    that are

    never

    to be

    known

    ",

    6

    their

    fondness

    for propagating

    iddles,

    their addiction

    o astrology,

    heir

    suscepti-

    bility

    to vapors.

    Like these seventeenth-century

    haracters,

    wift's

    ModernsoveMysteries, ashions,

    nd

    dissenting

    Cloaths

    ;

    delight

    in " Hieroglyphics,"

    n

    Alchemy

    and

    the

    "

    Philosopher's

    tone."

    Swift

    knew

    well these

    traditions

    mocking redulity

    ndcuriosity.

    2

    Just

    as

    Hobbes'

    digressive

    man departs

    from his

    discourse

    into a parenthesis,

    and from

    that

    into

    another,

    until

    he lose himself,

    so

    the Tale's

    Modem-no

    mean

    digressor

    by

    any standard-claims

    that

    " I

    have

    known

    some

    Authors

    inclose

    Digres-

    sions

    in

    one

    another,

    like

    a Nest

    of

    Boxes." (Tale,

    p.

    I24).

    43

    "

    There

    is a

    Brain

    that

    will

    endure

    but one

    Scumming:

    Let

    the Owner

    gather

    it with

    Discretion,

    and

    manage

    his little

    Stock

    with

    Husbandry;

    but

    of

    all

    things,

    let

    him

    beware

    of

    bringing

    it under

    the Lash of

    his

    Betters; because,

    That

    will

    make it all bubble up into Impertinence,and he will find no new Supply: Wit,

    without

    knowledge,

    being

    a

    Sort of

    Cream,

    which

    gathers

    in

    a

    Night

    to

    the

    Top,

    and by

    a

    skilful

    Hand,

    may

    be soon whipt

    into Froth;

    but once

    scumm'd

    away,

    what

    appears

    underneath

    will

    be

    fit

    for

    nothing,

    but to

    be

    thrown

    to

    the

    Hogs"

    ("

    The

    Battel

    of the

    Books,"

    Tale, pp.

    215-6).

    44

    "I HAVE

    sometimes

    heard

    of

    an

    Iliad

    in

    a

    Nut-shell;

    but it bath

    been

    mv

    Fortune

    to

    have

    much

    oftener

    seen a

    Nut-shell

    in

    an

    Iliad"

    (Tale,

    p.

    I43).

    45

    "

    It were

    much

    to

    be

    wisht,

    and

    I do

    here humbly propose

    for an

    Experiment,

    that

    every

    Prince

    in Christendomt

    will

    take

    seven

    of

    the

    deepest

    Scholars

    in his

    Dominions,

    and

    shut

    them up

    close for

    seven Years,

    in

    seven

    Chambers,

    with

    a

    Command

    to

    write

    seven ample

    Commentaries

    on this comprehensive

    Discourse3

    (Tale,

    p.

    I

    85).

    4"

    The typical "curious" schemer in Philosophy, according to the Modern

    persona,

    takes

    it into

    his

    Head

    "

    to

    advance

    new

    Systems

    with

    such

    an

    eager

    Zeal, in

    things

    agreed

    on all

    hands

    impossible

    o

    be

    known." (Tale,

    p.

    I66).

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    18/21

    John R. Clark 793

    Swift knew

    these traditionswell. But Swift's

    Modem teller of

    the

    Tale

    understands

    no such thing: all finely

    unaware, the

    persona

    argues that a mere "mobility of

    spirits" causes madness in

    both

    curious and

    credulous men. In a handsome

    anti-climax that enjoys

    developing the images of ghosts

    haunting an empty manse, Swift's

    Modern, full of

    singularity,contradicts he age-old

    classical

    tradition

    of

    excess and

    defect, arguing that the two

    deviations from prudence

    are

    the same. In

    his own private System, he

    deduces that

    every Species

    [of

    Madness] proceeds from a Redundancy

    of Vapour.... Now,

    it

    usually happens, that these active

    Spirits, getting Possession of the Brain,

    re-

    semble those that

    haunt waste and

    empty Dwellings, which for want of

    Business,

    either

    vanish, and

    carry away a Piece of the House, or else

    stay at home and

    fling

    it all

    out of the

    Windows. By which are mystically

    display'd the two

    principal

    Branches of Madness,

    and which some Philosophers not

    considering so well as

    I,

    have

    mistook

    to be different in their

    Causes, overhastily assigning

    the first

    to

    Deficiency, and the other to Redundance.

    (174)

    In

    this passage, although the

    Modem persona

    himself is unable to

    recognize

    it,

    we encounter precise examples of excess and of defect

    from

    that virtue which would

    adhere to the "common forms."

    In

    the

    modem

    world, credulous and curious men

    alike deviate

    from

    nature,

    from

    normalcy.

    On

    the one hand, in religion,

    politics, and deductive

    philosophy,

    those

    men adhering to "credulity"

    are governed

    by private

    visions

    of the

    moment: their projectsand

    dreams are, for

    them, Reality;

    and

    they ultimately recommend

    actions and attempt to win proselytes

    only to prove themselves. They

    have no sense whatever of

    a

    larger

    responsibility o the State, to Ethics, to God or to Man. They simply

    begin and end their

    motions in themselves. The

    project

    to

    free mad-

    men

    from Bedlam

    n the Tale'sSectionIX (I

    74-9)

    is

    but a

    bright

    central

    signal of the

    irresponsibilityof the credulous man's personal

    notions,

    a

    sign of the threat

    such men constitute

    to

    organized

    society,

    religion, and

    learning. Like Anne

    Hutchinson and the

    Antinomians

    of

    America, they

    are solipsists,

    relying for candlepowerupon

    a

    single,

    private

    "

    inner light."

    On

    the

    other hand, the curious man, the

    antomist or

    virtuoso

    who

    plumbs the depths of all things, likewise seeks a personal pleasure:

    he is

    the

    Cartesian

    observer,who

    satisfies

    himself

    about the world

    by

    measuring

    it

    from

    his own single

    point

    of

    view,

    from within

    the

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    19/21

    794 Swift's Knaves and Fools in the Tradition

    confines of a

    crampedcranium. That

    he is

    ultimately

    depressedand

    deluded

    by his practice is because a

    thoroughgoingmaterialismwill

    ultimately exclude

    the observer

    himself: there will be

    remaining

    only atoms and

    void-and nothing, quite, can ever be

    induced from

    these.47

    Both groups-credulous and

    curious-if they did

    not function

    privately,individually, and in

    isolation,

    would experience in a more

    unified society "a mighty Level in the Felicity and Enjoyments of

    Mortal

    Men"

    (172).

    But Renaissance ndividualismat its

    extremity

    leads to a terrible

    and isolating

    Subjectivism,

    whether

    it be tlle

    "

    credulity" of Cartesian egoism, the

    naivete

    of fanatic

    enthusiasm's

    mysterious

    beliefs,

    the gullible idealismof Hobbesian

    absolute mon-

    archy,

    the

    utopianismof the

    Roundhead Commonwealth;

    or whether

    it be

    the

    "curiosity"

    of Epicurean

    atomism and effete pleasure-seek-

    ing,

    the

    investigatingitch of alclhemists

    and Royal Society scientists,

    the

    historicaland

    rational

    investigationsof deistic theologians.

    However, it is not simply, as Kathleen Williams urges, that Swift

    would exhort

    us to

    steer

    betwveen redulity and curiosity,

    as

    between

    some

    Scylla and

    Charybdisof the mind, to a utopian-or an

    Anglican

    -compromise.48 For, in an amusing

    way, the Modern

    persona is

    this

    once

    quite

    correct

    in

    his postulates: he is certainly right that

    bothl

    types hiave t

    in common that they are

    abnormal-deviationsfrom

    the

    norm of moral

    virtue. At their

    very heart,

    both the

    credulous

    and

    the

    curious man function

    alike-dependent upon

    a basic

    subjectivism

    and

    selfishness that

    spreads

    both

    in the

    mind

    and

    in the state

    like a

    stain.

    This is why the phrases, "for the Universal Improvementof Man-

    kind" (i) and

    for "the

    good

    of my

    Country" (96),

    both

    of tllem

    frequently repeated throughout the

    Tale

    of

    a

    Tub,

    are

    so

    patently

    ridiculous.

    Credulous and curious

    mcn alike are

    ignorant,

    and

    what

    tlheyT

    gnore

    is

    precisely that social and moral sense of

    responsibility

    o

    4"This point is

    made by

    Alfred

    North

    Whitehead,

    Science and

    the

    Modern

    World

    (New York,

    I948), pp. 44-5:

    acceptance of Cartesiandualism

    of Mind and

    Matter even

    eliminates

    the

    possibility

    of induction.

    48

    Kathleen

    Williams, Jonathaan Swift and

    the Age of

    Compromise

    (Lawrence,

    Kansas,

    I958),

    p.

    I34.

    Miss XVilliamspostulates that Swift endorsesa "mean"'

    everywhere n his writing and

    thinking; in

    Section

    IX

    the mean is

    between Reason

    and Passion.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    20/21

    John R. Clark 795

    something

    outside

    themselves

    embodied

    n

    the more

    classic

    view

    of man.

    What weight of

    ancient

    witness

    can prevail,

    If

    private

    reason

    hold

    the

    public

    scale?

    "

    What, indeed?

    The modem

    eccentrics

    are

    utterly

    devoid

    of

    virtue,

    of

    thought,

    of

    action,

    of patriotism,

    and of

    a

    sense of

    civic duty;

    not

    for

    them the

    ancient

    maxim,

    "

    Salus

    populi suprema

    est

    lex

    ";50

    neither do they heed traditionalconcepts of sophrosyne,of balance,

    of

    ideal

    harmony.

    Nor are

    they

    controlled

    by

    the most

    elementary

    Prudence, a

    prudence

    that, Aristotle

    believed,

    "calculate[s]

    well

    with

    a view

    to

    attaining

    some particular

    end

    of value."

    1

    Instead,

    both credulous

    and

    curious

    men

    live for

    the

    present

    moment,

    concerned

    with yesterday's

    dissection

    or

    with this

    morning's

    trope or

    the midday

    vision;

    for both,

    immediate

    and

    unweighed

    ex-

    perience

    takes

    precedence

    over

    all

    the traditions

    of

    the

    past-of

    history,

    of custom,

    of Scripture.

    Nevertheless, despite the brotherhoodof credulityand curiosityin

    so many

    ways,

    these two

    still

    remain

    isolated,

    the poles

    of Cartesian

    dualism:

    mind and

    matter.

    Descartes' famous

    "

    Cogito,

    ergo

    sumn"

    in

    the seventeenth

    century

    had isolated

    at a stroke

    the

    observer

    from

    the

    observation,

    res

    cogitans

    from

    res extensa,

    the

    perceiving

    subject

    from

    the external

    object.

    The

    result

    in

    philosophy

    was

    to

    allow,

    and

    eventually

    to

    insist

    upon,

    man's inability

    accurately

    to observe

    an

    "outside" world

    (if

    there be

    one)-ultimately

    isolating

    one

    from

    another

    the Cartesian

    Egoist

    and the Mechanical

    World,

    just

    as

    Swift's credulous egoist is divorcedfrom curiousscientist.

    The

    mind

    kicked

    out-of-doors

    nto the enormous

    bin of

    quanta,

    of

    mass,

    and of

    motion;

    the mind

    turned

    inward

    upon

    itself and

    left

    alone,

    allowed,

    like the

    cannibal,

    to

    feed-these

    directions

    are

    truly

    what

    have

    given

    the brain,

    in the latter

    end of

    the

    seventeenth

    "9

    Dryden,

    "The

    Hind

    and

    the Panther,"

    Pt.

    I,

    lines

    62-3.

    5'

    Cicero,

    Le

    Legibus

    III. iii.

    8.

    Man's

    duties

    should

    direct

    him outside

    himself,

    away

    from solipsism,

    and

    toward

    that

    humanistic goal

    of

    becoming

    that

    "civem

    totius

    mundi quasi

    unius

    urbis" (De

    Legibus

    I. xxiii).

    Following

    Aristotelian

    deals,

    Cicero

    argues

    that

    virtue

    must

    be

    actively

    exercised,

    its

    noblest

    employment

    being

    the

    government

    of

    the

    state (De

    Re

    Publica

    I.

    ii.

    2).

    "

    Nicomachean

    Ethics,

    VI. v. 2, P.

    337.

  • 8/12/2019 TOAT - Section IX, Rhetoric v Poetic - Clark, 1969

    21/21

    796 Swift's Knavesand Fools in the Tradition

    century, ts "unlucky

    shake."Like so many

    ghosts,the humors

    of

    the

    "

    curious

    man utterlyvanish,

    uming

    him outwardn his atten-

    tion, andkickinghis

    mind, as it were, out-of-doors;

    hile the spirits

    of the

    "

    credulous

    man causehim, like the

    Dead in

    Bryant's oem,

    to

    be

    vacantly oothed y an unfaltering

    rust,

    andto wrap he drapery

    of his couch about

    him, and lie

    down to pleasantdreams.

    These, finally,

    are the tacit andsuggestivemeanings

    f the credu-

    lous and the curiousman n theTaleof a Tub'sSection X-tacit and

    suggestive

    ecause

    Swift himselfmakesno

    statement.Rather,Swift

    is artistic,

    dramatic;e has

    createdand shaped he Modern

    persona

    as well

    as the contestbetweencredulity

    nd

    curiosity,

    ike

    little tubs,

    and

    has embarked

    hem

    upon

    their

    own sea of

    dramaticaction.

    Swift

    himselfsustains

    an artisticaloofness, onsistently

    etains

    "aes-

    thetic distance."

    That is the

    important oint

    which

    must

    again

    be

    emphasized:

    n Section

    X

    of

    the

    Tale

    of

    a

    Tub the

    Modern

    persona

    is certainly

    ommitted

    o the defenceof

    credulity

    and

    to the tactiCs

    of rhetoric; utSwiftis not. Swift is notat all the rhetoricaldvocate

    eitherof

    curiosity

    r of

    credulity,

    s a numberof critics eem

    to be-

    lieve. Nor

    is Swift

    the

    idle

    or the confused

    orator,

    easing

    his

    audience

    when

    he shouldhavebeen

    delivering

    irtuousdoctrine.

    As

    artist,rather,

    Swift stands

    well alooffrom the actions

    of the

    drama

    taking place

    upon

    his

    stage.

    New

    York

    University.