11
The Eupsychian Impulse Psychoanalysis and Left politics since '68 Barry Richards My purpose here is to offer some reflections on the part flayed by psychoanalysis in Left politics in Britain since 1968. I will attempt a broad and critical characterisation of the major uses to which psychoanalytic theory has been put in political dis- course during this period. There will be very little in this that readers already familiar with this field will have not read else- where, or concluded for themselves (though they may disagree with my evaluation of those uses). However, I think that the is- sues of political vision involved here are important enough to justify a review of the field, even one as summarily crude as the following. 3 This account is based in part on retrospective research into the publications and activities of this period, and in part on my experience of involvement (since 1974) in work concerned with the problems and challenges posed by psychoanalytic thought for Left politics, and vice versa. Since 1984 my main context for this work has been the journal Free Associations; for about six years before that its primary support was in a 'Freud-Marx' reading group linked to the Radical Science Journal. 4 This inevitably partial experience means that some areas of work are given less detailed attention than others in what follows, but this will detract from my argument only if I . have misrepresented any of the positions discussed. I hope to use personal report illustratively and as an expository con- venience rather than as a substantive basis for argument. It would though be an odd thing if some personal reflection did not have an important place somewhere in any intellectual en- gagement with psychoanalysis. SOME HISTORICAL BACKGROUND The use of psychoanalytic thinking in political philosophy and in analyses of specific political situations dates back to the earliest phase of the psychoanalytic movement The Psychopathology of Everyday Life, published in 1901, was concerned mainly with mundane phenomena in the life of the individual, yet was also a first systematic demonstration by Freud of how psychoanalysis could be used to examine non- clinical domains. The second step in its development as an in- strument for the analysis of political life was its application to collective phenomena in Freud's first sociological essay, "'Civilised" sexual morality and modem nervous illness' (1908). Here Freud argued that the limitation of legitimate sex to monogamy, the product of civilisation's tendency to increas- ing sexual restrictiveness, was probably not worth its costs in increased neurotic misery. In Britain the leading Freudian Ernest Jones was quick to see the potential of psychoanalysis as a framework for political comment In 1915, the year that Freud published 'Thoughts for the times on war and death', Jones also published two papers on war (Jones, 1915a and b), thus initiating in British psychoanalysis a tradition of writing about socio-political mat- ters. Jones himself, Edward Glover and Roger Money-Kyrle were subsequently leading contributors to this tradition, for which war remained a major concern and in which a spectrum of reforming ambitions were represented (see Richards, 1986a, for an account of some of this work). It is in its links with more revolutionary ambitions, however, that psychoanalysis is best known as a contribution to political thought, particularly in the forms of Wilhelm Reich's Freudo- Marxism and the Freudian cultural critique of Herbert Marcuse and other members of the Frankfurt School of 'critical theory'. The writings of the Frankfurt School do not though point one- directionally towards revolutionary politics as the requisite framework for psychoanalytic insights. Also, the work of more recent American writers such as Philip Rieff (1959; 1966) and Christopher Lasch (1979; 1984), linked in some ways to criti- cal theory, has established powerful claims for more liberal and democratic-socialist directions for psychoanalytic cultural theory. In the history of psychoanalysis itself such directions can also be traced; for example in the minor tradition in British psychoanalysis already referred to, and in the Austro-German beginnings of psychoanalysis. Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con- tributions to political Freudianism of Otto Fenichal and others 3

The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    1

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

The Eupsychian Impulse Psychoanalysis and Left politics since '68

Barry Richards

My purpose here is to offer some reflections on the part flayed by psychoanalysis in Left politics in Britain since 1968. I will attempt a broad and critical characterisation of the major uses to which psychoanalytic theory has been put in political dis­course during this period. There will be very little in this that readers already familiar with this field will have not read else­where, or concluded for themselves (though they may disagree with my evaluation of those uses). However, I think that the is­sues of political vision involved here are important enough to justify a review of the field, even one as summarily crude as the following. 3

This account is based in part on retrospective research into the publications and activities of this period, and in part on my experience of involvement (since 1974) in work concerned with the problems and challenges posed by psychoanalytic thought for Left politics, and vice versa. Since 1984 my main context for this work has been the journal Free Associations; for about six years before that its primary support was in a 'Freud-Marx' reading group linked to the Radical Science Journal.4 This inevitably partial experience means that some areas of work are given less detailed attention than others in what follows, but this will detract from my argument only if I

. have misrepresented any of the positions discussed. I hope to use personal report illustratively and as an expository con­venience rather than as a substantive basis for argument. It would though be an odd thing if some personal reflection did not have an important place somewhere in any intellectual en­gagement with psychoanalysis.

SOME HISTORICAL BACKGROUND

The use of psychoanalytic thinking in political philosophy and in analyses of specific political situations dates back to the earliest phase of the psychoanalytic movement The Psychopathology of Everyday Life, published in 1901, was concerned mainly with mundane phenomena in the life of the individual, yet was also a first systematic demonstration by Freud of how psychoanalysis could be used to examine non­clinical domains. The second step in its development as an in­strument for the analysis of political life was its application to collective phenomena in Freud's first sociological essay, "'Civilised" sexual morality and modem nervous illness' (1908). Here Freud argued that the limitation of legitimate sex to monogamy, the product of civilisation's tendency to increas­ing sexual restrictiveness, was probably not worth its costs in increased neurotic misery.

In Britain the leading Freudian Ernest Jones was quick to see the potential of psychoanalysis as a framework for political

comment In 1915, the year that Freud published 'Thoughts for the times on war and death', Jones also published two papers on war (Jones, 1915a and b), thus initiating in British psychoanalysis a tradition of writing about socio-political mat­ters. Jones himself, Edward Glover and Roger Money-Kyrle were subsequently leading contributors to this tradition, for which war remained a major concern and in which a spectrum of reforming ambitions were represented (see Richards, 1986a, for an account of some of this work).

It is in its links with more revolutionary ambitions, however, that psychoanalysis is best known as a contribution to political thought, particularly in the forms of Wilhelm Reich's Freudo­Marxism and the Freudian cultural critique of Herbert Marcuse and other members of the Frankfurt School of 'critical theory'. The writings of the Frankfurt School do not though point one­directionally towards revolutionary politics as the requisite framework for psychoanalytic insights. Also, the work of more recent American writers such as Philip Rieff (1959; 1966) and Christopher Lasch (1979; 1984), linked in some ways to criti­cal theory, has established powerful claims for more liberal and democratic-socialist directions for psychoanalytic cultural theory. In the history of psychoanalysis itself such directions can also be traced; for example in the minor tradition in British psychoanalysis already referred to, and in the Austro-German beginnings of psychoanalysis. Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con­tributions to political Freudianism of Otto Fenichal and others

3

Page 2: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

from the end of the First World War to the 1950s, and indicate the variety of socialist and communist, revolutionary and reformist politics with which the development of psychoanalysis was closely interwoven until the Second World War.

This evidence of the diversity of political perspectives with which psychoanalysis has been associated should make clear the inadequacy of any dichotomisation between 'revolutionary' and 'reactionary' applications of psychoanalysis in political thought. A substantial amount of Left intellectual effort has been expended within the terms of this dichotomy, usually in order to recruit Freud, despite himself, from the side of reaction to that of revolution. This effort has been comparable to the Marxist inversion of Hegel in order for his insight into histori­cal change to be of service to revolutionary politics. While Hegel had to be transposed from idealism to materialism, Freud has had to be removed from the pulpit of ahistorical bourgeous fatalism and repositioned at the barricades such that his mes­sage reads not downwards as a ruling class prescription dis­guised as natural law, but upwards as a demand for libidinal freedom or the recognition of desire.5 The notion that psychoanalysis is essentially 'ambivalent' (lngleby, 1984) im­proves upon the seizure of its essence for one side of the other, but still does not reflect the complexity of its political meanings.

WHY PSYCHOANALYSIS?

In the early 1960s some paths which could have led towards psychoanalysis were struck by some on the emergent New Left, notably Ronald Laing and David Cooper in early articles in New Left Review. However, it is since 1968 that increasing numbers of people who would identify themselves as of the radical Left have turned towards psychoanalysis, or have sought to bring together in some way what might otherwise have been their disconnected or divergent interests in socialism and psychoanalysis. Two simple, apparently competing ex­planations for this development suggest themselves. One is that there was something, in the cluster of political, cultural and philosophical forces which have been identified as comprising the 'moment of 68', which prescribed or pointed towards a political appropriation of psychoanalysis. The other is that the turn to psychoanalysis was a post-'68 phenomenon, part of a reaction to an experience of the failure of the millenarian ideals of 'May 68'. An analogy here would be with the reasons for Herbert Marcuse and others becoming interested in psychoanalysis in the 1930s, in response particularly to the ex­perience of what seemed to be the corruption of the revolution

4

in Russia, and of mass support for fascism in Germany. If suc­cessful revolutions were so difficult to achieve, then perhaps there were deep intrapsychic impediments to them which needed to be understood and which psychoanalysis could il­luminate.

In other words the turn to psychoanalysis can be seen as either positively or negatively produced by '68, as a direct development of it or as part of the attempt by a new New Left, sadder and wiser, to make a fresh start in the aftermath of '68. I will argue that in general the first of these explanations provides the more basic truth, though it is importantly qualified by the truth, at a certain level, of the second.

I will first of all consider two very different kinds of pos­sible reasons for intellectuals (of any political stripe) to turn towards psychoanalysis.

PERSONAL EXPERIENCE OF PSYCHOANALYTIC THERAPY

In many cases the decision to enter psychoanalytic therapy, as opposed to seeking some other form of therapy or eschewing all expert help, is determined by a pre-established familiarity with and sympathy for psychoanalytic discourse. However, there may well be some people for whom the experience of therapy came first, and was followed by an interest in psychoanalysis as a theory and as an input to politics. My own impression is that such people are few, which is not surprising given the relatively small and circumscribed scale of psychoanalytic practice in Britain, and the tendency for patients to be already familiar with some ideas about psychoanalysis.

Whether for any particular individual the experience of therapy is the cart or the horse, it is clear that therapy and politics can become intertwined in the lives of some in­dividuals, such that the work of therapy (whether as therapist or patient) becomes experienced as part of a political life­project (though probably in some tension with other, more conventionally political, parts of that project). The growth of 'feminist therapy' is the most important example of this phenomenon, but this takes us largely beyond the sphere of psychoanalytic work, within which it is not usual to recognise such a sociologically-defined specialism. Within psycho­analytic work, the only distinctions which can be recognised are those which depend on what the analyst or therapist brings (in theoretical orientation, personal technique) or on the clini­cal context (e.g. whether long- or short-term work is planned, what the institutional setting is). Otherwise, each patient is uni­que, and the socio-political categories within which the patient lives (and the therapist), and the belief-systems with which the patient may try to interrogate the therapist or the therapy, are basically material for the analytic work of interpretation.

Thus at least in the case of orthodox psychoanalytic prac­tices, there is a considerable distance between the experience of analytic therapy, and the political project of engaging with psychoanalytic insights and their implications for understand­ing society. In those few cases where there is some direct and major initiation of an intellectual/political interest by therapeutic experience, it is likely to be in a non-specific way, in that, for example, a helpful therapy may establish psychoanalysis in the mind of the patient as a good thing, a tradition to be regarded with respect.

In his sustained analysis of the relationship between his clinical work as a psychoanalyst and his political commitment as a Marxist (and psychoanalytical) intellectual, the American writer Joel Kovel (1981; 1984; forthcoming) presents an un-

l

Page 3: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

J

J

resolved contradiction, in which the problem is not one of mere distance but one of disjunction: 'Psychoanalysis is a practice which belongs to bourgeois experience in late-capitalist urban society' (1984, p. 152). 'Perhaps someone else will be able to figure out how to do an authentically proletarian psychoanalysis. I can't' (ibid.).

One need not share Kovel's historical judgement on psychoanalysis to concur in his practical judgement that psychoanalytic therapy and political work are at the least sepa­rate spheres, and may in some way be incommensurable or immiscible. We can take his failure to synthesise his clinical work with his politics to be definitive, and not only for the Marxist position which Kovel represents. In my own case the experience of a (Kleinian) analysis was itself a very important factor in bringing about a shift of outlook, from viewing the world in the totalised terms of a Marxism tending towards the monolithic, to a more pluralistic conception of the- autonomy, within historical contexts, of specific social practices. Here in the session, and in the analytic process as a whole, was an in­stance in which the primacy of the conflict between class inter­ests clearly did not obtain. A practical struggle about being honest with oneself has little to do, for practical purposes, with class struggle (though it may be possible to describe some of its phases in terms of their mediations through class, gender and other social-structural relations). In the intensity of its refusal to become preoccupied with the 'real event' , psychoanalysis may be more easily the vehicle for such a change of outlook than would other less reclusive practices, but its autonomy is not of a fundamentally unique kind, being based as it is on a technical procedure, more or less rigorously adhered to.

I am not claiming the complete autonomy of technique from social context (that would indeed be a volte face for someone once active in a collective one of whose slogans was 'Science is social relations'); my point is rather that psychoanalytic therapy has a technical interior which, though historically produced and not fully insulated, has a large degree of discursive autonomy from its currently prevailing political exterior. This point helps to explain the generally low participa­tion of psychoanalytic therapists in the public domain, not­withstanding their spontaneous political sympathies (Richards, 1986b). It will also hopefully clarify that the personal change of outlook to which I referred above was not the result of my becoming imbued with a radical-Kleinian doctrine of the pure endogeneity of unconscious phantasy, since specific theoretical positions of that sort are not necessary to establish the technical specificity of psychoanalysis as an interpretive exploration of personal meaning and self-deception.

At the same time I do not want to imply that psychoanalytic experience has no relation to politics; a particular school of clinical work may dispose its participants more towards some political concerns, and less to others. Also, my self-example above illustrates how the acquisition of a particular political conception-of the practical autonomy of social spheres--was facilitated by analytic experience. Moreover I subscribe to the complaint that one of the most serious weaknesses in much of the discussion about psychoanalysis in political theory is that it is cut off from clinical work, and from the major developments in psychoanalytic theory which are-in the empirical, though not unproblematically so, nature of psychoanalysis-closely tied to the clinical literature. While radical theorists have been re-arranging some earlier Freudian concepts, freezing them at one stage or another in the process of their formation and change, many actual psychoanalysts have been transforming the theory in practical contexts. It is only in some areas of the

interchange between feminism and psychoanalysis that clinical experience (which is not necessarily understood by those in­volved in it as 'feminist therapy')--has been at the heart of the theoretical effort, as evidenced by the recent collection of es­says from the Women's Therapy Centre (Ernst and Maguire, 1987).

Overall, then, some personal experience of psychoanalysis, and strong links between the communities of clinicians and of intellectuals, are prerequisites, or at least very desirable con­ditions, for interesting and useful work on psychoanalysis and politics. Yet the clinical and political domains are fundamen­tally distinct, and simple, direct movement from one to the other is not on the whole possible.

THE SEARCH FOR A PHll..OSOPIDCALLY SATISFACTORY PSYCHOLOGY

Philosophical debate about psychoanalysis has tended to be mainly in the philosophy of science, which is perhaps symptomatic of the general cultural response of marginalising the substantive and moral questions raised by psychoanalysis. Nonetheless, the debate about scientificity has provided for some people an approach to psychoanalysis. For myself, an at­tachment to a particularly scientistic form of Marxism­Leninism, which persisted until the mid-1970s, meant that I was looking for scientific truth, and hoped to find that psychoanalysis was epistemologically more sophisticated and sound than other schools of psychology, trapped as they were in empiricism and positivism. (It was of course very helpful in this that the judgement of bourgeois philosophy on psychoanalysis was in general so damning.) Accordingly I at­tached great importance to the advocacies of psychoanalysis found in the Left scientism of Louis Althusser (1965) and the feminist scientism of Juliet Mitchell in 1974. A little later I found that the realist philosophy of Rom Harre (1974; 1977) and Roy Bhaskar (1975) expanded and improved the philosophical armamentarium with which to instal and defend psychoanalysis in the citadel of science.6

However, this kind of philosophical preference can serve only as a rationalisation obscuring other reasons for turning to psychoanalysis, or as the basis for an empty and formalistic approach to it. I had already become interested (through ex­periences in training as a clinical psychologist) in varieties of psychoanalysis (the Kleinian and object-relational schools) which are very little troubled by the question of scientificity. They occasionally advance a claim to a particular scientific method (e.g. in Harry Guntrip's formulation of what a 'psychodynamic science' should look like7

), but on the whole they are notable more as expressions of a certain kind of psychological humanism. By this I mean that they tend to stress elements of human need and feeling which for most prac­tical purposes can be regarded as universals; that they see the individual subject as a basic entity, as potentially coherent and as a moral agent; and that they at least implicitly support the notion that the most fundamental kind of discourse is moral.

Of course none of these features is necessarily incompatible with some kind of concern with scientificity. However, there is an important difference of emphasis, and the compassionate understanding and emotional truth of this humanism came to seem of greater value for me than the search for scientific truth, notwithstanding the tendency of some object-relations writers particularly to slip into somewhat sentimental and rhetorical styles of humanism, in which the individual or Self is naturalised and elevated into an absolute principle, rather in the manner of Rogerian 'humanistic psychology'.

5

Page 4: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

Moreover, despite the growing interest in realism, the issue of scientificity has now lost some of.the topicality it had on the Left in the 1970s, insofar as that was generated by the Althus­serian influence. Work on a number of fronts continues, however, and the characterisation of psychoanalytic method and epistemology remains an important task. The consideration of psychoanalysis in terms of realist theory has been carried forward by David Will (1980; 1986), Andrew Collier (1981) and Michael Rustin (1987). An explicitly humanistic perspec­tive, proposing biography as the core discipline of psychoanalytic human science, has been put forward by Robert Young (1986; 1987). And while the Althusserian flame may have flickered, the torch of Lacanianism which it helped to light continued to burn quite fiercely, such that from some viewpoints one of the main commendations of psychoanalysis is its allegedly anti-humanist theory of the subject, or its claimed potential for circumventing the humanism/anti­humanism debate (Henriques et al, 1984).

One other bridge from philosophy into psychoanalysis must also be mentioned, since it is part of a body of work which has been steadily gaining influence since 1968. This is the work of J urgen Habermas, who in fact provides the most explicit and elaborated model for a philosophical appropriation of psychoanalysis. Habermas (1968; see also McCarthy, 1978) proposes that psychoanalysis is the only example of an eman­cipatory, self-reflective science, or rather that it is once shorn of Freud's theory of biological instincts, a physicalistic misun­derstanding by Freud of his own discoveries. Russell Keat (1981) provides a critical discu~ion of Habermas' use of psychoanalysis, arguing that he departs from Freud in ways other than those which he announces. Joel Whitebook (1985) makes a similar criticism of the neglect of the body by Haber­mas, whose 'etherealised' picture (Keat) of the psyche, in which the unconscious functions only as the source of distor­tions of communication, is certainly far removed from the pic~ tures of mental life found in British psychoanalysis (and, in a different way, from the Lacanian picture). This may partly ac­count for the lack of impact here of his reading of Freud Despite the interest in his work as a whole, it has not been a springboard for a wider engagement with psychoanalysis.

THE MULTIVALENCE OF PSYCHOANALYSIS

Thus neither personal experience of therapy, nor philosophical commitments, are in themselves likely to provide much of a basis for a political appropriation of psychoanalysis, and if for particular individuals they are important factors then they may each be linked with one of a number of very different kinds of psychoanalytic politics. This was the conclusion drawn from the brief historical background sketch given earlier, namely that psychoanalysis is available to diverse and often quite divergent political appropriations. There is a notional common element in all these appropriations, which is some kind of stress on unconscious interiority. Mitchell (1974), however, ar­gued persuasively that in the cases of Reich and Laing no real conceptual commonality with Freud existed, since the genuinely interior, unconscious and psychological dimensions were lacking in the work of the more 'political' thinkers. Jacoby (1975) offers a somewhat similar critique of the Ad­lerians, neo-Freudians and ego-psychologists as well as the Laingians. Even if this commonality is not regarded as superfi­cial, it is very secondary in political terms. What can be the political significance and value of a concept of 'the uncons­cious' if it can be inserted with equal conviction into both his­torical materialism (e.g. Schneider, 1973; Lichbnan, 1982) and

6

classical liberalism (e.g. Badcock, forthcoming)? This is actually the wrong question, although it is based on

a fact which must be observed, namely that psychoanalysis does not bear with it a stable set of political values which act as a constant factor in different combinations with other intellec­tual elements. It does not follow from this though that it has no political effectivity; although it has no general political impact, it is at least potentially important in the specific contributions it makes to particular political outlooks, in the ways it may ex­tend, inflect or enrich them.

These contributions are not a matter of logical affinities between abstract forms of discourse (e.g. the question of the philosophical compatibility, or otherwise, of psychoanalysis and Marxism) but of whether there are the people around able and willing to do the intellectual work required to establish cooperative relationships between psychoanalytic thinking and any particular kind(s) of political perspective (e.g. the question of whether sufficient philosophers are interested in establishing the compatibility of psychoanalysis and Marxism). In other words, the political value of psychoanalysis is a historical, con­junctural matter, its content and impact open to negotiation between contending social forces. Of course" the particular forms of psychoanalysis may lend themselves more easily to certain kinds of appropriation, and some political traditions may be hostile to all forms of psychological thought, but these limits are very broad ones, and even quite well-defined schools of psychoanalysis have been claimed by very different political interests. 8

The right question to ask is therefore an empirical one: what has been the political significance of psychoanalysis in those theoretical appropriations of it which have been made?

There are, I suggest, three very broad problematics or political agenda from which people have sallied forth to lay hands on psychoanalytic theory. They are distinct and will to some extent be discussed separately, though the main argument advanced here is that at an important level they draw upon a common source, psychodynamically and ideologically. Empiri­cally, they have no doubt been frequently associated with each other in individuals' political outlooks. For each I will suggest an alternative (and in my view, preferable) reading of psychoanalysis.

FEMINISM

The feminist interest in psychoanalysis has been one of the main reasons for its coming to be placed on the agendas of the Left. This interest, to the extent that it has been a positive one, was at first mainly in psychoanalysis as an instrument for the critique of patriarchy and for the promotion of anti-familism. Work here was mainly around the classical Freudian texts, and was usually either part of the Lacanian 'return to Freud' (see below) or was seen to involve an inversion of Freud similar to

L

Page 5: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

that described above, though here the emphasis was on Freud­the-patriarch rather than Freud-the-bourgeois (if such a distinc­tion were recognised). Partly through the influence of Kleinian and object-relational ideas, the feminist critique of gender dif­ference shifted its focus to mothering and to the gendered divi­sion of labour in child-care (Dinnerstein, 1976; Chodorow, 1978), developing a highly influential rationale for the aboli­tion of that division as the key to the general subversion of gender identity and the overthrow of patriarchal power.

For almost everyone, the first Other is a woman. In Din­nerstein's view, influenced by Klein, the infant's first ex­periences of the Other necessarily bring terrifying intimations of its separate individuality and mortality. As a defence against this, the realm of sensuous experience embodied by the (m)other is rejected in favour of rational worldly activity. Hence the splits between heart and head, feeling and reason, private and public. Woman is continually invested and reinves­ted with the first half of each of these splits, and man with the second, so that both gender identities are dangerously im­poverished and fearful. Chodorow's thesis is similar, but stres­ses the mother's different cathexes of boys and girls. Daughters are more narcissistically identified with, while sons are related to as different others. Thus boys are driven back into a harsh separateness in which they cannot adequately feel with or for others; girls are unable to differentiate themselves sufficiently and to transcend their pre-Oedipal mother-love.

It was in these forms that the feminist appropriation of psychoanalysis was, for a period around the end of the 1970s, a major influence upon many of us interested in the political meanings of psychoanalysis. However, these ideas, despite their still current dominance on the Left and their popularity beyond, have been subjected to powerful criticism. For exam­ple, Jean Elshtain (1984) found these uses of psychoanalysis to be schematic and prescriptive, while a paper by Jane Temper­ley (1984) showed that a more thoroughgoing engagement with Kleinian theory can see specific patterns of early psychic development, not intrinsic to the general structure of heterosexually-differentiated parenting, as major sources of the damage represented by adult 'femininity', or rather by par­ticular organisations of femininity. (And it might be said that the clinical literature has always been replete with evidence that this is the case for 'masculinity'.) Thus some alternative positions are being articulated, linked to wider and more sym­pathetic re-evaluations of gender difference, and more concer­ned with clinically-observed qualities of parenting than with abstract notions of patriarchal power. In many readings of it, psychoanalysis teaches that gender is the most fundamental dimension of identity, and that a model of cooperative com­plementarity, based on good relations between the sexes, can be posited as an ideal for human relations generally.

'THE PERSONAL IS POLITICAL'

The hope that the theory of the unconscious could provide a deeper and more truthful version of this statement was at the heart of much of the feminist involvement in psychoanalysis, and was also a crucial element in the motives of those coming from other, though overlapping, political directions. Earlier versions of the persona1/political equation had tended to col­lapse the personal into the political, but as time went by it be­came clear that this would not do. Working in the mental health field I was unavoidably impressed by the inaccessibility of per­sonal madness to political analysis, let alone to political inter­vention, as long as one worked only with a rationalistic psychology of 'environment', 'stress' and other similar con-

cepts. Psychoanalysis was thought to promise to deliver the mediations; the concepts of internalisation, introjection and identification, for example, seemed to offer a vocabulary for talking about the political and historical constitution of our in­ner worlds. The concept of the unconscious was the key to a new way of understanding the totality of our social life, in that it could illuminate how the social outside gets into the psychic inside, and vice versa, and provide the most sophisticated ac­count of how the personal and the political are interwoven. The essential unity, beneath our segmented experience, of all op­pressive structures, and of personal and political domains, is implied by this view, which thereby is a point of convergence of an otherwise disparate set of libertarian, (post-)structuralist and critical theory perspectives.

However, this project from the start was in a deep tension with itself. The attraction of psychoanalysis was that it provided the most radically personal and internal account of subjectivity, in comparison with which most other theories of personality seemed banal. But for that same reason it was likely to buck the theoretical burden it was being required to carry, whether that was the Marx-Freud synthesis or some other programme of specifying an inner-outer dialectic. Psychoanalysis has a radical disinterest in the external. (I am referring here to its core conceptual range, not to the interest shown, in particular cases, in the significance of external events by individual practitioners, who mayor may not be justly criticised for one-dimensionality.) This leads to several points of tension in the project of totalisation.

One, already discussed above, concerns the relationship of therapeutic experience to the intellectual agenda. Another is related to the theory of narcissism, which has occupied (in my view rightly) a central place in a number of debates during the last decade about the input of psychoanalysis to social theory.9 The equation of the personal and the political may in some con­texts be seen as a narcissistic inflation of the self, consistent with the non-psychoanalytic criticism of the 'personalisation' of politics for which '68' is sometimes held responsible (see, for example, Janice Raymond's critique of 'therapism' and the 'publicisation of personal life' , 1986). Not only may individual misfortune or responsibility be projected out into the public domain, but personal investments in group and sectional inter­ests and demands may lead to their being presented as a

7

Page 6: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

general interest. The third and major difficulty which psychoanalysis

presents for the personal=political formulation stems not from a particular diagnostic category but from the routine and general nature of psychoanalytic discourse. Let us take the ex­ample of domestic violence, and the view that wife-beating is no more nor less than a public, political issue, that of patriarchal violence. This rules out of consideration any specific familial or personal factors, and exploration of how the wider societal dimensions are potentiated into violence in some families and not in others. It empties the particular family of its own emotional content, immobilises those professionals wish­ing to make helpful interventions, and liquidates the personal responsibilities of all those involved for the violence and its consequences. A psychoanalytic approach is necessarily con­cerned with putting all these questions back on the agenda, by examining the psychodynamics of the family as a private, par­tially bounded domain, and seeing the personal and interper­sonal specificity of the situation as crucial to understanding it

In the case of domestic violence, one psychoanalytic hypothesis likely to be of central importance, both in practical understanding and in theorising the personal/political relationship, is that individuals are usually partly responsible for the relationships which they find themselves in. Another hypothesis which, when confirmed, points towards the need for some firm distinction between the private and the public, con­cerns the conditions for trust and intimacy. In psychoanalytic theory, deep emotional attachments are generally seen as form­ing slowly, on the basis of repeated experiences of reciprocity, security and satisfaction. These experiences are available only within a bounded (not necessarily physically so) interpersonal space in which the distinctive qualities of the other, in relation to oneself, can be registered.

It has been a main feature of some of the techniques of humanistic psychology that the persona1/political boundary is breached at just this point The best example is probably the encounter group, introduced to Britain around 1970, in which intimacy and confession are demanded in a semi-public setting of people who may be in contact with each other only for a matter of hours. In other words, intimacy and trust are deman­ded when the conditions for their development-essentially those of longer-term relationships-are absent, and conse­quently the intimate relating which ensues is necessarily in part fake. This at least is a psychoanalytic view, and correspond­ingly it is towards humanistic psychology rather than psychoanalysis that some radicals who have remained commit­ted to a persona1/political fusion have turned (e.g. in the 'despair workshops' undertaken by peace movement ac­tivists).10

Thus, far from showing us how the personal and political are fused, psychoanalysis offers ways of theorising the in­authenticities which result when the public-private distinction is eroded such that neither domain can sustain the forms of relationship appropriate to it-authentic intimacy in the private domain and authentic civility in the public. In this role, which is one that I would now claim for it, psychoanalysis is at odds with simple equations of the personal and political, and instead is in keeping with more pluralistic understandings of where power is located, and whom it oppresses. This is not to jettison the insights gained in the more totalising moment, nor to aban­don the research programmes which we are now only begin­ning to project in, for example, the historicity of subjectivity.ll It is though to introduce a quite different orientation, for which psychoanalysis is of interest to social theory partly because it can inform the argument that the personal sphere not only is

8

but also should be a distinctive segment of social life, and that in general the principle of boundaries and segmentation is a crucial element in good social organisation.

THE REVOLUTIONARY PROGRAMME

The most general feature of the Left-political context within which interest in psychoanalysis took initial shape in 1970s' Britain was the frustration of the aspirations of '68'. For many of us psychoanalysis held the promise of revitalising these aspirations. A major problem with the revolutionary program­mes, it seemed was that they had overlooked the internal resis­tances to social change and to socialism, resistances which psychoanalysis could illuminate. Of course this hope had been entertained before, by Reich, Fromm, Marcuse et al; an impor­tant difference was that we could bring the conceptual gains of more recent developments in psychoanalysis to bear on the problem, and not be shackled by the limitations of classical Freudianistn. Psychoanalysis was the theory which could help to explain why socialism had not yet arrived, and to do so in a way that sustained the belief that when it does it will enable us to transcend the world as we know it. Capitalism is still strong because of its anchorage in inner repression, but if that repres­sion could be undone then an unprecedented condition of psychic fulfilment and harmony would ensue, as part of the so­cial transformation.

This political appropriation of psychoanalysis cannot ac­curately be called utopian, since those who advanced it were generally Marxists for whom the idea of utopia was, at least in theory, impermissible.12 But to borrow-with due irony-a term from the humanist psychologist Abraham Maslow (1965), it might well be called 'eupsychian', since the transcendent condition to which it aspires, though not necessarily one of so­cial perfection, is one of intrapsychic ease, release and satisfac-~a . .

Two major routes to this condition have been mapped out One is via the overthrow of the capitalist State and the undoing of the repression which is the psychic base and effect of its authority-the Reichian route of which Kovel is today's most eloquent advocate. The other is that which leads away from the capitalist market, and leaves behind the psychic splitting which is the consequence of engaging in instrumental exchange relationships with other persons. Erich Fromm (1947) was an early guide to this route, which takes one through the extensive post-Weberian critique of rationality, and is one of the main highways of critical theory. This latter route is sometimes seen

Page 7: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

as leading towards the reestablishment of social authority in a re-moralised world, and may not include a critique of repres­sion, in which case (e.g. Richards, 1984) it would diverge from the more libertarian path of the first. Often, though, the two routes are felt by their would-be travellers to be running in parallel towards the same destination, where the deep psychic organisation of the majority will be different to what it is now.

This is certainly a simplification, though it falls far short of parody. I am referring most obviously to Reichian and some Marcusan doctrines, though I have not indicated the important differences between the two. Whereas Reich's attack on the ego, on 'character' and repression was unremitting, Marcuse sought to salvage 'basic' repression, and his hostility to the ego was historically relative. But there is little argument that Mar­cuse as much as Reich was interested in a wholesale transcen­dence of our current structures of repression.

Traditionally posed against this revolutionary appropriation of Freud is the view that psychoanalysis offers both an analysis of why 'revolution', as theoretically imagined, is impossible, and a diagnostic critique of revolutionary politics and of the personal motives at work in them. In many of its specifics (though not as a general rule) the latter has been welcomed by the psychoanalytic Left (indeed, has sometimes been seen as the major contribution psychoanalysis has to make), but the former, understandably, has not. Yet this kind of selectivity is hard to maintain, since the two anti-revolutionary arguments are linked. The theory of the post-revolutionary society is simply an intellectual expression and a flip-side of the same delusions and defences which are active in the paranoid machinations of sectarian politics.

It is not possible here to rehearse the main forms in which this attack on the revolutionary impulse has been put; I will however make mention of a recent exchange in which the two traditional antagonists have once again been tested against each other. In the mid-1970s, when the Left's romance with psychoanalysis was at a peak in France, two analysts working in Paris wrote a book in which they posited a fundamental op­position between Freudian theory and the ideas of Reich, which they rejected not only as anti-psychoanalytic but as exemplify­ing clearly the omnipotence of the revolutionary imagination. Freud or Reich?, by Janine Chasseguet-Smirgel and Bela Grunberger, has recently been published in Britain, and a commentary upon it written by Joel Kovel (1986). Despite the clinical sophistication and intellectual breadth of the com­batants, this exchange demonstrates the limits of this debate as it has been characteristically constructed. Chasseguet-Smirgel and Grunberger combine a clear-headed argument for the in­trinsic anti-utopianism of psychoanalysis, and an analysis of Reich's regressive wish to dissolve the Freudian insistence on conflict, with an outlandish assertion of the endogenously in­dividual roots of social life. Kovel, on the other hand, disposes most effectively with the claim for the primacy of internal fac­tors, but does not respond to the substance of the critique of Reich.

Even Philip Reiff, the most profound expositor of Freud's anti-utopianism, does not provide a fully adequate alternative to the terms of this debate, since in his account the whole ter­rain of politics is at risk of reduction to the search for consola­tion. Nonetheless, to complete the catalogue of shifts in my personal views with which this article has been laced,13 I must now report that psychoanalysis has come to seem to me (in part through my reading of Rieff) primarily to be a doctrine of tragedy and forbearance-to be none the less political for that, but to be opposed (at least in the context of the liberal democracies) to programmes of revolutionary political change.

It is difficult even to allow these programmes the status of in­nocence, since I think we must now admit, to put one aspect of the matter rather crudely, that the impulse to destroy a society is usually a basically destructive impulse, whatever altruistic and reparative motives it may trick into acting alongside it Even where a more benign language of social transformation is used, one which in its imagination of the transformative scenario does not give licence to envious or retributive feelings, then a psychoanalytic scrutiny would still be un­charitable, focussing on the grandiosity and denial of the politi­cal vision.

This is by no means an apolitical counsel of despair. For example, Jeffrey Abramson (1984) makes an interesting at­tempt to proceed from Rieff's exposition towards the recovery from Freudian theOry of a more 'communitarian' vision of psychic development in which the satisfactions of public life play an essential and honourable part. And there are a number of other suggestions in the literature of recent years about the directions which a positive psychoanalytic input to political thought might take.

PURSUING lRANSCENDENCE

All three agendas-the feminist, 'personalist' and revolu­tionary-have in common a wish to transcend some existing set of structures or boundaries. The distinctions between men and women, private and public, libido and action are all under attack-to a great variety of ends, but all sharing in some vision of transcending both oppression and misery. In the Left's use of psychoanalysis, from Adler and Reich on, social justice and individual happiness are characteristically fused together. It is assumed that a single, psychoanalytically-informed political project will necessarily change both inner and outer worlds to the same degree. The construction of a basically non-oppres­sive social order, it is assumed, will result in (or 'Could only be achieved along with) radically different states of mind from those obtaining at present. This eupsychian prescription is most obviously spelt out in revolutionary Freudo-Marxism, as noted earlier, but is also present in the other agendas-in visions of a healing psychological androgyny, and in psychoanalytic con­tributions to the study of the capitalist totality and its 'social reproduction'. The vision of psychic emancipation, as an in­tegral part of social liberation, is as much a part of the scholarly and intricate work of Habermas as it is of sub­Reichian banality.

Eupsychian images of fulfilment, wholeness and happiness therefore underly and unify many of the concerns of the psychoanalytic Left, including and especially the attacks on patriarchy and on repression. The lifting of repression promises to remove not only unnecessary frustration but also the painful experience of being divided against oneself. The ever­provisionally integrated self offered by psychoanalytic therapy is spurned or devalued as mere palliative; the desire for a unified self predominates, and may interact with the desire for an idealised social unity (Alexander, 1984). Any programme for the dissolution of structures of authority and difference in the external world may carry, for its proponents and opponents alike, the unconscious meaning of the dissolution of inner structures and divisions, whether or not such psychic de-dif­ferentiation is explicitly advocated, but in much of the work I have been discussing the transcendence of inner conflicts is of­ten consciously the aim.

I am here suggesting some psychoanalytic reflection upon the psychoanalytic Left and its aims, albeit with due caution and care not to disguise political dismissal as diagnostic in-

9

Page 8: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

sight Chasseguet-Smirgel and Grunberger suggest that under­lying Reich's politics, and any other promises of heaven on earth, is the narcissistic wish for fusion with the ego-ideal. They advance a strong form of the hypothesis that utopian politics are at root an expression of emotional need, by claim­ing that the aim of such politics is the restoration of the ex­perience of narcissistic perfection. One does not have to accept their political judg~ments, nor even their specific psychoanalytical formulation, to take this hypothesis seriously and consider that the eupsychian tone of much radical psychoanalysis may be the product of deeply regressive wishes, and of omnipotent beliefs that the pains of separation and vulnerability can be avoided. Take for example the closing statement of Repression, a book in which Gad Horowitz (1977) argues carefully for a moderation of Marcuse's theory such that the ego and genital primacy are reestablished as indices of health, with re-erotisation and pre-genitality envisoned as deployed within the ego's organisation of libido. Despite these substantial revisions, the wish for transcendence is preserved, to emerge fully in his closing description of the 'communist man' as one for whom 'the pain of separation is no longer ex­perienced as the essence of selfbood' (p. 214).

This can be seen only as wishful thinking when set against the increasingly well-documented post-Freudian conception of selfhood as intrinsically rooted in the pain of separation, though also--crucially-thereby rooted in the satisfactions and compensations that can come from struggling with separate­ness and from building bridges to others. Again, the alternative to transcendental eupsychianism is not necessarily reactionary despair, since the makings of quite optimistic fortitude are to be found in the psychoanalytic tradition precisely as it focusses on the constitution of subjectivity in the experiences of loss and gUilt

THE LACANIAN INFLUENCE

In my discussion so far the main bodies of work implicitly centralised have been the classical Left Freudianisms of Reich and critical theory, and some psychoanalytic feminism, with a counter-plot emanating from British psychoanalysis. What then about that range of political appropriations of psychoanalysis that emphatically distance themselves from all this? Despite a growing mood of reevaluation in the British Lacanian con­stituency, the French influence is still strong and widespread. Both the journals founded in the 1970s with the aim of incor­porating psychoanalysis into a politically-defined project (mlf and Screen) were strongly Lacanian, as are some non-clinical psychoanalytic societies founded in the 1980s.14

10

At first sight it seems that my argument about the transcen­dent impulse is not relevant here. A major complaint about Lacan has been that far from holding out a promise of a eupsychian paradise in some future society, he did not even concede the possibility of moderate psychic improvement through psychoanalysis in the present one. The inevitably frac­tured, alienated condition of the human subject is routinely enunciated in Lacanian texts, and the similarity with an existen­tialist negativity has been noted (Rustin, 1982).

However, a number of convergences with other strands of the Freudian Left can be noted, some of them at points found on the agendas discussed earlier. Firstly, Lacanian theory has been very suitable for incorporation into the attack on the patriarchal family, which Lasch (1981) sees as having been the central purpose of the Freudian Left. Secondly, the radical decentring of the subject and the evacuation of the subject into language is, at a very intellectualised level, a manoeuvre equivalent to the collapsing of the personal/political distinction. Thirdly, the psychoanalytic critique of the market, though most often associated with critical theory, has received analogous formulations within Lacanian paradigms (e.g. Gallop, 1982) via the equation of the Symbolic with the realm of exchange. Fourthly, and most importantly, the Freudo-Marxist tirade against repression and against the ego is profoundly matched by Lacan, whose bitterness against ego-psychology exceeded that of Marcuse, and who built upon it a theory of the ego as in-

. trinsically narcissistic and paranoid (e.g. Lacan, 1966; Ben­venuto and Kennedy, 1986; see also Bird, 1982). Also, the Marcusan critique of heterosexual 'genital tyranny' and celebration of polymorphous sexuality (Marcuse, 1955) is comparable, as rhetorical cultural analysis, to the Lacanian description of our uncertain sexual identities.

Points of similarity are sometimes noted also between Lacan and British psychoanalysis, which has also developed a picture of the ego as necessarily split. Here however the differ­ences are more important: the multiple egos of object-relations theory are not the equivalent of the shifting identity of the Lacanian subject, but are the dynamically-interrelated agencies of the mind. Whereas Lacan concluded that if there is in­evitable multiplicity and conflict within the psyche, then there can be no stable identity nor integration, most other schools of psychoanalysis (not only ego-psychology) have continued to believe (as, it might be claimed, did Freud) that coherence and stability can be achieved, though they must be continually reestablished as the dominant moment in the inner struggle with fragmentation.1S Since the Lacanians dismiss this hope as adaptationist, humanist fiction, it leaves them with only a romance of 'desire' (equivalent, perhaps, to the lurking naturalism which Russell Keat [1986] finds in Foucault, and likens to that of Reich). At worst, it leads to an extravagant Nietzschean celebration of psychosis (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972). It also leaves them with a shadowy transcendent image of psychological de-alienation. The locus of transcendence, for semioticised psychoanalysis, is not so much, for practical pur­poses, in the political institutions of society as in the literary and cinematic text and its deconstruction, but it is none the less transcendent for that, as can be seen in its precursors in the Surrealist movement (Macey, 1983).

Thus, although Sally Alexander (1984) suggested that Lacan's thought may yield insight into the utopian 'mentality of transcendence', this possibility cannot be understood as one of psychodynamic clarification of a particular pathological state of mind but as one of reflection upon our collective and absolute lot-transcendence is largely ruled out on metaphysi­cal grounds as an actual possibility, yet it is all that the

Page 9: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

Lacanian political imagination has to work with. For a number of reasons, then, the Lacanian development is

appropriately included in a discussion of psychoanalytic Lef­tism and the pursuit of transcendence. Jacqueline Rose (1983, p. 11) observed that 'The political use of Lacan's theory therefore stemmed from its assault on what English Marxists would call bourgeois "individualism".' The assault is however not only a philosophical one on the 'myth' of the unitary, coherent subject; it is also an emotional and political one on the ego and its cultural representatives. Onto the rational ego of the 'bourgeois individual' is projected much that is limiting, bounding, untruthful, frustrating and oppressive, and here we have the most striking parallel with German and American traditions. It is useful to refer again to the lucid work of Joel Kovel, whose most powerful influences are Reich, Marcuse and his clinical experience, and who has on that basis brought American Freudo-Marxism and the psychoanalytic castigation of the bourgeois individual to its most sophisticated form, and yet who also has absorbed into his language some key Lacanian terms and thus created a neo-Reichian discourse of Desire.

SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL HAPPINESS

Political radicalism is linked to the eupsychian impulse by the assumption that social oppression and personal unhappiness more or less reflect each other, with the social as the ultimately leading moment. Challenging oppressive social relations has been seen as necessarily involving psychic transformation.

Any social changes which were effective in reducing the misery of those millions of people in the Third World living in or on the edge of destituion, or in making life and health more secure anywhere, would bring in their train inestimable relief of mental suffering, and reduce the mental disorder which is the precipitate of suffering. To that extent the causes of justice and happiness are one. But a measure of security from the pains of hunger or torture is not by any means the same as the psychic transcendence. of the pains of loss and guilt The con­scription of psychoanalysis by the Left has been in the main according to this transcendent, distinctly metropolitan, project (though reports of psychotherapeutic work in Nicaragua have recently introduced a different note).

This eupsychian project is not the same as, and cannot be . hitched to, the socialist project in the liberal democracies. The latter must include plans for changing the social arrangements for responding to distress, but it is an error to confuse these with the totality of the distress and its sources. This is not to say that much mental disorder in our present society is not so­cially produced and historically specific in content, but it is to stress that some considerable part of the social means of its production may be (to borrow and extend a term from Joel Kovel) 'transhistorical', or pan social-at least in the universe of modernity. The management of unhappiness is clearly and directly a matter of mutable social institutions (and is of great political significance in that unhappiness may assume many different political expressions, depending on how a culture is able to manage it), but the reconstruction of basic forms of the psyche is something else. This sounds like Freud, though it is more the Freud of Civilisation and its Discontents than that of "'Civilised" sexual morality and modem nervous illness'. It is the Freud who pointed towards a possibility for uncoupling political visions of justice from the intolerance of psychic con­flict and pain.

Acknowledgements. Thanks to Michael Rustin and Robert Young for comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Notes

1 This paper grew out of a short talk given at the Radical Philosophy Conference in London in 1986, as part of a workshop on psychoanalysis.

2 My focus here is on tendencies in British Left-political culture in the last twenty years. However, since an indigenous British body of work in this area has been emerging, rather slowly and patchily, only since the rnid-1970s, many .of the intellectual reference points in the following account are non-British (and most are pre-1968!). For that reason, at least some of the points to be made here wilI apply to other national contexts as well, in­sofaras debates there have been organised around the same sources and paradigms: .

3 No such review seems to have appeared to date, though there are a small number of widely-read articles defining important positions, e.g. Rustin, 1982a and b; Lasch, 1981; Rose, 1983. Part ill of the recent book by Stephen Frosh (1987) covers some of the same ground as this paper.

4 Here, as in many other contexts, Juliet Mitchell's 1974 book was a starting point-see Waddell et al, 1978.

5 This inversion of Freud has to be distinguished from the effOJ;ts of Jacoby and others to reclaim Freud and the early spirit of psychoanalysis-humanistic, intellectually outgoing and cul­turally committed-from the fate of professionalisation and technicisation which, Jacoby argues, overtook it in the exigencies of fleeing fascism and relocating in post-war America. This his­torical analysis of the politics of psychoanalysis does not prescribe any particular view of the psychoanalysis of politics.

6 This meant that the present incumbents of the citadel-be­haviourism and other schools of empirical psychology-bad to be booted out, which could be accomplished, I hoped, with the critique of empiricism-WilIer and Wilier, 1973; Richards, 1977.

7 Guntrip (1961) was particularly explicit about his philosophical influences, chief amongst whom was the Scottish philosopher of the 'personal', John Macmurray. Radical Philosophy archivists can find an interesting resume of Macmurray's thought in Con­ford,1977.

8 Compare for example the use made of Guntrip's work by cultural critic David Holbrook (e.g. 1972) with that by feminist therapists Eichenbaum and Orbach (1982).

11

Page 10: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

9 The best known and most controversial position in these debates is that of Lasch (1979; 1984). For two different evaluations of his work, see Barrett and McIntosh (1982), and Richards (1985). See also the symposium on narcissism reported in Telos 44 (1980).

10 The 'despair work' of Joanna Macy, for example, is a mixture of humanistic psychology and eco-mysticism. See Macy, 1983; Childs, 1986.

11 Victor Wolfenstein's (1981) analysis of Malcolm X's autobiog­raphy, and the work of Peter Gay (e.g. 1985), are outstanding ex­amples of how psycho-historical work might develop.

12 It does though seem very appropriate to speak, as does Rose (1983), of a 'utopianism of the psyche' with reference to the call of Irigaray and some other feminists for a return to a condition of psychic oneness.

13 What I am saying overall at a personal level is that I now remain involved in psychoanalytically-oriented intellectual work for reasons which are in some ways the opposite of those which originally led me to it. I do not assume that others will have as perverse a relationship to the subject as this, and I am not clear about the extent to which this personal movement is an age­related emotional change, a trajectory of the political times, or the outcome of psychoanalytic teachings. My hope is that these fragments of intellectual autobiography illustrate some signifi­cant moments in the Left's post-'68 relationship with psychoanalysis, and the diverse options available for engagement with it.

14 For example the Cultural Centre for Freudian Studies and Research in London, and the Oxford Psychoanalytic Study Group.

15 This view of the self does not though necessarily involve a con­ception of an original whole, contrary to the implication of Mitchell's definition of humanism (1982, p. 4) as entailing the assumption that 'the subject exists from the beginning' .

References Abramson, J. (1984) Liberation and its Limits. The moral and politi­cal thought of Freud, New York: Free Press.

Alexander, S. (1984) Women, class and sexual differences in the 1830s and 184Os: some reflections on the writing of a feminist history, History Workshop Journal 17, pp. 125-49. Altbusser, L. (1965) For Marx, New York: Vintage, 1970.

Badcock, C. (forthcoming, 1988) Essential Freud, Oxford: Blackwell.

Barrett, M. and McIntosh, M. (1982) Narcissism and the family: a critique of Lasch, New Left Review 135, pp. 35-38.

Benvenuto, B. and Kennedy, R. (1986) The Works of Jacques Lacan. An Introduction, London: Free Association Books. Bbaskar, R. (1975) A Realist Theory of Science, Leeds: Leeds Books. Bird, J. (1982) Jacques Lacan-the French Freud? Radical Philosophy 30, pp. 7-14.

Cbasseguet-Smirgel, 1. and Grunberger, B. (1976) Freud or Reich? Psychoanalysis and Illusion, London: Free Association Books, 1986.

CbUds, D. (1986) A deep ecology workshop with Joanna Macy, Psychologists for Peace Newsletter, Wmter 1986, pp. 2-3.

Cbodorow, N. (1978) The Reproduction of Mothering, Berkeley: University of California Press. Collier, A. (1981) Scientific realism and the human world: the case of psychoanalysis, Radical Philosophy 29, pp. 8-18.

Conford, P. (1972) John Macmurray: a neglected philosopher, Radi­cal Philosophy 16, pp. 16-20. Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (1972) Anti-Oedipus, London: Athlone, 1984. Dlnnerstein, D. (1976) The Rocking of the Cradle, and the Ruling of the World, London: Souvenir Press, 1978.

12

Elcbenbaum, L. and Orbach, S. (1982) Outside In ... Inside Out, Hann<?Ildsworth: Penguin. Elsbtain, J. (1984) Symmetry and soporifics: A critique of feminist accounts of gender development. In B. Richards (ed.), Capitalism and Infancy, London: Free Association Books, pp. 55-91.

Ernst, S. and Maguire, M. (eds.), Living with the Sphinx, London: The Women's Press.

Freud, S. (1901) The Psychopathology of Everyday Life. Standard Edition, Vol. VI. Freud, S. (1908) 'Civilised' sexual morality and modem nervous ill­ness, Standard Edition, Vol. IX, pp. 181-204.

Freud, S. (1915) Thoughts for the times on war and death, Standard Edition, Vol. XIV, pp. 275-302. Fromm, E. (1947) Manfor Himself, London: Ark, 1986.

Frosb, S. (1987) The Politics of Psychoanalysis, Basingstoke: Mac­millan.

Gallop, J. (1982) The mother tongue. In F. Barker et al (eds.), The Politics of Theory, Colchester: University of Essex Sociology of Literature Conference, pp. 49-56.

Gay, P. (1985) Freud for Historians, New York: Oxford University Press. Guntrip, H. (1961) Personality Structure and Human Interaction, London: Hogarth. Habermas, J. (1968) Knowledge and Human Interests, London: Heinemann, 1972.

Harre, R. (1974) Blueprint for a new science. In N. Annistead (ed), Reconstructing Social Psychology, Hannondsworth: Penguin, pp. 240-259.

Harre, R. (1977) Making psychology scientific, Bulletin of the British Psychological Society 30, p. 167.

Henriques, 1. et al (1984) Changing the Subject, London: Methuen.

Holbrook, D. (1972) The Masks of Hate, Oxford: Pergamon.

Horowltz, G. (1977) Basic and Surplus Repression in fsychoanalytic Theory: Freud, Reich and Marcuse, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

Ingleby, D. (1984) The ambivalence of psychoanalysis, Radical Science 15 (Free Associations Pilot Issue), pp. 39-71.

Jacoby, R. (1975) Social Amnesia, Hassocks: Harvester, 1977.

Jacoby, R. (1983) The Repression of Psychoanalysis, New York: Basic Books.

Jones, E. (1915a) War and individual psychology. In Essays in Ap­plied Psychoanalysis, London: Hogarth, Vol. 1, pp. 55-76.

Jones, E. (1915b) War and sublimation. In Essays in Applied Psychoanalysis, Vol. 1, pp. 77-87.

Keat, R. (1981) The Politics of Social Theory, Oxford: Blackwell.

Keat, R. (1986) The human body in social theory: Reich, Foucault and the repressive hypothesis, Radical Philosophy 42, pp. 24-32.

Kovel,1. (1981) The Age of Desire, New York: Pantheon.

Kovel, J. (1984) On being a Marxist psychoanalyst (and a psychoanalytic Marxist), Radical Science 15 (Free Associations Pilot Issue), pp. 149-54.

Kovel,1. (1986) Why Freud or Reich? Free Associations 4, pp. 80-99.

Kovel, J. (forthcoming) The Radical Spirit. Essays in Psychoanalysis and Marxism, London: Free Association Books. Lacan, J. (1966) Ecrits: A Selection, London: Tavistock, 1977.

Lascb, C. (1979) The Culture of Narcissism, New York: Norton.

Lascb, C. (1981) Freud and the New Left: the theory of cultural revolution, New Left Review 129, pp. 23-34.

Lascb, C. (1984) The Minimal Self, New York: Norton.

Llcbtman, R. (1982) The Production of Desire, New York: Free Press.

Page 11: The Eupsychian Impulse - Radical Philosophy€¦ · Russell Jacoby's explorations of these (1983) have brought to light the less well-known con ... psychoanalytic work, within which

McCarthy, T. (1978) The Critical Theory of Jurgen Habermas, Cambridge: Polity Press.

Macey, D. (1983) Fragments of an analysis: Lacan in context, Radical Philosophy 35, pp. 1-9.

Macy, I. (1983) Despair and Personal Power in the Nuclear Age, Philadelphia: New Society Publishers.

Marcuse, H. (1955) Eros and Civilisation, Boston: Beacon, 1974.

Maslow, A. (1965) Eupsychian Management: A Journal, Homewood, Illinois: Irwin and Dorsey.

Mitchell, I. (1974) Psychoanalysis and Feminism, Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Mitchell, I. (1982) Introduction. In I. Mitchell and I. Rose, Feminine Sexuality: Jacques Lacan and the Ecole Freudienne, London: Macmil­lan, pp. 1-26.

Raymond, I. (1986) A Passion for Friends, London: The Women's Press.

Rlchards, B. (1977) Empiricism and after, Bulletin of the British Psychological Society 30, p. 181.

Rlchards, B. (1984) Schizoid states and the market. In B. Richards (ed.) Capitalism and Infancy, London: Free Association Books, pp. 122-66.

Richards, B. (1985) The politics of the self, Free Associations 3, pp. 42-64.

Richards, B. (1986a) Military mobilisations of the unconscious, Free Associations 7, pp. 11-26.

Rlchards, B. (1986b) Psychotherapy and the public domain, British Journal of Psychotherapy 3(1), pp. 42-51.

Rleff, P. (1959) Freud, the Mind of the Moralist, London: Gollancz.

Rleff, P. (1966) The Triumph of the Therapeutic, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973.

Rose, I. (1983) Femininity and its discontents, Feminist Review 14, pp. 5-19.

Rustln, M. (1982a) A socialist consideration of· Kleinian psychoanalysis, New Left Review 131, pp. 71-96.

Rustln, M. (1982b) Kleinian psychoanalysis and the theory of culture. In F. Barker et al (eds.), The Politics of Theory, Colchester: University of Essex Conference on the Sociology of Literature, pp. 57-70.

Rustln, M. (1987) Psychoanalysis, philosophical realism and the new sociology of science, Free Associations 9, pp. 102-136.

Schneider, M. (1973) Neurosis and Civilisation, New York: Seabury Press, 1975.

Temperley, I. (1984) Our own worst enemies: unconscious factors in female disadvantage, Radical Science 15 (Free Associations Pilot Is­sue), pp. 23-38.

Waddell, M. et al (1978) Marxism, psychoanalysis and feminism, Radical ScienceJournal6n, pp. 107-117.

Whltebook, 1. (1985) Reason and happiness: some psychoanalytic themes in critical theory. In R. Bemstein (ed.), Habermas and Moder­nity, Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 140-60.

Will, D. (1980) Psychoanalysis as a human science, British Journal of Medical Psychology 53, pp. 201-11.

Will, D. (1986) Psychoanalysis and the new philosophy of science,ln­ternational Review of Psycho-Analysis 13, pp. 163-73.

Wilier, D. and Willer, 1. (1973) Systematic Empiricism: Critique of a Pseudo-Science, London: Prentice-Hall.

Wolfenstein, E. (1981) The Victims of Democracy, Berkeley: Univer­sity of California Press.

Young, R. (1986) Freud: scientist and/or humanist? Free Associations 6, pp. 7-35.

Young, R. (1987) Biography: the basic discipline for human science, Free Associations, forthcoming.

SUBSCRIBE TO RADICAL PHILOSOPHY

SUBSCRIBE TO RADICAL PHILOSOPHY AT REDUCED RATES

As w~1I as critical C?mmen~~ry on contemporary philosophical issues, and a continuing engagement with the ManClst.and H~~ll8n traditions: RP has carried.articles on issues in: feminism, race, imperialism, ecology, aHematlVe med.IClne, nuclear dISarmament, radical psychology and science, post-structuralism - and on many other topICS.

Subscribe nowl A two-year subscription saves you even more.

Individual Subscription Rates

Inland Overseas surface Overseas airmail

annual (3 issues) £5.00 £8.001$20.00 £12.001$30.00

2 years (6 Issues) £9.00 £13;00/$35.00 £20.00/$50.00

13