Spring 2010 Final Print

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    1/31

    ENQUIRY

    Spring 2010

    Washington UniversitysUndergraduate Philosophy Journal

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    2/31

    Senior EditorSharon Barbour

    Editorial Staff

    Vanessa EakenAJ HandlerPeter Murray

    Amanda SabeleAdam Sadaka

    Nicole Satar

    Faculty AdvisorMariska Leunissen

    Washington University in St. LouisDepartment of Philosophy

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    3/31

    ENQUIRYWashington Universitys

    Undergraduate Philosophy Journal

    Spring 2010

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    4/31

    Special thanks to Washington Universitys Department of Philosophy, particularlyMariska Leunissen, Mark Rollins, Dennis Des Chene, and Mindy Danner.

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    5/31

    TABLE OF COnTEnTS

    rAdiCAL rESpOnSESTO VAn inwAgEnS

    SpECiAL COmpOSiTiOn QuESTiOnByEriC TOrrES 1

    BAruCh SpinOzAAnd mOSES mEndELSSOhn: JEwiShphiLOSOphiESOFThE STATE, rELigiOn, And indiViduAL

    ByJOnAThAn SALzingEr 5

    ThE KnOwLEdgE ArgumEnT, QuALiA, AndThE ABiLiTy

    hypOThESiSByKATySOuThwOrTh 10

    zOmBiE

    idEnTiTy

    : A dEFEnSE

    OF

    phySiCALiSm

    FrOm

    KripKES idEnTiTyAnd nECESSiTy ByAJAySundAr 14

    TEmpOrAL OVErLApASASOLuTiOnTO pArAdOxES

    OF COinCidEnCEByAdAm SAdAKA(EdiTOr) 18

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    6/31

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    7/31

    rAdiCAL rESpOnSESTO VAn inwAgEnS SpECiAL COmpOSiTiOn QuESTiOn

    The special composition question

    asks under what circumstances do a set

    of xs compose a greater object y? Re-

    sponses to this question run the gambit

    from under no circumstances to un-

    der every circumstance that there exist a

    set of xs. It is this latter response, for-

    malized under the heading of Universal-

    ism, which is the concern of my analysis.

    I believe that tracing the successes

    and failures of the Universalist response to

    the question of special composition revealsthe holes in our normal intuitions about

    the metaphysical basis of composition and

    prompts the conclusion that we cannot ever

    give a consistent account of where com-

    position does and does not apply without

    cheapening the notion of composition so

    greatly that it no longer refers to anything

    at all. In order to make this case I will rstoutline the Universalist outlook and then

    consider the advantages such a theory

    holds over moderate and nihilist responses

    to the special composition question. I will

    conclude by arguing that the implications

    that come from accepting the Universalist

    perspective on the nature of composition

    actually point us towards a nihilist answer

    to the special composition question, de-spite the diametrically opposite conclusion

    Universalism purportedly seeks to reach.

    The Universalist response to the

    question of special composition is that any

    given set of distinct xs compose a unique

    y. This is to say that given a universe with

    only particles A, B and C, the Universal-

    ist will posit that there are seven distinct

    entities, three of which are the simples A,

    B, and C and four of which are composed

    of the physical simples. In total the Uni-

    versalist posits A, B, C, AB, AC, BC, and

    ABC. I take physical simples to be whatev-

    er particles, should there exist any, which

    physics determines to exist as irreducible.

    The power of this account is that nothing

    escapes classication as an object. All ob-

    jects we colloquially refer to exist and their

    basis for doing so is a simple and univer-

    sally applicable rule. Furthermore, the on-tology of Universalism is relatively simple,

    despite the tremendous amount of things;

    there are only two types, simples and com-

    posites, where each is easily identiable.

    The immediate trouble with this re-

    sponse, however, is twofold. First, it posits

    an immense if not innite number of real

    distinct entities. And second, Universal-ism construes as objects sets of xs that our

    intuitions tell us have nothing to do with

    one another. For example, it seems strange

    that there is an object composed of my toe-

    nails, a single hydrogen atom in the sun,

    and a seven-forty-seven parked at Lam-

    bert airport, but according to Universalism

    not only does this object exist, but this odd

    composite is every bit as much an object asare computers, tables, and human beings.

    To each of these grievances the Uni-

    versalist has a response, however. In re-

    gards to the enormous number of objects

    that result from the Universalist conception

    of composition, the Universalist need only

    shrug her shoulders. The fact that Univer-

    salism proposes an enormous or perhaps

    By: EriC TOrrES

    1

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    8/31

    innite number of objects is not a prob-

    lem unique to Universalism; moderate and

    even nihilist ontologies may be populated

    by innite objects as well if it turns out that

    the universe is limitless and therefore lled

    with innite irreducible particles. Even if

    it is not, the quantity relevant to evaluating

    a theorys quality in terms of parsimony is

    not tokens but rather types, and Universal-

    ism is very tidy in this regard. Universal-

    ist theory only proposes the existence of

    simples and composites, and every case is

    very clear-cut; if an entity exists and is nota simple, it is reducible to a composite of

    simples. This is not to say that there can-

    not exist composites whose constructions

    are not framed in terms of other compos-

    ites, but rather that an exhaustive reduc-

    tion of any given entity that is not a simple

    will invariably result in its being composed

    of simples. For instance, we might say that

    a book is composed of its pages, but were

    we to continue with the process of analyz-

    ing the composition of the pages we would

    eventually land upon physical simples. I

    believe that it is not the quantity of ob-

    jects that grounds the intuitive rejection

    of Universalism however, but rather the

    variety of strange properties of the things

    that Universalism classies as objects.To this more serious objection (that

    Universalism takes too loose a stance on

    what it includes as objects) the Universal-

    ist might press her critic as to why exactly

    this is a problem. While this conception

    of what grounds the composition of an ob-

    ject certainly stands in contrast to the way

    we casually speak about the world, I pro-

    pose that there is no principled reason to

    call things like tables and people objects

    while not calling the sum of my friend Josh

    and the Eiffel tower an object. I believe

    that should we wish to speak of composite

    objects at all, to impose a distinction be-

    tween those things is anthropocentric and

    lacking in a justiable metaphysical basis.

    To illustrate this point, I propose a

    thought experiment. Consider two forks,

    one resting on top of another. Our intu-

    ition tells us that these two things do not

    compose a unique object. But what if plac-ing one fork on top of another enabled

    time travel? I believe that it is not far-

    fetched to argue that our intuitions would

    tell us that in this circumstance, we would

    want to say that those two forks compose

    a larger object, a timefork, lets say. I pro-

    pose that this distinction gives us good

    reason to mistrust our intuitions on the

    basis that they are rooted in a consider-

    ation not of the metaphysics of objects but

    rather of their perceived purpose to us.

    One may concede that this would

    be true without believing that it is cause

    for us to doubt our intuitions, however.

    It seems plausible that the example I just

    gave points towards an answer to the spe-

    cial composition question in which thefunction of an entity is a necessary condi-

    tion for the xs to compose a further object

    y. In regards to the example I just gave,

    one might say that in order for two forks to

    constitute a further object, they must have

    some functional signicance that one fork

    resting atop another in our world simply

    doesnt have. This is a vague and subjective

    2

    EriC TOrrES

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    9/31

    criterion, however. It is unclear to me how one

    would dene something as being functionally

    signicant without appealing to anthropocen-

    tric notions of purpose or usefulness. If there

    does turn out to be vagueness in this crite-

    rion, it follows that there might be vagueness

    in composition and therefore vagueness of ex-

    istence, which does not seem possible given

    that we commonly hold existence as being an

    absolute property that is either instantiated or

    not. While it remains possible that there may

    be an objective line to be drawn delineating a

    point after which a set of xs attain function-al signicance, I nd this to be a strange idea

    to appeal to and, if nothing else, this theory

    proposes a vagueness in terms of epistemol-

    ogy, which a Universalist perspective avoids.

    But Universalists are not out of the

    woods yet. Consider a set of simple xs that

    compose a greater y at time t, let us say a

    toaster. Now at time t1, this toaster has

    been destroyed. The simples that composed

    the toaster have now been entirely rear-

    ranged such that they, and only they, make

    up a blender. According to Universalism,

    there is nothing to suggest a difference be-

    tween the toaster and the blender. In fact,

    based on the claims of Universalism, it seems

    that these entities must be the same object.

    To this, the Universalist might respondthat yes, it is the same object; it has merely

    changed its appearance, which is something

    that should not be at all counterintuitive. In

    the same way that we consider a frowning

    child and a smiling child the same child, so we

    should consider the blender and the toaster the

    same entity. One might posit that the differ-

    ent properties of the toaster and the blender

    make such a rearrangement go beyond mere

    aesthetics, but the Universalist may claim that

    the smiling child too has different properties,

    literally speaking. While most of them would

    not be relevant to what we generally consider

    different, the smiling child has the property of

    exhibiting happiness while the frowning child

    has the property of exhibiting sadness. The

    fact that we would not call them two separate

    children actually works in favor of a Univer-

    salist position. The critic is again pressed to

    provide an account of identity that is not based

    upon the physical substructure of a given ob-ject. While this is certainly not an impossible

    task, it at least puts the burden on the side of

    the critic of Universalism to come up with a

    reason why particulate substructure cannot

    be the basis of our identication of an object.

    While this previous example does not

    disprove the Universalist response, it does

    much to undermine the force of the original

    claim that all sets of xs compose distinct ys.

    The previous example shows that for Univer-

    salism to succeed, the identity of objects can-

    not have to do with anything but the simple

    particulate substructure. Consider a more ex-

    treme version of the previous example. What

    if the xs at time t were at time t1 strewn about

    in no relation to one another? It is problem-

    atic to our casual notion of the identity of ob-jects to propose that they compose the same y

    as was once a toaster, but it seems that this is

    what the Universalist must say. While such a

    conclusion is not paradoxical, the Universal-

    ist case crafts a very cheap notion of composi-

    tion. If they attempt to introduce any further

    criterion for circumstances under which a set

    of xs compose y, they too are subject to the

    rAdiCAL rESpOnSESTO VAn inwAgEnS SpECiAL COmpOSiTiOnQuESTiOn

    3

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    10/31

    problem of vagueness that plagues the mod-

    erate accounts. This example I believe gets to

    the heart of our problem with Universalism.

    If composition does not necessarily make any

    claims on the form or function of the xs that

    compose a further y, it seems to make no more

    demand of the world than that there exist xs.

    Saying that the xs compose a further object is

    a hollow notion if there is nothing else that we

    can learn from such a relationship than that

    the xs exist. The appealing parsimony

    and broad application of the Universal-

    ist case seem compromised by the sharp-ly degraded notion of composition that it

    provides and it seems that Universalism,

    when considered in detail, is actually a

    version of nihilism with a different hat on.

    wOrKS CiTEd

    Van Inwagen, Peter. Material Beings.

    Ithaca, NY. Cornell University Press, 1990

    Sattig, Thomas. Metaphysics and Episte-

    mology Lectures, Washington University

    in St. Louis. St. Louis, MO. September-

    November, 2008.

    EriC TOrrES

    4

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    11/31

    BAruCh SpinOzAAnd mOSES mEndELSSOhn: JEwiSh phiLOSOphiESOFThE STATE, rELigiOnAnd indiViduAL

    As modernity slowly emerged across

    Europe, Jews were faced with the questionsof what identity to assume and what role to

    play in European society. Of particular con-

    cern to Jewish intellectuals at the time was

    how the state, which had previously been

    characterized by the inuence of interme-

    diary bodies and importance of corporate

    identities, and religious powers would in-

    teract with the Jewish populace in light of

    the changes. In response to the politicaland economic climate of the mid-17th cen-

    tury, Jewish philosopher Baruch Spinoza

    endeavored to strengthen individual free-

    dom and widen liberty, envisioning a soci-

    ety that dramatically differed from his own.

    In the Theological-Political Trea-

    tise, Spinoza sought to weaken the hold of

    religion over the individual and encour-aged Jews to reject their particularistic be-

    liefs in favor of a universal system based

    upon natural law. Just over a century

    after Spinozas work was published, the

    German Haskalah the Jewish Enlight-

    enment thinker Moses Mendelssohn

    responded to the same issue of interac-

    tion between the state, religious author-

    ity and individual with Jerusalem. As the

    Aufklarung the German Enlightenment

    developed traction in his native Germa-

    ny and Enlightenment ideals spread across

    Europe, Mendelssohn witnessed the rise

    of the modern centralized state and a shift

    from governments interacting with collec-

    tive entities to the individual. Mendels-

    sohn sought to synthesize traditional Jew-

    ish and Enlightenment ideals and argued

    that Jews were fully able to participate inEnlightenment thinking while remaining

    true to Judaism. This, he reasoned, was

    possible because Judaism revealed leg-

    islation that could be dened by the very

    particularizing elements in Mosaic Law;

    this law was not intended to coerce the

    mind but rather provide eternal truths

    as long as the need for Jewish distinc-

    tiveness persists (Mendelssohn, 24-24). Although they lived in different

    times and under different circumstances,

    both Spinoza and Mendelssohn recognized

    the need to examine the relationship be-

    tween the state and individual religious

    belief as the character of Europe changed.

    Both men envisioned a society governed

    by a social contract between citizens, ab-sent of civil or coercive authority held by

    religious powers, with individual religious

    freedom. Spinoza, however, cast aside

    Mosaic Law and forged a secular vision for

    future European life, based upon univer-

    sal natural laws. Mendelssohn differed

    from Spinoza in this respect; he viewed

    Mosaic Law as valid because it contains

    eternal truths that make Jews unique and

    believed that Jews should continue to be

    observant but not let their religion prevent

    interaction with European society. Both

    Spinoza, who was excommunicated from

    the Jewish community, and Mendelssohn,

    whose religious beliefs were publicly chal-

    lenged on several occasions, faced severe

    criticism for their views from others with-

    By: JOnAThAn SALzingEr

    5

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    12/31

    6

    in and outside of the Jewish community.

    However, the models that they conceived

    for the state and its relationship to individ-

    ual religious belief have had lasting inu-

    ence on political and religious philosophy.

    In the mid-17th century, the per-

    vasive mercantilism and political turmoil

    across Europe posed a unique situation for

    Jews living there. As the seeds of capital-

    ism took hold, Jews came to be regarded as

    possessing distinct and desirable qualities,

    including knowledge of and familial ties

    across much of Europe. Although mostJews were still subject to the repressive

    laws of the Middle Ages and power of in-

    termediary bodies, by proving useful to the

    mercantilist goals of European states, some

    Jews were granted opportunities, particu-

    larly in the economic sphere, that they did

    not posses before. It is from this evolving

    context that Baruch Spinoza examined the

    question of what roles Jews were to play in

    European society. While most Jews across

    Europe remained largely oppressed, Spi-

    noza resided in Holland, which was rela-

    tively liberal; he observed Amsterdam to

    be a place where people of every sect and

    nation live together in the greatest harmo-

    ny (Spinoza, 257). In Amsterdam, deci-

    sions to make a loan to someone were notpredicated on religion and religion or sect

    does not come into it because this does

    not help win or lose a case before a court,

    and no sect is so hugely resented by oth-

    ers that its members are not defended

    by the public authority and under the pro-

    tection of the magistracy (Spinoza, 257).

    Spinozas conception of an ideal

    state, which would allow Jews to hold an

    unbiased place in society, found itself at

    odds with many of the entrenched monar-

    chical and religious powers across Europe

    at the time. Spinoza saw modern faith as

    having been turned into nothing more

    than credulity and prejudices (Spinoza,

    7). This transformation of otherwise ra-

    tional men into brutes was not a natu-

    ral development; according to Spinoza,

    it was a tool used by rulers to hold power

    over their citizenry: It may indeed be the

    highest secret of monarchical governmentand utterly essential to it, to keep men di-

    vided, and to disguise the fear that sways

    them with the specious name of religion

    (Spinoza, 6). In order to establish control

    and loyalty, Spinoza says that pomp and

    ceremony has been used to adorn religion

    and ensure zealous observance (Spinoza,

    5). He asserts that states should not use

    religion as a divisive tool to maintain pow-

    er and that the purpose of the state should

    be to free everyone from fear and allow

    for freedom and diversity of thought so

    that Jews and Christians can live together

    in harmony (Spinoza, 252). Further, Spi-

    noza argues, Trying to control everything

    by law will encourage vices rather than cor-

    rect them (Spinoza, 254). He goes on tosay that freedom of judgment must nec-

    essarily be permitted and people must be

    governed in such a way that they can live

    in harmony, even though they openly hold

    different and contradictory positions (Spi-

    noza, 257). This claim is the crux of his ar-

    gument for how Jews and European soci-

    ety at large should interact: people should

    JOnAThAn SALzingEr

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    13/31

    BAruCh SpinOzAAnd mOSES mEndELSSOhn

    reject the authority of those whose power

    is derived from divisiveness, fear and co-

    ercion, and all people should be allowed to

    freely express their own personal beliefs

    and live their lives benevolently alongside

    even those they disagree with. This lib-

    eral society will naturally enter into a so-

    cial contract to ensure that natural rights

    are not alienated, says Spinoza, yielding a

    democratic form of government under the

    aegis of a sovereign power (Spinoza, 200).

    The harmonious society envisioned

    by Spinoza required the removal of barriers which set members of different religious

    groups apart. According to Spinoza: It

    has been the case for a long time that one

    can hardly know whether anyone is Chris-

    tian, Turk, Jew or gentile, other than that

    he has a certain appearance and dresses

    in a certain way or attends one or another

    church and upholds a certain belief or pays

    allegiance to one magistrate rather than

    another (Spinoza, 7). In his view, empha-

    sis of these differences creates avoidable

    conict. He contends that the differences

    between Judaism and Christianity should

    not cause people to live disharmoniously;

    he argues that the division of the Old and

    New Testament is not because the books

    of the Testaments differ in doctrine, norbecause they were written as conventional

    texts, nor, nally, because the universal

    religion, which is supremely natural, was

    anything new except to those people who

    did not know it (Spinoza, 168). He makes

    the case that the Laws revealed by God to

    Moses were nothing but the decrees of the

    historical Hebrew state alone, and accord-

    ingly that no one needed to adopt them

    but the Hebrews, and even they were only

    bound by them so long as their state sur-

    vived (Spinoza, 9). As a consequence of

    this view, Spinoza takes the stance that

    Jews should discard Mosaic Law in favor of

    a way of life based upon universal morals.

    With the dismissal of particularistic Jew-

    ish law, as well as his rejection of the idea

    of Jewish chosenness, Spinoza advocates-

    limited religious power and encourage Jew-

    ish acculturation into European society.

    As the early-modern period of Spi-noza drew to a close, Jewish and Gentile

    relations expanded considerably as Jews

    came to occupy increasingly important

    economics roles. Despite increasing eco-

    nomic interdependence, however, Jews

    and gentiles largely did not closely associ-

    ate until the onset of the Enlightenment in

    the 18th century. It is in the context of the

    Aufklarung in Germany that Moses Men-

    delssohn emerged as the gurehead of the

    Haskalah. Mendelssohn sought to recon-

    cile his beliefs in Judaism and in Enlight-

    enment thinking, calling for Jews to be

    permitted to participate in secular endeav-

    ors by dividing the religious and secular

    aspects of their lives. Mendelssohn viewed

    his Judaism as a personal issue and as a fac-tor which should not prevent him or other

    Jews from engaging in secular endeavors.

    Indeed, he lived his own life at the van-

    guard of Jewish and Christian interaction.

    Mendelssohns idea of the state and

    its relationship to an individuals religion

    shares many similarities with Spinozas

    view. Mendelssohn echoes Spinozas be-7

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    14/31

    JOnAThAn SALzingEr

    lief that civil and religious powers should

    grant freedom of thought and religious

    practice; Jews should not be compelled

    to give up their integrity by being forced

    to publicly afrm beliefs they do not hold.

    According to an account by a student at-

    tending a lecture given by Mendelssohn,

    he instructed that Jews must throw off

    the heavy yoke under which the king and

    judges of this country, who are not of our

    people, have harnessed us; to throw off,

    furthermore, that other yoke which we

    have taken upon us with the rule of ourown rabbis and communal leaders (Men-

    delssohn Visits the Seer of Koenigsberg).

    Like Spinoza, Mendelssohn believed that

    state and religious authorities are unable

    to legislate what the human mind thinks,

    and that genuine religious belief cannot

    be compelled. According to Mendelssohn,

    state and church have as their object ac-

    tions as well as convictions, the former

    insofar as they are based on the relations

    between man and nature, the latter insofar

    as they are based on the relations between

    nature and God (Mendelssohn, 56-57).

    He explains that while people may elect to

    give up their independence and enter into

    a social contract with other members of the

    state which punishes and rewards based onpositive laws, the churchs prerogatives

    can never conict with ours (Mendels-

    sohn, 59). This social contract allows the

    state, when necessary, to resort to pub-

    lic measures, coercive laws, punishments

    of crime, and rewards of merit, however,

    religious bodies can have no such contract

    because all contracts presuppose cases of

    a collision [in interests] to be decided and

    no such collision is possible if the church

    cannot have conicting prerogatives

    with the individual (Mendelssohn, 59).

    Mendelssohn differs from Spinoza

    in his view of revealed legislation; he intu-

    its that the revealed Mosaic Law remains

    valid because it was passed to the Jews by

    God not in his capacity as Creator and Pre-

    server of the universe, but God as Patron

    and Friend by covenant of their ancestors,

    as Liberator, Founder and Leader, as King

    and Head of this people (Mendelssohn,127). These laws, which represent the par-

    ticularizing elements of Jewish existence,

    remain valid because they hold public and

    private felicity as their ultimate aim (Men-

    delssohn, 25, 127). Mendelssohn holds that

    this contention is in keeping with his belief

    that the mind cannot be coerced because

    of the Mosaic law, there is not a single one

    which says: You shall believe or not be-

    lieve. They all say: You shall do or not do.

    Faith is not commanded, for it accepts no

    other commands than those who come to it

    by way of conviction (Mendelssohn, 100).

    Spinoza and Mendelssohns respec-

    tive visions of the relationship between the

    state and individual religious belief were

    pioneering responses to the challenges ofmodernity. These two intellectuals, despite

    differences in their immediate situations,

    shared much in common between their re-

    spective philosophies regarding the need

    for individual freedom of thought, though

    they parted ways over the afrmation of Mo-

    saic Law and importance of maintaining a

    distinct Jewish identity. As a result of their8

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    15/31

    BAruCh SpinOzAAnd mOSES mEndELSSOhn

    controversial positions, both men faced

    harsh criticism from segments of the Jew-

    ish community and the European society.

    Spinozas views were particularly

    radical for his time; he called for a compre-

    hensive departure from the prevalent cor-

    porate and collective form of governance of

    the day, removal of the power held by many

    contemporary civil and religious authori-

    ties and Jewish rejection of Mosaic Law

    and the concept of chosenness. Spinozas

    claims challenged the power of the Jewish

    community as a corporate entity with civilauthority and threatened Judaism as a re-

    ligion by casting aside those aspects which

    historically distinguished it from other

    religious denominations. Because of Spi-

    nozas wrong opinions and behavior, the

    Jewish community excommunicated him.

    Mendelssohns views, while not as

    extreme as Spinozas, placed him in a pre-

    carious position in society as well. His ac-

    ceptance of Enlightenment ideals, advocacy

    of the subordination of religious beliefs to

    secular academic and philosophic endeav-

    ors, and dismissal of the coercive power

    of Judaism attracted the ire of many crit-

    ics. In arguing against ecclesiastical pow-

    er while remaining an observant Jew and

    afrming Halakha Jewish religious law, Mendelssohn alienated both orthodox

    and heterodox Jews and Christians. Men-

    delssohns attempts to blend his Judaism

    with enlightenment ideals led many to be-

    lieve that the synthesis he settled on was

    merely a waypoint in converting to Chris-

    tianity; his faith was publicly challenged

    by prominent Christians Johann Cas-

    par Lavater and August Friedrich Cranz.

    Despite the critical reception that

    Spinoza and Mendelssohn received, their

    arguments addressed important issues re-

    garding the proper relationship between

    state and individual religious belief and

    manners of relating their conceptions of

    Judaism to the limits of political and reli-

    gious power. Their respective positions of-

    fer interesting and widely inuencial per-

    spectives on the struggle by Jews to dene

    their role and identity in modern Europe.

    wOrKS CiTEd

    Mendelssohn, Moses. Jerusalem: Or on

    Religious Power and Judaism. Trans. Allan

    Arkush. Hanover, NH: Brandeis University

    Press, 1983.

    Spinoza, Benedictus de. Theological-Polit-

    ical Treatise. Trans. Michael Silverthorne

    and Jonathan Israel. Cambridge: Cam-

    bridge University Press, 2007.

    9

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    16/31

    10

    ThE KnOwLEdgE ArgumEnT,QuALiA, AndThE ABiLiTyhypOThESiS

    The Knowledge argument is used

    to refute physicalism by showing the im-portance of phenomenal feels called qua-

    lia. In this paper, I examine the Knowl-

    edge argument with the example of Mary,

    a color expert who has lived her entire life

    in black-and-white, to show that there is

    important information that exists outside

    of the purely physical realm. I analyze two

    counterarguments to this position, which

    attempt to avoid the conclusion of theKnowledge argument, and I offer an expla-

    nation of why these are insufcient to sub-

    vert the argument. This leads to the no-

    tion of epiphenomenal qualia, something

    that at rst appears impossible, but which

    deeper analysis reveals is plausible. I ex-

    amine Frank Jacksons argument, which

    shows that there is no reason why epiphe-nomenal qualia cannot exist. I conclude

    by examining the Ability Hypothesis, the

    Physicalists rebuttal to the Knowledge ar-

    gument, which I argue does not adequate-

    ly controvert the Knowledge argument.

    The Knowledge argument is often

    introduced with a thought experiment

    about a woman called Mary who is the

    worlds leading expert on color and color

    vision in spite of the fact that she has, since

    birth, lived in a cell where everything is ei-

    ther black or white. Despite the fact that

    she knows all of the physical information

    about colors, she has never experienced

    color and therefore does not know what it

    is like to see color. One day she escapes

    her cell and goes to a meadow where she

    sees color for the rst time and learns what

    it is to see color (Lewis 281-283). BecauseMary learns more about color after leaving

    her cell, it cannot be the case, the argument

    goes, that everything can be explained us-

    ing just physical information. So Physical-

    ism, the argument that all information is

    purely physical information that has been

    discovered by chemists, physicists, and

    biologists must be false (Jackson 273).

    There is an important difference betweenfactual information and rst person ex-

    perience; someone can know all the facts

    about something but not know what it is

    like to experience it until she experiences

    it. This indicates the existence of qualia,

    phenomenal information beyond physical

    information. Qualia are what it is like to

    have a sensation and include (1) Percep-tual experiences, for example, experiences

    of the sort involved in seeing green... (2)

    Bodily sensations, for example, feeling a

    twinge of pain(3) Felt reactions or pas-

    sions or emotions, for example, feeling de-

    light, lust, fear, love...(4) Felt moods, for

    example, feeling elated, depressed, calm,

    bored, (Stanford Encyclopedia). By us-

    ing qualia to explain these sensations

    instead of relying on physical explana-

    tions, the Knowledge argument provides

    a better account of Marys experience with

    color and proves Physicalism to be false.

    Two counterarguments which seek

    to avoid the conclusions of the Knowl-

    edge argument do so either by comparing

    the unknown experience to known expe-

    By: KATySOuThwOrTh

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    17/31

    11

    riences, or by giving a more precise de-

    scription of the experience (Lewis 282).

    Those who use comparisons to ex-

    plain away the Knowledge argument are

    misguided because using experiences to

    explain other experiences presupposes that

    all people experience the same events in

    the same way. For instance, suppose I ask

    what it is like to eat Nutella and my friend

    attempts to explain it to me as chocolate

    peanut butter. I have never eaten choco-

    late and am allergic to peanut butter. One

    part of the analogy totally fails because Ido not know what it is like to eat chocolate,

    and the other part of the analogy fails be-

    cause when I eat peanut butter my throat

    swells shut, and this would not happen if

    I ate Nutella because it is not made from

    peanuts. Thus, I will never know what it is

    like to eat Nutella until I eat it. This ex-

    ample illustrates that one cannot use com-

    parisons to other experiences to explain a

    particular experience because one does not

    know if the other person shares in the same

    background information or whether the

    other person experiences the comparative

    event in the same way. Qualia are personal

    sensations and can only be accessed by in-

    trospection, not third person perception.

    The second counterargument holdsthat by giving a more precise description

    of the unknown experience the Knowledge

    argument can be avoided (Lewis 282).

    Those who put forth this claim think that

    explaining what it is like to do something

    can be done by breaking that action into

    smaller experiences and because the per-

    son knows what it is like to have these

    smaller experiences they will know what it

    is like to have the bigger one. Lewis says

    that these sub-experiences could be ex-

    planations of the larger event in terms of

    their causestheir effectsor.the physi-

    cal states of the nervous system that me-

    diate between those causes and effects,

    (Lewis 283). However, if we apply this

    argument to Mary, one would explain to

    her the things she already knew as a result

    of being a color expert. Thus, according

    to this argument, if she knew what it was

    like to have the sub-experiences then sheshould not have learned anything new on

    her escape to the meadow. Because of this,

    knowing which sub-experiences make up

    an experience does not fully capture what

    it is like to have that experience, and there-

    fore do not derail the Knowledge argument.

    There are certain aspects of life that

    cannot be explained by Physicalism and

    thus qualia are necessary. The example of

    Mary shows that Physicalism alone cannot

    explain everything. The fact that the two

    most plausible rebuttals to the Knowledge

    argument fail to bring it down also supports

    the acceptance of the Knowledge argument.

    Because Mary has all the physical informa-

    tion possible but still does not understand

    what it is like to see color before she escapesher cell, qualia must exist. That is, because

    it is possible to have all the physical facts

    and not know what it is like to experience

    something, qualia must be important.

    The conclusion of the Knowledge

    argument entails epiphenomenalism: if

    one knows all the physical information

    about something without knowing the as-

    ThE KnOwLEdgE ArgumEnT, QuALiA, AndThE ABiLiTyhypOThESiS

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    18/31

    sociated qualia, qualia cannot possess

    physical causal powers. In Marys case,

    she knows all the physical information

    in the world about color and color vision,

    but she does not know the qualia of see-

    ing color. If qualia had causal powers then

    Mary would know about them because

    she knows all the physical information,

    but because Mary does not know the qua-

    lia involved with seeing color, qualia must

    have no physical manifestations. Thus, de-

    spite being caused by physical brain states,

    qualia lack causal powers, a notion whichcauses qualia to be epiphenomenal. This

    is problematic because it is traditionally

    thought that qualia are causally efcacious.

    While epiphenomenal qualia ini-

    tially appear to present a problem for the

    Knowledge argument, Frank Jackson dem-

    onstrates that there is no knockdown ref-

    utation of the existence of epiphenomenal

    qualia by pointing to multiple objections

    to epiphenomenal qualia and each objec-

    tions downfall (Jackson, 277). One ex-

    ample Jackson gives is that it is generally

    thought that qualia have a physical cause,

    like the hurtfulness of pain and the inclina-

    tion to exhibit pain behavior, for example.

    Jacksons argument is that although it may

    seem like the qualia of pain caused thephysical movement it could also be that it

    is just a coincidence that the two events are

    linked, or perhaps they are linked because

    activating one part of the brain causes both

    to occur (Jackson 276). The other argu-

    ment Jackson presents and then rebuts

    centers around evolution. It states that

    qualia must be an evolved characteristic

    since not all animals have them, and since

    traits are evolved to help animals survive,

    qualia must have been evolved for surviv-

    al purposes. The argument then asks how

    qualia could help humans survive if they

    did nothing in the physical world. Jack-

    son rebuts this argument by noting that

    some evolved characteristics are simply

    side effects of characteristics that evolved

    for survival; they are not helpful in surviv-

    ing. He uses polar bears coats as an ex-

    ample, noting that the coat evolved to be

    a warm coat, but that to make it that wayit was also heavy and slows the animal

    down. The weight of the coat is not con-

    ducive to survival and is just a byproduct

    of the evolution of a warm coat (Jackson

    277). Thus, the idea of epiphenomenal

    qualia is not untenable and the Knowl-

    edge argument continues to stand strong.

    There are Physicalists who think

    that the Knowledge argument can be

    avoided through the use of the Ability Hy-

    pothesis. The Ability Hypothesis focuses

    on a distinction between knowing-that

    and knowing-how. Knowing-that rep-

    resents knowledge of physical informa-

    tion, whereas knowing-how refers to the

    actual action being performed (Lewis 293).

    For example, Mary knows which patternsof neurons re when a person sees red, but

    she does not know how red looks. Propo-

    nents of this argument go on to say that the

    Knowledge argument is mistaken in look-

    ing for a change in factual knowledge be-

    tween what Mary knew before seeing the

    meadow and what she knew after. Instead,

    they argue that Mary learned how, and

    KATySOuThwOrTh

    12

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    19/31

    that learning what an experience is like

    means gaining certain abilitiesabilities to

    remember, imagine, and recognize rather

    than gaining particular sensational knowl-

    edge about the experience (Lewis, 293).

    Through the Ability Hypothesis,

    Physicalists attempt to rebut the Knowl-

    edge argument, but in this attempt they

    fail to acknowledge the importance of sen-

    sations in understanding an experience.

    How does the Ability Hypothesis affect

    Mary? For Mary, the Ability Hypothesis

    implies that the only thing Mary learnedfrom actually seeing colors in the meadow

    was how to remember, imagine, and rec-

    ognize them (Lewis 293). For Mary this

    does not sound like such a bad conclu-

    sion. But now lets think about Bart, who

    is about to go sky diving for the rst time,

    after spending years meticulously studying

    everything there is to know about jump-

    ing out of planes. The sensations that Bart

    feels as he drops through the sky and then

    is whipped upward by the opening of his

    chute the dropping in his stomach and

    the air whooshing by his ears are more

    signicant when discussing what it is like

    to skydive than the sensationless physical

    facts and descriptions that can be used to

    recall or imagine the jump. Thus, while itmay be possible to avoid the conclusions

    of the Knowledge argument with the Abil-

    ity Hypothesis, it is better not to do so in

    order to accurately describe experiences.

    The Knowledge argument shows

    that everything cannot be explained us-

    ing purely physical information. Instead,

    qualia are needed in order to know the

    experience of phenomena feels. While

    Physicalists attempt to rebut this claim

    and avoid the use of qualia either by ex-

    plaining the experience using more pre-

    cise descriptions of what is happening, or

    by explaining the experience by breaking it

    down into sub-experiences, both of these

    methods do not bridge the gap between

    physical facts and what it is like to actu-

    ally experience something. This leaves the

    problem of epiphenomenal qualia, qualia

    which can have no physical cause in the

    world. At rst this seems impossible be-cause qualia are typically thought to have

    causal powers, but Frank Jacksons argu-

    ment demonstrates that it is not necessary

    that qualia have physical causal powers.

    wOrKS CiTEd

    Jackson, Frank. Epiphenomenal Qualia.Philosophical Quarteryly 32: 127-136,1982. Rpt. In Philosophy of Mind: Classi-cal and Contemporary Readings. David J.Chalmers. New York, New York: Oxford,2002.

    Lewis, David. What Experience Teaches,Proceedings of the Russellian Society,

    1988. Rpt. In Philosophy of Mind: Classi-cal and Contemporary Readings. David J.Chalmers. New York, New York: Oxford,2002.

    Nida-Rmelin, Martine, Qualia: TheKnowledge Argument, Stanford Encyclo-pedia of Philosophy. 2002. Web.

    ThE KnOwLEdgE ArgumEnT, QuALiA, AndThE ABiLiTyhypOThESiS

    13

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    20/31

    14

    Saul Kripke, in Identity and Ne-

    cessity, argues that all identity relationsare necessary, and that no identity rela-

    tions are contingent. He concludes from

    this analysis that physicalism is false and

    that the mind and the brain, because one

    can posit a possible world in which a brain

    exists without a mind, are distinct. In this

    paper, I contend that physicalism can be

    saved from Kripkes account of necessary

    identity, and ultimately that the commit-ted physicalist can maintain her position

    while still accepting that all identity is

    necessary. First, I will outline Kripkes ar-

    gument for necessary identity. I will then

    contest the claims that the arguments for

    philosophical zombies and necessary iden-

    tity pose serious problems for physicalism.

    Kripke outlines the argument thatall identity is necessary. He writes, If

    X=Y, then X and Y share all properties, in-

    cluding modal properties (131). If X and

    Y share all modal properties, then it fol-

    lows that X=Y must hold true in all pos-

    sible worlds. Kripke uses the example

    of heat=molecular motion, an identity

    relation that appears to hold contingent-

    ly, but in fact (like every identity rela-

    tion) holds necessarily. The argument for

    Heat=molecular motion as contingent

    rests on the claim that people had very

    specic circumstances in mind under

    which, so they thought, the judgment that

    heat is the motion of molecules would have

    been false. Consequently, those arguing

    for contingent identity need only imagine

    a situation in which we have had the very

    same sensation and it would have been pro-duced by something other than the motion

    of molecules. Kripke disputes this claim,

    arguing that positing such a situation con-

    ates heat with our feeling of heat. Rather,

    Kripke argues, if we identify heat as iden-

    tical with mean molecular kinetic energy,

    then we would have to imagine a situation

    in which heat (as molecular motion) exist-

    ed without molecular motion (128). Sincethis situation is absurd, Kripke concludes

    that if X=Y, X could fail to be Y no more

    than X could fail to be X, and therefore that

    if heat is identical with molecular motion,

    then that identity must be necessary and

    hold true in every possible world. Kripke

    concludes, The identity theorist who holds

    that pain is the brain state, also has to holdthat it is necessarily the brain state He

    has to hold that we are under some illu-

    sion in thinking that we can imagine that

    there could have been pains without brain

    states (132). Thus, for Kripke, we can see

    that if one can conceive of a philosophical

    zombie, a person in a possible world exact-

    ly like a person in our world but without

    any conscious experience, then minds and

    brains are not necessarily identical and if

    they are not necessarily identical, they can-

    not be identical at all, and must be distinct.

    I contend that conceiving of a phil-

    osophical zombie could in fact be used as

    ammunition for a physicalist argument.

    Imagine that a normal human being makes

    the claim I am conscious. Obviously, the

    By: AJAySundAr

    zOmBiE idEnTiTyA dEFEnSEOF phySiCALiSmFrOm KripKES idEnTiTyAnd nECESSiTy

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    21/31

    15

    claim would be true, and barring some

    extreme solipsistic argument, we have no

    reason to doubt that the statement is false.

    However, if a zombie were to utter that ex-

    act same phrase in a possible world, the

    claim would have to be false, since by de-

    nition philosophical zombies are not con-

    scious. now consider the same situation

    except that the phrase is I believe I am

    conscious. while the claim is still true for

    the normal human, the truth-value of the

    zombies claim is far less clear. Presumably

    the zombie could hold this belief even with-out having consciousness, in the same way

    that I could still hold a belief while asleep or

    otherwise unconscious. we must consider

    how this is so. We know of our conscious-

    ness through direct privileged access to it,

    but being conscious by itself does not entail

    the belief of consciousness after all, one

    could be conscious and through stubborn-

    ness or even lunacy deny it. Rather, there

    must be some sort of cognitive mechanism

    to move from consciousness to the belief of

    consciousness, and both the zombie and I

    must have it. whatever this cognitive mech-

    anism is, it must lead in the humans case

    from the (fact that I am conscious to the

    belief that I believe that I am conscious.)

    This same mechanism, which is by deni-tion the same in both the human and the

    zombie, must lead in the zombies case

    from the (incorrect) fact that I am con-

    scious to the same, mistaken, belief that

    I believe I am conscious. If the process

    by which we derive belief of consciousness

    is like this, then we have no reason to con-

    dently assert that we are not philosophi-

    cal zombies, and that we could be just as

    mistaken as the zombie could in our belief

    in conscious states. if this is true, then the

    zombie argument is rendered accid the

    whole point of the zombie experiment was

    to distinguish between the mental (as con-

    scious experience) and physical (as brain),

    but if we have reason to doubt that we have

    conscious experience, then physicalism

    holds: the physicalist could just as eas-

    ily use the zombie thought experiment to

    assert that there is no mind, only brain.

    I will grant Kripkes argument thatwe can conceive of philosophical zombies,

    and I will even grant that mind and body

    are distinct; however, I would argue that

    even given this, physicalism could still be

    salvaged. To do so, I will outline an argu-

    ment rst sketched by Allan Gibbard in

    Contingent Identity. Consider a lump of

    clay, Lumpl, and a statue formed from the

    clay, Goliath. Lumpl is identical with Goli-

    ath: they coincide in their spatiotemporal

    existence, and both pick out one specic

    object in the world. Now imagine that the

    creator smashes the statue, thereby ending

    both the statue and the clay. Here, Gibbard

    argues, the statue and the piece of clay are

    identical. They began at the same time, and

    on any usual account, they had the sameshape, location, color, and so forth ev-

    erything that happened to one happened

    to the other; and the act that destroyed the

    one destroyed the other (191). Now, how-

    ever, Gibbard moves to a parallel example

    he writes, Suppose I had brought Lumpl

    into existence as Goliath, just as I actual-

    ly did, but before the clay had a chance to

    zOmBiE idEnTiTy

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    22/31

    dry, I squeezed it into a ball. In this case,

    the statue would have ceased to exist, but

    the piece of clay would continue to exist.

    Gibbard concludes that this case shows

    an example of contingent identity (192).

    I do not wish to make the exact

    same conclusion as Gibbard to claim that

    the example above is a case of contingent

    identity would pose more problems here

    than it would solve. Rather, I would grant

    the convinced Kripkean that the statue

    and the lump of clay are distinct things,

    but that they are distinct in a non-myste-rious way that physicalism can account

    for. Even if we grant that Lumpl and Go-

    liath are distinct entities, they are distinct

    in a very mundane way, and the statue be-

    ing distinct from the lump of clay does not

    contradict the tenets of physicalism. The

    physicalist could maintain, for example,

    that the statue is a lump of clay that is orga-

    nized in a specic way, and though Goliath

    and Lumpl both point out the same object

    in the world, they differ in the way they are

    organized. In a parallel sense, the mind

    could simply be a brain organized in a cer-

    tain way. The physicalist could also argue

    that Lumpl and Goliath only differ concep-

    tually (with Goliath being picked out by its

    aesthetic qualities and Lumpl by its lackthereof). My argument is not for any given

    specic reason why Goliath and Lumpl are

    distinct, only that if they are indeed dis-

    tinct; they are distinct in a way that can

    be accounted for by physicalism. If such a

    physicalist explanation can be accounted

    for between Goliath and Lumpl, a parallel

    explanation can be accounted for between

    mind and brain as well. Insofar as a physi-

    calist account can be given in this manner,

    the notion of minds and brains as distinct

    no longer poses a threat to physicalism,

    but rather physicalism can still hold even

    if minds and brains are distinct entities.

    The core of my argument is not that

    minds and brains are not distinct, or that

    contingent identity is possible or impos-

    sible. Rather, I believe that even if con-

    tingent identity is impossible, and even if

    minds and brains are distinct, a coherent

    physicalist account can still stick despiteclaims to the contrary. Even if philosophi-

    cal zombies are conceivable, the physicalist

    can account for them, and can even use the

    idea of zombies as support for physicalism.

    Moreover, even if minds and brains are

    distinct, they can be distinct without re-

    linquishing physicalism, at least insofar as

    a statue and a lump of clay can be distinct

    without appeal to the supernatural. Thus,

    while Kripkes arguments are compelling

    as reasons against contingent identity,

    they need not pose the problems for physi-

    calism that appear on the surface. This

    would suggest a revision of physicalism to

    create coherent theses for the mind-body

    problem, and such a revision, though likely

    large in scope and detail, provides hope forprogression within the physicalist position.

    wOrKS CiTEd

    Kripke, Saul A. Identity and Necessity.

    Philosophy of Mind: a guide and anthol-

    ogy. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2004. 128-33.16

    AJAySundAr

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    23/31

    17

    Print.

    Gibbard, Allan. Contingent Identity.

    Journal of Philosophical Logic 4.2 (1975):

    187-221. Print.

    zOmBiE idEnTiTy

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    24/31

    Paradoxes of coincidence arise from

    the problem of co-location: How can dis-tinct objects wholly exist in one place at the

    same time? To fully address these puzzles,

    we must restrict the question at hand to

    material objects subject to the natural laws

    of our universe. We say objects coincide if

    and only if they share the same spatial lo-

    cation and are comprised of identical parts

    at or during a given time. Furthermore, by

    Leibnizs Law, we say objects are numeri-cally distinct if do not share the exact same

    set of properties. Of the many solutions to

    the paradoxes of coincidence, most fall into

    one of two categories: monism or pluralism.

    Monism adheres to the anti-coincidence

    principle, which states only one object can

    exist in a specic spatial location at a given

    time. Specically, I will address the domi-nant sorts account, which claims coincid-

    ing objects are dominated by the sort that

    determines its persistence conditions. On

    the other hand, pluralism rejects the anti-

    coincidence principle, embracing the no-

    tion that multiple objects can be co-located

    and share identical parts. Of the views that

    fall into this category, I will address the

    temporal parts account, which presupposes

    perdurantism [i]. This account claims that

    objects coincide at a given time if and only

    if their temporal segments perfectly over-

    lap. Although both monist and pluralist

    solutions provide convincing support, the

    paradoxes of coincidence are best resolved

    by the temporal parts account because it

    strictly obeys Leibnizs Law without caving

    to philosophical concessions. Moreover, it

    explains coincidence in a way that is unob-jectionable; it reduces coincidence to noth-

    ing more than the temporal equivalent of

    overlapping roads. I will begin by laying

    out two examples of the paradoxes of co-

    incidence and will follow by explaining

    how the dominant sorts account and tem-

    poral parts account attempt to solve them.

    At rst glance, it seems ridiculous to

    say material objects ever coincide. Peoplecannot coincide with walls, protons cannot

    coincide with neutrons, and so on. All fac-

    ets of our universe seem to oppose material

    coincidence as we have dened it. But cer-

    tain cases force us to think otherwise. First,

    let us consider the case of the clay and the

    statue. Suppose an artist nds a lump of

    clay, and after days of hard work, sculptsthe clay into the statue of David. Although

    it is intuitive to say the statue and the lump

    are the same, further thought shows they

    differ in a variety of aspects. They have dif-

    ferent histories: the lump existed before

    the artists efforts, but the statue did not.

    Additionally, they have opposing modal

    properties: the lump can survive being

    smashed, but the statue cannot. It follows

    from Leibnizs Law that the two objects are

    distinct. So while it appears the artist has

    only one object in his possession, it seems

    there are actually two, both of which occu-

    py a single location and consist of identical

    parts. A second case is that of Tibbles and

    Tib. Suppose Tibbles is a fully functioning

    male cat, while Tib consists of every part

    By: AdAm SAdAKA(EdiTOr)

    TEmpOrAL OVErLApASASOLuTiOnTOThE pArAdOxESOF COinCidEnCE

    18

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    25/31

    of Tibbles save for his tail. Tibbles and Tib

    are distinct in a variety of ways. For one,

    Tibbles and Tib are comprised of different

    parts. Furthermore, their modal proper-

    ties are different: Tibbles potentially can

    wag his tail, while Tib can never undertake

    such an action. By Leibnizs Law, Tibbles

    and Tib cannot be one and the same. Now

    imagine Tibbles is in a terrible car crash re-

    sulting in the loss of his tail. Surely Tibbles

    survives, as cats can survive the loss of an

    outer appendage. Obviously Tib survives

    as well, unharmed by the accident. We areleft with the fact that after the accident, two

    distinct objects wholly exist in one place,

    the cat-except-a-tail region, and share all

    the same cat-parts. Hence, it appears it is

    possible for two material objects to be co-

    located and comprised of identical parts.

    The dominant sorts account is a

    monist solution to these issues. The afore-

    mentioned paradoxes distinguish between

    two distinct entities which are said to co-

    incide. The dominant sorts account does

    away with the problem of co-location by

    eliminating one of the two contenders.

    Consider the following principle: For any

    object O and sort S, if O is an S, then the

    persistence conditions of O are determined

    by S [ii]. This principle seems completelyrational, but runs into trouble when faced

    with the paradoxes of coincidence. If one

    object is clearly two different things, how

    can it have opposing persistence condi-

    tions? The dominant sorts account of coin-

    cidence rejects this principle, and instead

    claims that if an object O is of two sorts,

    S1 and S2, it can only have the persistence

    conditions associated with its dominant

    sort. The dominant sort is dened as that

    which determines the objects persistence

    conditions [iii]. Take the paradox of the

    lump of clay and the statue. Before the art-

    ist molds the clay, the object in question is

    only a lump and nothing else, and there-

    fore its persistence conditions are in accor-

    dance with that sort. (For ease, call it SLUMP

    )

    Thus, SLUMP

    must be this objects dominant

    sort. But when the lump is molded into a

    statue, we encounter the paradox: the ob-

    ject is seemingly both a lump and a statue,and therefore is of both sorts. The object

    in question is ostensibly both SLUMP

    and

    SSTATUE

    ; however, new persistence condi-

    tions (e.g. cannot survive being smashed)

    result in SSTATUE

    becoming the objects

    dominant sort. One object cannot magical-

    ly become a different one, so it follows that

    the original lump must be destroyed when

    the statue comes into existence. No object

    can change its dominant sort. We are left

    with an object that is solely a statue and

    no longer a lump of clay, conforming to

    the anti-coincidence principle. Similarly,

    in the case of Tibbles and Tib, we must say

    that after the accident, Tib goes out of exis-

    tence. The surviving object from the crash

    is still a functioning cat that eats, dreams,sleeps, thinks, and so on, even though he

    no longer has a tail. Because the persis-

    tence conditions of cats allow for the loss

    of appendages, we must classify what is left

    of Tibbles to exclusively be Tibbles. That

    is, STIBBLES

    is the objects dominant sort.

    Because no object can change its domi-

    nant sort, Tib must be annihilated in the19

    TEmpOrAL OVErLAp ASASOLuTiOnTOThE pArAdOxESOF COinCidEnCE

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    26/31

    20

    AdAm SAdAKA(EdiTOr)

    process. Therefore the object in question

    (a cat without a tail) is only Tibbles, which

    observes the anti-coincidence principle.

    Although the dominant sorts ac-

    count apparently solves the paradoxes of

    coincidence, there is something very odd

    about saying the lump of clay simply goes

    out of existence when it is sculpted and

    that Tib goes out of existence even though

    it goes untouched. This view is highly

    counterintuitive. What is more troubling is

    what happens when the statue is smashed.

    After smashing the statue, it would seemthat the resulting object is once again a

    lump. But because no object can change its

    dominant sort, this account asserts that a

    new lump of clay is created. The new lump

    differs from the original lump because the

    two have different histories (the new lump

    came into existence only after smashing

    the statue), therefore the two lumps must

    be numerically distinct. It seems highly im-

    plausible to say we can annihilate a lump

    of clay by merely molding it, and then cre-

    ate a new, different lump of clay merely

    by smashing a statue, even though both

    lumps are composed of identical parts.

    The dominant sorts account faces

    even larger problems when we consider

    some denitions of modern art. Supposethat instead of sculpting the lump of clay

    into a statue, the artist leaves it as is, and

    decides he would like to invite all of his art-

    ist friends to judge his new work. Imag-

    ine further that all of his friends consider

    his work to be a masterpiece and a per-

    fect representation of postmodern cubism.

    Although the artist has not altered the clay

    in any way whatsoever, the lump of clay

    no longer exists and has been replaced by

    a postmodern cubist statue. If our percep-

    tion of aesthetics alone is the sole require-

    ment to create art, then our perception is

    all that is needed to destroy a lump of clay.

    Correspondingly, if we change our aesthet-

    ic preferences, we can destroy the artwork

    and create a new lump of clay. The same

    line of thought applies to the case of Tibbles

    and Tib. After the accident, Tib is entirely

    unharmed, so it is odd to say Tib is annihi-

    lated when Tibbles loses his tail. To claimthe loss of an external part can destroy a

    separate object seems highly outlandish.

    But if we suppose Tib survives, we would

    be forced into saying Tibbles dies from the

    loss of his tail, which also seems wrong (In

    general, cats can survive such traumas).

    Furthermore, because Tib shares a head

    with Tibbles, it is plausible that Tib en-

    gages in cat-like activities as Tibbles does,

    such as eating, thinking, and so on. We are

    left with an epistemic choice to determine

    which object survives and which object is

    destroyed. In both cases, it is ridiculous to

    presume we can create and destroy materi-

    al objects with the power of thought alone.

    A nal blow to the dominant sorts

    view is that it cannot account for coin-ciding objects of the same sort. Suppose

    there is a single piece of paper that con-

    tains two identical memos written at dif-

    ferent times. Again, we encounter an ob-

    ject that is two distinct objects (differing

    histories) in the same place at the same

    time. Because both are of the same sort,

    SMEMO, the persistence conditions of both

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    27/31

    21

    TEmpOrAL OVErLAp ASASOLuTiOnTOThE pArAdOxESOF COinCidEnCE

    are identical, so it is impossible to assign

    a dominant sort. This account cannot ad-

    equately solve paradoxes of this nature.

    Pluralists reject the anti-coincidence

    principle and accept the notion that two or

    more distinct objects can share the same

    parts and location at a given time. This ap-

    proach is best explained by the temporal

    parts account of coincidence. While it may

    be counterintuitive to say two distinct ob-

    jects wholly coincide, by this view, there is

    really nothing problematic about it. From

    this perspective, coincidence can be best vi-sualized by considering overlapping roads:

    Consider now the case of U.S. Route 29,

    which runs from the western suburbs of

    Baltimore, Maryland, to Pensacola, Flori-

    da. As U.S. 29 passes through Charlotte it

    becomes Tyson St.a street wholly located

    within the state of North Carolina. The two

    roadways in this case are not identical, but

    they are partly identical, for Tyson St. is iden-

    tical to a proper spatial part of U.S. 29 [iv].

    By presupposing perdurantism, the tempo-

    ral parts account denes coincidence to be

    a given time, or time interval, when distinct

    temporal segments perfectly overlap, just

    as Tyson Street perfectly overlaps a seg-

    ment of U.S. Route 29. During the overlap,

    neither object is exclusively present; in-stead, they equally occupy one four-dimen-

    sional region in space-time. This accounts

    for why we identify only one object when

    two distinct objects coincide. It follows that

    if coinciding objects occupy a single loca-

    tion, they must also share parts at the time

    of coincidence. Consider again the case of

    the lump of clay and the statue. According

    to the temporal parts account, the lump

    of clay is a four-dimensional space-time

    worm, while the statue is a shorter, distinct

    worm. After the clay is sculpted, we seem-

    ingly have two distinct objects coinciding

    in one location. According to the temporal

    parts account, the statue-worm intersects

    a temporal segment of the lump-worm at

    the time (or time interval) of coincidence.

    Therefore, the statue-worm composed of

    the lumps temporal slices that span the

    time of coincidence. Because both persist-

    ing objects share a temporal segment, at agiven moment both objects share a three-

    dimensional location. As a result, we only

    perceive one physical object but accept the

    existence of both the statue and lump. The

    case of Tibbles and Tib can be viewed in a

    similar light. This case is equivalent to a

    road in which one lane merges into the main

    road [v]. Tibbles and Tib are both persist-

    ing four-dimensional objects, and after the

    accident, their temporal worms merge into

    one four-dimensional region and perfectly

    overlap. Although they are distinct objects,

    Tibbles and Tib are perfectly co-located

    and therefore share all the same parts at

    the time of coincidence. In both cases, two

    distinct objects share one location and one

    set of parts. The temporal parts accountperfectly explains these paradoxes of coin-

    cidence, allowing objects with distinct his-

    tories and different modal properties to be

    co-located and composed of identical parts.

    Although the temporal parts theory

    of coincidence accounts for many of the

    shortcomings that plague the dominant

    sorts account, it faces its own set of criti-

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    28/31

    22

    AdAm SAdAKA(EdiTOr)

    cisms. This view runs into trouble when we

    consider two distinct, coinciding objects

    that come into existence and are destroyed

    at the same moments in time. For example,

    suppose that through some chemical acci-

    dent, clay is created from aqueous miner-

    als. Moreover, suppose that the clay comes

    into existence in the form of the statue of

    David. Although the lump of clay and the

    statue are created simultaneously, they still

    differ in a number of aspects and must be

    considered distinct from one another. Now

    imagine the chemist treats his product witha series of chemicals that instantly disin-

    tegrate the object, annihilating the statue

    and lump together. These distinct space-

    time worms are numerically identical, per-

    fectly overlapping at every instant of their

    existence. This creates a paradox: at the

    core of four-dimensionalism is the belief

    that every distinct object is a unique space-

    time worm. If two objects have identical

    worms, they must be one in the same; how-

    ever, this cannot be the case here because

    the statue and lump of clay are denitively

    distinct. The answer to this objection is as

    follows: The object in question is bound to

    our universe, but it has counterparts in al-

    ternate universes that account for all pos-

    sible ascriptions. Simply put, just becausethe two space-time worms happen to be

    identical in one case does not assure they

    must be identical in all cases. It is plausible

    to assume that in an alternate universe,

    the product of the accident is smashed by a

    hammer rather than annihilated by chemi-

    cals. In this alternate case, the lump would

    survive, but the statue would be destroyed.

    Even when objects have entirely identi-

    cal histories and properties, Leibnizs Law

    still distinguishes them by their modal

    possibilities. Unlike other solutions to

    the paradoxes of coincidence, embracing

    Leibnizs Law in the strictest sense does

    not weaken the temporal parts account.

    One of the most appealing features of

    the temporal parts account of coincidence

    is that it actually embraces the notion of

    coincidence. Unlike monist solutions, the

    temporal parts theory uses Leibnizs Law

    to its advantage, grounding its frameworkin the undisputable claim that two distinct

    objects are present wherever coincidence

    occurs. The dominant sorts account of co-

    incidence fails precisely because it tries to

    circumvent Leibnizs Law. By recognizing

    only the sort that determines persistence,

    this view fails to fully account for the true

    nature of an object. An object might be a

    letter, but when it is folded into a paper

    plane, the dominant sorts account claims

    the letter goes out of existence, even though

    it is clearly still there. On the other hand,

    the temporal parts account captures co-

    incidence in the literal sense: two distinct

    objects simultaneously existing in one giv-

    en location. By positing that coincidence

    occurs during the overlap of four-dimen-sional temporal segments, this view ex-

    plains coincidence in a way that is not only

    conceptually simple, but also undeniable.

    wOrKS CiTEd

    Hawley, Katherine. Temporal Parts.

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    29/31

    23

    TEmpOrAL OVErLAp ASASOLuTiOnTOThE pArAdOxESOF COinCidEnCE

    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 1

    Oct. 2004. Web.

    Sider, Theodore. Four-Dimensionalism

    An Ontology of Persistence and Time).

    New York: Oxford UP, 2003. Print.

    Wasserman, Ryan. Material Constitu-

    tion. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philoso-

    phy. 25 Feb. 2009. Web.

    nOTES

    [i] Objects persist through space-time as

    four-dimensional worms and have tem-

    poral parts; distinct objects have distinct

    space-time worms.

    [ii] Material Constitution, Stanford En-

    cyclopedia of Philosophy, 2009 ed.

    [iii] Theodore Sider, Four-Dimensional-

    ism An Ontology of Persistence and Time

    (New York: Oxford UP, 2003), 162.

    [iv] Material Constitution, S.E.P.

    [v] Sider 152.

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    30/31

  • 8/9/2019 Spring 2010 Final Print

    31/31

    Enquiry is Washington Universitys undergraduate journal of philosophy.Our mission is to provide a showcase for undergraduate students philo-

    sophical writing, and to enhance the philosophical community at Washing-ton University. Each year, the editorial staff selects high-quality submis-

    sions from students for publication in the new edition of the journal.

    The editorial staff is comprised of the members of Poiesis, undergraduatestudents committed to philosophical pursuits and academic excellence.

    For more information, please email:[email protected]

    Or visit our blog:enquiryphilosophy.blogspot.com

    ABOuT EnQuiry