1
5 Cracraft, J. (1983) Species concepts and speciation analysis. Curr. Ornithol. 1, 159–187 6 Ghiselin, M. (1974) A radical solution to the species problem. System. Zool. 23, 536–544 7 Hull, D. (1976) Are species really individuals? System. Zool. 25, 174–191 8 Sober, E. (1984) The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus, Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press 9 Mayr, E. (1963) Animal Species and Evolution, Belknap Press 10 Templeton, A.R. (1989) The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. In Speciation and its consequences (Otte, D. and Endler, J.A. eds), pp. 3–27, Sinauer 11 Bush, G.L. (1994) Sympatric speciation in animals: new wine in old bottles. Trends Ecol. Evol. 9, 285–288 Published online: 21 August 2002 Species concepts versus species criteria Response from Werner Kunz Richard Paul’s letter is of great importance for parasitologists because it highlights the species debate. Within a group of similar parasitic individuals, some can be specific for one host, others for another; some can be pathogenic, others not; some can be sensitive to a drug and others are resistant. As a result of these data, individual parasites can be classified into groups. In several cases, host specificity, pathogenicity and drug resistance cannot be seen immediately with our eyes when we observe a parasite in a test tube or under the microscope; therefore, we prefer to use morphological or molecular traits as a ‘number plate’ to recognize which group the respective individual belongs to. However, biodiversity is much more heterogeneous and complex than taxonomists want for their aim of classification, particularly in light of the fact that each individual differs from the other by thousands, if not tens of thousands, of different alleles [1]. Taxonomists have to find out which individuals, having one or a few traits in common, belong to a common species. If we are to encourage parasitologists into the species debate and the study of speciation, it is essential to provide the foundations. Otherwise, there is a serious danger of running into contradictions. Paul’s letter contains some contradictions. If a species is a ‘cross-section in an evolutionary lineage’, it cannot be at the same time, ‘a chunk of phylogenetic nexus’. Which time interval is covered by this ‘cross-section’? One second, or a thousand years? Even during a short time interval, mutation and selection can change several traits in some individuals. Consequently, after a certain time, several genes and phenotypic characters are not the same as they were before. So, when does a species begin and when does it end? We cannot define a species as a slice of a sausage, while at the same time, we acknowledge its spatiotemporal dimension. Furthermore, what does ‘a single line of direct ancestry and descent’ mean? This would be easy to understand if we look at clonal propagation. But what are separate lineages in highly polymorphic populations? Are they gene lineages or lineages of species? These are not necessarily the same [2]. Sexuality, in addition, often ignores separate lineages because in certain groups of organisms, or under certain conditions, hybridization among different lineages occurs, resulting in genetic introgression of parts of the genome into non-directly related organisms. In several plants, in some animals, particularly in parasites, and, to a spectacular extent, in protists, new groups of organisms can arise by hybridization of distantly related groups, replacing the radiation principle of the evolutionary tree by a ‘modular principle’, contradicting the branching tree of Darwin and Haeckel [3]. Therefore, within certain limits, the formation of networks obscures proper lineages. Does Mayr’s biological species concept (population thinking) offer a solution? First, it is most important to discriminate between the properties of a population and those of its individuals. The properties of a population are, for example, population density or balanced polymorphism. The bearers of properties (such as colours, feathers, sexuality and reproduction) are not populations or reproductive communities, but only the individuals of populations. Individuals can mutate, populations cannot and, consequently, almost all the targets of selection are the traits of individuals, not those of the population. In other words, a population can evolve only in an indirect sense, namely as a consequence of the evolution of the individuals, which belong to that population [4]. Unfortunately, our daily language is not precise. We say that a certain species has a yellow bill. In fact, it is the individuals, not the species, which have a yellow bill. Under normal conditions, our abbreviated manner of speaking is harmless because we are able to state it more precisely, if necessary. However, such manner of speaking can become dangerous, when we construct theories or definitions. With this intention, it is a logical mistake to attribute the properties of the members of a class to the class [4]. The species is not a material object. It is the result of a conceptual operation that combines individuals into a set in a mathematical sense. Of course, cladistic lineages and reproductive communities are real, but they are completely different from taxa. In some examples, a taxon can be understood as the transfer of such natural things into an artificial taxonomic system [5]. All real objects that will be used (and misunderstood) as species are only useful as an indicator for subsequent taxonomic classification. The reproductive community, for example, sometimes can be used to group individuals into a species taxon. However, in the majority of organismic biodiversity, particularly in plants, but also in several animal groups, a reproductive community either does not exist, or it represents a group of organisms that is not suited by any means to be used as a species taxon. Reproductive barriers are often not the cause of divergent evolution, nor are they essential for it to occur [6]. Also, sexual interaction is not a definition for a species because it does not tell us what a species is. Werner Kunz Section of Genetic Parasitology, Heinrich Heine University, Institute for Genetics, Universitätsstrasse 1, D-40225 Düsseldorf, Germany. e-mail: [email protected] References 1 Powell, J.R. (1997) Progress and Prospects in Evolutionary Biology – The Drosophila Model. Oxford University Press 2 Nichols, R. (2001) Gene trees and species trees are not the same. Trends Ecol. Evol. 16, 358–364 3 Doolittle, W.F. (1999) Phylogenetic classification and the universal tree. Science 284, 2124–2129 4 Mahner, M. and Bunge, M. (1997) Foundations of Biophilosophy. Springer-Verlag 5 Mahner, M. (1998) Why evolution still exists if species do not evolve. Theory Biosci. 117, 173–199 6 Mishler, B.D. and Donoghue, M.J. (1994) Species concepts: a case for pluralism. In: Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology. (Sober, E. ed.), pp. 217–232, Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press Published online: 21 August 2002 TRENDS in Parasitology Vol.18 No.10 October 2002 http://parasites.trends.com 1471-4922/02/$ – see front matter © 2002 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. PII: S1471-4922(02)02320-6 440 News & Comment

Species concepts versus species criteria: Response from Werner Kunz

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Species concepts versus species criteria: Response from Werner Kunz

5 Cracraft, J. (1983) Species concepts andspeciation analysis. Curr. Ornithol. 1, 159–187

6 Ghiselin, M. (1974) A radical solution to thespecies problem. System. Zool. 23, 536–544

7 Hull, D. (1976) Are species really individuals?System. Zool. 25, 174–191

8 Sober, E. (1984) The Nature of Selection:Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus,Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press

9 Mayr, E. (1963) Animal Species and Evolution,Belknap Press

10 Templeton, A.R. (1989) The meaning of speciesand speciation: a genetic perspective. InSpeciation and its consequences (Otte, D. andEndler, J.A. eds), pp. 3–27, Sinauer

11 Bush, G.L. (1994) Sympatric speciation inanimals: new wine in old bottles. Trends Ecol.Evol. 9, 285–288

Published online: 21 August 2002

Species conceptsversus species criteriaResponse from Werner Kunz

Richard Paul’s letter is of great importancefor parasitologists because it highlightsthe species debate. Within a group ofsimilar parasitic individuals, some can bespecific for one host, others for another;some can be pathogenic, others not; somecan be sensitive to a drug and others areresistant. As a result of these data,individual parasites can be classified intogroups. In several cases, host specificity,pathogenicity and drug resistance cannotbe seen immediately with our eyes whenwe observe a parasite in a test tube or underthe microscope; therefore, we prefer to usemorphological or molecular traits as a‘number plate’to recognize which group therespective individual belongs to. However,biodiversity is much more heterogeneousand complex than taxonomists want fortheir aim of classification, particularly inlight of the fact that each individualdiffers from the other by thousands, if nottens of thousands, of different alleles [1].Taxonomists have to find out whichindividuals, having one or a few traits incommon, belong to a common species.

If we are to encourage parasitologistsinto the species debate and the study ofspeciation, it is essential to provide thefoundations. Otherwise, there is a seriousdanger of running into contradictions.Paul’s letter contains some contradictions.If a species is a ‘cross-section in anevolutionary lineage’, it cannot be at thesame time, ‘a chunk of phylogenetic nexus’.

Which time interval is covered by this‘cross-section’? One second, or a thousandyears? Even during a short time interval,mutation and selection can change severaltraits in some individuals. Consequently,after a certain time, several genes andphenotypic characters are not the same asthey were before. So, when does a speciesbegin and when does it end? We cannotdefine a species as a slice of a sausage,while at the same time, we acknowledgeits spatiotemporal dimension.

Furthermore, what does ‘a single line ofdirect ancestry and descent’mean? Thiswould be easy to understand if we look atclonal propagation. But what are separatelineages in highly polymorphic populations?Are they gene lineages or lineages ofspecies? These are not necessarily thesame [2]. Sexuality, in addition, oftenignores separate lineages because in certaingroups of organisms, or under certainconditions, hybridization among differentlineages occurs, resulting in geneticintrogression of parts of the genome intonon-directly related organisms. In severalplants, in some animals, particularly inparasites, and, to a spectacular extent, inprotists, new groups of organisms canarise by hybridization of distantly relatedgroups, replacing the radiation principleof the evolutionary tree by a ‘modularprinciple’, contradicting the branching treeof Darwin and Haeckel [3]. Therefore,within certain limits, the formation ofnetworks obscures proper lineages.

Does Mayr’s biological species concept(population thinking) offer a solution? First,it is most important to discriminate betweenthe properties of a population and those ofits individuals. The properties of apopulation are, for example, populationdensity or balanced polymorphism. Thebearers of properties (such as colours,feathers, sexuality and reproduction) are notpopulations or reproductive communities,but only the individuals of populations.Individuals can mutate, populations cannotand, consequently, almost all the targets ofselection are the traits of individuals, notthose of the population. In other words, apopulation can evolve only in an indirectsense, namely as a consequence of theevolution of the individuals, which belongto that population [4].

Unfortunately, our daily language is notprecise. We say that a certain species has ayellow bill. In fact, it is the individuals, notthe species, which have a yellow bill. Undernormal conditions, our abbreviated manner

of speaking is harmless because we are ableto state it more precisely, if necessary.However, such manner of speaking canbecome dangerous, when we constructtheories or definitions. With this intention,it is a logical mistake to attribute theproperties of the members of a class tothe class [4].

The species is not a material object. It isthe result of a conceptual operation thatcombines individuals into a set in amathematical sense. Of course, cladisticlineages and reproductive communitiesare real, but they are completely differentfrom taxa. In some examples, a taxon canbe understood as the transfer of suchnatural things into an artificial taxonomicsystem [5]. All real objects that will beused (and misunderstood) as species areonly useful as an indicator for subsequenttaxonomic classification. The reproductivecommunity, for example, sometimes canbe used to group individuals into a speciestaxon. However, in the majority oforganismic biodiversity, particularly inplants, but also in several animal groups,a reproductive community either does notexist, or it represents a group of organismsthat is not suited by any means to be usedas a species taxon. Reproductive barriersare often not the cause of divergentevolution, nor are they essential for it tooccur [6]. Also, sexual interaction is not adefinition for a species because it does nottell us what a species is.

Werner Kunz

Section of Genetic Parasitology, Heinrich Heine University, Institute forGenetics, Universitätsstrasse 1, D-40225 Düsseldorf, Germany.e-mail: [email protected]

References

1 Powell, J.R. (1997) Progress and Prospects inEvolutionary Biology – The Drosophila Model.Oxford University Press

2 Nichols, R. (2001) Gene trees and species trees arenot the same. Trends Ecol. Evol. 16, 358–364

3 Doolittle, W.F. (1999) Phylogenetic classificationand the universal tree. Science 284, 2124–2129

4 Mahner, M. and Bunge, M. (1997) Foundations ofBiophilosophy. Springer-Verlag

5 Mahner, M. (1998) Why evolution still exists if species do not evolve. Theory Biosci. 117,173–199

6 Mishler, B.D. and Donoghue, M.J. (1994) Speciesconcepts: a case for pluralism. In: ConceptualIssues in Evolutionary Biology. (Sober, E. ed.),pp. 217–232, Massachusetts Institute ofTechnology Press

Published online: 21 August 2002

TRENDS in Parasitology Vol.18 No.10 October 2002

http://parasites.trends.com 1471-4922/02/$ – see front matter © 2002 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. PII: S1471-4922(02)02320-6

440 News&Comment