13
Le rire à nouveau: Rereading Bergson Author(s): Bernard G. Prusak Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 (Autumn, 2004), pp. 377-388 Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1559232 Accessed: 03-11-2016 12:40 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1559232?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    1

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

Le rire à nouveau: Rereading Bergson

Author(s): Bernard G. Prusak

Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 (Autumn, 2004), pp.

377-388

Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics

Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1559232

Accessed: 03-11-2016 12:40 UTC

REFERENCES

Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:

http://www.jstor.org/stable/1559232?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents

You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted

digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about

JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

http://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve andextend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 2: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

BERNARD G. PRUSAK

Le nire a nouveau: Rereading Bergson

Although Henri Bergson's 1900 Le rire. Essai creative artist whose every gesture redefines the sur la signification du comique predates his avant-garde. In Le rire, this tension between L'e'volution cre'atrice by seven years, the earlier matter and the elan vital makes its debut. book not only anticipates, but is already organ- According to Bergson, the comic is born from a ized by the doctrine of the elan vital or "life conflict between matter and what L'e'volution drive" that the later book would elaborate. It is cre'atrice would identify as the principle of argued in this paper that Bergson' s metaphysics human life, namely, "intelligence." distorts Le rire's account of laughter and the Le rire presents, then, a metaphysics of nature of the comic. A critical reading of laughter. To be sure, the book does not expli- this book, however, also finds in it insights citly advance the doctrine of the elan vital; that Bergson himself apparently did not see. however, this doctrine operates in the back- Notably, we stand to gain new insight into the ground.3 In light of this fact, I propose here to meaning of the scholastic proposition, Homo est consider two questions: first, whether Bergson' s animal risibile. metaphysics distorts his account of laughter and

Why did Bergson write Le rire?1 Toward the the comic; and second, if so, whether we can book's beginning, he gives five reasons: to learn from his book nevertheless. I answer yes learn about (1) laughter and (2) the nature of to both questions. things comic, but also (3) "the social, collective, and popular imagination," (4) art, and (5) what

he calls life or, more precisely, the character of I. INCONGRUITY, SUPERIORITY, AND THE DEMANDS everyday life or, better yet, what Martin OF SOCIETY Heidegger would later call "everydayness" (R 2/L 8). In retrospect, however, we can also Let us begin again, then, with both the title of see that Le rire anticipates, even prepares the Bergson's book, Le rire. Essai sur la significa- way for, L'evolution cre'atrice, the book that tion du comique, and its opening sentences, gave rise to "Bergsonism" as a popular move- "What does laughter mean? What is at the ment and made Bergson so influential that in bottom of the laughable?" (R 1/L 7). From title 1914 the Holy Office, struggling with the crisis to subtitle and first question to second, there is a of "modernism" in the Church, felt compelled subtle but significant displacement: away from to put his writings on the Index of Prohibited laughter to the laughable or the comic. (Bergson Books. In L'evolution cre'atrice, Bergson elabo- employs the terms "the laughable" and "the rates the thesis that the evolution of life is best comic" interchangeably.) Given this displace- understood not as the product of blind muta- ment, the question might be asked: What right tions, but as the expression of an elan vital does the book have to its title? As the anthro- seeking to realize ever higher and higher forms pologist Mary Douglas remarks, Bergson in fact of life.2 This "life-drive" is limited only by the "says very little about laughter," or, more resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4 work to date. This work is never finished. Little, but not nothing. Bergson calls atten- Instead, the life-drive is like an eternally tion to the "bodiliness" of laughter in criticizing

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62:4 Fall 2004

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 3: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

378 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

the so-called incongruity theory of laughter, ments of our fellow pedestrians and of the birds, which locates the inducement to laughter in "a dogs, and so forth that may cross our way. Fur- surprising disproportion between that which ther, we need to be able to coordinate our move- one expects and that which one sees."5 Kant's ments with all these movements surrounding us: and Scho penhauer's theories may serve as we need to be able to go with the flow, to bob examples. According to Kant, laughter arises and to weave our way to our destination. If we out of "the sudden transformation of a strained do not have the "elasticity of body and mind" to expectation into nothing," or, in other words, its do what it takes-if, instead of bobbing and reduction to absurdity (his italics). To explain weaving, we can only amble stiffly along, the bodily expression of laughter, he postulates bumping into every urinating dog or flapping, a parallelism between body and mind: as he diving bird that strays into our path; if, seeing sees it, the body's convulsions reflect its sym- no way to extract ourselves from the flow, we pathy with the mind's jostling.7 According to make it our habit to stop in the middle of the Schopenhauer: "Laughter originates in every sidewalk and to stand still, perhaps to read the instance from nothing other than the suddenly newspaper until the crowd diminishes, or sud- perceived incongruity between a concept and denly to make a wild leap for it when we sense a the real objects that had been thought through hole-we risk making a comic spectacle of it... and is itself only the expression of this ourselves. Schoolchildren will come to watch incongruity," a reflex reaction to "mental us, adults will talk about us at dinner parties, we stimuli."8 Against such thinkers, Bergson puts will become figures of fun. But our spectators, the question, "Why should it be that the percep- too, will need to be vigilant. Bergson further tion of this particular logical relation [of observes that it is not enough, in society, just to incongruity] contracts, dilates, and shakes us, live, to satisfy the essential, say, to make it while [all other such relations] leave our body without incident to our destination and through indifferent?" (R 6/L 12). He makes a similar our day. Society also demands that its parti- remark in his book's appendix, included as of cipants live well, display suppleness rather than 1924: "I do not see ... why 'disharmony,' as stiffness, be flexible rather than mechanical, disharmony, should provoke from its witnesses quick rather than dull. Here schoolchildren and a specific manifestation such as laugher, while adults at dinner parties find themselves at risk. so many other properties, qualities, or flaws The mispronounced word, missed allusion, leave the spectator's facial muscles unmoved" misunderstood joke, abnormality, eccentricity, (R 157).9 The incongruity theory also suffers obliviousness to what is a' la mode or de from the obvious problem that we do not laugh rigueur, all the rage or "gotta have"-these too at all occasions of incongruity. 10 can be fatal, if comic, flaws.

Still, Bergson does not turn to a study of the On this interpretation, the bodily expression bodily expression as bodily expression. Instead, of laughter is essentially punitive: it is a punish- he immediately looks away from the body. "In ment that society inflicts on persons exhibiting order to understand laughter," Bergson writes, behavior that offends society's sense of recti- "we must return it to its natural milieu, which is tude, that gives evidence of stiffness of body or society; we must, before all else, determine the mind where there should be vigilance, elasticity, function for which it is used, which is a social or ilan. Here, Bergson's metaphysics enters the function. Such will be ... the guiding idea of all picture. To use several of Bergson's better- our investigations" (R 6/L 13). known formulations, we laugh at "automatism

According to Bergson, what makes some- installed within life and imitating life" (R 25/L thing laughable, at bottom, is that it is somehow 34), at the "mechanical encrusted upon the offensive in relation to social norms and ideals. living" (R 29/L 39), and at the "sudden trans- Life in society, Bergson observes, demands "of figuration of a person into a thing" (R 44/L 56). each of us a constant attention and wake- We laugh, in short, at incongruities, but not just fulness," "an elasticity of body and mind" to any incongruities, which for Bergson is the discern and perform whatever the present decisive point. We do not laugh at just any demands (R 14/L 22). Walking down the street, incongruity or disproportion, but at a quality for example, we need to be aware of the move- "that this disproportion can in some instances

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 4: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

Prusak Le rire a' nouveau: Rereading Bergson 379

disclose," namely, life sending up itself in the This description of laughter seems, however, guise of the mechanical (R 65/L 81). In an oft- somewhat fantastical. Also, does it not apply quoted criticism of Bergson's theory, Arthur just as well to crying?) Koestler writes: "If 'we laugh each time a In making this argument, Bergson appropri- person gives us the impression of being a thing' ates the so-called superiority theory of laughter, there would be nothing more funny than a classically formulated by Hobbes and retrieved corpse."'1 This criticism misses the point. Its by Baudelaire, perhaps by way of Stendhal.14 simple rebuttal is that a corpse is not laughable According to Hobbes: since it is only a corpse and no longer a living person. By contrast, a person who somehow the passion of laughter is nothing else but sudden acts like a corpse-a person who is somehow glory arising from some sudden conception of some "dead" to the world-may be laughable since eminency in ourselves, by comparison with the infirm- he or she gives the appearance of being at once ity of others, or with our own formerly: for men laugh living and dead. at the follies of themselves past, when they come

Now, such behavior is not threatening to life suddenly to remembrance, except that bring with or limb, but it nonetheless calls for correction them any present dishonor.15 inasmuch as it interferes with society's func- tioning as efficiently and aesthetically as it can. According to Baudelaire, laughter at the Violent action to repress this behavior, which comic-first and foremost, the spectacle of "a Bergson notes is "at most a gesture" of disobe- man falling on the ice"-is based on an "uncon- dience and often an all-too-human, unwilled scious pride" and a need to assert our superior- gesture at that, would be disproportionate to the ity over the objects of our laughter. It is worth threat that this behavior presents (R 15/L 23). remarking, however, that Baudelaire's interest Instead, the appropriate reaction would be a in laughter is as much theological as philosoph- gesture in turn, which, according to Bergson, is ical. "In the eyes of Him who knows all and can just what the bodily expression of laughter is: "a do all," the Incarnate Word, Baudelaire writes species of social gesture" that "by the fear it toward the beginning of his essay, "the comic inspires" at once "represses eccentricities" and does not exist." An omniscient and omnipotent redeems its violators from the darkness into creature would not have a need to assert its which they had fallen or brings the lost back superiority and would thus be free of any urge into the fold. As Helmuth Plessner summarizes to laugh. In making this argument, Baudelaire Bergson's argument: "In laughter, the presence positions himself on the side of the "orthodox" of society in us, the social instinct, calls atten- in the longstanding controversy over whether tion to a danger to which man is exposed Jesus laughed. As the historian Daniel Menager

through his physical existence. Yet while laugh- recounts, the primary argument in the Renais- ter punishes, at the same time it heals the wound sance against Jesus having laughed was that which it inflicts on him: it brings him back to laughter was contrary to his dignity. Some life."192 (It should be noted, by the way, that authors, however, ventured to argue that "Christ Bergson never explains why he thinks that did not laugh because he was the perfect laughter, rather than crying or whatever else, is wisdom and the perfect prudence" and as such just the right "gesture" here. F. C. T. Moore incapable of breaking out into cachinnations. proposes, on Bergson's behalf, that "laughter Noting the danger of this argument, yet others itself," like the behavior that laughter purport- rallied to the formerly "unorthodox" side. For edly seeks to correct, "is a systematic parody of does not denying Jesus even the capacity to our ordinary functioning" and thus fitting to the laugh call into question his full humanity and so occasion. In the bodily expression of laughter, the dogma of the Incarnation? Baudelaire seems "[w]hat is ordinarily 'mechanical,"' the involun- to be working toward such a denial, at the same tary action of the diaphragm in expulsing time as he ties laughter to "the accident of an air from the lungs, "tries to become like what ancient fall" from grace and interprets it as a is purposive, and what is ordinarily purposive," symbol of humanity's depravity. Not wasting the production of sound through the vocal chords, any words, "[l]aughter," Baudelaire affirms, "is "tries to become like what is mechanical."13 satanic, and it is thus profoundly human." In

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 5: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

380 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Baudelaire's hands, humanity is at once cast (The "or" in the question: Are we laughing with into the dark and deprived of the possibility of him against the hated Hobbists, or at the notion Christian salvation. For the injunction to imita- of taking in pet "Snails, and Oysters... "? is tio Christi becomes senseless: in a distinctive if not exclusive but inclusive.) The superiority not essential way, Christ is no longer like us.16 theorist need not deny this fact; but the super-

The problem with the superiority theory is iority theory does not account for it. The upshot obviously what to do with examples of laughter is that this theory needs supplementing if it is that do not seem to express superiority. John not to be laughed into irrelevance. Morreall cites laughter at puns and at other Bergson answers this need by coupling the forms of verbal humor, such as "use of a triple superiority theory with the incongruity theory. rhyme or of excessive alliteration," and laughter According to Bergson, we laugh not just at any at our very own selves as we presently are, incongruity, and not just at any "conception of laughter that flows from the joy of self-recogni- some eminency in ourselves," but when we see tion, even if it is of our limitations.17 Francis an incongruity that, as we see things, needs Hutcheson asks why Hobbes does not distin- bettering. Or so Bergson would have us believe. guish between joyful laughter and derisive In laughter, Bergson writes, we find "an una- laughter, where the laughter of ridicule "is but vowed intention to humiliate" and an "uncon- one particular Species" of the genus. Hutcheson scious arriere-pense'e to correct and to instruct" also gives a good example of ridicule at work. (R 104, 130-131/L 123, 153). How do we find "It is a great pity," he writes: these facts? Apparently not by introspection, since

they are "unavowed" and "unconscious." The that we had not an Infirmary or Lazar-house to retire answer is: by subscribing to several presupposi- to in cloudy Weather, to get an Afternoon of Laugh- tions articulated toward the beginning of his ter at these inferior Objects: Strange that none of our book. Hobbists banish all Canary Birds and Squirrels, and Lap-Dogs, and Puggs, and Cats out of their Houses,

and substitute in their Places Asses, and Owls, and II. THE CONDITIONS OF THE COMIC Snails, and Oysters to be merry upon. From these

they might have higher Joys of Superiority, than from Three "observations"-in Bergson' s words, those with whom we now please ourselves.18 "three observations that we hold for fundamen-

tal"-structure his theory. (By 'observations,' Although Hutcheson clearly intends to be understand not only something noted, but some-

critical of the superiority theory, his ridicule of thing that must be remembered and respected as it might be taken, ironically, to work in this the- we proceed: "observed" somewhat as a custom ory's favor. For does he not invite us to laugh or rite is observed.) As Bergson writes, these derisively? He certainly seems to fancy himself observations "bear less on the comic itself than superior to the superiority theory's defenders. on the place where we must look for it" (R 2/L 8), Yet, if we consider his joke more closely, it will laughter's "natural milieu" (R 6/L 13). be seen to reveal the superiority theory's limita- Bergson's first observation is that only "what tions. If his joke makes us laugh, are we laugh- is properly human" is comic: that the human ing with him against the hated Hobbists, or at being is not only the only animal who can the notion of taking in pet "Snails, and Oysters laugh, but the only animal who is genuinely to be merry upon"? It is not a given that laughable (R 2-3/L 9; his italics). "A land- we need be laughing with Hutcheson against scape," Bergson writes, "might be beautiful, the hated Hobbists: perhaps we like Hobbists graceful, sublime, unremarkable, or ugly; it will or belong to the ranks ourselves, but find never be laughable." We might, it is true, laugh Hutcheson's joke just irresistible. Yet, even if it at an inanimate object, or a plant, or all the more is correct that we are laughing with Hutcheson at an animal, but we do so, according to Bergson, against the hated Hobbists (and not just out of only by reason of some resemblance to human joy or titillation, but at the joke itself), we are beings that we find in it-some resemblance to surely also laughing at the notion of taking in human willfulness, attitudes, or expressions. pet "Snails, and Oysters to be merry upon." We laugh, say, at the baseball cap's apparent

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 6: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

Prusak Le rire a' nouveau: Rereading Bergson 381

devilishness in escaping our grasp every time erally laugh most amply and heartily in a circle that we lunge for it; at the oak's apparent solici- of friends. The initial tentativeness of this tude for its sapling; at the dog's apparent stimu- observation, however, is quickly suppressed. lation at a topic of intellectual conversation that The question that we have to consider now is we address to it. But we are not really laughing the status of these observations. "It seems that at the baseball cap's devilishness, the oak's the comic is born," Bergson writes, "when men, solicitude for its sapling, the dog's stimula- united in groups, direct their attention upon one tion-we are laughing at the appearances that among them, quieting their feelings and exercis- they give of being human. According to ing their intelligence alone" (R 6/L 13). In other Bergson, "if some other animal, or an inanimate words, according to Bergson, these observa- object," brings us to laugh, "it is by a resemb- tions articulate necessary conditions for finding lance with man, by the mark that man gives it things comic. The comic comes into being [i.e., its form rather than matter], or by the use when the conditions articulated in Observation that man makes of it." Laughter may break out 3 ("when men, united in groups"), 1 ("direct at what is not human, but must always lead us their attention upon one among them"), and 2 back to what is. ("quieting their feelings and exercising their

Bergson's second observation is that laughter intelligence alone") are satisfied. My critique is not an emotional, but an intellectual, gesture; will respect this order, which Bergson seems it arises not from the heart, but from the mind. to regards as somehow organic: first comes To burst forth, it requires a moment of "insensi- society, then comes a challenge to society, bility," what he memorably calls "a momentary finally comes its defense. (Admittedly, why anesthesia of the heart" (R 3-4/L 9-11). Now, Bergson did not present his observations in this Bergson does not deny that we can laugh at a order is perplexing.) person who moves us to pity or to affection. The point is just that, in order to see a person as laughable, we must detach ourselves from our III. BERGSON'S "OBSERVATIONS" PURSUED feelings for how he or she must be feeling and take up the position of spectators at a perform- Let us return, then, to Bergson's observation ance. Let us put ourselves again in the role of that "our laughter is always the laughter of a the hapless pedestrian. If a schoolchild were to group." What is his evidence? Here it is useful feel for us in the moment of our distress, he to turn to the contemporary research scientist could not laugh, but would be made indignant Robert R. Provine, who praises Bergson for the by all such laughter. He would not see what is "significant insight that all laughter is inher- so funny in a dog' s urinating on us. To see us as ently social," but criticizes him for his "depend- laughable requires at once emotional disinterest ence on anecdotal evidence."20 Provine prefaces and a species of intellectual interest. We must his findings with a discourse: "I began," he tells interest him, not in our singularity, but in what us, "with the assumption that the best way to we represent, a comical deviation from the obtain laughter for study was to invite individ- norm. uals or small groups of two or three people into

Finally, Bergson's third observation is that my laboratory." But it turned out-surely not "our laughter is always the laughter of a group," surprisingly-that this method was a failure: or, in other words, that all laughter is laughing once in the laboratory, his would-be laughers with-not with the butt of our ridicule, but with would not laugh at all. Thus chastened, he and others who share our way of looking at the three undergraduate assistants "set forth on an world, what we commonly call our sense of urban safari to study humans in their natural humor (R 4-5/L 11-12). Like Augustine in his habitat of shopping malls, city sidewalks, and Confessions, Bergson observes that we are not the university student union," recording over much given to laughing by ourselves: as a rule, the course of a year "1,200 laugh episodes. "21 a feeling of isolation slackens our enjoyment of Among the discoveries Provine claims to the comic.19 "It seems," he writes, "that laugh- have made is that "laughter, like speech, is a vocal ter needs an echo," or at least is amplified by signal that we seldom send unless there is an

one, which is supported by the fact that we gen- audience.... Indeed, laughter is the quintessential

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 7: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

382 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

human social signal. Laughter is about relation- us laugh more heartily and amply, often culti- ships."22 To confirm as much, he also conducted vates our laughter; but it is unwarranted to con- an experiment involving "72 undergraduate dude from this fact that laughter is inherently or student volunteers from [his] classes," who essentially social in the sense that other persons wrote down when they laughed "and its social must be somehow physically present for us to circumstance in small, pocket-sized note- laugh. "Other things being equal, whether at a books." "The sociality of laughing," Provine cocktail party or the cinema, a large crowd writes, "was striking": "My logbook keepers laughs more than a small one," Provine writes laughed about 30 times more when they were in his appendix entitled "Ten Tips for Increas- around others than when they were alone- ing Laughter." "The social multiplier effect laughter almost disappeared among solitary ['the more the merrier'] brihtens even the subjects not exposed to media stimulation."23 mood of customers at malls."25 However, not

Now, without denying that Provine's research all crowds are equal. To begin with, a very big has much to teach us, the question that I want funeral is not necessarily a very cheery funeral. to pose here is whether his interpretation of it We might also wonder whether the incidence of is valid. Provine takes his two studies, of laughter in social settings like parties tells us "anonymous laughing people in public places" more about the types of discourse possible or and of "72 undergraduate student volunteers," likely in such settings than it does about laugh- to support the conclusion that a "social setting ter. Finally, it is important to note, again with [is] essential for laughter." But there is a rather Augustine, that though we are not much given obvious problem with each of Provine's sam- to laughing by ourselves, "nevertheless, laugh- ples. Note first that Provine goes from studying ter sometimes overcomes human beings even "isolated people being scrutinized in a labora- when they are solitary and single, when no one tory setting," with all of its inherent problems, else is present, if something extremely ridicu- to studying "people in public places" (emphasis lous is presented either to the senses or to the added), places like malls, "the venue of much of soul" (emphasis added).26 Does Augustine not [his] research."24 But social interaction of one speak for experience here? By contrast, Pro- or another kind is the rule in such places, and it vine's silencing of laughter "among solitary is my own experience that they present little subjects" seems to serve another master: not opportunity for solitary reverie. Is it any won- experience, but a conviction that the facts must der, then, that the laughter of people in such a be consistent with a Darwinistic picture of the setting-an essentially social setting-seems to world, according to which behaviors must have be essentially social? Let us move on to the some social utility. As Marcel Gutwirth study involving the undergraduates. Again it is remarks, this thesis has lately become a dogma my own experience, and I have it on the word of in some circles.27 more than a few undergraduates, that under- As we have seen, it is likewise axiomatic for graduates do not tend to be the most solitary of Bergson that laughter must have a "social func- creatures and also do not always spend all that tion"; such is his "guiding idea." I think that we much time, at least initially, thinking by them- can now conclude that this idea leads him selves, which it seems reasonable to consider a astray. Doubtless Provine is right that the surest condition for laughing by themselves. What, way to laugh is to go out with a number of then, do we learn from Provine's study? To put friends. Doubtless Bergson is right that laughter a point on it, do we learn anything essential that does not find an echo often does not sound about laughter, or do we learn, instead, some- again. Otherwise we risk stigmatizing ourselves thing about undergraduates? as eccentric in one or another sense: as not from

It would be wrongheaded to deny that we here, or as an eccentric, worthy of laughter our- laugh more heartily and amply in a circle of selves. But it does not follow from the fact that friends. The fact is that we generally do-a fact, socializing is the best way to make ourselves I would think, that each and every person may laugh that "our laughter is always the laughter confirm for himself or herself and that a study of a group." such as Provine's second supports. Being with Admittedly, Bergson's exposition of this others, it is true, often has the effect of making "observation" is in fact ambiguous; I have

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 8: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

Prusak Le rire a' nouveau: Rereading Bergson 383

presented and criticized only the most straight- find these and like animals comic or laughable, forward reading of the text. The ambiguity but why? derives from Bergson's remark that "laughter A brief digression suggests an answer. The implies an arriere-pensee of agreement, or I am art of the caricaturist, as Bergson vividly tempted to say complicity, with other laughers, describes it, is to divine, "under the superficial real or imaginary" (R 5/L 12; emphasis added). harmonies of form, the profound revolts of By "real," Bergson apparently means present at matter" and to present its subject as himself or hand; but by "imaginary"? What is the imagin- herself subject to tics or tendencies that will not ary presence that he has in mind? Surely we be mastered, bodily deformations that seem to need not imagine laughing with Jack or Jill in express the soul precisely by encumbering and all her finery; they need not be present in mind twisting it (R 20/L 29). As such, these tics or for us to laugh. Bergson seems to have in mind tendencies-the locked jaw, the upturned nose, what he earlier calls "the social, collective, the roving eye-violate the norms of vitality popular imagination"; but we need to know that the subject in question nevertheless obeys much more about it than he tells us, which is as a living thing. They give the subject the next to nothing. The psychologist Daniel N. appearance of not being at home in what is, Stem's concept of what he calls an "evoked after all, his or her own body. The subject companion" opens another avenue of interpreta- appears as an embodied contradiction, at once tion. On his theory, an evoked companion living and somehow dead-and the appearance serves an infant as a self-regulating other: an of this contradiction may lead us to laugh. The other who regulates the infant's own experi- art of the caricaturist, as Bergson also writes, ence. Yet this companion need not be either has accordingly "something diabolic" to it. Its present at hand or present in mind to have this purpose is to make us laugh at the condition of effect. Instead, the experience of "being with, or our fellow human beings, fallen, like the fallen in the presence of, a self-regulating other may angels of mythology, into the indignities of the occur in or out of awareness." According to flesh.29 Stem, "because of memory, we are rarely alone, Yet the art of the caricaturist is only diabolic; even (perhaps especially) during the first half- it is not divine. In other words, it does not create

year of life."28 Could this theory be brought to norms, but fixes on and fascinates us with viola- bear on Bergson's? Something like it seems to tions of norms. It exploits such violations, and be just what is needed. in this exploitation lies its secret. By concentrat-

Bergson's first observation, namely, that only ing on the caricaturist's typical subject matter, "what is properly human" is comic or laugh- namely, persons, Bergson loses sight of what able, can likewise be criticized from within. As really matters to the caricaturist's art, namely, Plessner observes in his own critique of Bergson norms. That these norms need not be moral or on this point, the defense provides the most immoral, need not have the least to do with penetrating criticism of its own position (LW morality, is evident enough: the caricaturist's 295/LC 84). It is conceded that we may laugh at field is the whole of behavior, from walking to an inanimate object, or a plant, or an animal- talking, wherever norms apply. But what is but only by reason of some resemblance to sometimes overlooked-and what Bergson human beings. The examples of a baseball cap' s again overlooks-is that norms apply to all

apparent devilishness, an oak's apparent solici- behavior, human and animal. Animals too tude, or a dog's apparent stimulation appear to behave, and they do so, as Plessner writes, "in support this qualification; the examples, say, of the light of norms," "gracefully or clumsily, a lumbering hippopotamus (Plessner's example), impetuously or sluggishly, aggressively or hesi- a dog leaping at its own shadow, or a miniature tantly" (LW 296/LC 85). horse, full grown at two-feet tall, do not. (Imagine The upshot of these observations is to topple such a thing galloping across a field.) As Plessner Bergson's (and Provine's) anthropocentrism. writes: "Here there is no longer a question of It may be argued that some standards apply

anything human, but these creatures themselves only to human beings and have been derived appear as caricatures of animals," as parodies of exclusively from human beings. But others, say themselves (LW 296/LC 85). We sometimes of gracefulness, swiftness, or aggressiveness,

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 9: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

384 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

to use Plessner's examples, or intelligence, to then, that laughter also need not be corrective. supply another, have no such exclusive deriva- To be sure, it might be claimed that our laughter tion and apply not only to human behavior, but at an animal represents a desire that it behave to that of the lumbering hippopotamus, leaping properly; but it is difficult to imagine anybody dog, and galloping two-foot horse as well. In arguing this position other than for laughs. defense of Bergson's observation, Provine Imagine someone expatiating, tongue in cheek, proposes what he calls "the fruit test."30 After on the argument that our laughter at animals is ticking off several pieces of fruit-"the firm in fact corrective. (Take my two-foot horse.) As roundness of a grape, the plump purple majesty the argument builds, its rhetoric becoming ever of an eggplant, or the blood red juice of a sweeter and grander-is purely joyful laughter pomegranate"-Provine concludes: "Although really so difficult to imagine? Likewise we you can do funny things with a fruit [take 'the might ask whether a comic effect must always lowly banana peel'], by itself, fruit just isn't be mechanical or, more generally, whether the funny. For something to be funny it must be comic must always give evidence of a conflict associated with the actions of people, not between "matter" and "life." Do we laugh, for objects." Once again, however, Provine's example, at a two-foot horse because it reminds argument does not prove what he thinks it us of a machine? Picture a number of these proves: "the fruit test" does not establish the horses racing against one another at a Triple claim that "something" can be funny only if it Crown-like event. Imagine the pride of the is "associated with the actions of people," but winning horse's owner as he bends over to con- only that fruit and the like (vegetables?) appar- gratulate the horse's radically diminutive jockey. ently must be so associated. Yet even this con- Bergson's focus on the mechanical appears too clusion is questionable. In Woody Allen's narrow to capture the comic in these images. Sleeper (1973/2173), several enormously over- However, this limitation is no reason to discard sized bananas, strawberries, and celery sticks, Bergson's theory altogether; its lens can be among other remarkable things, make comical widened. As Plessner observes, drawing from appearances. Bergson, the comic presents an ambivalence.

The important point is that, in behavior, the Something appears as living, yet mechanical; animal presents itself as "more or less in har- animal, yet human-somehow in violation of a mony with its body or in opposition to it" (LW norm that it nevertheless obeys. (Simple viola- 297/LC 85). The animal's appearance conse- tion of a norm is offensive or criminal, not quently may lead us to laugh at it for the same comic.) reason that we laugh at a human being: not by Once more, however, it ought to be acknow- reason of resemblance to human beings, but on ledged that Bergson's exposition is ambiguous the basis of "a conflict between an idea or norm and that I have presented and criticized only the which we apply to the appearance" and what most straightforward reading of the text. Here actually appears (LW 297/LC 86). In other the ambiguity turns on Bergson's proposition: words, animal behavior may appear comic to us "There is nothing comic outside of what is in the light of the ideas we have of normal four- properly human" (R 2/L 9). More precisely, the legged locomotion, of how a creature ought to question is how to interpret the first of the two comport itself toward its shadow, or of how a copulas: "There is nothing comic," which trans- real horse runs. As in the art of the caricaturist, lates the French, "11 n'y a pas de comique." In the behavior in question "offends against a brief, what does it mean to be comic? To norm which it nevertheless obviously obeys" explain by way of an example, I once saw a (LW 297/LC 86). We laugh by reason of how madly squawking duck somehow flying and the subject in question appears: in contradiction swimming at once and at breakneck speed, with itself. flaunting all the rules of being a nice, peaceful

Bergson's first observation thereby falls like duck. It struck me as unspeakably comic-the his third. It turns out that laughter need not be words 'absurd' and 'ridiculous' also seem with other human beings and that it need not be appropriate here-and led me to break out at other human beings, or even at something laughing. Why this impression? Here again that resembles us. It seems more than likely, Plessner is helpful. The zoologist who knows

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 10: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

Prusak Le rire a' nouveau: Rereading Bergson 385

her ducks would answer: because I do not know the world. Yet this thesis raises a problem: Why mine. But, as Plessner writes: "The zoologist should a person in the position of a spectator tries in vain to enlighten us on this point" (LW laugh rather than simply look? Bergson's 297/LC 86). A madly squawking duck flying/ answer is: to correct and to instruct. But this swimming at breakneck speed is not really answer, as we have seen, is vulnerable to count- comic, absurd, or ridiculous, for evidently less counterexamples. ducks now and again do such things.3' A duck It also ignores how we ordinarily talk about cannot really be comic, since a duck can only our relation to the comic. We say that it is "too be a duck. A duck cannot be other than it is. much" or that we "can't handle it" or "can't "Our common sense," as Plessner puts it, "must take it"-often in a wheezing, barely articulate convince us of the expediency and necessity of voice. At its most powerful, the comic leaves us [the] behavior and appearance" in question. disarmed and speechless. It leaves us disorgan- Accordingly, talk of absurdity when it comes to ized in the root sense of the word, namely, ducks and other animals is somehow infelici- deprived of the tools with which we normally tous, to use J. L. Austin's term, it somehow come to terms with the world. It leads us to does not come off. It is not so much true or false "lose it," where the referent is our control over as inappropriate, what he calls "a peculiar form our bodies. Whence this power? As Plessner of nonsense."32 Nevertheless, "[wihat is not observes: "Unanswerableness, coupled with the really comic can really appear so," even despite lack of an immediate threat to our existence, is our better judgment (LW 298/LC 86). A madly the necessary but not yet sufficient condition squawking duck cannot really be comic; but it that a situation must fulfill in order to provoke can really appear comic-and this appearance laughter" (LW 328/LC 111). The situation must can be enough to make us laugh. Relevant to also exercise constraint on us by means of an Bergson, the significance of these reflections is "illusion of seriousness" (LW 363/LC 141). that it appears that only human beings can be That is, it must appear to respond to our expec- comic in a strict sense. Why? Only human tations even while thwarting us.33 So doing, it beings, as beings capable of responsibility and "holds us fast and at the same time deprives us control, can be prescribed, expected to meet, of every possibility of fastening onto it" (LW and genuinely violate norms. 328/LC 112). In a word, it enthralls us. We do

Finally, we have to consider Bergson's not know what to do with it. To be sure, we can second observation, namely, that laughter is not keep trying, or try to brush it aside; but some- an emotional but intellectual gesture. As Bergson times we cannot help ourselves. Instead, all rightly notes, to see a situation as comic, our that we can do is to laugh-paradoxically, position toward it makes all the difference. dispose of the appearance by losing control of Bergson characterizes this position both nega- ourselves. tively and positively: he says what it cannot be As Plessner sees it: "The reason why laughter and how it must be. To see a situation as comic, reveals itself here in its purest and freest form Bergson claims, we cannot be emotionally doubtless lies" in the laugher's "distance" from absorbed in it (the negative claim), but must the occasion of her laughter (LW 329/LC stand back from it as spectators to a perform- 112-113). Vis-a'-vis things comic, we enjoy a ance (the positive claim). The negative claim liberty to let our laughter ring out. "In play, by makes good sense. If we were really, thoroughly contrast, or again in embarrassment, to say emotionally absorbed in a situation, we could nothing of situations of titillation or despair, the not but take it seriously-see it through from preoccupation and participation of the whole beginning to end-and would see nothing man prevails too strongly for him to be able to comic in it. The positive claim also makes a laugh from a full heart and without restraint" measure of sense. Given the negative claim that (LW 330/LC 113). Circumstances prevent us we cannot be emotionally absorbed in a situ- from letting ourselves go. Plessner agrees, then, ation in order to see it as comic, the positive with Bergson that laughter at the comic is predi- claim that we must have distance from it cated on distance. Yet, according to Plessner, appears to follow. For Bergson, laughter is this distance is necessary only for laughter's full predicated on and resounds across a distance to development. To reiterate, for laughter to burst

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 11: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

386 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

forth, the situation must initially exercise some constraint on us as well.

IV. L'HOMME RISIBLE

Lest the foregoing criticisms appear ungrateful toward Bergson-to whom the history of phi- losophy has been unkind since his glory days in the early decades of the twentieth century-it is worth observing that they may be reconfigured, at least in part, as a reinterpretation rather than a refutation. According to Bergson's third obser- vation, laughter at the comic is always the laughter of a group. According to his first observation, only what is human is comic. Now, following Plessner, I have argued that neither being in a group nor resemblance to human beings is essential to the comic. Instead, my account has concentrated on norms. Concentrat- ing on norms suggests new directions for both these observations. A norm need not be acknowledged by all peoples in order to be a norm, and we may individually prescribe our- selves norms in the sense of holding ourselves to standards. Also, we may say that a person is not being his or her normal self, by which we mean that the person is less cheerful or lugubri- ous or whatever else than most days. But it makes no sense to say that what is normal is always and everywhere relative to each person. If norms of behavior varied in this way, they would not be norms. Talk of norms is based on a common sense of what is normal and what is not. It follows that, if laughter at the comic implicates norms, it implicates others-the others with whom we share this common sense, whoever they might be. We can accordingly reinterpret Bergson's third observation to mean not that laughter needs an echo, but that it both draws and reflects on our common sense. (Compare Bergson himself, R 4/L 12.) It is just this common sense that is implicated, for example, when we laugh at an animal other than a human being. Yet a little reflection allows us to realize that, though an animal can appear comic, it cannot strictly be comic. We can accordingly reinterpret Bergson's first observa- tion to mean that only human beings can be comic in a strict sense.

If this claim is credible, we can also reinter- pret the scholastic proposition, Homo est animal

risibile. This proposition is in fact ambiguous. It has historically been interpreted to mean that only man has the capacity to laugh,34 "but it may mean as well ... that man is the only laugh- able animal," that is, the only animal genuinely warranting laughter.35 It is a delicate point. To be sure, we may laugh at other animals, and not only because they resemble us. The way that an animal behaves may really appear comic or ridiculous to us. Once we study that animal fur- ther, however, we will realize that it is not really comic or ridiculous, but that it is just behaving as it naturally does. Human beings, by contrast, have no such excuse. We cannot be simply natural. It is our nature to have to live artificially in the light of social norms. If we appear laugh- able in this regard, we really are. Ironically, our "laughableness" attests to our dignity in the animal world.36

BERNARD G. PRUSAK

Core Curriculum, College of Arts and Sciences

Boston University

Boston, Massachusetts 02215

INTERNET: [email protected]

1. Henri Bergson, Le rire. Essai sur la signification du comique, 123rd ed. (Presses Universitaires de France, 1940); English trans., Laughter: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic, trans. Cloudesley Brereton and Fred Rothwell (London: MacMillan, 1911; repr., Copenhagen: Green Inte- ger, 1999). Further references will be given parenthetically in the text: R stands for Le rire, L for Laughter. All transla- tions will be mine. Bergson first published this work in the Revue de Paris in 1899.

2. See Bergson, L'&volution creatrice, 8th ed. (Presses Universitaires de France, 1998), pp. 53, 88; English trans., Creative Evolution, trans. Arthur Mitchell (New York: Random House, 1944), pp. 60, 97-98.

3. Compare Leszek Kolakowski, Bergson (Oxford University Press, 1985), pp. 65-66.

4. Mary Douglas, "Jokes" in Implicit Meanings: Selected Essays in Anthropology, 2nd ed. (London: Routledge, 1999), p. 148.

5. Pascal, Les Provinciales, letter 11, August 18, 1656 in his cEuvres completes, ed. Jacques Chevalier (Paris: Gallimard, 1954 [Pleiade ed.]), p. 783.

6. Bergson rarely names names. He does once quote Kant (R 65/L 80), but never mentions Schopenhauer. The influence of Schopenhauer, however, would be hard to deny. See in this regard Philip Merlan, "A Certain Aspect of Bergson's Philosophy," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 2 (1942): 529-545, who persuasively pushes Bergson's "optimism" toward Schopenhauer's "pessimism."

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 12: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

Prusak Le rire a' nouveau: Rereading Bergson 387

7. Immanuel Kant, Kritik der Urteilskraft, 7th ed., ed. Karl Vorlander (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1990), ?54a, pp. 190,192; English trans., Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard (New York: Hafner, 1951), pp. 177, 179. For a discussion of Kant's theory, see Michel Canivet, "Le rire et le bon sens," Revue philosophique de Louvain 86 (1988): 354-377.

8. Arthur Schopenhauer, Die Welt als Wille und Vorstel- lung, vol. 1 of Sdmtliche Werke, ed. Wolfgang Frhr. von Lohneysen (Stuttgart/Frankfurt am Main: Cotta-Insel, 1960), vol. 1, bk. 1, ?13, p. 105; English trans., The World as Will and Representation, vol. 1, trans. E. F. J. Payne (New York: Dover, 1969), p. 59 and Parerga und Para- lipomena, vol. 5 of Sdmtliche Werke (Stuttgart/Frankfurt am Main: Cotta-Insel, 1965), vol. 2, ch. 6, ?96, p. 200. (Not insignificantly, the title of this book may be translated Hors d'aeuvres and Leftovers.)

9. The English translation, first published in 1911, lacks this appendix.

10. Compare John Morreall, Taking Laughter Seriously (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1983), pp. 18-19.

11. Arthur Koestler, The Act of Creation (New York: Macmillan, 1964), p. 47.

12. Helmuth Plessner, Lachen und Weinen. Eine Untersu- chung nach den Grenzen menschlichen Verhaltens in vol. 7 of his Gesammelte Schiften, Ausdruck und menschliche Natur, ed. Gunter Dux, Odo Marquard, and Elisabeth Stroker, et al. (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1982), p. 292; English trans., Laughing and Crying: A Study of the Limits of Human Behavior, trans. James Spencer Churchill and Marjorie Grene (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1970), p. 82. Further references will be given paren- thetically in the text: LW stands for Lachen und Weinen, LC for Laughing and Crying. All translations will be mine. Lachen und Weinen was first published in the Netherlands in 1940.

13. See F. C. T. Moore, Bergson: Thinking Backwards (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 89-90.

14. Stendhal reports having rediscovered Hobbes's thinking on laughter "toward the year 1803" and communi- cates this discovery in an 1823 essay entitled "Du rire." See the collection of his essays and notes published under the title of Moliere, Shakespeare et le rire, ed. Henri Martineau (Paris: Le Divan, 1930), pp. 289-320.

15. Hobbes, "Human Nature" in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, ed. William Molesworth (London: John Bohn, 1840), vol. 4, ch. 9, ?13, p. 46. For a discussion, see David Heyd, "The Place of Laughter in Hobbes's Theory of Emotions," Journal of the History of Ideas 43 (1982): 285-295. For an account of the development of Hobbes's theory, see Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 198-211.

16. See Baudelaire, "De 1'essence du rire et generale- ment du comique dans les arts plastiques" (1855) in his (Euvres completes, 2nd ed., ed. Y.-G. Le Dantec and Claude Pichois (Paris: Gallimard, 1961 [Pliade ed.]), pp. 980, 981, 977, 978; English trans., "On the Essence of Laughter" in The Mirror of Art: Critical Studies, ed. and trans. Jonathan Mayne (London: Phaidon, 1955), pp. 139, 135-136; and Daniel Manager, La Renaissance et le rire (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1995), pp. 124, 125. See also Jacques Le Goff, "Rire au moyen age" in Un autre moyen dge (Paris: Gallimard, 1999), p. 1347, who reports that,

each year during the thirteenth century at the University of Paris, there was traditionally a quodlibet on the question of Jesus' risibility.

17. Morreall, Taking Laughter Seriously, pp. 10-13. Paradoxically, the reduction of laughter to ridicule is perhaps facilitated by the very richness or breadth of exten- sion of the word 'laugh.' Whereas ancient Hebrew and

Greek each have two words to distinguish between joyful laughter and derisive laughter, modem English, like Latin, has but one. See Le Goff, "Rire au moyen age" in Un autre moyen dge, p. 1352.

18. Francis Hutcheson, Reflections upon Laughter, in vol. 7 of his Collected Works, Opera Minora, ed. Bernhard Fabian (Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1990), pp. 107-108. For a discussion, see Elizabeth Telfer, "Hutcheson's Reflections upon Laughter," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1995): 359-369. Hutcheson Reflections were originally published in the Dublin Review in 1725.

19. Augustine, Confessions, ed. James J. O'Donnell (Oxford University Press, 1992), vol. 1, bk. 2, ?9, p. 22; English trans., Confessions, revised ed., trans. F. J. Sheed (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), pp. 30-3 1.

20. Robert R. Provine, Laughter: A Scientific Investiga- tion (New York: Viking, 2000), p. 16.

21. Provine, Laughter, pp. 24, 25, 27. 22. Provine, Laughter, pp. 43-44. 23. Provine, Laughter, pp. 44, 45. 24. Provine, Laughter, pp. 25, 210. 25. Provine, Laughter, p. 210. 26. Augustine, Confessions, bk. 2. ?9, p. 22; English

trans., Confessions, pp. 30-31.

27. Marcel Gutwirth, Laughing Matter: An Essay on the Comic (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993), p. 23. According to Provine: "You can define 'friends' and 'group members' as those with whom you laugh. But laughter has a darker side," a side that aims to exclude, as when we laugh at somebody or something. It is just this side that, for some reason, seems to be the more attractive to some, who would as soon forget that it is only a side. See Provine, Laughter, p. 47. Compare Steven Pinker, How the Mind Works (New York: W.W. Norton, 1997), pp. 550-554.

28. See Daniel N. Stern, The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology (New York: Basic Books, 1985), pp. 111-119, especially 112, 118.

29. The representation of laughter as demonic has its roots in the Middle Ages and the Renaissance and came to bloom with the Romantics, most fully with Baudelaire's "De l'essence du rire." Typically, Bergson does not cite Baudelaire's essay, but it does seem to have influenced him. It is perhaps not insignificant that Bergson's first example is of a man who falls (R 7/L 13).

30. Provine, Laughter, p. 48. 31. See the Clark's grebe in Jacques Perrin's film

Winged Migration.

32. J. L. Austin, "Performative Utterances" in his Philosophical Papers, 3rd ed., ed. J. 0. Urmson and G. J. Warnock (Oxford University Press, 1979), pp. 237-238, 248.

33. As Plessner remarks, two senses of "seriousness" must be distinguished: something can be serious by threatening us, or by responding to our expectations (LW 362/LC 141). The exclamation, "Be serious!" invokes the second sense.

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 13: Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 62, No. 4 … · 2016. 12. 11. · resistance of matter, that is, the life-drive's precisely, laughter as a bodily expression.4

388 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

34. See Helen Adolf, "On Mediaeval Laughter," Speculum 22 (1947): 251-253.

35. Andre Bremond, "Hints on Risibility," The Modem Schoolman 17 (1940): 29.

36. I thank Daniel 0. Dahlstrom, Juliet Floyd, Margaret Kowalsky, and Lydia Moland for commenting on earlier

drafts of this paper. I am also grateful to my paper's referees and to Susan L. Feagin for constructive criticisms.

This content downloaded from 137.151.141.100 on Thu, 03 Nov 2016 12:40:02 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms