2
Some doubts about in vitro eugenics as a human enhancement technology Andrew W Siegel Robert Sparrow highlights the possibility that future success in deriving gametes from human pluripotent stem cells could forge a path to the creation of multiple generations of embryos in vitro, ultimately allowing for selective breeding of embryos as a means of producing humans with enhancedgenomes. 1 Sparrow refers to this iterative use of gametogenesis as in vitro eugenics, and argues that proponents of enhance- ments have a strong moral reasonto embrace it. He also speculates that current barriers to research on this technology will be lifted to permit the advances in vitro gametogenesis research promises in addres- sing infertility. One might thus expect the possibility of in vitro eugenics to stoke the hopes and fears of those with competing views about human enhancement. However, as I argue below, such reactions would be misplaced in the context of this technology both because we should antici- pate very little, if any, demand for it as a means of creating children, and because, contra Sparrow, even proponents of enhancements can plausibly deny that there exist strong moral grounds for employing this technology. These considerations will further suggest that some substantial ethical and regulatory barriers to research on in vitro eugenics are likely to remain. Let us suppose researchers succeed in using in vitro gametogenesis to breed embryos with genetically enhanced genomes and that there are no unusual risks in using these embryos to create children. There is good reason to think it unlikely that persons wishing to have children would have much interest in acquiring these embryos. Selective breeding has long been technologically feasible, but it has never gained much traction. Some early eugeni- cists, like Hermann Muller, promoted a eugenic revolution through (voluntary) arti- cial insemination with the seed of excep- tional men. Their hope was that people would be willing to sever the traditional link between biological and social fatherhood for the sake of bettering humankind. The possibilities for selective breeding have expanded with the advent of in vitro fertil- isation (IVF), which allows for creating chil- dren with both donor eggs and donor sperm. But while articial insemination and IVF are widely used as assisted reproductive technologies, and while those who use them often seek gamete donors with desirabletraits, what has driven the use of these tech- nologies is not a desire to improve the genetic prole of offspring. Rather, these technologies are employed in order to produce as strong a genetic tie as possible between parents and children. Prospective parents typically wish that their children will possess a large set of advantageous traits, but rare is the individual who would sacrice genetic ties to achieve this. The longing for direct descendants is an ancient one, and it has proven itself more potent than the interest in creating the best children possible. Given that in vitro eugenics would eliminate or at least signicantly attenuate the genetic link between parents and chil- dren, we should expect little or no demand for it as a means of having children. But even if we are disposed to privilege genetic ties over genetic enhancement, are there moral grounds for reversing our pri- orities? Sparrow argues that those who advance welfare-based arguments for enhancements should be committed to pro- moting in vitro eugenics: [I]f our reasons for enhancement concern the welfare of future individuals then, given that in vitro eugenics might produce individuals with signicantly enhancedgenomes, it seems that advocates of enhancement should argue that parents have strong moral reasons to choose to have children created by this means. 1 The rst thing to note in response to this argument is that (a) the welfarist need not hold that any particular individual has an obligation to have chil- dren and (b) many prospective parents might wish to bring a child into the world only where he or she is their direct descend- ant. Now, where individuals would elect to have a child only where that child would be their genetic offspring, the failure to have a genetically enhanced but unrelated (or dis- tantly related) child arguably does not entail a failure to maximise the welfare of future individuals, since in such instances, there would be no child whose welfare is an issue in the absence of genetic parenthood. But even assuming one would violate a duty to maximise welfare by choosing genetic parenthood, that does not establish grounds to have a child through in vitro eugenics, for it could well be that the net increase in welfare produced by adopting an existing child whose prospects are otherwise bleak would exceed that produced by having a genetically enhanced child. Given that the pursuit of in vitro eugen- ics as a means of breeding enhanced humans appears to have questionable social and moral value, it is not clear that in vitro eugenics research that has this specic agenda would or should be approved by institutional stem cell and human subjects research oversight committees. First, it is doubtful that a compelling rationale for cre- ating and destroying embryos exists where the clinical application the research ultim- ately aims at is both morally controversial and unlikely to generate much demand. Second, while Sparrow correctly observes that the issues about safety and risk in testing in vitro eugenics with human sub- jects are similar to those that arose in testing IVF with humans, it does not follow that we should view the risks as equally acceptable in both cases. To impose research risks on human subjects, the risks must be reasonable in relation to the antici- pated benets. In the case of testing whether IVF could produce healthy human children, the risks were deemed reasonable in relation to the anticipated benet of an effective infertility treatment. In the case of clinical testing of in vitro eugenics, it is much less clear that a favourable riskbenet ratio would exist given the limited value we can expect persons to attach to this technology (not to mention the great disvalue some would ascribe to it). Of course, attitudes could change over time, with the desire for human enhancement overriding the desire for genetic ties. But at present in vitro eugenics lacks a robust raison detre as a reproductive technology. Competing interests None. Provenance and peer review Commissioned; internally peer reviewed. To cite Siegel AW. J Med Ethics Published Online First: [ please include Day Month Year] doi:10.1136/ medethics-2013-101511 Received 22 June 2013 Accepted 23 July 2013 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2012-101200 J Med Ethics 2013;0:1. doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101511 REFERENCE 1 Sparrow R. In vitro eugenics. J Med Ethics. Published Online First: 4 Apr 2013. doi:10.1136/medethics- 2012-101200 Correspondence to Dr Andrew W Siegel, Berman Institute of Bioethics, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD, USA; [email protected] Siegel AW. J Med Ethics Month 2013 Vol 0 No 0 1 Commentary JME Online First, published on August 28, 2013 as 10.1136/medethics-2013-101511 Copyright Article author (or their employer) 2013. Produced by BMJ Publishing Group Ltd under licence. group.bmj.com on July 6, 2014 - Published by jme.bmj.com Downloaded from

Some doubts about in vitro eugenics as a human enhancement technology

  • Upload
    a-w

  • View
    214

  • Download
    2

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Some doubts about in vitro eugenics as a human enhancement technology

Some doubts about in vitro eugenicsas a human enhancement technologyAndrew W Siegel

Robert Sparrow highlights the possibilitythat future success in deriving gametes fromhuman pluripotent stem cells could forge apath to the creation of multiple generationsof embryos in vitro, ultimately allowing forselective breeding of embryos as a means ofproducing humans with ‘enhanced’genomes.1 Sparrow refers to this iterativeuse of gametogenesis as ‘in vitro eugenics’,and argues that proponents of enhance-ments have a ‘strong moral reason’ toembrace it. He also speculates that currentbarriers to research on this technology willbe lifted to permit the advances in vitrogametogenesis research promises in addres-sing infertility. One might thus expect thepossibility of in vitro eugenics to stoke thehopes and fears of those with competingviews about human enhancement.However, as I argue below, such reactionswould be misplaced in the context of thistechnology both because we should antici-pate very little, if any, demand for it as ameans of creating children, and because,contra Sparrow, even proponents ofenhancements can plausibly deny that thereexist strong moral grounds for employingthis technology. These considerations willfurther suggest that some substantial ethicaland regulatory barriers to research on invitro eugenics are likely to remain.

Let us suppose researchers succeed inusing in vitro gametogenesis to breedembryos with genetically enhancedgenomes and that there are no unusual risksin using these embryos to create children.There is good reason to think it unlikelythat persons wishing to have children wouldhave much interest in acquiring theseembryos. Selective breeding has long beentechnologically feasible, but it has nevergained much traction. Some early eugeni-cists, like Hermann Muller, promoted aeugenic revolution through (voluntary) arti-ficial insemination with the seed of excep-tional men. Their hope was that peoplewould be willing to sever the traditional linkbetween biological and social fatherhoodfor the sake of bettering humankind. Thepossibilities for selective breeding haveexpanded with the advent of in vitro fertil-isation (IVF), which allows for creating chil-dren with both donor eggs and donor

sperm. But while artificial insemination andIVF are widely used as assisted reproductivetechnologies, and while those who use themoften seek gamete donors with ‘desirable’traits, what has driven the use of these tech-nologies is not a desire to improve thegenetic profile of offspring. Rather, thesetechnologies are employed in order toproduce as strong a genetic tie as possiblebetween parents and children. Prospectiveparents typically wish that their childrenwill possess a large set of advantageoustraits, but rare is the individual who wouldsacrifice genetic ties to achieve this. Thelonging for direct descendants is an ancientone, and it has proven itself more potentthan the interest in creating the best childrenpossible. Given that in vitro eugenics wouldeliminate or at least significantly attenuatethe genetic link between parents and chil-dren, we should expect little or no demandfor it as a means of having children.But even if we are disposed to privilege

genetic ties over genetic enhancement, arethere moral grounds for reversing our pri-orities? Sparrow argues that those whoadvance welfare-based arguments forenhancements should be committed to pro-moting in vitro eugenics: “[I]f our reasonsfor enhancement concern the welfare offuture individuals then, given that in vitroeugenics might produce individuals withsignificantly ‘enhanced’ genomes, it seemsthat advocates of enhancement shouldargue that parents have strong moralreasons to choose to have children createdby this means”.1 The first thing to note inresponse to this argument is that (a) thewelfarist need not hold that any particularindividual has an obligation to have chil-dren and (b) many prospective parentsmight wish to bring a child into the worldonly where he or she is their direct descend-ant. Now, where individuals would elect tohave a child only where that child would betheir genetic offspring, the failure to have agenetically enhanced but unrelated (or dis-tantly related) child arguably does notentail a failure to maximise the welfare offuture individuals, since in such instances,there would be no child whose welfare is anissue in the absence of genetic parenthood.But even assuming one would violate a dutyto maximise welfare by choosing geneticparenthood, that does not establish groundsto have a child through in vitro eugenics,for it could well be that the net increase in

welfare produced by adopting an existingchild whose prospects are otherwise bleakwould exceed that produced by having agenetically enhanced child.

Given that the pursuit of in vitro eugen-ics as a means of breeding enhancedhumans appears to have questionable socialand moral value, it is not clear that in vitroeugenics research that has this specificagenda would or should be approved byinstitutional stem cell and human subjectsresearch oversight committees. First, it isdoubtful that a compelling rationale for cre-ating and destroying embryos exists wherethe clinical application the research ultim-ately aims at is both morally controversialand unlikely to generate much demand.Second, while Sparrow correctly observesthat the issues about safety and risk intesting in vitro eugenics with human sub-jects are similar to those that arose intesting IVF with humans, it does not followthat we should view the risks as equallyacceptable in both cases. To imposeresearch risks on human subjects, the risksmust be reasonable in relation to the antici-pated benefits. In the case of testingwhether IVF could produce healthy humanchildren, the risks were deemed reasonablein relation to the anticipated benefit of aneffective infertility treatment. In the case ofclinical testing of in vitro eugenics, it ismuch less clear that a favourable risk–benefit ratio would exist given the limitedvalue we can expect persons to attach tothis technology (not to mention the greatdisvalue some would ascribe to it). Ofcourse, attitudes could change over time,with the desire for human enhancementoverriding the desire for genetic ties. But atpresent in vitro eugenics lacks a robustraison d’etre as a reproductive technology.

Competing interests None.

Provenance and peer review Commissioned;internally peer reviewed.

To cite Siegel AW. J Med Ethics Published OnlineFirst: [please include Day Month Year] doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101511

Received 22 June 2013Accepted 23 July 2013

▸ http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2012-101200

J Med Ethics 2013;0:1.doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101511

REFERENCE1 Sparrow R. In vitro eugenics. J Med Ethics. Published

Online First: 4 Apr 2013. doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-101200

Correspondence to Dr Andrew W Siegel, BermanInstitute of Bioethics, Johns Hopkins University,Baltimore, MD, USA; [email protected]

Siegel AW. J Med Ethics Month 2013 Vol 0 No 0 1

Commentary JME Online First, published on August 28, 2013 as 10.1136/medethics-2013-101511

Copyright Article author (or their employer) 2013. Produced by BMJ Publishing Group Ltd under licence.

group.bmj.com on July 6, 2014 - Published by jme.bmj.comDownloaded from

Page 2: Some doubts about in vitro eugenics as a human enhancement technology

doi: 10.1136/medethics-2013-101511 published online August 28, 2013J Med Ethics

 Andrew W Siegel human enhancement technologySome doubts about in vitro eugenics as a

http://jme.bmj.com/content/early/2013/08/28/medethics-2013-101511.full.htmlUpdated information and services can be found at:

These include:

P<P Published online August 28, 2013 in advance of the print journal.

serviceEmail alerting

the box at the top right corner of the online article.Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article. Sign up in

CollectionsTopic

(8 articles)Special issue: Stem cell derived gametes   � Articles on similar topics can be found in the following collections

Notes

(DOIs) and date of initial publication. publication. Citations to Advance online articles must include the digital object identifier citable and establish publication priority; they are indexed by PubMed from initialtypeset, but have not not yet appeared in the paper journal. Advance online articles are Advance online articles have been peer reviewed, accepted for publication, edited and

http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissionsTo request permissions go to:

http://journals.bmj.com/cgi/reprintformTo order reprints go to:

http://group.bmj.com/subscribe/To subscribe to BMJ go to:

group.bmj.com on July 6, 2014 - Published by jme.bmj.comDownloaded from