9
British philosopher and sociologist, Herbert Spencer was a major figure in the intellectual life of the Victorian era. He was one of the principal proponents of evolutionary theory in the mid nineteenth century, and his reputation at the time rivaled that of Charles Darwin. Spencer was initially best known for developing and applying evolutionary theory to philosophy, psychology and the study of society — what he called his “synthetic philosophy”. Today, however, he is usually remembered in philosophical circles for his political thought, primarily for his defense of natural rights and for criticisms of utilitarian positivism, and his views have been invoked by ‘libertarian’ thinkers such as Robert Nozick. Life sketch of Herbert Spencer : Spencer was born in Derby, England on 27 April 1820, the eldest of nine children, but the only one to survive infancy. He was the product of an undisciplined, largely informal education. His father, George, was a school teacher, but an unconventional man, and Spencer’s family were Methodist ‘Dissenters,’ with Quaker sympathies. From an early age, Herbert was strongly influenced by the individualism and the anti-establishment and anti-clerical views of his father, and the Benthamite radical views of his uncle Thomas. Indeed, Spencer’s early years showed a good deal of resistance to authority and independence. A person of eclectic interests, Spencer eventually trained as a civil engineer for railways but, in his early 20s, turned to journalism and political writing. He was initially an advocate of many of the causes of philosophic radicalism and some of his ideas (e.g., the definition of ‘good’ and ‘bad’ in terms of their pleasurable or painful consequences, and his adoption of a version of the ‘greatest happiness principle’) show similarities to utilitarianism. From 1848 to 1853, Spencer worked as a writer and subeditor for The Economist financial weekly and, as a result, came into contact with a number of political controversialists such as

Sociology

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Sociology

Citation preview

British philosopher and sociologist, Herbert Spencer was a major figure in the intellectual life of the Victorian era. He was one of the principal proponents of evolutionary theory in the mid nineteenth century, and his reputation at the time rivaled that of Charles Darwin. Spencer was initially best known for developing and applying evolutionary theory to philosophy, psychology and the study of society what he called his synthetic philosophy. Today, however, he is usually remembered in philosophical circles for his political thought, primarily for his defense of natural rights and for criticisms of utilitarian positivism, and his views have been invoked by libertarian thinkers such asRobert Nozick. Life sketch of Herbert Spencer :Spencer was born in Derby, England on 27 April 1820, the eldest of nine children, but the only one to survive infancy. He was the product of an undisciplined, largely informal education. His father, George, was a school teacher, but an unconventional man, and Spencers family were Methodist Dissenters, with Quaker sympathies. From an early age, Herbert was strongly influenced by the individualism and the anti-establishment and anti-clerical views of his father, and the Benthamite radical views of his uncle Thomas. Indeed, Spencers early years showed a good deal of resistance to authority and independence.A person of eclectic interests, Spencer eventually trained as a civil engineer for railways but, in his early 20s, turned to journalism and political writing. He was initially an advocate of many of the causes of philosophic radicalism and some of his ideas (e.g., the definition of good and bad in terms of their pleasurable or painful consequences, and his adoption of a version of the greatest happiness principle) show similarities to utilitarianism.From 1848 to 1853, Spencer worked as a writer and subeditor forThe Economistfinancial weekly and, as a result, came into contact with a number of political controversialists such as George Henry Lewes, Thomas Carlyle, Lewes future lover George Eliot (Mary Ann Evans [1819-1880])with whom Spencer had himself had a lengthy (though purely intellectual) associationand T.H. Huxley (1825-1895). Despite the diversity of opinions to which he was exposed, Spencers unquestioning confidence in his own views was coupled with a stubbornness and a refusal to read authors with whom he disagreed.In his early writings, Spencer defended a number of radical causes particularly on land nationalization, the extent to which economics should reflect a policy oflaissez-faire, and the place and role of women in societythough he came to abandon most of these causes later in his life.In 1851 Spencers first book,Social Statics, or the Conditions Essential to Human Happinessappeared. (Social staticsthe term was borrowed from Auguste Comtedeals with the conditions of social order, and was preliminary to a study of human progress and evolutioni.e., social dynamics.) In this work, Spencer presents an account of the development of human freedom and a defense of individual liberties, based on a (Lamarckian-style) evolutionary theory.Upon the death of his uncle Thomas, in 1853, Spencer received a small inheritance which allowed him to devote himself to writing without depending on regular employment.In 1855, Spencer published his second book,The Principles of Psychology. As inSocial Statics, Spencer saw Bentham and Mill as major targets, though in the present work he focused on criticisms of the latters associationism. (Spencer later revised this work, and Mill came to respect some of Spencers arguments.) The Principles of Psychologywas much less successful thanSocial Statics, however, and about this time Spencer began to experience serious (predominantly mental) health problems that affected him for the rest of his life. This led him to seek privacy, and he increasingly avoided appearing in public. Although he found that, because of his ill health, he could write for only a few hours each day, he embarked upon a lengthy projectthe nine-volumeA System of Synthetic Philosophy(1862- 93)which provided a systematic account of his views in biology, sociology, ethics and politics. This synthetic philosophy brought together a wide range of data from the various natural and social sciences and organized it according to the basic principles of his evolutionary theory.SpencersSynthetic Philosophywas initially available only through private subscription, but he was also a contributor to the leading intellectual magazines and newspapers of his day. His fame grew with his publications, and he counted among his admirers both radical thinkers and prominent scientists, including John Stuart Mill and the physicist, John Tyndall. In the 1860s and 1870s, for example, the influence of Spencers evolutionary theory was on a par with that of Charles Darwin.In 1883 Spencer was elected a corresponding member of philosophical section of the French academy of moral and political sciences. His work was also particularly influential in the United States, where his book,The Study of Sociology, was at the center of a controversy (1879-80) at Yale University between a professor, William Graham Sumner, and the Universitys president, Noah Porter. Spencers influence extended into the upper echelons of American society and it has been claimed that, in 1896, three justices of the Supreme Court were avowed Spenserians. His reputation was at its peak in the 1870s and early 1880s, and he was nominated for the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1902. Spencer, however, declined most of the honors he was given.Spencers health significantly deteriorated in the last two decades of his life, and he died in relative seclusion, following a long illness, on December 8, 1903.Within his lifetime, some one million copies of his books had been sold, his work had been translated into French, German, Spanish, Italian, and Russian, and his ideas were popular in a number of other countries such as Poland (e.g., through the work of the positivist, Wladyslaw Kozlowski). Nevertheless, by the end of his life, his political views were no longer as popular as they had once been, and the dominant currents in liberalism allowed for a more interventionist state. Spencers theory of evolutionSpencers originality lies in his formulation and application of the laws of evolution to the Scientific study of psychology, sociology, biology, education and ethics. John Dewey, in a chapter entitled The Work of Herbert Spencer in his Characters and Events (1929), pointed out that the theory of evolution had a long history in European philosophy. In its nineteenth century reformulation, it created enormous controversy because it ran contrary to Christian belief in the story of creation. Charles Darwin is regarded as the nineteenth century scientist who are-discovered evolution. His On the Origin of Species appeared in 1859. Very modestly, Spencer pointed out that his version of evolution had been published some years before Darwins book appeared. Certainly, the theory was fully developed in First Principles published in 1862. What is clear, however, in the words of Darwin himself, is that in on the Origin of Species he restricted the application of the theory to biological changes. Spencer did not. Analyzing change in First Principles, he deduced the laws of evolution from changes in the solar system, the Earths structure and climate, in plants and animals, in individual men and in society. Change, in accordance with these universal laws, included processes of integration and differentiation. Integrative changes in the social organism were clearly and abundantly exemplified by Spencer. Uncivilized societies display them when wandering families, such as we see among the Bushmen, join into tribes of considerable numbers (Spencer, 1862, p. 316). The progress from rude to, small, and simple tools to perfect, complex and large machines in a progress in integration (ibid., p.324). In modern machines, a number of smaller simple machines are united. Evolution then, under its primary aspect, is a change from a less coherent form to a more coherent form. (ibid., p. 327). This is a universal process. Of more consequence to an understanding of modern societies is the process of differentiation as change from a homogeneous state to a heterogeneous state. As before, Spencer took his examples from all fields of scientific knowledge: in geology a molten mass is changed into mountains; in geography there is a differentiation of climates. Differentiation takes place in plants and animals. Man has grown more heterogeneous; for example, civilized man has a more heterogeneous nervous system and his thoughts are more heterogeneous than uncivilized man. In the human being this change from an indefinite, herent homogeneity, to a definite coherent heterogeneity (ibid., p. 389) was illustrated by changes from homogeneous infant noises to more and more differentiated and definite sounds. Social change from homogeneity to heterogeneity was exemplified in the progress of civilization in every tribe and nation. Society, in its first and lowest form, was a homogeneous aggregate of individuals. Every man, for example, was a warrior, tool-maker, fisherman and builder. All women performed the same drudgeries. Every family was self-sufficient and may well have lived apart from the rest. Chieftainship was the first sign of a differentiation of function. Power then became hereditary and religion co-existed with government. The next stage of social evolution was characterized by laws, manners and ceremonial usages. The specialization of labour occurred. Transport systems stimulated the development of districts 7with their own occupational characteristics. Society eventually became differentiated into classes. Spencer concluded: Comparing the rule of a savage chief with that of a civilized government, aided by its subordinate local governments and their officers, down to the police in the streets, we see how, as men have advanced from tribes of tens to nations of millions, the regulative process has grown large in amount; how, guided by written laws, it has passed from vagueness and irregularity to comparative precision; and how it has sub-divided into processes increasingly multiform (ibid., 395). These forms of differentiation were accompanied by differentiation in language, painting and sculpture, dancing and poetry. Spencer concluded: From the remotest past which Science can fathom, up to the novelties of yesterday, an essential trait of Evolution has been the transformation of the homogeneous into the heterogeneous (ibid., p. 359). Along with change from homogeneity to heterogeneity, Spencer recognized moves from the indefinite to the definite, from simplicity to complexity, and from confusion to order. Darwin is usually credited with what is called social Darwinism. It could more accurately be termed social Spencerism. The examples of his analysis of social change given here are designed to demonstrate the wealth of examples Spencer used to establish his deductive hypothesis that societies, like everything else, change according to the scientific laws of evolution. He also applied the biological notion of survival of the fittest to societies. Modifications arise as a consequence of social differentiation and persist if they are well adapted to the environment. They will eventually perish if they are not well-adapted. Spencer also held steadfastly, against scientific consensus, to a hotly contested biological theory advanced by Lamarck, who maintained that acquired characteristics were passed on to ones offspring. A majority of scientists rejected this view as the century progressed. In social affairs it has major implications. It means that characteristics acquired by parents through education can be inherited by their children. Thus, the characteristics of national charactera concept used by nineteenth century comparative educatorscould be inherited. Racial characteristics, if not genetic, may also be passed on from one generation to the next. It is an assumption that can be used by both racists and anti-racists. Convinced that all changes are evolutionary, Spencer argued from analogy in the absence of direct evidence. He used the analogy of the simple homogeneous human ovum which grows into an adult with specialized featureslegs, arms, muscles, brain and so onwhich help the human adult to adapt to his/her environment and survive; this justified his argument that, as societies evolve, functions become more specialized. In fact, his own sociological evidence was enough to persuade not only him, but the nineteenth-century sociologists in America and Europe, that homogeneous rural communities were changing to complex urban societies. Men like William Graham Sumner, Emile Durkheim, Ferdinand Tonnies, Karl Marx and Lester Ward, each in his own way, pointed to the fact that the political and economic functions once performed by all people had become the responsibility of specialists. Specialist agencies, like national and local governments and factories, had emerged in which could be performed specialist functions. The theories of social change favoured by Sumner and William Ogburn (in Social Change) owed something to Spencers theory. Indeed, his theory of social evolution was itself a significant forerunner of the theories of social change enunciated by a succession of nineteenth and twentieth century sociologists, who saw differentiation of function as the key to an understanding of change.