Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    1/14

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/Security Dialogue

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/content/42/4-5/329The online version of this article can be found at:

    DOI: 10.1177/0967010611419000

    2011 42: 329Security DialogueStefano Guzzini

    Securitization as a causal mechanism

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    On behalf of:

    International Peace Research Institute, Oslo

    can be found at:Security DialogueAdditional services and information for

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    What is This?

    - Oct 21, 2011Version of Record>>

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/content/42/4-5/329http://sdi.sagepub.com/content/42/4-5/329http://sdi.sagepub.com/content/42/4-5/329http://www.sagepublications.com/http://www.sagepublications.com/http://www.prio.no/http://www.prio.no/http://sdi.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://sdi.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://sdi.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://sdi.sagepub.com/content/42/4-5/329.full.pdfhttp://sdi.sagepub.com/content/42/4-5/329.full.pdfhttp://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://sdi.sagepub.com/content/42/4-5/329.full.pdfhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://sdi.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://sdi.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://www.prio.no/http://www.sagepublications.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/content/42/4-5/329http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    2/14

    Security Dialogue

    42(4-5) 329341

    The Author(s) 2011Reprints and permission: sagepub.

    co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav

    DOI: 10.1177/0967010611419000

    sdi.sagepub.com

    Special issue on The Politics of Securitization

    9000 424510.1177/0967010611419000Guzzini:Securitization as a causalmechanismSecurity Dialogue

    Corresponding author:Stefano Guzzini

    Email: [email protected]

    Securitization as a causalmechanism

    Stefano GuzziniDanish Institute for International Studies, Denmark & Uppsala University, Sweden

    AbstractThe article seeks to offer a way forward in discussions about the status of securitization theory. In my

    reading, this debate has been inhibited by the difficulty of finding an appropriate version of understanding/

    explanation that would be consistent with the meta-theoretical commitments of a post-structuralist theory.

    By leaving explanation and/or all versions of causality to the positivist other, the Copenhagen School also left

    its own explanatory status often implicit, or only negatively defined. Instead, the present article claims that

    the explanatory theory used in securitization research de facto relies on causal mechanisms that are non-

    positivistically conceived. Using the appropriate methodological literature renders this explanatory status

    explicit, exposing the theorys non-positivist causality and thus, hopefully, enhancing its empirical theory.

    Keywords

    Copenhagen School, securitization theory, constructivism, international security, casual mechanism

    Introduction

    Conceived for a special occasion, the purpose of this article is a friendly intervention into the theo-

    retical discussion around securitization. Focusing on the original contributions of the Copenhagen

    School, it does not aim at assessing the various debates that have characterized the reception of

    securitization theory, although it raises points pertinent to it. Its main aim is another: to offer a way

    forward in the discussion about the status of securitization theory. In my reading, debate on thistopic has been inhibited by the difficulty of finding an appropriate version of understanding/expla-

    nation that would be consistent with the meta-theoretical commitments of a post-structuralist

    theory. By leaving explanation and/or all versions of causality to the positivist other, the

    Copenhagen School also left its own explanatory status often implicit, or only negatively defined.

    Instead, the present article claims that the explanatory theory used in securitization research de

    facto relies on causal mechanisms that are non-positivistically conceived. Using the appropriate

    methodological literature renders this explanatory status explicit, exposing the theorys non-

    positivist causality and thus, hopefully, enhancing its empirical theory. The article is an invitation

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    3/14

    330 Security Dialogue 42(4-5)

    to scholars working within the Copenhagen School to explore such a path, which is both consistent

    with the underlying meta-theoretical commitments of the Copenhagen School and implicitly

    applied in many of the latters empirical analyses.

    The argument proceeds in three steps. First, I specify the different ways in which the theoretical

    status of the Copenhagen Schools approach has been conceived: namely, as a conceptual move, aframework of analysis, and an empirical and political theory of security. Focusing on its empirical

    theory for the rest of the article, I specify in a second step how to conceive of a causal mechanism

    in a way that is compatible with a constructivist/post-structuralist meta-theory. Finally, this view of

    a causal mechanism is applied to securitization.

    What does securitization?

    When the Copenhagen School coined the term securitization, it provided a next step in the ongo-

    ing discussion on how best to understand security. However, what this improved understanding

    exactly meant turned out to be ambivalent in its theoretical scope, since it alternatively implied aconceptual move, a framework of analysis, and an empirical and political theory of security.

    It is probably fair to say that securitization was foremost a broad conceptual move.1 It went

    beyond conceptualizing security in objectivist terms where threats are threats, security is secu-

    rity, and taking a careful look at political reality is all that is needed. But, it also left a subjectivist

    security concept behind, where security is whatever significant actors may regard as such. In fact,

    both approaches beg the question. An objectivist approach seems unable to fix what triggers inse-

    curity, since a particular situation or event does not give an unambiguous input into behaviour.

    When actors disagree on how to read the real situation, and do so systematically, then perhaps the

    problem lies not with them but with the allegedly objective input to start with. Similar questions

    are begged by a subjectivist approach. If all is in the eye of the beholder, then anything could inprinciple be a threat. Yet, ripe tomatoes, which visitors to Valencia can experience as a weapon

    once a year, never appear as a general security threat in our intelligence statistics. As this last

    example illustrates, perceptions can be subjectively varied, but are not reducible to personal whim

    on that account. And so the real questions arise. What provides some regularity to perception?

    Indeed, perceptions may not be subjective to start with, but only made possible by intersubjective

    understandings embedded in the dominant discourses among foreign policy elites. Why is it, for

    instance, that the foreign policies of some countries are historically more paranoid than those of

    others?

    Securitization broke with this potentially interminable security debate by proposing a series

    of conceptual moves. For one, it sociologized the analysis of security. Rather than conductinga first-level analysis of the exact meaning of security, it looks at how that meaning is socially

    produced. If discussions about the content of security can go on endlessly, why not concentrate on

    the role or function of security instead? And so, to use the famous turn of phrase, the analysis of

    security is about not what security means but what security does. Security is understood not

    through its substance but through its performance: securitization. According to the reference defi-

    nition, securitization is a successful speech act through which an intersubjective understanding is

    constructed within a political community to treat something as an existential threat to a valued

    referent object, and to enable a call for urgent and exceptional measures to deal with the threat

    (Buzan and Wver, 2003: 491).

    Yet, although opening up valid research avenues, such a conceptual move leaves us ultimatelyunsatisfied. Sociologizing added much needed reflexivity to the debate. But, in the end, it cannot

    avoid debates about substance. Conceiving of security as a speech act is important, because it

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    4/14

    Guzzini: Securitization as a causal mechanism 331

    shows that the form/performance of security is its content. However, it cannot show that this is all

    that there is to its content.2 For, unlike the original conception of a speech act, security speech

    does not in itself constitute the significant act, as does, for instance, a promise. Talking up certain

    issues or marking them as vital or national interests (by specifying the object of threat and the

    subject) are in themselves insufficient to trigger (de)securitization. Therefore, the literature distin-guishes between securitization as such and (de)securitization attempts or moves. Another dif-

    ficulty arises from the fact that, sometimes, rather than lifting an issue out of normal politics

    altogether, as securitization analysis claims, the securitization move exacerbates political debate.

    For this, the literature talks about politicization. Other similar qualifications have been added.

    What they have in common is that they theoretically develop the issue that securitization refers

    not to a single act or ritual (like marriage) but to aprocess that can lead to the anticipated effects,

    but does not do so necessarily. This then begs the question of under which (political, cultural, eco-

    nomic, etc.) conditions, with which audience, while using which discourse, etc., (de)securitization

    attempts (can) succeed.

    It is therefore coherent to see securitization not only as a conceptual move but also as aframework for analysis (Buzan et al., 1998). This framework develops several dimensions or

    conditions that must be specified if we are to know how securitization takes place. These promi-

    nently include the different sectors of security (and implicitly different audiences). And much of

    the Copenhagen School cottage industry has been about specifying the conditions on which the

    effects of securitization depend.

    This framework for analysis can, in turn, be part of an empirical theory of security. The frame-

    work qualifies the internal logic of securitization as a process, specifying the conditions for its

    possibility. In a next step, securitization has been framed within the so-called regional security

    complex approach, which makes it a security theory in terms of substance. This framing takes place

    through a redefinition of both the objectivist and subjectivist conceptions of security within a con-structivist setting. To some extent, and in some passages, regional security complex theory seems to

    start from the objective geopolitical environment (the region) in which countries find them-

    selves, which predisposes for certain security issues to be threatening and prompts almost by the

    nature of things certain foreign policy positions. Yet, the whole theory is set up in such a way that

    security is never given by geopolitical realities: it is the effect of (national) securitization processes

    and their aggregation that is, the ways in which national security discourses, intersubjectively

    shared and with a repertoire of common historical lessons, make sense of geopolitical realities. The

    constructivist horse has been put before the geopolitical cart: regions are what they (mainly

    regional actors) make of them. Hence, it would be mistaken to assume a given geopolitical reality.

    But, whereas such reification is to be avoided by the observer, it is not wrong to take it as anempirical fact in the meaning system of the security actor. Since there are no private meaning

    systems, the regional or geographic component in the analysis refers to a social as opposed to

    natural fact, one that is moreover of an intersubjective, and not just subjective, character.3 It is

    from here that the empirical theorizing takes its origins. Knowing different security discourses and

    analysing how the other is constructed within each allows the observer to see potential policy

    fault-lines and securitization processes. In turn, this makes it possible to state that (regional) secu-

    rity crises appear when such discourses simultaneously start securitizing the other, or that regional

    dtente is possible when such discourses simultaneously desecuritize. Such statements carry an

    implicit causality that will be the central focus of this article.

    Finally, securitization is also part of apolitical theory of security. In other words, here we areinterested not only in what security may mean or do, or when security problems will arise, but more

    fundamentally in the role security plays both in human nature and in political order. Much has been

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    5/14

    332 Security Dialogue 42(4-5)

    suggested (more than really analysed) about a potential link between the state of exception in

    securitization theory and Carl Schmitts political theory.4 But, as Ole Wver once remarked,

    whereas exceptionalism is the fundament of the political in Schmitt, it is the end of the political

    in securitization studies. More congenial would therefore be political theories that more generally

    relate to the role of identity (both personal and collective) and, or so I think, to processes of recog-nition in the reproduction of a social order.

    In sum, securitization does a lot: it is a conceptual move, a framework of analysis, an empirical

    theory and a political theory of security. A lifetime job! In the following, I will concentrate on its

    empirical theory. I will use the various above-mentioned steps as a background, since each of them

    has quite important implications for the type of social and action theory that would be necessary

    for thinking securitization. Speech-act theory implies the existence of performatives and hence a

    non-representational understanding of language. Moreover, securitization is strongly connected to

    a social ontology of discourses and practices. Finally, its very analysis focuses on security as a

    (contingent) process. Within the understanding of this process, I suggest that securitization has

    been and can be coherently used as a causal mechanism.

    A causal mechanism in a constructivist/post-structuralist setting

    In the following, I seek to show that causal mechanisms5 are not limited to certain meta-theoretical

    commitments and that non-rationalist and non-positivist approaches can also use them.6 Indeed, or

    so I believe, securitization studies are already constantly using them in their empirical analyses.

    Let me start with Elsters reference definition and why he got there. He defines (social) mecha-

    nisms as frequently occurring and easily recognizable causal patterns that are triggered under

    generally unknown conditions or with indeterminate consequences (Elster, 1998: 45; 2007: 36).

    To unpack this definition, more context is needed. Like other sociological rationalists, Elster startshis analysis by openly repudiating the covering-law model of explanation and simple correlational

    analysis. In his reading, a correlation does not explain; at best, it summarizes an explanation.

    Hence, it is important to open the black box of why and how a particular outcome was actually

    reached. In Elsters prominent approach to the matter, mechanisms are the intermediate level of

    generalization available between universal laws, which are unattainable in the social sciences, and

    descriptions, which are too unambitious. Not being general laws, mechanisms can explain (ex

    post) why something happened, but cannot be used for predictions, since we cannot know whether

    a mechanism will be activated or not and/or whether it will always have the same effects (Elster,

    1998: 45; see also Grosser, 1972).

    Hence, with mechanism goes the covering-law model of generalization and theorization.Oddly enough, this has gone unnoticed by some of the defenders of using mechanisms in politi-

    cal science. Alexander George and George Bennetts (2005: 2257) analysis of process-tracing

    is based on such mechanisms, which they unhelpfully conceive as a series of small-range cover-

    ing-law explanations. This seems to reduce mechanisms and hence process-tracing to a

    sequence of intervening variables. But, conceiving of mechanisms as intervening variables

    slides back into correlational analysis, now sequentially applied to however many different steps

    the analyst finds in the process traced (as in Gerring, 2007: 172). De facto, this means that cor-

    relations are explained by more micro-correlations (as in Mahoney, 2001: 578). The only thing

    process-tracing or mechanisms change for the analysis is the number of causal links; they do

    nothing to the very idea of causality implied. Indeed, for the positivist, they add little to theexplanation, since there is nothing to exclude an increasing chain of links. Worse, they do noth-

    ing to avoid an infinite regress, making such mechanisms ultimately descriptive, not causal

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    6/14

    Guzzini: Securitization as a causal mechanism 333

    (King et al., 1994: 86). Consequently, an analysis of mechanisms in terms of variables ends up

    re-importing correlational analysis by the back door, where bivariate correlations can, and may

    need to, serve as a first step of the analysis, or may even be combined with positivist (Hempel

    Oppenheim) covering-law explanations (Opp, 2005).

    However, such reduction of mechanisms to variables does away with their very specificity.First, and in contrast to mechanisms, an intervening variable is added to increase the total variance

    explained in a multivariate analysis, but that is different from providing the links in a process

    (Mayntz, 2004: 245). Similarly, such an approach starts from an assumption of static and additive

    causes, moreover understood as constant conjunctions, not in terms of sequence and the relational

    configuration of factors. Second, reducing mechanisms to variables implies that they are not just

    observable but observed (Johnson, 2006: 248), which not all mechanisms are. Here, the commit-

    ment to observation primes and effectively excludes one of the specificities of mechanisms. Third,

    at least in some approaches, mechanisms are not attributes of the unit of analysis, as they would be

    if they were variables. Instead, mechanisms describe the relationships or the actions among the

    units of analysis or in the cases of study (Falleti and Lynch, 2009: 1147). Again, reducing mecha-nisms to variables denies the possibility of a combinatorial or configurational explanation.

    Hence, to be non-redundant, a reference to mechanisms needs to leave the covering-law model

    of explanation and a conception of causality as regularity. As Hedstrm and Ylikovski (2010: 53)

    write, talking about mechanisms excludes approaches that define causality in terms of regularities

    (such as Humes constant conjunction theory or many probabilistic theories of causation). A cen-

    tral point of the mechanism debate is to redefine causality in an interpretivist and/or scientific

    realist manner, not to deny it (Patomki, 1996).

    So far, so good. Causal mechanisms la Elster get us out of the positivist understanding of

    explanation and of viewing causality in terms of efficient regularities, both pillars of mainstream

    social science research. But, what about their underlying social theory that is, their rationalismand individualism?

    It is quite understandable that rationalist scholars have insisted on mechanisms. Such an

    approach squarely meets the demands of methodological individualism, which says that all events

    need eventually be connected to the effects of intended or unintended action. It is therefore quite

    normal to double-check which micro-behaviour has resulted in which macro-states. When apply-

    ing a straightforward macromicromacro scheme, there would be three mechanisms: one relating

    the macro to the micro level, one on the micro level, and one from the micro to the macro level

    (Hedstrm and Swedberg, 1998). In the most extreme version of this understanding of mecha-

    nisms, rationality becomes the supreme mechanism. Yet, taking moreover the workings of rational-

    ity for granted, such an analysis then ends up short-circuiting individual agency and the analysis ofmechanisms altogether, since all is reduced to a narrowly mechanistic through-put.7

    But also more relaxed versions of rationalism tend to define mechanism analysis in terms of a

    rationalist action theory alone (e.g. Gambetta, 1998: 103). True, most rationalists using mecha-

    nisms are sociologists who base the analysis on a not exclusively utilitarian understanding of ratio-

    nality. There, the role played by Werterationalittis equal to, if not more important than, the role

    of instrumental rationality (Boudon, 1998).8 Alternatively, the analysis is conducted in terms of

    reasons, widely defined, in the classical rationalist desirebelief(opportunities)behaviour trian-

    gle (Elster, 1998, 2007). In this wider post-Weberian lineage, interpretation is part and parcel of the

    approach and methodology. Still, these different versions of rationality or cognitive processes are

    eventually all there is to mechanisms.Yet, there is no inherent reason why the idea of mechanisms cannot apply to other social theo-

    ries, including those that feature a social ontology. Arguing from an institutionalist position, Renate

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    7/14

    334 Security Dialogue 42(4-5)

    Mayntz stresses that once we try to understand relational mechanisms, we may find that these

    micromacro mechanisms may not involve motivated individual behaviour to start with.

    Institutional and structural components are decisive parts of the micromacro link: If the explanan-

    dum is a macro-phenomenon, or the connection between two macro phenomena the main cogni-

    tive challenge is therefore to identify the structural and institutional features, that organize theactions of different actors so as to produce their macro effect (Mayntz, 2004: 252). As she also

    writes, however, we have as of yet no similarly filled tool box of mechanisms where specific types

    of corporate actor constellations and relational structures play the crucial role.

    And corporate actor constellations and relational structures need not be naturalist or materialist;

    they are indeed often best conceived as social ontologies. There is nothing in the analysis of mech-

    anisms thatper se asks for a materialist conception of institutions and structures. This tendency to

    naturalist reductionism is surely understandable, since, by looking for mechanisms that would

    explain certain effects, and by opening up boxes after boxes, the analysis seeks to stop at some

    original, natural, point, as for example in the recourse to cognitive psychology. Thus has Jon

    Elster, in particular, used results from psychology to exemplify the working of mechanisms. Takehis example of the pair of forbidden fruit and sour grapes. Unable to reach the fruits growing in

    the neighbours garden, some people start thinking that those particular fruits are the very best,

    whereas others convince themselves that they are the opposite. Hence, deprivation may make some

    people desire an object more, others less. Although we would be hard pressed to predict the behav-

    iour in general, we can retroactively explain the psychological mechanism for whatever happened.

    Accordingly, Elster (2007: 36) rightly notes that for a methodological individualist position, the

    recourse to psychology and perhaps biology is of fundamental importance in explaining social

    phenomena.9

    Yet, this can obviously be pushed too far. When Mario Bunge (2004: 202), who has done much

    to introduce mechanistic explanations, writes that learning is explained by the formation of newneuronal systems that emerge when they fire jointly in response to certain (external and internal)

    stimuli, that may appeal to some natural scientists, but it will leave or so I guess most social

    scientists wanting more. In an excellent response to Bunge, Colin Wight (2004: 296) exposes the

    latters physicalist reductionism and shows the need to include what he calls conceptual and/or

    semiotic mechanisms in social analysis:

    All social activity presupposes the prior existence of social forms. Speech requires language; making,

    materials; actions, conditions; agency, resources; activity, rules. Equally, these prior social forms are

    concept dependent the concepts possessed by agents matter; they make a difference. And in complex

    social settings they are part of the causal complex and, hence, may be mechanisms.

    Is securitization one of those?

    Securitization as a mechanism

    Understanding securitization as a mechanism is not solving the issue of securitization. But, taking

    the detour of the methodological discussion makes it possible to more clearly expose some of the

    challenges for understanding and analysing securitization. For one thing, many empirical analyses

    do not really acknowledge the intersubjective (i.e. both non-materialist and non-individualist) char-

    acter of the initial framework. When so many analysts (and innumerable student papers) fall prey toreducing securitization to studies in which they simply expose the intentional war-mongering of

    some political actors, then perhaps a better specification of what the analysis is all about could be

    helpful. Moreover, it may also provide a useful intermediate level at which securitization can be

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    8/14

    Guzzini: Securitization as a causal mechanism 335

    pitched. Whereas, as mentioned above, some defenders use the concept basically as a fancy descrip-

    tive term for successful propaganda, some critics have read securitization as a self-referential

    automaton that, once applied, miraculously affects the political agenda. Not so surprisingly, such

    automatism is then empirically faulted or found contradictory to the underlying assumptions of the

    theory (Balzacq, 2005). In contrast, my endeavour here is to see whether causal mechanisms understood as contingent or indeterminate, and applicable to many different contexts, yet not as a

    universal or regular cause could help to specify the theorys explanatory import.

    In a first step, let me stress the procedural character of the original securitization analysis.

    Conceiving of security as performative meant for me that it is simply part of an ongoing social

    construction of (social) reality. Only in its most legal sense can security be empirically conceived

    as a speech act in terms of a single event. This would apply to those moments where a formal

    national security speech constitutes a threat of war, an offer of peace or, paradigmatically, a decla-

    ration of war or surrender. Lawyers have little difficulty understanding the idea of a speech act,

    since they have defined the practical effects of such statements in laws or customs. However, this

    was never the case for the paradigmatic case from which securitization indeed desecuritization initially derived: German Ostpolitik cannot be thought of as a single authoritative act via which

    the USSR or the threat of communism were desecuritized (Wver, 1995). A policy of gradual

    change affected the logic of high politics that had locked up the political agenda. Hence, the idea

    of a speech act refers here to a process, not a kind of single bombshell event.

    Consequently, second, the whole analysis only makes sense within the specific cultural contexts

    in which the performatives are realized. As Wvers (2004) analysis of foreign policy discourses

    and the different identity layers testifies, the theory relies on a quite huge repository of common

    meanings and selfother understandings within which we can understand why certain political

    processes may lead to securitization or desecuritization (why? understood here in the sense of

    how possible?). It is not a generic friendfoe distinction but embedded selfother understandingsthat predispose political discourses, public opinion and hence also the receptivity of the wider

    public to certain political moves. There is no reason to assume that these are universal contexts

    within which speech acts (always) function, if only the right conditions apply. Looking for case-

    independent generic scope conditions for (de)securitization therefore misses the point.10 Indeed,

    the empirical theory of security that combines those discursive layers and dynamics in regional

    interaction requires analysis that is very rich empirically if it is to explain the political dynamics,

    threat constructions and hence discursive processes in the first place.

    Third, the often-mentioned facilitating conditions for the success of (de)securitization include

    contingency and endogenous effects. True, a major aspect of those conditions is more structural

    that is, concerns (1) the way certain arguments are empowered through the mobilization of abias within existing foreign policy discourses and identities (dispositional) and (2) the validity that

    accrues to an argument by force of the reputation and positional power of the agent (relational).

    But, in a second aspect, contingent factors can play a role, since both such discourses and such

    positions are also endogenous to the process (i.e. they can be affected by the process and are not

    necessarily constant throughout).

    Finally, the understanding of (de)securitization is historical. The strong emphasis on an

    allegedly realist reading of security (connected to war, exceptional measures, done by foreign

    policy elites, etc.) is not to be understood as the essence of security, but rather as the effect of

    a historical development in which certain actors have come to be authorized to talk and effect

    war and peace in a realist way.11

    This implies that securitization theory may indeed help tore-produce such an understanding, although it does not need to. It also implies that if a different

    understanding of security appears and becomes shared, also the content of the approach will

    have to adapt.12

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    9/14

    336 Security Dialogue 42(4-5)

    In short: the empirical theory is about a process; a process in which (de)securitization can only

    be understood against the background of existing foreign policy discourses, their embedded collec-

    tive memory of past lessons, defining metaphors and the significant circles of recognition for the

    collective identities of a country; and whose success does obviously depend on, but cannot be

    reduced to, the distribution of authority and the different forms of capital in the relevant field. Itseffectiveness (just as with a law) is historically constituted and evolving.

    When the empirical theory of securitization is rephrased in this hopefully not unfair manner,

    similarities with the previous discussion on causal mechanisms abound, which can hold out impor-

    tant lessons. One issue is the better understanding of the alleged automatic nature of securitization.

    If we recall Elsters definition, there are basically two ways to think about a mechanisms trigger-

    ing capacity. In one, prompting the trigger is straightforward but the effects stay indeterminate. In

    the other, the effect is determinate but triggering the mechanism itself contingent. In the first, the

    automatic component of the mechanism lies in the triggering; in the second, in its effect. If auto-

    maticity would apply to both, the event concerned would be a positivist causal regularity.

    Both aspects seem to have been applied to (de)securitization. The reference definition surelyinsists on the automaticity of the effects of (de)securitization once it has been successfully trig-

    gered. Consequently, much discussion has moved to the facilitating conditions, adding context,

    culture, power, etc. But, this type of discussion is a bit misleading, since it heaps on factors to

    enhance causal efficacy, when the underlying question may be whether such efficacy can be

    expected in the first place. To be fair, the reference definition and usage do encourage such

    discussion.

    Yet, we can also encounter the other aspect of a causal mechanism in the actual analysis of (de)

    securitization where the effect stays contingent but not the prompting of the trigger. Here,

    a certain event triggers securitizing moves in which actors lay claim to the actualization of a pre-

    existing action-complex. For instance, if a countrys foreign policy discourse has features thatcause certain events to recall earlier threats, those events mobilize a shift in political debate towards

    a security logic.13 This corresponds to the third facilitating condition (conditions historically asso-

    ciated with that threat) and is consistent with the foreign policy discursive component of the

    approach. Hence, there is some sort of an automatic mobilization of bias within that particular

    context. Yet, importantly, such an event may trigger a parallel move. For instance, knowing about

    the propensity to move into a security logic when threats of the specified kind appear, most foreign

    policy discourses are heterogeneous enough to include a tradition that tries to pre-empt such secu-

    ritization.14 This is easily illustrated by the debate around Huntingtons clash of civilizations

    thesis, where his critics immediately latched on to, and tried to prevent, the potentially self-fulfill-

    ing dynamic of his analysis. Here, the final effect is indeterminate, since a move is accompaniedby a counter-move, both triggered out of the heterogeneous reservoir of a foreign policy discourse.

    But, that does not diminish its performative component. Both securitizing and desecuritizing

    moves can be part of self-fulfilling prophecies by becoming shared beliefs and then affecting

    pre-existing routine action-complexes related to them (say: deterrence or reassurance strategies).

    This is the way I understand the move to the exceptional: it is a historically evolved routine

    response that may well not function in all societies just as much as desecuritization is a routine

    response to it.

    This double aspect of automaticity one where origins are mechanical but effects are contin-

    gent, and vice versa also points to an underlying ambiguity both of mechanism studies and (de)

    securitization analyses.15

    Let us recall Elsters definition: frequently occurring and easily recog-nizable causal patterns that are triggered under generally unknown conditions or with indetermi-

    nate consequences. Here, mechanisms are not themselves the triggers, as common parlance would

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    10/14

    Guzzini: Securitization as a causal mechanism 337

    have it, but the things that are triggeredby something else. Applied to securitization, that would

    mean that one could see securitization either as the process that is triggered by something else or

    as itself the trigger of certain effects both explanandum and explanans. And, indeed, some studies

    concentrate on what made (de)securitization possible, whereas others look at the effects it has on

    other processes. It is perfectly possible to use it both ways, and a process vision that links mecha-nisms up in a sequence may resort to both. But, again, something is gained by being explicit about

    how the determinacy in the analysis is configured.

    This last point is, in turn, related to the difficult location of causal mechanisms in and over

    time. The literature does not necessarily agree on where exactly to temporarily locate a mecha-

    nism: is the mechanism confined to the triggering itself, or to the type of triggered (routine)

    action-complexes, or does it encompass the process taken as a whole, as when historical sociolo-

    gists use the term?16 This multiple focus also applies to securitization: the very definition stresses

    the moment of the trigger, whereas the political theory stresses the content of the routine action

    involved, and most of the empirical applications trace the evolution of the conditions for the per-

    formative to take effect that is, the process. I do not think it necessary at this stage to decidewhich is the right use. In fact, the choice of a specific understanding is partly driven by the

    empirical question. If the research is directed towards individual events, trying to find out whether

    they contribute to (de)securitization, then analysis of the possible triggering moments seems appro-

    priate. If, however, as in the case of German Ostpolitik, a political strategy or long-term process is

    the focus of the research question or, indeed, if the question turns on a comparison of different

    processes, as in comparative historical sociology then it makes more sense to define the sequence

    of moves in their particular context as the relevant understanding of securitization. Analysts,

    however, need to be clear about the differences between the two, one leading rather more to within-

    process comparison and its methodological needs, the other to the comparison of the given process

    itself with other processes.Finally, conceptualizing securitization as a causal mechanism does not in any way prejudice its

    ontological status, but may alert scholars employing it to the need to be more self-conscious about

    their choice. For mechanisms have been used by defenders of almost all meta-theories in the social

    sciences. They can be found in the work of scholars who, if often implicitly, would subscribe to

    some version of a correspondence theory of truth. Here, mechanisms are about real-world pro-

    cesses. Inversely, and closer to the post-structuralist part of securitization theory, such mechanisms

    can also be seen as purely theoretical constructs or heuristic devices, which we apply to our obser-

    vations in order to classify them. They make sense of history but do not drive it (Pouliot, 2007:

    37374). And this becomes still more distinct when an instrumentalist position (assumptions need

    not be realistic if they work) is added, a position endorsed by Patrick Jackson (2011: 11255).Finally, for others still, positioning themselves somewhat in between, mechanisms are surely heu-

    ristic constructs, but one cannot rule out their independent existence. That position would apply to

    critical realists who do not subscribe to a correspondence theory of truth (Kurki, 2008; Patomki,

    2002, 2008; Wight, 2006, 2007), and also to some more agnostic constructivists (e.g. Kratochwil,

    2007a,b).

    So what?

    Security as securitization has been part of a strategy to contaminate existing common knowl-

    edge (Wver, 1989). Using the opener of a subjective definition of security (perception andmisperception), securitization takes out a central concept, redefines it, and then reinserts it into the

    mainstream discourse in order to affect the latter from the inside. It does not leave security to the

    conceptual habitus of the would-be experts whether these are socialized in the arms race of

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    11/14

    338 Security Dialogue 42(4-5)

    the Cold War or the asymmetrical warfare and Revolution in Military Affairs today since this

    would only reproduce their definitional power. No such sanctuary is granted.

    What the approach to causal mechanisms presented in this article seeks to do is something simi-

    lar. It uses the opening of some rationalist analysis in its insistence that explanations, even positiv-

    ist ones, are based on mechanistic reasoning (correlations do not explain), and that while more thandescription is possible in the social sciences, general laws are not. Yet, rather than leaving causality

    and mechanism to a naturalist and/or individualist research programme, it shows how to conceptu-

    alize causal mechanisms in an interpretivist environment, here applied to discourse analysis.

    Consistent with the approaches adopted by critical realists and constructivists, it takes a different

    understanding of causality (in a non-regular manner) and breaks out of the positivistic blackmail

    that asserts that explanation is either positivistic or no explanation at all. Securitization analysis can

    be directed to the understanding of why certain moves can be expected in given national security

    discourse, why some of them may find a receptive audience (given the underlying security imagi-

    nary), and indeed why certain action-complexes can then follow. But, such why is always a how

    causality. It does (also)17

    explain, just not in a positivistic manner. Successful desecuritizationexplains Ostpolitik (why and how it has become possible), even if it does not constitute a cause

    in any law-like sense. Also here, no sanctuary is granted.

    And the present article proposes to use the idea of securitization as a causal mechanism in a type

    of interpretivist process-tracing to allow for more coherence in the use of securitization in empirical

    explanations,18 because explanations they are. Securitization seems to travel quite well from one

    analysis to another, being used in all possible research contexts. Just what is it that travels? Some

    critics contend that some universal feature of the speech act allows its analysis in different contexts.

    Such a contention, however, does not work with the underlying theory and philosophy of science.

    This article claims that what makes different security analyses comparable as to their process and

    dynamics within an empirical theory of securitization is the idea of a causal mechanism (or, moreprecisely, two, since desecuritization is the other potentially available). That mechanism may be

    contingent in its prompting or indeterminate in its effect. Its exact content cannot be understood

    outside of the context, discursive and other, in which it applies. In other words, the travel needs to

    be understood from case to case. And yet, when the mechanism does travel, it is part of an explana-

    tion. It allows securitization to constitute itself as an empirical theory of security. And the historical

    constitution of securitization then also allows for assessing its contextual limits. Additional mecha-

    nisms can be part of the security analysis for sure, but no security analysis or so my reconstruction

    of securitization theory would claim can be conducted without it.

    Notes1. For an early good statement about the implications of this as a conceptual move, see Huysmans (1998).

    2. See also McDonald (2008).

    3. As one referee remarked, the expression intersubjectivity may be subject to different understandings. It

    is here not meant to refer to the interaction of different subjectivities, in which meaning is subjectively

    created and then shared. It refers instead to a genuinely structural idea, heir to the linguistic turn in the

    social sciences, and akin to Foucaults episteme or Searles collective intentionality. For this use in inter-

    national relations, see in particular Ruggie (1998).

    4. For perhaps the best discussion, see Williams (2003).

    5. As in much of the literature, I use the expressions social mechanism and causal mechanism inter-

    changeably. As the discussion will show, this is not because I believe that the analysis of mechanisms is

    just a subform of (Humean) causal analysis, but, to the contrary, because mechanism analysis makes more

    sense in an analysis where causality is redefined.

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    12/14

    Guzzini: Securitization as a causal mechanism 339

    6. Obviously, this has been argued earlier (e.g. Wendt, 1999, 2000; Checkel, 2006, 2008).

    7. On conflating (rational) action with mechanisms, see Hedstrm and Swedberg (1998: 1112).

    8. For a more general argument that the core of this conceptualization is Werterationalitt, to which

    Zweckrationalittis just a residual or parasitarian category, see Pizzorno (2007: 1549).

    9. This can then also lead to the critique of (utilitarian) rationality by psychological theories. In international

    relations, see in particular Mercer (2005).

    10. I am indebted to Ludvig Norman for stressing this aspect.

    11. This corresponds to the necessary third leg of any constructivist conceptual analysis that needs to include

    the analysis of concepts as potential performatives and a conceptual history to establish how those per-

    formatives have acquired their effect (and where); see Guzzini (2005).

    12. Jef Huysmans has cautioned against these reflexive effects from early on. He has also insisted on expos-

    ing the historicity of Schmitts approach to the exception in the discussion of contemporary security. See,

    for example, Huysmans (2006: 23).

    13. What I understand as security logic in our Western political discourses is a logic that reverses

    Clausewitzs dictum: politics becomes the prolongation of war by other means. Putting war as the main

    organizing principle for thinking foreign policy profoundly affects the role of politics.

    14. Hence, the same outcome could have come about through the non-existence of mechanisms or through

    their multiplicity, whereby they cancelled each other out. Elster insists that precisely for this possible

    multiplicity of mechanisms, any explanation needs to focus on the process, not the outcome. For doing

    otherwise runs into the problem of equifinality, that is, where the same outcome could come about by

    following different causal paths.

    15. I am indebted to Colin Wight for pointing me to this ambiguity and for the discussion in this paragraph.

    16. See, for example, Tilly (1995, 2001).

    17. It allows for both constitutive and causal relations.

    18. For more on interpretivist process-tracing and the use of mechanisms therein, see chapters 3 and 11 of

    Guzzini (forthcoming).

    References

    Balzacq T (2005) The three faces of securitization: Political agency, audience and context.European Journal

    of International Relations 11(2): 171201.

    Boudon R (1998) Social mechanisms without black boxes. In: Hedstrm P and Swedberg R (eds) Social Mech-

    anisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 172203.

    Bunge M (2004) How does it work? The search for explanatory mechanisms. Philosophy of the Social Sci-

    ences 34(2): 182210.

    Buzan B and Wver O (2003)Regions and Powers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Buzan B, Wver O and De Wilde J (1998) Security: A New Framework for Analysis. Boulder, CO: Lynne

    Rienner.Checkel JT (2006) Tracing causal mechanisms.International Studies Review 8(2): 362370.

    Checkel JT (2008) Process tracing. In: Klotz A and Prakash D (eds) Qualitative Methods in International

    Relations: A Pluralist Guide. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 114128.

    Elster J (1998) A plea for mechanisms. In: Hedstrm P and Swedberg R (eds) Social Mechanisms: An Analyti-

    cal Approach to Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 4573.

    Elster J (2007)Explaining Social Behavior: More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cam-

    bridge University Press.

    Falleti TG and Lynch JF (2009) Context and causal mechanisms in political analysis. Comparative Political

    Studies 42(9): 11431166.

    Gambetta D (1998) Concatenations of mechanisms. In: Hedstrm P and Swedberg R (eds) Social Mecha-nisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 102124.

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    13/14

    340 Security Dialogue 42(4-5)

    George A and Bennett A (2005) Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences. Cambridge,

    MA: MIT Press.

    Gerring J (2007) Review article: The mechanistic worldview: Thinking inside the box. British Journal of

    Political Science 38(2): 161179.

    Grosser A (1972) Lexplication politique. Une introduction lanalyse comparative [Political Explanation:An Introduction to Comparative Analysis]. Paris: Armand Colin.

    Guzzini S (2005) The concept of power: A constructivist analysis.Millennium: Journal of International Stud-

    ies 33(3): 495522.

    Guzzini S (ed.) (forthcoming) Geopolitics Redux? Identity Crises and Social Mechanisms in the Revival of

    Geopolitical Thought in Europe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Hedstrm P and Swedberg R (1998) Social mechanisms: An introductory essay. In: Hedstrm P and Swedberg

    R (eds) Social Mechanisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press, 131.

    Hedstrm P and Ylikovski P (2010) Causal mechanisms in the social sciences. Annual Review of Sociology

    36: 4967.Huysmans J (1998) Security! What do you mean? From concept to thick signifier.European Journal of Inter-

    national Relations 4(2): 226255.

    Huysmans J (2006) International politics of insecurity: Normativity, inwardness and the exception. Security

    Dialogue 37(1): 1129.

    Jackson PT (2011) The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implica-

    tions for the Study of World Politics. London & New York: Routledge.

    Johnson J (2006) Consequences of positivism: A pragmatist assessment. Comparative Political Studies 39(2):

    224252.

    King G, Keohane RO and Verba S (1994) Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative

    Research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Kratochwil F (2007a) Evidence, inference, and truth as problems of theory building in the social sciences. In:

    Lebow RN and Lichbach MI (eds) Theory and Evidence in Comparative Politics and International Rela-

    tions. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2554.

    Kratochwil F (2007b) Of false premises and good bets: A plea for a pragmatic approach to theory building (the

    Tartu lecture).Journal of International Relations and Development10(1): 115.

    Kurki M (2008) Causation in International Relations: Reclaiming Causal Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    McDonald M (2008) Securitization and the construction of security.European Journal of International Rela-

    tions 14(4): 563587.

    Mahoney J (2001) Beyond correlational analysis: Recent innovations in theory and method. SociologicalForum 16(3): 575593.

    Mayntz R (2004) Mechanisms in the analysis of social macro-phenomena.Philosophy of the Social Sciences

    34(2): 237259.

    Mercer J (2005) Rationality and psychology in international politics. International Organization 59(1):

    77106.

    Opp KD (2005) Explanations by mechanisms in the social sciences: Problems, advantages, and alternatives.

    Mind & Society 4(2): 16378.

    Patomki H (1996) How to tell better stories about world politics.European Journal of International Rela-

    tions 2(1): 105133.

    Patomki H (2002)After International Relations: Critical Realism and the (Re)construction of World Politics.London and New York: Routledge.

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13, 2011sdi.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/
  • 7/31/2019 Securitization as a Causal Mechanism

    14/14

    Guzzini: Securitization as a causal mechanism 341

    Patomki H (2008) The Political Economy of Global Security: War, Future Crises and Changes in Global

    Governance. London and New York: Routledge.

    Pizzorno A (2007)Il velo della diversit. Studi su razionalit e riconoscimento [The Veil of Diversity: Studies

    on Rationality and Recognition]. Milan: Feltrinelli.

    Pouliot V (2007) Sobjectivism: Toward a constructivist methodology. International Studies Quarterly51(2): 35984.

    Ruggie JG (1998) Constructing the World Polity: Essays on International Institutionalization. London and

    New York: Routledge.

    Tilly C (1995) To explain political processes.American Journal of Sociology 100(6): 15941610.

    Tilly C (2001) Mechanisms in political process.Annual Review of Political Science 4: 2141.

    Wver O (1989) Beyond the beyond of critical international theory. Working Paper 1/1989. Copenhagen:

    Copenhagen Peace Research Institute.

    Wver O (1995) Securitization and desecuritization. In: Lipschutz R (ed.) On Security. New York: Columbia

    University Press, 4686.

    Wver O (2004) European integration and security: Analysing French and German discourses on state,nation, and Europe. In: Howarth DR & Torfing J (eds) Discourse Theory in European Politics: Identity,

    Policy and Governance. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 3367.

    Wendt A (1999) Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Wendt A (2000) On the Via Media: A response to the critics.Review of International Studies 26: 165180.

    Wight C (2004) Theorizing the mechanisms of conceptual and semiotic space.Philosophy of the Social Sci-

    ences 34(2): 283299.

    Wight C (2006)Agents, Structures and International Relations: Politics as Ontology. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Wight C (2007) A manifesto for scientific realism in IR: Assuming the can opener wont work. Millennium:

    Journal of International Studies 35(2): 379398.Williams MC (2003) Words, images, enemies: Securitization and international politics.International Studies

    Quarterly 47(4): 511531.

    Stefano Guzzini is a Senior Researcher at the Danish Institute for International Studies, Copenhagen, and

    Professor of Government at Uppsala University. Email: [email protected]. For the revision of this article, the

    author gratefully acknowledges the helpful comments and criticisms from Andreas Behnke, Jef Huysmans,

    Patrick Jackson, Anna Leander, Jon Mercer, Ludvig Norman, Heikki Patomki, Vincent Pouliot, Colin Wight,

    Ole Wver, three anonymous referees, and Karen Lund Petersen and Ulrik Pram Gad, the two editors of this

    special issue. He is aware that he could not address all of their incisive queries.

    at Uni Tehnica on December 13 2011sdi sagepub comDownloaded from

    http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/http://sdi.sagepub.com/