Review on "Obligatory Presupposition in Discourse"

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/6/2019 Review on "Obligatory Presupposition in Discourse"

    1/5

    Obligatory Presupposition in Discourse : A Review

    Pascal Amsili& Claire Beyssade

    Universit Paris Diderot & Laboratoire de Linguistique Formelle,CNRS Institut Jean Nicod, CNRS Paris.

    Reviewed by : Arko Chakraborty, Research student, Dept. of Linguistics,

    University of Calcutta, India.

    [scheduled assignment under the PhD coursework: June, 2011]

    The review of this article would start off with a brief introduction on the twin concepts of

    Presupposition and Discourse/text Analysis in Section 1, which is to be followed by a critical

    appreciation of the content and arguments as presented in the article in Section 2 and the last section

    would deal with the possibilities of application of the same on the structure of Bangla/ Bengali

    language.

    1.Presupposition and DiscourseA presupposition, as a common concept given by several scholars, is a pragmatic inference

    drawn from the proposition of a statement. This inference is in itself a distinct proposition but it is, in

    most cases, not the prime focused proposition, rather the original statement asserts (or negates) with

    a prime focus some other proposition B for the validity of which the presupposed proposition A is a

    necessary pre-condition. In terms of truth-conditionality, the presupposition of a statement must

    always be true irrespective of whether the statement is true.

    Scholars like Karttunen, Frege, Strawson, and many others studied and found that such

    presuppositions are possible when certain particular linguistic elements belonging to various

    categories like verbs, proper nouns, adjectives of comparison, etc. are present in the structure of the

    statement under consideration. These linguistic elements are usually morphological and sometimes

    even syntactic and/or prosodic in nature and these were called by such scholars as presuppositional

    triggers. Hence, these markers generate presuppositions.

    On the other hand, while studying the structural and semantic relations both intra- and inter-sententially we come across several discourse markers, or to be more specific the so-called cohesive

    markers, which define and link up the abovesaid relations in a text or spoken discourse. Often it is

    found that some discourse markers happen to be presuppositional triggers too and perform their

    characteristic functions independently but simultaneously.

    The article here deals with some such linguistic elements which have both a presuppositional

    and a discourse function.

  • 8/6/2019 Review on "Obligatory Presupposition in Discourse"

    2/5

    2.Critical appreciation of the articleThe article deals with the additive or emphatic particles/ morphemes like too and its

    classmates like still, also, again, anymore, indeedquoting some examples from Zeevat (2002,2003)

    and adding some of their own pertaining to the French language. Amsili & Beyssade, in this article,

    in keeping with the observations of Green (1968) and Kaplan (1984), justify the presence and/or use

    of such additive particles that do not apparently seem to add any further content/ information and

    thereby seem to create redundancy. However, this redundancy is maintained as a price for the

    presuppositional behavior of such additive particles most or all of which also act as anaphoric

    cohesive markers.

    Usually the second clause of a sentence (or the later part of a paragraph in a longer text)

    contains an additive particle that holds a contrastive relation to some other element mentioned

    earlier. Thus, following Kaplan, one of the major obligations for the use of particles like too is to

    uphold the similarity between two contrastive topics. In quite a similar tune, Krifka (1999) upholdsthe utility of prosodic stress accent on the additive particle (giving examples from German and

    English) and also upholds the function of differentiation and contrast as a major reason for the

    obligatory presence of additive particles like too. Sb (2004) puts several objections to Krifkas

    proposals but Amsili & Beyssade uphold the validity of the propositions of all the abovesaid

    scholars.

    Zeevat (2002) however shifts his emphasis from the importance of the presuppositional

    function to the discourse function saying that the latter is more crucial for the obligatory presence of

    such additive particles. Amsili & Beyssade strive towards classifying and grouping together a set of

    presuppositional triggers and non-presuppositional discourse markers on the basis of three

    parameters:

    (i) obligatoriness, (ii) minimal meaning with no further lexical content added, and (iii) that they

    give rise to an accessibility anomaly. By accessibility Amsili & Beyssade mean the access or

    anaphoric co-reference of such a particle/ marker to its antecedent.

    Amsili & Beyssade include the following in their class of triggers (from French), however,

    the exemplary statements that they provide to substantiate the argument do not necessarily abide by

    all the above three properties:

    Pure additive items aussi (also), ne...plus (not anymore).

    Aspectual items re-, encore (still), de nouveau (again), ne...plus (not anymore).

    Cleft and intonation

    Some factive verbs savoir (to know)+ que/si, ignorer (not to know)+ que/si, vrifier +que/si,

    realize, be aware.

    In the third section of the article Amsili & Beyssade explain their argument in terms of

    conversational and scalar implicatures following Gricean notions as well as the theories of Hawkins

    (1978) and Heim (1991). So far as the conversational implicatures are concerned, Amsili &

    Beyssade, in line with Krifka, state that assertion of the condition or state of affairs of some entity x

    implicates that no other entity shares the same set of conditions or state of affairs which belongsolely to x and thus now if any other entity y is stated to share the same then it leads to an anomaly

  • 8/6/2019 Review on "Obligatory Presupposition in Discourse"

    3/5

    or contradiction whereby the existing implicatures gets nullified upon further information as in the

    example below. Then to maintain the truthfulness and validity of the assertions regarding both the

    entities x & y such additive particles like too are required.

    A: What did Peter and Pia eat?_________ (Peter =x and Pia = y)B: Peter ate pasta. _____________________ (implicates Pia didnt eat pasta)

    C: Peter ate pasta, and Pia ate pasta________ (contradicts with B)

    Solution: i) C: Peter ate pasta, and Pia ate pasta too.______(saves all implicatures)

    ii) C: Peter and Pia ate pasta._________( Grices maxim of manner followed)

    This explanation is followed by the comparison with scalar implicatures whereby a statement s

    without an additive particle/trigger is placed higher on the scale than another statement having the

    additive particle s+too in the order < s, s+too > which they call a scalar alternative; however the

    incomplete explanation of this point lacks justification and is controversial, since the criterion ofsuch classification is the maximum number of presuppositions which a statement (with and without

    additive particles) can generate. Surely, s+too can give rise to more presuppositions, yet it is placed

    lower on the scale.

    In the fourth and final section of the article Amsili & Beyssade talk of the connection

    between the obligatoriness of such additive particles or presuppositional triggers on one hand and

    discourse relations (in a text) on the other hand.

    Their argument is that if the cohesion of structure and coherence of meaning (jointly called the

    discourse relation) between successive parts of a text is already clear prior to the use of such a

    particle/ trigger, then the use of the trigger becomes optional but is never forbidden. The following

    example (showing wider discourse context) quoted from the article explains this.

    (1)Jean est malade, Marie est malade, Paul est malade, tout le monde est malade alors!John is sick, Marie is sick, Paul is sick, everybody is sick then!

    The above example does not have such particles or triggers because through a system of

    enumerationor counting a discourse relation becomes evident in the entire text which shows that

    the presuppositions of the individual parts implicate each time that no one else is sick but when we

    reach the end of the text we find that multiple counting leads to the fact that every single person as

    well as every other person is sick. This is actually a case of projection problem and defeasibility of

    presuppositions in wider discourse contexts which Amsili & Beyssade do not refer to here. As an

    alternative, they say that the same statement above can be equally well-formed if the

    particles/triggers are used, as follows:

    (2)Jean est malade, Marie aussi, Paul aussi, tout le monde est malade alors!John is sick, Marie too, Paul too, everybody is sick then!

  • 8/6/2019 Review on "Obligatory Presupposition in Discourse"

    4/5

    Also what they didnt point out in their article is that the word sick itself acts as a cohesive

    marker (contextually) since it prevails as an unchanged predicate or state of affairs for each

    individual. If different predicates were used then the additive particle too cannot be used, e.g.

    (3)John is sick. Mary is happy. Paul is unconscious.

    This sentence (3) cannot be replaced with an alternative statement using too, at the same time one

    cannot say that there exists no semantic relation or coherence between each clause/simplex sentence.

    Momentarily it might be assumed and in a still wider context as given below the discourse relations

    might become more obvious. Thus we can assume (4) from (3) by inserting the omitted/ elided

    cohesive markers.

    (4)John is sick,so Mary is happy,but Paul is unconscious.Even without using the above discourse markers we can deduce the same coherent relations very

    easily from a wider context.

    (5)Mary always keeps John in her bad books. John hasntbeen to office for several days. He issick. Johns little brother, Paul, went to report this at the office. Mary is happy. She clapped

    her hands and told Paul to tell John that he is fired. Paul is unconscious as John was the only

    earning member in their family.

    The point here is that whether a discourse relation is present in a small or large text due to the

    presence of overt cohesive markers or due to the sequence of events (abiding by the Gricean notionofmaxim of manner), the additive particles or presuppositional triggers like too, still, again, etc. do

    not have a discrete optionality of occurrence. So, it goes against the proposition of Amsili &

    Beyssade that such particles or triggers remain optional and are not barred from occurring, rather as

    we see in the examples (3,4 and 5) above, such triggers can be barred.

    This argument can be extended to one more step when we find that instead of using identical or

    totally different predicates, if synonymous or hyponymous predicates are used then the predicates of

    the successive clauses can be replaced with too, as in (6) and (7) below. Even this was not

    considered in the article of Amsili & Beyssade.

    (6a) John is sick, Marie is down with fever, Paul has a backache, everybody is sick then!

    (6b) John is sick, Marietoo, Paultoo, everybody is sick then! ____________ (hyponymy)

    (7a) John is joyous, Marie is merry, Paul is cheerful, everybody is happy then!

    (7b) John is joyous, Marietoo, Paultoo, everybody is happy then! ____ (near-synonymy)

    Lastly, they conclude the article saying that the presence of one such marker/trigger pre-empts but

    does not bar the necessity or obligatoriness of the presence of parallel or co-functional triggers.

  • 8/6/2019 Review on "Obligatory Presupposition in Discourse"

    5/5

    3.The perspective of Bengali (a brief outline)Although Bengali has its own conjunctions or additive discourse markers pertaining to English

    and = [ar ~ ebo], these sometimes do and sometimes do not function like presuppositional triggers,

    as distinguished in (8) and (9) below:

    (8) John khelche ar Peter mai kache

    John (is) playing and Peter soil digging____ use of [ar] as additive cohesive marker

    (9) John okhane ar jabe na

    John there again go not____________ [ar] is a presuppositional trigger here.

    Thus in a statement like (9) the additive discourse marker acts as a presuppositional trigger and

    presupposes that John had gone there earlier.

    However, Bengali has an emphatic inclusive particle {-o} which is suffixed to any base

    morpheme irrespective of the grammatical category of the base. This particle is both an additive

    discourse marker as well as a presuppositional trigger and it performs both these functions

    simultaneously as shown below in (10).

    (10) A: ami skule jabo na

    I to school will go not.

    B: ami-o

    I-too ( = Me too in colloquial English).

    C: ami-o jabo na

    I-too will go not

    This {-o} not only functions as an additive marker thereby adding upon or including the latter

    speaker B to the same state of affairs, but also performs the optional cohesive function of substitution

    whereby the construction [skule jabo na] is not repeated but elided and replaced or substituted by theparticle or bound suffix {-o} in B and partially substituted in C. However, [ami], the first personal

    pronoun, being the focal element in each statement cannot be deleted and it is the focal element only

    that takes the additive marker.

    Now, looking at B or C, whenever a native speaker of Bengali would find the presence of such an

    additive marker like {-o} s/he would presume or presuppose that apart from the current speaker who

    addresses himself/herself as [ami + o] there is some other participant who is equally involved in the

    concerned action or state of affairs. Thus this presupposition of the involvement of at least another

    participant is triggered by the presence of the bound suffix {-o}.