27
Reconquering Polynarrative and Plurality: Arendt’s Political Phenomenology Jasmina Tacheva Abstract: This paper examines the status of narrative in late capitalist society and claims that despite capitalism’s promises to not just “deliver the goods,” but also to offer a virtually limitless variety of choices, what reality amounts to is a very constrained landscape of only the latest, most viable options available on the market. This process limits the ability of human beings to be actors in the political realm, but it also deprives them of the possibility to be “world spectators” – an idea Kant advances in The Critique of Aesthetic Judgment, which Hannah Arendt picks up and expands upon in her Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, by focusing on the sociability aspect of a “reading public” “always in the plural” which serves as the foundation for judgment. It is argued that the concept of judgment is Arendt’s attempt to overcome the shortcomings she finds in Husserl’s phenomenological project in favor of a political phenomenology that can be practiced collectively by the members of the community. After investigating Arendt’s analysis of both plurality and the characteristics of critical thinking and judgment, this paper turns to a major conflict identified by Arendt in her reading of Kant’s third Critique – that between actor and spectator. The paper suggests that by inventively reconciling the two on the plateau of sociability, Arendt charts a way to bring about social change through the power of personal narratives. Concrete examples of the strong influence of this transformation are provided from the fields of feminism and environmentalism.

Reconquering Polynarrative and Plurality: Arendt's Political Phenomenology

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Reconquering Polynarrative and Plurality: Arendt's Political Phenomenology

Citation preview

Reconquering Polynarrative and Plurality: Arendts Political Phenomenology

Jasmina Tacheva

Abstract:

This paper examines the status of narrative in late capitalist society and claims that despite capitalisms promises to not just deliver the goods, but also to offer a virtually limitless variety of choices, what reality amounts to is a very constrained landscape of only the latest, most viable options available on the market. This process limits the ability of human beings to be actors in the political realm, but it also deprives them of the possibility to be world spectators an idea Kant advances in The Critique of Aesthetic Judgment, which Hannah Arendt picks up and expands upon in her Lectures on Kants Political Philosophy, by focusing on the sociability aspect of a reading public always in the plural which serves as the foundation for judgment. It is argued that the concept of judgment is Arendts attempt to overcome the shortcomings she finds in Husserls phenomenological project in favor of a political phenomenology that can be practiced collectively by the members of the community.After investigating Arendts analysis of both plurality and the characteristics of critical thinking and judgment, this paper turns to a major conflict identified by Arendt in her reading of Kants third Critique that between actor and spectator. The paper suggests that by inventively reconciling the two on the plateau of sociability, Arendt charts a way to bring about social change through the power of personal narratives. Concrete examples of the strong influence of this transformation are provided from the fields of feminism and environmentalism.

IntroductionIn the spirit of Arendts Lectures on Kants Political Philosophy, this paper explores the political implications of being and thinking in todays world, and claims that one such consequence is the scientification of the capitalist narrative, seeking to express every process with a formula that can be replicated and re-used to classify or evaluate new data a process of mechanization that nonetheless assumes the role of hard science with undeniable laws that can ostensibly not be rejected by common sense because they are able to explain general trends while ruling out or otherwise disguising (indeed, actively striving to eliminate) outliers that, in this paradigm, represent noise, uncertainty, or simply deviations from the norm. Thus, while Lyotards diagnosis of skepticism towards metanarratives in postmodernity may indeed hold, what counts as narrative has dramatically changed in late capitalism, taking the capitalist narrative out of its narrative milieu and elevating it to the level of science or the even harder to disprove state of common sense. The direct political implication of this is the economization of both business and private social relations which capitalist logic infuses with the Pareto principle (80-20 rule/law of the vital few) 80% of profits come from the top 20% of your customers, etc. What this amounts to is the false dilemma of having to decide who is more important and who should count less in plain opposition to Arendts rigorous attempt to restore, in todays moral and political thought, the importance of particulars she finds in Kant. The generality of capitalist logic aims at identifying a common trend, or an interesting pattern (two drivers of data mining), whereas Arendts notion of generality includes a perspective able to incorporate all actual and potential particulars. What we end up with, then, is a progressive destruction of polynarrativity in favor of a mainstream typifying mononarrative that effectively replaces human plurality with the most current market trend. This way, the monologic of a hegemonic narrative parading as a hard science is introduced and actively sustained in a world that wants us to know we can buy anything, but change nothing. A way out of this is possible, through concept of judgment advanced by Arendt who, it is argued in this paper, takes on the phenomenological project started by Husserl and expanded upon by Heidegger, and brings it into the political realm where it can be practiced by the community collectively. Plurality and JudgmentIn her Lectures on Kants Political Philosophy (hereafter Lectures) Hannah Arendt examines Kants work in search of the political philosophy he never explicitly formulated. She is convinced that signs of his thinking about political questions can be found throughout his philosophical oeuvre, despite always seemingly on the periphery, particularly in his later years that resulted in his third and last Critique, the Critique of Judgment. It is no small irony that in a similar fashion, Arendt herself did not live to more than type the first page of what was meant to be the third and concluding part of her elaboration on the vita contemplativa, comprising the parts Thinking, Willing, and the unfinished Judgment of The Life of the Mind. As Ronald Beiner suggests, the groundwork for this last part can be discovered precisely in the Lectures where she investigates Kants principles of aesthetic judgment in order to incorporate them in the wider canvas of judging in the political realm. This paper argues, furthermore, that Arendts political philosophy is a valuable extension to phenomenology, since it builds upon the foundation provided by Husserl and Heidegger by exploring the sociopolitical dimension both thinkers shied away from in their analyses. The philosophical tutelage Arendt received from Heidegger is widely discussed and almost notorious, whereas the semester she spent studying under Husserl in 1926 is much less known,[endnoteRef:1] perhaps because while she often comments on the philosophy of the former in both her theoretical and personal writings, the only explicit mentioning of Husserls phenomenology is to be found in one of the first philosophical pieces she published after the end of World War II, the 1946 article What Is Existential Philosophy. There, she welcomes Husserls (to be sure, from Arendts perspective, not entirely understood by Husserl himself) attempt to part with historicism as the central pillar of philosophy since Hegel (something that, curiously enough, she ascribes to Kant as well in her much later Lectures on Kants Political Philosophy), while still criticizing the impracticability of his otherwise admirable project of returning to the things themselves which she compares to Hofmannsthals appreciation for little things.[endnoteRef:2] She calls classicist the wish of the two to conjure up a new home from a world perceived as alien[endnoteRef:3] - a project she herself will undertake much later in The Human Condition, which has become known as her amor mundi love of the world which Julia Kristeva sees as the red thread connecting all her works.[endnoteRef:4] It is thus surprising that she would be so critical of Husserls project which she calls a liberation of philosophy, but which, according to her, reflects both profound modesty when it comes to the careful attention to the smallest things in the universe, and also the open and naive hubris of hoping that man can become what man cannot be: the creator of the world and of himself.[endnoteRef:5] Her later concept of natality, the possibility to be re-born in the political realm, seemingly follows in Husserls footsteps, but the important difference between her view of Husserls phenomenology and her conceptualization of natality, the one that shines through in the quote above, is Arendts both materialist [through her reading of Marx], although she would not admit it, and social perception of the world as existing long before any of us and as continuing to exist long after we vanish not just in terms of Kants ruse of nature, but even more so in terms of the political accomplishments of humans in both the past and the future a perspective for which her understanding of Husserl makes him sound too individualistic and too cut-off from the communality that is at the crux of the human world as she sees it. Her love of the world is the love of something already existing that can be changed, for better or for worse, but something we do not have either the first or the last word about, not of the need, as she reads Husserl, to (re)create it first, be it just in our own consciousness. [1: See, for example, the biographical notes in Hannah Arendts ber das Bse: eine Vorlesung zu Fragen der Ethik, Piper 2007.] [2: See What Is Existential Philosophy in Arendts Essays in Understanding, p. 165.] [3: Ibid., p. 165] [4: See Julia Kristeva, Hannah Arendt: Life as a Narrative, 2001.] [5: What Is Existential Philosophy, pp. 166-67.]

It shall be noted that for Arendt, the political is the sphere where the highest form of human activity, action, is carried out, in public. By public she means the world itself, in so far as it is common to all of us and distinguished from our privately owned place in it.[endnoteRef:6] An important consideration in this respect is Arendts notion of the in-between, our embeddedness in the world that both brings us together and keeps us apart: To live together in the world means essentially that a world of things is between those who have it in common, as a table is located between those who sit around it; the world, like every in-between, relates and separates men at the same time.[endnoteRef:7] This in-between is literally something which inter-est, which lies between people and therefore can relate and bind them together.[endnoteRef:8] But there is another in-between, which has overgrown the first one - the web of human relationships which is intangible because it consists of deeds and words and owes its origin exclusively to mens acting and speaking directly to one another.[endnoteRef:9] Arendt terms this interrelatedness plurality, which she categorizes as the state of the common world as being divided into a great many units, and it is only as a member of such a unit, that is, of a community, that men are ready for action. [endnoteRef:10] This essential condition of plurality is the basic condition of both action and speech,[endnoteRef:11] which, in turn, comprise the condition of all forms of political organization.[endnoteRef:12] The very existence of freedom in the political realm is possible only in the sphere of human plurality,[endnoteRef:13] but even more importantly than making the political possible, it is one of the basic existential conditions of human life on earth.[endnoteRef:14] [6: Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition, Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 1958, p. 52.] [7: Ibid.] [8: Human Condition, p. 182 cf. On Revolution, p. 86] [9: Arendt, Human Condition, p. 183] [10: Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind, Orlando, FL: Harcourt Brace & Company, 1978, p. 201.] [11: Arendt, Human Condition, p. 175] [12: Ibid., p. 202] [13: Arendt, Life of the Mind, p. 200; she expresses a similar idea in Essays in Understanding, p. 436: our concept of freedom, at least in its political aspects, is inconceivable outside of plurality. ] [14: Ibid., p. 74 ]

While in The Human Condition Arendt approaches plurality from the perspective of action, in the Lectures the focus is on judgment. Here, she announces two key findings in Kants Critique of Judgment closely related to the constitution of plurality: first, that in his last Critique, Kant does not speak of man as an intelligible or a cognitive being, but of men in the plural, as they really are and live in society, and second, that the faculty of judgment deals with particulars.[endnoteRef:15] These observations are indispensable to plurality because they hold the promise of preventing the exclusion of human beings from the public based on rationality or generality criteria, i.e. no one can be stopped from partaking in the political world on the grounds of lacking cognitive abilities or because they do not conform to some general idea of what a person should be. The defining condition Arendt finds in Kants third Critique is rather political freedom which he defines as to make public use of ones reason at every point, whereby Kant means the use which a person makes of it as a scholar before a reading public. [endnoteRef:16] Here, already it is clear that the solitude typically associated with thinking is overcome by thought being confronted with a public, and not just any kind of public, but a reading one, which means that for this process to take place, both an actively thinking conveyor of thought and a no less actively thinking group of recipients are needed. Moreover, Arendt explains that the term scholar here is not as restrictive as it might appear at first glance, and that in Kants vision the scholar is in fact a broader concept than the citizen who is bound to the tradition and legality of a particular country; the scholar is, in fact, a member of a society of world citizens,[endnoteRef:17] or as Arendt then states, a world spectator,[endnoteRef:18] an onlooker who can discover a meaning in the course taken by events; a meaning that the actors ignored,[endnoteRef:19] since the spectator is impartial by definition no part is assigned to him[endnoteRef:20] The reading public itself, cannot be a public of actors or participators in government,[endnoteRef:21] hence, it is also comprised of spectators, but, unlike the traditional view of the spectator as a solitary figure (she gives the chained inhabitants of Platos cave parable as an example to show that contemplation has traditionally been viewed as conducted in private[endnoteRef:22]), for Kant, and subsequently Arendt, the spectator observing the spectacle of history exists only in the plural The spectator is not involved in the act, but he is always involved with fellow spectators. He does not share the faculty of genius, originality, with the maker or the faculty of novelty with the actor; the faculty they have in common is the faculty of judgment.[endnoteRef:23] [15: Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kants Political Philosophy, p. 13] [16: Lectures, 39] [17: Lectures, 39] [18: Lectures, 44] [19: Lectures, 55] [20: Lectures, 56] [21: Lectures, 60] [22: Lectures, 59] [23: Lectures, 63]

Acting or Judging?It thus appears that the way opinion plays out in the political realm is by being delivered by a spectator to a multiplicity of spectators an image much different from the scenes Arendts vita activa presents in The Human Condition. Oddly, the two conditions need not be mutually exclusive: In the Lectures, one by one Arendt overthrows age-old conventions such as the secondary importance of a spectator vis--vis the primacy of the actor, or the inferiority of the spectators taste compared to the productive imagination needed to create a work of art to be judged by that taste,[endnoteRef:24] in order to alleviate the antagonism between theory and practice in political matters which is the distinction between the spectator and the actor.[endnoteRef:25] Arendt realizes that historically, a great challenge in this conflict has been presented by the incommunicability of an evidently subjective and inner sense such as taste (one can only woo or court the agreement of everyone else[endnoteRef:26]), but plurality, with its manifestation in publicity, enables her to turn this obstacle into an opportunity, the inauguration of a conversation, first with oneself, and then with the public. The way this general incommunicability stemming from the uniqueness and singularity of taste becomes shareable, according to Arendt, is through tastes transformation into judgment via the faculties of imagination and common sense. Based on her reading of Kant, Arendt defines imagination as the faculty of having present what is absent.[endnoteRef:27] Its importance in the process of rendering communicable what is innately personal lies in its capacity to make an object into something I do not have to be directly confronted with but that I have in some sense internalized, so that I now can be affected by it as though it were given to me by a nonobjective sense.[endnoteRef:28] This step signifies the passage from taste to judgment, since now the proper distance needed for impartiality which is the condition of judgment, has been established. The second part of this process is the appeal to what is for Kant an extra, sixth sense as it were, that fits us into a community sensus communis, which Arendt translates as community sense, rather than common sense, to make clear that it has to do with the ability to take the community into consideration, and not with the reasonably expected understanding common to all that the latter has been used to denote.[endnoteRef:29] Enhanced by sociability, mans need to be in the company of other human beings, these two steps bring one closer to the necessary condition for the greatest possible enlargement of the enlarged mentality what Kant calls the original compact, regulating not just our reflections but actually inspiring our actions. It is here, in this idea, or rather in the desire and willingness for it - for reaching out to the greatest number of standpoints, it very potentiality, regardless of whether it is actually brought to fruition, that actor and spectator become united.[endnoteRef:30] [24: Lectures, 62] [25: Lectures, 65] [26: Lectures, 72] [27: Lectures, 66] [28: Lectures, 67] [29: Lectures, 70] [30: Lectures, 75]

Where We Are Today From an Arendtian point of view, it should not be difficult to see how in late capitalism, it appears that people are being prepared predominantly for the toil of the activities of labor and work, rather than for the capacity of political action. This way, preference is given precisely to the view Arendt, through Kant, opposes most ardently viewing humans as a means to an end, in this case, the end of sustaining an economic system through the functionalization of human qualities, streamlined into tools used for its perpetuation. This, however, is not the focus of the following analysis. What is at its heart, is a more subtle but no less deleterious critique, generated from Arendts position on judgment. Whereas the consequences of action or non-action in the political realm are by the very nature of this human activity easy to see, those of suspending judgment are less visible, but no less dangerous in the long run. In what follows, several contributing factors to this threat of extinction of judgment are examined.To begin with, the erasure of the boundaries between theoretical and applied, or public and industry knowledge has often been noted.[endnoteRef:31] The results-based culture thriving on this instrumentalized knowledge places far greater emphasis on application and use than on explanation ambiguities are managed without an attempt at being resolved, as long as they can meet the desired prediction target. In the field of data mining, the increasing use of neural networks as models for solving data aggregation problems can be given as an example of black box systems where interpretability has given precedence to model fitness conglomerates of ostensibly weakly correlated data sources (such as NFL scores used as inputs to predict stock prices on Wall Street) are being fed into the model, whereby explanation of the actual relationship between data bits is abandoned completely, and only the models performance of actually approximating the real values of target variables is factored in.[endnoteRef:32] This way, a greater scope of topics and areas of interest is covered, but the understanding thereof is becoming thinner and thinner. [31: The latest occasion I have had to witness this view was a lecture by University at Buffalos Sociology professor Steve G. Hoffman, entitled Capitalism in Academia, in March, 2015.] [32: Jiawei Han, Data Mining: Concepts and Techniques, 3rd edition, 2011.]

What is even worse, these garbage models trying to map human behavior onto a market basket, despite their obvious deficiencies in explanatory power because of their almost complete randomness, somehow successfully usurp the role of a rigorous science, because of their approximation of real-world market interactions. The laws of the market seem today almost as undeniable as the laws of nature. Reagan and Thatchers no alternative slogan of capitalism thus becomes doubly dangerous, since apart from the sterility of the opposition in politics, they spell the eclipse of judgment in Arendts common political realm not just parties have stopped envisioning a different future, but most of us as well. The way the law absolves us from the necessity to negotiate and define every social relationship anew each time, by taking capitalism as a given, we effectively abdicate from the responsibility to reflect on it. In this paradigm, objectivity becomes objectification, and the conventional denominator of all relations becomes the systems utility rather than human rights once again, Arendts fear has come true humans are turned into a means to an economic end. Coupled with the manageriality of capitalism, its paranoid obsession with controlling all processes and actors in order to prevent undesirable outcomes and maximize profits, this process chips away at the very foundation of humanity by first denominating human beings as market agents, and then demonstrating the false necessity of having to choose whose needs are more important, because, as the Pareto principle makes abundantly clear, you cannot possibly satisfy all your customers all the time. In fact, the top 20 per cent of your customers likely generate 80 per cent of your profits, so it is only logical, common-sensical (how different from Arendts use of the sensus communis!) to focus on this upper stratum and give the rest just enough so they do not resort to a different vendor. This logic, supported by capitalisms focal point the idea of the scarcity of resources has long ago left the market place and penetrated social and legal relationships, or rather, the market place has billowed to engulf these spheres of human interaction and inject them with its logic. Because its garbage-neural-network-predictor models work, and because of political maneuvers of nationalizing corporate debt, we are made to believe the system can weather any storm, so it is indeed the only viable economic option, which gives its prosperity narrative pseudo-scientific validity, and makes it appealing to common sense. In his book Capitalist Realism Mark Fisher demonstrates the way in which those not willing to buy into the viability of capitalist scienfication and common-sensicality are pronounced hopeless idealists or outright insane.[endnoteRef:33] Their opinions are being communicated, but the reading audience remains indifferent, or even worse infuriated by their attempts to subvert something that evidently not even economic laws can subdue. The only explanation is that the audience has stopped reading, as it were, and has instead succumbed to the sheer dogmatism of blindly obeying the precepts of tradition or authority, a state Kants way out of which Arendt sees as his first awakening.[endnoteRef:34] [33: See Mark Fisher, Capitalist Realism: Is There No Alternative? Zero Books, 2009.] [34: Lectures, 32]

Uncritically following the dogmatism of capitalisms pseudoscience and common-sensicality represents the shallowness of the second term in the market agents form of society the system has created. Far from being tantamount to the actions of the actors in Arendts Lectures, the activities of market agents are closely monitored, indeed dictated, by seemingly natural (hence, the markets obsession with presenting its equilibrium laws as no less valid than the laws of nature) mechanisms of supply and demand, and the plurality which democracy promises to preserve and respect, is transformed into general market trends whose generality, unlike the one prescribed by Arendt, ruling out the assumption of a higher, objective point of view in favor of acknowledging the multiplicity of actual and potential standpoints, aims at charting the most robust cost curve, the most accurate demand forecast, or the latest hot commodities trending on the market. What is even worse, however, is that aside from the illusion of a possibility for genuine action the system presents, the role of a world spectator, the way Kant conceives of it, has also been greatly limited, again, by the dogmatism mentioned above. Thus, sociability, what Adam Phillips calls the unwilled choreography of society,[endnoteRef:35] is fundamentally threatened by the possibility of conversation, the conversation about particulars, ceasing altogether. [35: Adam Phillips, Becoming Freud Lecture at University at Buffalo, April 27, 2015.]

Narrative as a Way outIn Arendts creative reconciliation of spectator and actor via sociability lies a potent opportunity for social change. The way it can be brought about is through narrative judgment, more specifically, through sharing the plurality of narratives that under the current system are silenced, typified, or streamlined into either a general norm, served by the market (as per the Pareto principle), or deviations from that norm that the behavioral manageriality approach tries to either isolate and disregard, or bring back to the centrality of the regression line depicting the conformity of the general public. Is it too far-fetched to suggest that the two steps Arendt describes as comprising the process of transformation of taste into judgment imagination and community sense, are also the underlying elements of narrative? Through imagination, making present what is absent, a name, an account, a story is born, that is then bounced off of a community, real or imaginary, which picks it up and re-activates it through remembering or retelling, thereby achieving the apparently impossible giving the particulars a public voice, a public memory, a public response. As the documentary about the story of the Second Wave of feminism in America, She Is Beautiful When Shes Angry (Dore, 2014), shows through a series of interviews with Ellen Willis, Alix Kates Shulman, Kate Millett, Rita Mae Brown, and other iconoclastic feminist pioneers, before oppression can be recognized, in the political, social, or legal realm, it has to be named first, it has to be made present in the minds not just of the victims and perpetrators, but also of people who likely never experienced it. Imagination needs to be employed. The film traces the entrance of the concepts of sexual harassment and domestic violence into the social and legal realm, their naming - the initial, challenging, laborious, but at the same time absolutely essential and indispensable step towards fighting it. As Ruth Rosen explains in the movie, We named it, then made it illegal.[endnoteRef:36] By giving sexual repression a name, what Arendt sees in Kant as preparing the idea for reflection, is performed the concept has entered sociability through the process of communicability now it can be shared with others, it can be put to the test of sensus communis and debated in common. [36: She Is Beautiful When She Is Angry, Dir. Mary Dore, 2014]

A name is always a starting point. Activist and journalist Naomi Klein makes this abundantly clear when she explains with regard to This Changes Everything - her newest book which aims at putting the question of environmental destruction square on the table of the common, in Arendtian parlance. She explains that in interviews, the first question is usually precisely about the name of the book what is it that changes everything? To which she is well prepared (for this is exactly the effect she says she has sought with the title in the first place) to reply, the environment.[endnoteRef:37] This is the first step, imagination has been employed, a name has been given, the absent has been made present, and memorably so. Next comes sharing the judgment contained within the name with the public. Through this process, the name is effectively filled with the personal narratives of the spectators, whether acting or not, but always reflecting. The name forces reflection, it does not leave anyone indifferent, and this is precisely Arendts point on imagination. After the idea of sexual harassment was given a name, a multitude of women realized they were not alone and gathered to share their stories, not just among one another, but in front of the world; they forced the world to become a reading public, be it at the expense of having to confront people not willing to listen on a daily basis. The power of personal narratives has not escaped Naomi Kleins attention either. Her book starts out with a captivating account of her reading from a childrens book to her two-year-old son. The name of the book is Have You Ever Seen a Moose?, and as Klein reads it over and over again to her spellbound son, it suddenly hits her that he might never see a moose, based on the observations of the Beaver Lake Cree Nation about the toxicity of the water moose drink from.[endnoteRef:38] Will he ever see a moose? a simple question spelling the manifold disastrous effects of an impending environmental monstrosity in a way that cannot be denied. Personal narrative elevates the position of the spectator to that of the actor in terms of the potentiality of its social influence because it cuts to the heart of indifference and prompts reflection. It holds undeniable truth that is very different from the one offered by science, especially by the pseudoscience of capitalism: Truth in the sciences is dependent on the experiment that can be repeated by others; it requires general validity. Philosophic truth has no such general validity. What it must have, what Kant demanded in the Critique of Judgment of judgments of taste, is general communicability, writes Arendt in her Lectures.[endnoteRef:39] If this example is not enough, or if it seems insufficient since it comes from a developed Western country that still chooses to close its eyes to the undeniable reality of destruction (even though entire states, like California, struggle with the consequences of reckless exploitation of natural resources), the power of personal narrative can be demonstrated with yet another instance of environmental activism Chai Jings film about air pollution in China, Under the Dome (2015), or rather, as Kant would say, not with the event of the film itself, but with the way it was perceived by the audience and what opinions it generated. The number of views has been growing exponentially, to the point where even the Chinese government could not remain silent on the issue. What captivates in this film is not just the well-documented, amply researched correlation between disease and air pollution; what truly shocks and invokes reflection, not just intellectual one, but more importantly, sensed, lived reflection, is the string of simple and yet resounding questions asked by Jing to a six-year-old girl living in an area heavily impacted by the smog in a similar vein as Kleins questions about the future of her son: Have you ever seen stars?, Have you ever seen white clouds? No. - Perhaps the longest monosyllable in the history of humanity. One that condemns a long, irresponsible past, but at the same time charts a gloomy, uncertain future. [37: Naomi Klein, This Changes Everything Capitalism vs. the Climate, September 30, 2014] [38: Naomi Klein, This Changes Everything, p. 30] [39: Lectures, 40]

Judgment, Arendt explains in her Lectures, is about things of the past, but it is also true that without judgment there can be no future, at least not a non-catastrophic one. In the preface to the Human Condition Arendt warns humanity of its growing ability to destroy the world; this warning has progressed into an unwavering sense of urgency in Kleins This Changes Everything and Jings Under the Dome. Here, the mere possibility of destruction has given way to an environmental apocalypse in full throttle that has erased most hope for reversal. And yet most of us remain calm in the face of a disaster that has already begun to unfold; those who have not encountered these powerful narratives, at least. Those who have, are beginning to wonder. Or reflect. And hopefully judge. Without a community of judging spectators, the world might cease to exist tomorrow. The phenomenological question is no longer how to recreate the world in ones consciousness, but rather how to preserve it from utter destruction. And this question can only be addressed by a phenomenology that is deeply political.

References:Arendt, Hannah. Lectures on Kants Political Philosophy. 1989.

--- --- ---. The Human Condition. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 1958.

--- --- ---. The Life of the Mind. Orlando, FL: Harcourt Brace & Company, 1978.

--- --- ---. The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York, NY: Meridian Books, 1962.

Fisher, Mark. Capitalist Realism: Is There No Alternative? Zero Books, 2009.

Han, Jiawei. Data Mining: Concepts and Techniques, 3rd edition, 2011.

Hoffman, Steve G. Capitalism in Academia, lecture at University at Buffalo, March, 2015.

Klein, Naomi. This Changes Everything. Alfred A. Knopf Canada, 2014.

Phillips, Adam. Becoming Freud Lecture at University at Buffalo, April 27, 2015.

Shes Beautiful When Shes Angry, directed by Mary Dore, 2014.

This Changes Everything Capitalism vs. the Climate. Naomi Klein. September 30, 2014

Under the Dome, directed by Chai Jing, 2015.