10

Click here to load reader

Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Undergraduate Essay

Citation preview

Page 1: Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Reynor May ‘05

Quine’s Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Thomas Reynor_____________________________________________________________________

In analysing the ontology’s of Quine and Carnap some

arresting resemblances between the two standpoints emerge,

which Quine himself recognizes1, and it the main aim of this paper

to investigate how ingrained these resemblances are. Once the

degree of resemblance or non-resemblance has been established, it

will be apparent how far Quine has to reach in order to defend his

ontology. I intend to show that his reach does not have to extend

incredibly far. In fact, through the course of the investigation it

becomes evident that instead of mounting a defence against

Carnap what Quine is attempting is an examination, one that

instead of creating a gulf will create a bridge and an attempt at a

unified ontology. The problem of explaining and assessing Quine’s

defence then revolves into the problem of explaining and assessing

the value of Quine’s attempt at unification. The brilliance of Quine’s

method of defence is that he renders the situation such that there

is nothing in need of defence. Is it necessary to organise a defence,

or an attack, against something with which you agree? Certainly

not, instead of an attempt at defence Quine opts for an approach

that that is favourable for both ontology’s. Why argue for one

theory against another when it is possible to argue for both by

accepting reconciliation. If this reconciliation can be achieved

through unified theory, there is no need to defend at all. However,

how successful is Quine in his attempts at defence through

unification? First, I will be forwarding Quine’s ontology and his use

1 In his paper called ‘Carnap’s Views on Onology’, in ‘The Ways of Paradox and other essays’ (see bibliography).

1 of 8

Page 2: Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Reynor May ‘05

of a traditional defence against problems such as Plato’s beard;

after this, I will examine the apparent divergences of the two

theories and finally I will investigate how Quine maintains his

defence through reconciliation and whether it is a lucrative course

of action.

In Quine’s paper On What There Is we see him argue in

defence of his ontology against two fictional characters of his own

imagination. When defending his ontology against Carnap in his

earlier paper On Carnap’s Views on Ontology we are witness to a

distinctly contrary approach to defence, mentioned above, which I

will be getting to later. Firstly, let us look at Quine’s ontology as

expropriated from On What There Is. He begins with the problem

of Plato’s beard the tangled doctrine of non-being. Quine and his

fictional debating partner ‘Mr X’ differ in their ontology’s; ‘Mr X’

maintains that there is something, an entity, which Quine maintains

there is not, and thus the problem arises. With respect to Quine’s

formulation of the problem, he cannot without contradiction claim

that ‘Mr X’s’ entity is not, i.e. ‘Non-being must in some sense be,

otherwise what is it that there is not?’2Quine sustains that this is

confusion on the part of ‘Mr X’ who must admit that a physical

being, such as Pegasus, does not exist and instead must posit being

for the mental Pegasus-idea. However, this same ‘Mr X’ would

never suffer confusion regarding the Parthenon and Parthenon-

idea, so why tolerate it with Pegasus and why not just admit to the

non-being of Pegasus. Enter Quine’s second apparent opponent

‘Wyman’ who upholds the being of Pegasus as an unactualized

possible. ‘Wyman’ admits to the non-existence or non-actuality of

Pegasus while simultaneously maintaining that it is. Quine then

decides to ‘clear Wyman’s slum (of possibles) and be done with it’.

‘Wyman’ can hardly admit ‘the round square cupola on Berkeley

College’ as an unactualized possible instead he claims that it is

2 Ibid, p.1.

2 of 8

Page 3: Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Reynor May ‘05

meaningless. Now, to attempt an entanglement of Plato’s beard

Quine utilizes Russell’s theory of singular descriptions.

When a statement of being or non-being is analysed…it ceases to contain

any expression which even purports to name the alleged entity whose

being is in question, so that the meaningfulness no longer can be thought

to presuppose that there be such an entity.3

So now, in place of the meaningless ‘Pegasus’ we can use the

descriptive phrase ‘the winged horse of Bellerophon’; and if there

were no descriptive phrases available for Pegasus we could simply

substitute ‘is Pegasus’ or ‘pegasizes’, thus cutting off and disposing

with Plato’s beard. It can now be safely said that we do not commit

ourselves to an ontology containing ‘Pegasus’ if we commit

ourselves to ‘Pegasus is not’.

We now come to the beginning of the conflict between Carnap

and Quine. The essential difference between teacher and student

breaks down to this – Carnap’s dichotomy consists of a

‘fundamental distinction between the two kinds of questions

concerning the existence or reality of entities’4 and Quine

disagrees. Quine’s undivided idea develops from his opposition to

‘Mr X’ and ‘Wyman’ when he investigates the problem of

universals.

When we use the word ‘similar’, without defining it in any anterior terms,

do we thereby commit ourselves to the acceptance of an abstract entity

which is the relation of similarity.5

How do we discover if we are committing ourselves to abstract

entities? The anti-nominalist claims that in using a general term

such as ‘fish’ we are alluding to abstract entities. On the other

3 Ibid, p.7.4 Supplement ‘A’ ‘Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology’ from Carnap’s ‘Meaning and Necessity’, p.206.5 Ibid, p.204.

3 of 8

Page 4: Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Reynor May ‘05

hand, the nominalist would believe they are referring to a concrete

particular ‘fish’ and not committing themselves to naming an

abstract ‘fishhood’. In addition, when we say that the word ‘similar’

is true of each ‘X’ with regard to each ‘Y’ we do not however name

a relation of similarity. How could ‘fish’ or ‘similar’ be put on level

terms with ‘Dublin’ or ‘Morning Star’? Even if the nominalist is

found guilty of using the word ‘fishhood’, they could easily claim to

be alluding to the general term and not the abstract entity.

However, ‘Mr X’ may counter with the claim that ‘fishhood’ has

meaning and is still a universal and ‘Mr X’ believes we commit

ourselves to abstract entities in this way. Nevertheless, by

examining the difference between meaning and naming, we find a

gulf. Using Frege’s example of the phrases ‘Evening Star’ and

‘Morning Star’, we find that both phrases name the same entity but

have a different meaning. Quine, in response, must refuse to admit

meanings, but in doing so, he does not deny the meaningfulness of

statements and can still ‘view utterances as significant’ without

supporting a domain of meanings. He also denies a commitment to

entities by the use of alleged names that are quickly dismissed as

‘admissible without claiming to name’.6

Are there any entities that we commit ourselves to in a given

theory? By utilizing the phrases ‘there is a number between one

and ten’ or ‘there are brown cars’ are we not implying that there

are abstract entities and physical objects respectively.

…the objects we are to be understood to admit are precisely the objects

which we reckon to the universe of values over which the bound variables

of quantification are to be considered to range.7

Thus, to answer the earlier question, the entities we are

committing ourselves to, according to Quine, are bound variables

of quantification and not alleged names. The entities over which

6 Ibid.7 From Quine’s ‘Word & Object’, p.242.

4 of 8

Page 5: Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Reynor May ‘05

these bound variables range are the ones that are true for a given

theory. Using bound variables, we have full reign to commit to

entities that we cannot name, as it has already been shown that

names can be abolished with Russell’s theory of descriptions. ‘To

be assumed as an entity is…to be reckoned as the value of a

variable’8 However, in determining what entities we are allowed to

presuppose i.e. what there is, we see the dichotomy of Carnap

which I mentioned earlier. In Quine’s essay Carnap’s Views on

Ontology, he places questions of the being of a number between

one and ten or of there being brown cars on one side of Carnap’s

dichotomy and questions of physical entities or abstract entities on

the other. Quine, however, does not acknowledge this distinction

and instead unifies the dichotomy by blurring the distinctions and

allying the two question types. In Carnap’s paper Empiricism,

Semantics and Ontology, the dichotomy is at it most prevalent in

the discussion concerning the framework of the language.

If someone wishes to speak in his language about a new kind of entities,

he has to introduce a system of new ways of speaking, subject to new

rules; we shall call this procedure the construction of a linguistic

framework for the new entities in question. And now we must distinguish

two kinds of questions of existence: first, questions of the existence of

certain entities of the new kind within the framework; we call them

internal questions; and second, questions concerning the existence or

reality of the system of entities as a whole, called external questions.9

Now that I have forwarded Carnap’s ontological dicotomy, I will

proceed to explicate Quine’s method of reconciliation between

Carnap’s ontology and his own. Quine begins by reinterpreting

Carnap’s external and internal distinction as a distinction between

category questions, which ‘exhaust the range of a particular style

of bound variables’10and subclass questions, which do not exhaust

the range. However, Quine does re interpret the terminology used

8 From Quine’s ‘From a Logical Point of View’, p.13.9 Carnap, ‘Meaning and Necessity’, p.206.10 Quine, ‘The Ways of Paradox and other essays’, p.207.

5 of 8

Page 6: Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Reynor May ‘05

by Carnap that the analytic type of internal question is contained,

in Quine’s formulation, within the subclass range. Quine holds that

if we use a single style of variables to encompass the whole range

of entities then questions of numbers, classes, and physical objects

all become subclass questions, thus trivialising11 Carnap’s

dichotomy into the problem of whether to use one or two styles of

variables. He argues further against the compartmentalisation of

variables by utilizing Zermelo’s set theory12 under this theory all

questions of numbers or physical and abstract entities become

subclass questions. However, under a strict adoption of Russell’s

theory of types13 the problem remains until we take Russell’s

method of typical ambiguity and exploit it to its full potential

discarding the use of a distinct style of variables for every and all

types. In this way, Quine has shown that Carnap’s dichotomy is

trivial, and thus reconciled the two ontology’s even under the

adoption of the theory of types. With regard to Carnap’s paper

Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology Quine has shown that it is

possible to eradicate the distinction without damaging its

philosophical aims.

I have shown how Quine defends his theory against opponents

like ‘Mr X’ and ‘Wyman and also how he achieved what he set out

to and reconciled his ontology with that of Carnap’s rendering a

negligible need to defend against an ontology that ‘commits’ to the

same entities as his own. Nevertheless, the wound was stitched by

the re-interpretation of Carnap’s terminological distinction

between external and internal questions. However, this does not

11 Quine explains this triviality mathematically. He states that ‘…the difference between using the explicit hypothesis ‘x is a real number between 0 and 1’ and introducing the restricted variables is so negligible that at the level of ordinary mathematical writing it cannot usually be detected; nor is there any reason why it should be detected.’ Quine, ‘The Ways of Paradox’, p.208. 12 Zermelo’s axiomatization of set theory classified the existence of sets regulated by a predicate to just those sets whose members were members of a given set and satisfied the predicate.13 A proposition relating to other propositions must, Russell says, be of another type from, a higher order then, the proposition it is about. So we must say that the classes of all first order classes which are not members of themselves are a second order class, thus it is nonsense to say that a class is or isn’t a member of itself.

6 of 8

Page 7: Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Reynor May ‘05

affect Carnap’s formulation in any major respect; for the

introduction of his framework he to admits that entities of the new

kind, as internal within the framework, are substitutable for

variables and using these variables sentences of the new kind can

be generated. If the internal questions concern the existence of

entities of the new kind, mentioned above, then Quine’s subdivision

must lead to an analytic/synthetic distinction between category and

subclass questions within the internal framework. This further

implies that external category questions, which are synthetic, can

be abandoned in favour of internal subclass questions. Essentially

questions about the reality of the thing world or the system of

entities can be formulated as internal subclass questions. The

problem for Quine now lies with the quandary of the

analytic/synthetic distinction. In the paper Two Dogmas of

Empiricism Quine attempts to prove that there is no distinction,

Carnap however would appear to disagree until we look at his

formulation of the connotative, propositions of meaning, and

formal, syntactical propositions. It is possible to view connotative

as synthetic and formal as analytic modes of expression, and in On

the Character of Philosophical Problems Carnap, so as not to cut

the branch he sits on, reduces all propositions to the formal mode

while retaining their meaningfulness. In this way, he too is blurring

the lines between analytic and synthetic proposition and in a sense

bestowing the reconciliation upon Quine.

Bibliography:

Carnap, R; ‘Meaning and Necessity’; Chicago University Press

(Chicago 1988).

7 of 8

Page 8: Quine's Defence of Ontology against Carnap

Philip Reynor May ‘05

Carnap, R; ‘On the Character of Philosophical Problems’ reprinted

in ‘The Linguistic Turn’; ed: Rorty, R; Chicago University Press

(Chicago 1967).

Flew, A (ed.); ‘A Dictionary of Philosophy’; Pan Books Limited

(London 1979).

Quine, W.V.O; ‘From a Logical Point of View’; Harvard University

Press (U.S.A 1980-1996).

Quine, W.V.O; ‘The Ways of Paradox and other essays’; Harvard

University Press (London 1997).

Quine, W.V.O; ‘Word & Object’; M.I.T Press (U.S.A 1996).

8 of 8