131
Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications in Core Mathematics Ulrich Kohlenbach Department of Mathematics Technische Universit¨ at Darmstadt Workshop CSPM Computer Science, Philosophy, Mathematics Institute de Math´ ematiques de Toulouse, April 26, 2013 Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    6

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Proof Theory: From the Foundations of

Mathematics to Applications in Core Mathematics

Ulrich Kohlenbach

Department of Mathematics

Technische Universitat Darmstadt

Workshop CSPM Computer Science, Philosophy, Mathematics

Institute de Mathematiques de Toulouse, April 26, 2013

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 2: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Background: David Hilbert’s Program

Since the 19th century noneffective (set-theoretic) principles became

increasingly important.

The issue of their legitimacy led Hilbert to the program:

Establish that uses of these higher noneffective/transfinite (,,ideal”)

principles I in proofs of combinatorial/finitistic (,,real”) propositions

can be eliminated, at least in principle.

In particular: Show the consistency of I by finitistic means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 3: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Background: David Hilbert’s Program

Since the 19th century noneffective (set-theoretic) principles became

increasingly important.

The issue of their legitimacy led Hilbert to the program:

Establish that uses of these higher noneffective/transfinite (,,ideal”)

principles I in proofs of combinatorial/finitistic (,,real”) propositions

can be eliminated, at least in principle.

In particular: Show the consistency of I by finitistic means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 4: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Background: David Hilbert’s Program

Since the 19th century noneffective (set-theoretic) principles became

increasingly important.

The issue of their legitimacy led Hilbert to the program:

Establish that uses of these higher noneffective/transfinite (,,ideal”)

principles I in proofs of combinatorial/finitistic (,,real”) propositions

can be eliminated, at least in principle.

In particular: Show the consistency of I by finitistic means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 5: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Background: David Hilbert’s Program

Since the 19th century noneffective (set-theoretic) principles became

increasingly important.

The issue of their legitimacy led Hilbert to the program:

Establish that uses of these higher noneffective/transfinite (,,ideal”)

principles I in proofs of combinatorial/finitistic (,,real”) propositions

can be eliminated, at least in principle.

In particular: Show the consistency of I by finitistic means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 6: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Background: David Hilbert’s Program

Since the 19th century noneffective (set-theoretic) principles became

increasingly important.

The issue of their legitimacy led Hilbert to the program:

Establish that uses of these higher noneffective/transfinite (,,ideal”)

principles I in proofs of combinatorial/finitistic (,,real”) propositions

can be eliminated, at least in principle.

In particular: Show the consistency of I by finitistic means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 7: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Impossibility of the program (in the narrow sense)

Theorem [K. Godel 1931]

For no nontrivial consistent theory T is it possible to prove the

consistency of T in T itself.

Modified Hilbert Program:

Calibrate the contribution of the use of ideal principles in proofs.

Reduce the consistency of a theory T1 to that of a prima facie more

constructive theory T2.

In ordinary mathematics: the “Godel Phenomenon” is extremely rare.

Usually, “ideal” principles can be replaced by suitable more elementary

ones. However: this can be very difficult to accomplish.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 8: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Impossibility of the program (in the narrow sense)

Theorem [K. Godel 1931]

For no nontrivial consistent theory T is it possible to prove the

consistency of T in T itself.

Modified Hilbert Program:

Calibrate the contribution of the use of ideal principles in proofs.

Reduce the consistency of a theory T1 to that of a prima facie more

constructive theory T2.

In ordinary mathematics: the “Godel Phenomenon” is extremely rare.

Usually, “ideal” principles can be replaced by suitable more elementary

ones. However: this can be very difficult to accomplish.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 9: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Impossibility of the program (in the narrow sense)

Theorem [K. Godel 1931]

For no nontrivial consistent theory T is it possible to prove the

consistency of T in T itself.

Modified Hilbert Program:

Calibrate the contribution of the use of ideal principles in proofs.

Reduce the consistency of a theory T1 to that of a prima facie more

constructive theory T2.

In ordinary mathematics: the “Godel Phenomenon” is extremely rare.

Usually, “ideal” principles can be replaced by suitable more elementary

ones. However: this can be very difficult to accomplish.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 10: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Impossibility of the program (in the narrow sense)

Theorem [K. Godel 1931]

For no nontrivial consistent theory T is it possible to prove the

consistency of T in T itself.

Modified Hilbert Program:

Calibrate the contribution of the use of ideal principles in proofs.

Reduce the consistency of a theory T1 to that of a prima facie more

constructive theory T2.

In ordinary mathematics: the “Godel Phenomenon” is extremely rare.

Usually, “ideal” principles can be replaced by suitable more elementary

ones. However: this can be very difficult to accomplish.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 11: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

G. Kreisel: from consistency to mathematical applications

General malaise of consistency proofs:

‘To one who has faith, no explanation is necessary. To one without faith,

no explanation is possible’ (attributed to St Thomas Aquinas).

G. Kreisel: instead of focussing on purely universal statements

(consistency statements) consider proofs of existential statements

which may use arbitrary true universal axioms!

‘What more do we know if we have proved a theorem by restricted

means than if we merely know that it is true? (G. Kreisel, 50’s)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 12: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

G. Kreisel: from consistency to mathematical applications

General malaise of consistency proofs:

‘To one who has faith, no explanation is necessary. To one without faith,

no explanation is possible’ (attributed to St Thomas Aquinas).

G. Kreisel: instead of focussing on purely universal statements

(consistency statements) consider proofs of existential statements

which may use arbitrary true universal axioms!

‘What more do we know if we have proved a theorem by restricted

means than if we merely know that it is true? (G. Kreisel, 50’s)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 13: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

G. Kreisel: from consistency to mathematical applications

General malaise of consistency proofs:

‘To one who has faith, no explanation is necessary. To one without faith,

no explanation is possible’ (attributed to St Thomas Aquinas).

G. Kreisel: instead of focussing on purely universal statements

(consistency statements) consider proofs of existential statements

which may use arbitrary true universal axioms!

‘What more do we know if we have proved a theorem by restricted

means than if we merely know that it is true? (G. Kreisel, 50’s)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 14: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

G. Kreisel: from consistency to mathematical applications

General malaise of consistency proofs:

‘To one who has faith, no explanation is necessary. To one without faith,

no explanation is possible’ (attributed to St Thomas Aquinas).

G. Kreisel: instead of focussing on purely universal statements

(consistency statements) consider proofs of existential statements

which may use arbitrary true universal axioms!

‘What more do we know if we have proved a theorem by restricted

means than if we merely know that it is true? (G. Kreisel, 50’s)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 15: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 16: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Extractive Proof Theory (G. Kreisel):

New results by logical analysis of proofs

Input: Noneffective proof P of C

Goal: Additional information on C :

quantitative information: explicit effective bounds,

qualitative aspects:

existence of bound that is independent from certain parameters,

generalizations of proofs: weakening of premises.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 17: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Extractive Proof Theory (G. Kreisel):

New results by logical analysis of proofs

Input: Noneffective proof P of C

Goal: Additional information on C :

quantitative information: explicit effective bounds,

qualitative aspects:

existence of bound that is independent from certain parameters,

generalizations of proofs: weakening of premises.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 18: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Extractive Proof Theory (G. Kreisel):

New results by logical analysis of proofs

Input: Noneffective proof P of C

Goal: Additional information on C :

quantitative information: explicit effective bounds,

qualitative aspects:

existence of bound that is independent from certain parameters,

generalizations of proofs: weakening of premises.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 19: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Extractive Proof Theory (G. Kreisel):

New results by logical analysis of proofs

Input: Noneffective proof P of C

Goal: Additional information on C :

quantitative information: explicit effective bounds,

qualitative aspects:

existence of bound that is independent from certain parameters,

generalizations of proofs: weakening of premises.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 20: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Extractive Proof Theory (G. Kreisel):

New results by logical analysis of proofs

Input: Noneffective proof P of C

Goal: Additional information on C :

quantitative information: explicit effective bounds,

qualitative aspects:

existence of bound that is independent from certain parameters,

generalizations of proofs: weakening of premises.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 21: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Extractive Proof Theory (G. Kreisel):

New results by logical analysis of proofs

Input: Noneffective proof P of C

Goal: Additional information on C :

quantitative information: explicit effective bounds,

qualitative aspects:

existence of bound that is independent from certain parameters,

generalizations of proofs: weakening of premises.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 22: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Proof Interpretations

Let T1 and T2 be theories with languages L(T1) and L(T2).

Interpret propositions A from L(T1) (inductively over the logical

structure of A) by propositions AI from L(T2).

Transform a proof p of A into a proof pI of AI (induction on p).

AI contains the additional computational quantitative

information on A we are looking for such as effective bounds.

Central Method: Modern extensions of Godel’s 1958 (developed as part

of modified Hilbert program) Functional (‘Dialectica’) Interpretation!

Uses embedding into systems based in intuitionistic logic (Brouwer).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 23: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Proof Interpretations

Let T1 and T2 be theories with languages L(T1) and L(T2).

Interpret propositions A from L(T1) (inductively over the logical

structure of A) by propositions AI from L(T2).

Transform a proof p of A into a proof pI of AI (induction on p).

AI contains the additional computational quantitative

information on A we are looking for such as effective bounds.

Central Method: Modern extensions of Godel’s 1958 (developed as part

of modified Hilbert program) Functional (‘Dialectica’) Interpretation!

Uses embedding into systems based in intuitionistic logic (Brouwer).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 24: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Proof Interpretations

Let T1 and T2 be theories with languages L(T1) and L(T2).

Interpret propositions A from L(T1) (inductively over the logical

structure of A) by propositions AI from L(T2).

Transform a proof p of A into a proof pI of AI (induction on p).

AI contains the additional computational quantitative

information on A we are looking for such as effective bounds.

Central Method: Modern extensions of Godel’s 1958 (developed as part

of modified Hilbert program) Functional (‘Dialectica’) Interpretation!

Uses embedding into systems based in intuitionistic logic (Brouwer).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 25: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Proof Interpretations

Let T1 and T2 be theories with languages L(T1) and L(T2).

Interpret propositions A from L(T1) (inductively over the logical

structure of A) by propositions AI from L(T2).

Transform a proof p of A into a proof pI of AI (induction on p).

AI contains the additional computational quantitative

information on A we are looking for such as effective bounds.

Central Method: Modern extensions of Godel’s 1958 (developed as part

of modified Hilbert program) Functional (‘Dialectica’) Interpretation!

Uses embedding into systems based in intuitionistic logic (Brouwer).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 26: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Proof Interpretations

Let T1 and T2 be theories with languages L(T1) and L(T2).

Interpret propositions A from L(T1) (inductively over the logical

structure of A) by propositions AI from L(T2).

Transform a proof p of A into a proof pI of AI (induction on p).

AI contains the additional computational quantitative

information on A we are looking for such as effective bounds.

Central Method: Modern extensions of Godel’s 1958 (developed as part

of modified Hilbert program) Functional (‘Dialectica’) Interpretation!

Uses embedding into systems based in intuitionistic logic (Brouwer).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 27: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

“Proof Mining” in core mathematics

During the last 20 years this proof-theoretic approach has resulted in

numerous new quantitative results as well as qualitative

uniformity results in particular in: nonlinear analysis, fixed point

theory, ergodic theory, topological dynamics, approximation theory

etc.

General logical metatheorems explain these applications as

instances of logical phenomena (K. 2005, Gerhardy/K. 2008,

TAMS).

Some of the logical tools used have recently been rediscovered in

special cases by Terence Tao prompted by concrete mathematical

needs “finitary analysis”!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 28: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

“Proof Mining” in core mathematics

During the last 20 years this proof-theoretic approach has resulted in

numerous new quantitative results as well as qualitative

uniformity results in particular in: nonlinear analysis, fixed point

theory, ergodic theory, topological dynamics, approximation theory

etc.

General logical metatheorems explain these applications as

instances of logical phenomena (K. 2005, Gerhardy/K. 2008,

TAMS).

Some of the logical tools used have recently been rediscovered in

special cases by Terence Tao prompted by concrete mathematical

needs “finitary analysis”!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 29: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

“Proof Mining” in core mathematics

During the last 20 years this proof-theoretic approach has resulted in

numerous new quantitative results as well as qualitative

uniformity results in particular in: nonlinear analysis, fixed point

theory, ergodic theory, topological dynamics, approximation theory

etc.

General logical metatheorems explain these applications as

instances of logical phenomena (K. 2005, Gerhardy/K. 2008,

TAMS).

Some of the logical tools used have recently been rediscovered in

special cases by Terence Tao prompted by concrete mathematical

needs “finitary analysis”!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 30: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Goal: Extract effective bounds for ∀x ∈ X ∃n ∈ INA(x , n)-theorems.

Restriction: Because of classical logic: in general A existential.

If A is existential, then general logical metatheorems (K. 2005)

guarantee the extractability of effective bounds on ‘∃’ that are

independent from parameters x from

compact metric spaces K (if separability is used) and

metrically bounded subsets of abstract spaces X that are not

assumed to be separable (provided X belongs to a sufficiently

uniformly axiomatizable class of spaces).

Examples of such spaces X : metric, normed, Hilbert, uniformly convex

uniformly smooth, hyperbolic, CAT(0) spaces (but e.g. not separable,

strictly convex or uniformly Gateaux differentiable spaces).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 31: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Goal: Extract effective bounds for ∀x ∈ X ∃n ∈ INA(x , n)-theorems.

Restriction: Because of classical logic: in general A existential.

If A is existential, then general logical metatheorems (K. 2005)

guarantee the extractability of effective bounds on ‘∃’ that are

independent from parameters x from

compact metric spaces K (if separability is used) and

metrically bounded subsets of abstract spaces X that are not

assumed to be separable (provided X belongs to a sufficiently

uniformly axiomatizable class of spaces).

Examples of such spaces X : metric, normed, Hilbert, uniformly convex

uniformly smooth, hyperbolic, CAT(0) spaces (but e.g. not separable,

strictly convex or uniformly Gateaux differentiable spaces).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 32: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Goal: Extract effective bounds for ∀x ∈ X ∃n ∈ INA(x , n)-theorems.

Restriction: Because of classical logic: in general A existential.

If A is existential, then general logical metatheorems (K. 2005)

guarantee the extractability of effective bounds on ‘∃’ that are

independent from parameters x from

compact metric spaces K (if separability is used) and

metrically bounded subsets of abstract spaces X that are not

assumed to be separable (provided X belongs to a sufficiently

uniformly axiomatizable class of spaces).

Examples of such spaces X : metric, normed, Hilbert, uniformly convex

uniformly smooth, hyperbolic, CAT(0) spaces (but e.g. not separable,

strictly convex or uniformly Gateaux differentiable spaces).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 33: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Goal: Extract effective bounds for ∀x ∈ X ∃n ∈ INA(x , n)-theorems.

Restriction: Because of classical logic: in general A existential.

If A is existential, then general logical metatheorems (K. 2005)

guarantee the extractability of effective bounds on ‘∃’ that are

independent from parameters x from

compact metric spaces K (if separability is used) and

metrically bounded subsets of abstract spaces X that are not

assumed to be separable (provided X belongs to a sufficiently

uniformly axiomatizable class of spaces).

Examples of such spaces X : metric, normed, Hilbert, uniformly convex

uniformly smooth, hyperbolic, CAT(0) spaces (but e.g. not separable,

strictly convex or uniformly Gateaux differentiable spaces).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 34: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Goal: Extract effective bounds for ∀x ∈ X ∃n ∈ INA(x , n)-theorems.

Restriction: Because of classical logic: in general A existential.

If A is existential, then general logical metatheorems (K. 2005)

guarantee the extractability of effective bounds on ‘∃’ that are

independent from parameters x from

compact metric spaces K (if separability is used) and

metrically bounded subsets of abstract spaces X that are not

assumed to be separable (provided X belongs to a sufficiently

uniformly axiomatizable class of spaces).

Examples of such spaces X : metric, normed, Hilbert, uniformly convex

uniformly smooth, hyperbolic, CAT(0) spaces (but e.g. not separable,

strictly convex or uniformly Gateaux differentiable spaces).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 35: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Goal: Extract effective bounds for ∀x ∈ X ∃n ∈ INA(x , n)-theorems.

Restriction: Because of classical logic: in general A existential.

If A is existential, then general logical metatheorems (K. 2005)

guarantee the extractability of effective bounds on ‘∃’ that are

independent from parameters x from

compact metric spaces K (if separability is used) and

metrically bounded subsets of abstract spaces X that are not

assumed to be separable (provided X belongs to a sufficiently

uniformly axiomatizable class of spaces).

Examples of such spaces X : metric, normed, Hilbert, uniformly convex

uniformly smooth, hyperbolic, CAT(0) spaces (but e.g. not separable,

strictly convex or uniformly Gateaux differentiable spaces).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 36: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical interludium

In a very crude and simplistic way we will refer to the following

philosophical foundations of mathematics:

Platonism (in Mathematics e.g. Cantor, Godel as metaphysical and

epistemological realism) and

Intuitionism (Brouwer, Heyting etc. as metaphysical and - hence -

epistemological idealism); also Semi-Intuitionism → Predicative

Foundation etc.

Often a third approach to the foundations of mathematics

Formalism (Hilbert)

is discussed as yet another option.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 37: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical interludium

In a very crude and simplistic way we will refer to the following

philosophical foundations of mathematics:

Platonism (in Mathematics e.g. Cantor, Godel as metaphysical and

epistemological realism) and

Intuitionism (Brouwer, Heyting etc. as metaphysical and - hence -

epistemological idealism); also Semi-Intuitionism → Predicative

Foundation etc.

Often a third approach to the foundations of mathematics

Formalism (Hilbert)

is discussed as yet another option.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 38: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical interludium

In a very crude and simplistic way we will refer to the following

philosophical foundations of mathematics:

Platonism (in Mathematics e.g. Cantor, Godel as metaphysical and

epistemological realism) and

Intuitionism (Brouwer, Heyting etc. as metaphysical and - hence -

epistemological idealism); also Semi-Intuitionism → Predicative

Foundation etc.

Often a third approach to the foundations of mathematics

Formalism (Hilbert)

is discussed as yet another option.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 39: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Brouwer’s intuitionism

Mental constructions ‘by abandoning Kant’s a-priority of space but

adhering more resolutely to the a-priority of time’ (Brouwer 1912).

‘Intuituitionistic mathematics is an esentially language-less mental

structure which comes into being by the self-unfolding of the two-ity

as the Primordial Intuition’ (Brouwer 1947)

Onotological solipsism: ‘the only thing that is real to me is my own

self at this moment, surrounded by a wealth of images in which the

self believes and which make the self live. ... A second reality,

independent of my self and corresponding to these images, is out of

the question.’ (Brouwer 1898).

Logic is secondary to mathematics.

Law-of-excluded middle on infinite domains in general meaningless

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 40: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Brouwer’s intuitionism

Mental constructions ‘by abandoning Kant’s a-priority of space but

adhering more resolutely to the a-priority of time’ (Brouwer 1912).

‘Intuituitionistic mathematics is an esentially language-less mental

structure which comes into being by the self-unfolding of the two-ity

as the Primordial Intuition’ (Brouwer 1947)

Onotological solipsism: ‘the only thing that is real to me is my own

self at this moment, surrounded by a wealth of images in which the

self believes and which make the self live. ... A second reality,

independent of my self and corresponding to these images, is out of

the question.’ (Brouwer 1898).

Logic is secondary to mathematics.

Law-of-excluded middle on infinite domains in general meaningless

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 41: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Brouwer’s intuitionism

Mental constructions ‘by abandoning Kant’s a-priority of space but

adhering more resolutely to the a-priority of time’ (Brouwer 1912).

‘Intuituitionistic mathematics is an esentially language-less mental

structure which comes into being by the self-unfolding of the two-ity

as the Primordial Intuition’ (Brouwer 1947)

Onotological solipsism: ‘the only thing that is real to me is my own

self at this moment, surrounded by a wealth of images in which the

self believes and which make the self live. ... A second reality,

independent of my self and corresponding to these images, is out of

the question.’ (Brouwer 1898).

Logic is secondary to mathematics.

Law-of-excluded middle on infinite domains in general meaningless

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 42: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Brouwer’s intuitionism

Mental constructions ‘by abandoning Kant’s a-priority of space but

adhering more resolutely to the a-priority of time’ (Brouwer 1912).

‘Intuituitionistic mathematics is an esentially language-less mental

structure which comes into being by the self-unfolding of the two-ity

as the Primordial Intuition’ (Brouwer 1947)

Onotological solipsism: ‘the only thing that is real to me is my own

self at this moment, surrounded by a wealth of images in which the

self believes and which make the self live. ... A second reality,

independent of my self and corresponding to these images, is out of

the question.’ (Brouwer 1898).

Logic is secondary to mathematics.

Law-of-excluded middle on infinite domains in general meaningless

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 43: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 44: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Interludium continued

Both platonism and intuitionism have a metaphysical and a

formalistic reading.

Formalism is a way of viewing the ideal elements (Hilbert) of a

metaphysical reading of platonism/intuitionism as mere regulative

ideas (Kant) that are useful in proving facts about real statements

(Hilbert) of mathematics rather than as real objects themselves.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 45: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Interludium continued

Both platonism and intuitionism have a metaphysical and a

formalistic reading.

Formalism is a way of viewing the ideal elements (Hilbert) of a

metaphysical reading of platonism/intuitionism as mere regulative

ideas (Kant) that are useful in proving facts about real statements

(Hilbert) of mathematics rather than as real objects themselves.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 46: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Interludium completed

The metaphysical readings of these philosophies have had important

impact on modern mathematics and computer science:

Platonism → (naive) set theory as a universal ontology of

mathematics.

Intuitionism → Mathematics as mental constructions →(constructive) mathematics as a high level programming language:

‘Proof as Programs’ (Curry-Howard Correspondence),

Computational Mathematics.

We will discuss

Mathematical uses of a formalistic reading of

platonism/intuitionism.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 47: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Interludium completed

The metaphysical readings of these philosophies have had important

impact on modern mathematics and computer science:

Platonism → (naive) set theory as a universal ontology of

mathematics.

Intuitionism → Mathematics as mental constructions →(constructive) mathematics as a high level programming language:

‘Proof as Programs’ (Curry-Howard Correspondence),

Computational Mathematics.

We will discuss

Mathematical uses of a formalistic reading of

platonism/intuitionism.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 48: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Interludium completed

The metaphysical readings of these philosophies have had important

impact on modern mathematics and computer science:

Platonism → (naive) set theory as a universal ontology of

mathematics.

Intuitionism → Mathematics as mental constructions →(constructive) mathematics as a high level programming language:

‘Proof as Programs’ (Curry-Howard Correspondence),

Computational Mathematics.

We will discuss

Mathematical uses of a formalistic reading of

platonism/intuitionism.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 49: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Platonism Intuitionism

Ontology Naive set theory Intuitionistic universe(Semantics, Universe of all sets of mental constructions

Models)

Formalism Elimination of ‘ideal’ Elimination of(Syntax, elements in proofs choice sequences inProofs) ‘real’ statements arithmetical statements

⇓ ⇓

Finitism

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 50: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

‘Proof Mining’: Applied Foundations

The approach proceeds via a tranlation of a given proof into a

new proof of a new result based on intuitionistic logic while still

using ideal elements.

A kind of ‘finitistic’ analysis (relative to the ideal elements) of

the latter by exhbiting explicit constructions hidden in the use of

quantifiers.

The finitistic use of the ‘ideal elements’ makes it possible to replace

them by finitary versions (without the proof noticing the

difference!).

This in the end gives some form of finitistic realization of

∀∃-theorems poven together with an elementary proofs.

For semi-intuitionistic proofs the restriction to ∀∃-theorem can be

overcome: arbitary logical complexity allowed!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 51: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

‘Proof Mining’: Applied Foundations

The approach proceeds via a tranlation of a given proof into a

new proof of a new result based on intuitionistic logic while still

using ideal elements.

A kind of ‘finitistic’ analysis (relative to the ideal elements) of

the latter by exhbiting explicit constructions hidden in the use of

quantifiers.

The finitistic use of the ‘ideal elements’ makes it possible to replace

them by finitary versions (without the proof noticing the

difference!).

This in the end gives some form of finitistic realization of

∀∃-theorems poven together with an elementary proofs.

For semi-intuitionistic proofs the restriction to ∀∃-theorem can be

overcome: arbitary logical complexity allowed!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 52: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

‘Proof Mining’: Applied Foundations

The approach proceeds via a tranlation of a given proof into a

new proof of a new result based on intuitionistic logic while still

using ideal elements.

A kind of ‘finitistic’ analysis (relative to the ideal elements) of

the latter by exhbiting explicit constructions hidden in the use of

quantifiers.

The finitistic use of the ‘ideal elements’ makes it possible to replace

them by finitary versions (without the proof noticing the

difference!).

This in the end gives some form of finitistic realization of

∀∃-theorems poven together with an elementary proofs.

For semi-intuitionistic proofs the restriction to ∀∃-theorem can be

overcome: arbitary logical complexity allowed!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 53: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

‘Proof Mining’: Applied Foundations

The approach proceeds via a tranlation of a given proof into a

new proof of a new result based on intuitionistic logic while still

using ideal elements.

A kind of ‘finitistic’ analysis (relative to the ideal elements) of

the latter by exhbiting explicit constructions hidden in the use of

quantifiers.

The finitistic use of the ‘ideal elements’ makes it possible to replace

them by finitary versions (without the proof noticing the

difference!).

This in the end gives some form of finitistic realization of

∀∃-theorems poven together with an elementary proofs.

For semi-intuitionistic proofs the restriction to ∀∃-theorem can be

overcome: arbitary logical complexity allowed!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 54: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

‘Proof Mining’: Applied Foundations

The approach proceeds via a tranlation of a given proof into a

new proof of a new result based on intuitionistic logic while still

using ideal elements.

A kind of ‘finitistic’ analysis (relative to the ideal elements) of

the latter by exhbiting explicit constructions hidden in the use of

quantifiers.

The finitistic use of the ‘ideal elements’ makes it possible to replace

them by finitary versions (without the proof noticing the

difference!).

This in the end gives some form of finitistic realization of

∀∃-theorems poven together with an elementary proofs.

For semi-intuitionistic proofs the restriction to ∀∃-theorem can be

overcome: arbitary logical complexity allowed!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 55: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

The running theme: convergence statements in analysis

Let (xn) be a Cauchy sequence in a metric space (X , ρ), i.e.

∀k ∈ IN ∃n ∈ IN∀i, j ≥ n (ρ(xi, xj) ≤ 2−k) ∈ ∀∃∀

is noneffectively equivalent to

∀k ∈ IN g ∈ ININ∃n ∈ IN∀i, j ∈ [n; n + g(n)] (ρ(xi, xj) < 2−k) ∈ ∀∃

Herbrand normal form or metastability (Tao).

A bound Φ(k, g) on ‘∃n’ in the latter formula is a rate of metastability

(introduced by Kreisel in 1951 as no-counterexample interpretation).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 56: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

The running theme: convergence statements in analysis

Let (xn) be a Cauchy sequence in a metric space (X , ρ), i.e.

∀k ∈ IN ∃n ∈ IN∀i, j ≥ n (ρ(xi, xj) ≤ 2−k) ∈ ∀∃∀

is noneffectively equivalent to

∀k ∈ IN g ∈ ININ∃n ∈ IN∀i, j ∈ [n; n + g(n)] (ρ(xi, xj) < 2−k) ∈ ∀∃

Herbrand normal form or metastability (Tao).

A bound Φ(k, g) on ‘∃n’ in the latter formula is a rate of metastability

(introduced by Kreisel in 1951 as no-counterexample interpretation).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 57: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

The running theme: convergence statements in analysis

Let (xn) be a Cauchy sequence in a metric space (X , ρ), i.e.

∀k ∈ IN ∃n ∈ IN∀i, j ≥ n (ρ(xi, xj) ≤ 2−k) ∈ ∀∃∀

is noneffectively equivalent to

∀k ∈ IN g ∈ ININ∃n ∈ IN∀i, j ∈ [n; n + g(n)] (ρ(xi, xj) < 2−k) ∈ ∀∃

Herbrand normal form or metastability (Tao).

A bound Φ(k, g) on ‘∃n’ in the latter formula is a rate of metastability

(introduced by Kreisel in 1951 as no-counterexample interpretation).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 58: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

The running theme: convergence statements in analysis

Let (xn) be a Cauchy sequence in a metric space (X , ρ), i.e.

∀k ∈ IN ∃n ∈ IN∀i, j ≥ n (ρ(xi, xj) ≤ 2−k) ∈ ∀∃∀

is noneffectively equivalent to

∀k ∈ IN g ∈ ININ∃n ∈ IN∀i, j ∈ [n; n + g(n)] (ρ(xi, xj) < 2−k) ∈ ∀∃

Herbrand normal form or metastability (Tao).

A bound Φ(k , g) on ‘∃n’ in the latter formula is a rate of metastability

(introduced by Kreisel in 1951 as no-counterexample interpretation).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 59: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Effective full rates of convergence?

Usually possible for asymptotic regularity results

ρ(xn, f(xn))→ 0,

even when (xn) may not converge to a fixed point of f .

Possible for (xn) if sequence converges to unique fixed

point/solution. Extraction of modulus of uniqueness

Φ : IR∗+ → IR∗

+

∀ε > 0∀x, y ∈ X(ρ(x, f(x)), ρ(y, f(y)) < Φ(ε)→ ρ(x, y) < ε

)gives rate of convergence (or – in the noncompact case – existence

at all)! Numerous applications in analysis!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 60: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Effective full rates of convergence?

Usually possible for asymptotic regularity results

ρ(xn, f(xn))→ 0,

even when (xn) may not converge to a fixed point of f .

Possible for (xn) if sequence converges to unique fixed

point/solution.

Extraction of modulus of uniqueness

Φ : IR∗+ → IR∗

+

∀ε > 0∀x, y ∈ X(ρ(x, f(x)), ρ(y, f(y)) < Φ(ε)→ ρ(x, y) < ε

)gives rate of convergence (or – in the noncompact case – existence

at all)! Numerous applications in analysis!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 61: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Effective full rates of convergence?

Usually possible for asymptotic regularity results

ρ(xn, f(xn))→ 0,

even when (xn) may not converge to a fixed point of f .

Possible for (xn) if sequence converges to unique fixed

point/solution. Extraction of modulus of uniqueness

Φ : IR∗+ → IR∗

+

∀ε > 0 ∀x, y ∈ X(ρ(x, f(x)), ρ(y, f(y)) < Φ(ε)→ ρ(x, y) < ε

)gives rate of convergence (or – in the noncompact case – existence

at all)! Numerous applications in analysis!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 62: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rates of AsymptoticRegularity

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 63: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Asymptotic regularity of pseudocontractions

Let X be a Banach space, C ⊂ X a bounded convex subset and

f : C → C a (Lipschitzian) pseudocontraction (F.E. Browder), i.e.

∀u, v ∈ C∀λ > 1((λ− 1)‖u− v‖ ≤ ‖(λI− f)(u)− (λI− f)(v)‖

).

This generalizes the class of nonexpansive mappings.

A := I− f is accretive (and −A dissipative) which in Hilbert space is

equivalent to being monotone

∀u, v ∈ C(〈Au− Av, u− v〉 ≥ 0

).

In 1974 Bruck considered the following iteration schema

xn + 1 := (1− λn)xn + λnf(xn)− λnθn(xn − x1),

for suitable (λn), (θn) in (0, 1] and showed asymptotic regurality and

strong convergence (towards a fixed point) results in Hilbert space.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 64: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Asymptotic regularity of pseudocontractions

Let X be a Banach space, C ⊂ X a bounded convex subset and

f : C → C a (Lipschitzian) pseudocontraction (F.E. Browder), i.e.

∀u, v ∈ C∀λ > 1((λ− 1)‖u− v‖ ≤ ‖(λI− f)(u)− (λI− f)(v)‖

).

This generalizes the class of nonexpansive mappings.

A := I− f is accretive (and −A dissipative) which in Hilbert space is

equivalent to being monotone

∀u, v ∈ C(〈Au− Av, u− v〉 ≥ 0

).

In 1974 Bruck considered the following iteration schema

xn + 1 := (1− λn)xn + λnf(xn)− λnθn(xn − x1),

for suitable (λn), (θn) in (0, 1] and showed asymptotic regurality and

strong convergence (towards a fixed point) results in Hilbert space.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 65: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Asymptotic regularity of pseudocontractions

Let X be a Banach space, C ⊂ X a bounded convex subset and

f : C → C a (Lipschitzian) pseudocontraction (F.E. Browder), i.e.

∀u, v ∈ C∀λ > 1((λ− 1)‖u− v‖ ≤ ‖(λI− f)(u)− (λI− f)(v)‖

).

This generalizes the class of nonexpansive mappings.

A := I− f is accretive (and −A dissipative) which in Hilbert space is

equivalent to being monotone

∀u, v ∈ C(〈Au− Av, u− v〉 ≥ 0

).

In 1974 Bruck considered the following iteration schema

xn + 1 := (1− λn)xn + λnf(xn)− λnθn(xn − x1),

for suitable (λn), (θn) in (0, 1] and showed asymptotic regurality and

strong convergence (towards a fixed point) results in Hilbert space.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 66: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Asymptotic regularity of pseudocontractions

Let X be a Banach space, C ⊂ X a bounded convex subset and

f : C → C a (Lipschitzian) pseudocontraction (F.E. Browder), i.e.

∀u, v ∈ C∀λ > 1((λ− 1)‖u− v‖ ≤ ‖(λI− f)(u)− (λI− f)(v)‖

).

This generalizes the class of nonexpansive mappings.

A := I− f is accretive (and −A dissipative) which in Hilbert space is

equivalent to being monotone

∀u, v ∈ C(〈Au− Av, u− v〉 ≥ 0

).

In 1974 Bruck considered the following iteration schema

xn + 1 := (1− λn)xn + λnf(xn)− λnθn(xn − x1),

for suitable (λn), (θn) in (0, 1] and showed asymptotic regurality and

strong convergence (towards a fixed point) results in Hilbert space.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 67: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Asymptotic regularity of pseudocontractions

Let X be a Banach space, C ⊂ X a bounded convex subset and

f : C → C a (Lipschitzian) pseudocontraction (F.E. Browder), i.e.

∀u, v ∈ C∀λ > 1((λ− 1)‖u− v‖ ≤ ‖(λI− f)(u)− (λI− f)(v)‖

).

This generalizes the class of nonexpansive mappings.

A := I− f is accretive (and −A dissipative) which in Hilbert space is

equivalent to being monotone

∀u, v ∈ C(〈Au− Av, u− v〉 ≥ 0

).

In 1974 Bruck considered the following iteration schema

xn + 1 := (1− λn)xn + λnf(xn)− λnθn(xn − x1),

for suitable (λn), (θn) in (0, 1] and showed asymptotic regurality and

strong convergence (towards a fixed point) results in Hilbert space.Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 68: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Asymptotic regularity for Lipschitzian pseudocontractions

in arbitrary Banach spaces

Theorem (Chidume,Zegeye 2004): limn→∞

‖xn − f(xn)‖ = 0, where

(i) lim θn = 0, (ii)∞∑

n=1

λnθn =∞, (iii) lim λn

θn= 0,

(iv) limθn−1θn−1

λnθn= 0, (v) λn(1 + θn) ≤ 1.

Let M ≥ diam(C ) and (λn), (θn) ⊂ (0, 1] with rates of conv./div.

Ri : (0,∞)→ N1 ∀ε > 0∀n ≥ R1 (ε) (θn ≤ ε),

2 ∀x ∈ (0,∞)

(R2(x)∑n=1

λnθn ≥ x

),

3 ∀ε > 0∀n ≥ R3 (ε) (λn ≤ θnε),

4 ∀ε > 0∀n ≥ R4(ε)

( ∣∣∣ θn−1θn

−1∣∣∣

λnθn≤ ε

).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 69: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Asymptotic regularity for Lipschitzian pseudocontractions

in arbitrary Banach spaces

Theorem (Chidume,Zegeye 2004): limn→∞

‖xn − f(xn)‖ = 0, where

(i) lim θn = 0, (ii)∞∑

n=1

λnθn =∞, (iii) lim λn

θn= 0,

(iv) limθn−1θn−1

λnθn= 0, (v) λn(1 + θn) ≤ 1.

Let M ≥ diam(C ) and (λn), (θn) ⊂ (0, 1] with rates of conv./div.

Ri : (0,∞)→ N1 ∀ε > 0∀n ≥ R1 (ε) (θn ≤ ε),

2 ∀x ∈ (0,∞)

(R2(x)∑n=1

λnθn ≥ x

),

3 ∀ε > 0∀n ≥ R3 (ε) (λn ≤ θnε),

4 ∀ε > 0∀n ≥ R4(ε)

( ∣∣∣ θn−1θn

−1∣∣∣

λnθn≤ ε

).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 70: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rate of convergence extracted from Chidume/Zegeye (2004):

Theorem (D. Kornlein/K. Nonlinear Analysis 2011)

∀ε > 0∀n ≥ Ψ (M, L,R1,R2,R3,R4, ε) (‖xn − fxn‖ < ε)

where

Ψ (M, L,R1,R2,R3,R4, ε) = max{

N2 (C) + 1,R1

2M

)+ 1

}and

N1 (ε) := max

{R3

4M2 (2 + L)

),R4

(√ε

M2+ 1− 1

)},

N2 (x) := R2

(x

2

)+ 1,

C :=8 (1 + L)2 M2

ε2+ 2

(N1

(ε2

8 (1 + L)2

)− 1

).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 71: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rate of convergence extracted from Chidume/Zegeye (2004):

Theorem (D. Kornlein/K. Nonlinear Analysis 2011)

∀ε > 0∀n ≥ Ψ (M, L,R1,R2,R3,R4, ε) (‖xn − fxn‖ < ε)

where

Ψ (M, L,R1,R2,R3,R4, ε) = max{

N2 (C) + 1,R1

2M

)+ 1

}and

N1 (ε) := max

{R3

4M2 (2 + L)

),R4

(√ε

M2+ 1− 1

)},

N2 (x) := R2

(x

2

)+ 1,

C :=8 (1 + L)2 M2

ε2+ 2

(N1

(ε2

8 (1 + L)2

)− 1

).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 72: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rate of convergence extracted from Chidume/Zegeye (2004):

Theorem (D. Kornlein/K. Nonlinear Analysis 2011)

∀ε > 0∀n ≥ Ψ (M, L,R1,R2,R3,R4, ε) (‖xn − fxn‖ < ε)

where

Ψ (M, L,R1,R2,R3,R4, ε) = max{

N2 (C) + 1,R1

2M

)+ 1

}and

N1 (ε) := max

{R3

4M2 (2 + L)

),R4

(√ε

M2+ 1− 1

)},

N2 (x) := R2

(x

2

)+ 1,

C :=8 (1 + L)2 M2

ε2+ 2

(N1

(ε2

8 (1 + L)2

)− 1

).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 73: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rates of Full Convergencein Case of Uniqueness

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 74: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Example 1: Kirk’s theorem for asymptotic contractions

Definition (Kirk JMAA03)

(X , d) metric space. f : X → X is an asymptotic contraction with

moduli Φ,Φn : [0,∞)→ [0,∞) if Φ,Φn are continuous, Φ(s) < s for all

s > 0 and

∀n ∈ IN∀x, y ∈ X(d(fn(x), fn(y)) ≤ Φn(d(x, y)),

and Φn → Φ uniformly on the range of d .

Theorem (Kirk JMAA03)

(X , d) complete metric space, f : X → X continuous asymptotic

contraction with some orbit bounded. Then f has a unique fixed point

p ∈ X and (f n(x0)) converges to p for each x0 ∈ X .

(Proof uses ultrapower structures and hence the axiom of choice!)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 75: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Example 1: Kirk’s theorem for asymptotic contractions

Definition (Kirk JMAA03)

(X , d) metric space. f : X → X is an asymptotic contraction with

moduli Φ,Φn : [0,∞)→ [0,∞) if Φ,Φn are continuous, Φ(s) < s for all

s > 0 and

∀n ∈ IN∀x, y ∈ X(d(fn(x), fn(y)) ≤ Φn(d(x, y)),

and Φn → Φ uniformly on the range of d .

Theorem (Kirk JMAA03)

(X , d) complete metric space, f : X → X continuous asymptotic

contraction with some orbit bounded. Then f has a unique fixed point

p ∈ X and (f n(x0)) converges to p for each x0 ∈ X .

(Proof uses ultrapower structures and hence the axiom of choice!)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 76: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Example 1: Kirk’s theorem for asymptotic contractions

Definition (Kirk JMAA03)

(X , d) metric space. f : X → X is an asymptotic contraction with

moduli Φ,Φn : [0,∞)→ [0,∞) if Φ,Φn are continuous, Φ(s) < s for all

s > 0 and

∀n ∈ IN∀x, y ∈ X(d(fn(x), fn(y)) ≤ Φn(d(x, y)),

and Φn → Φ uniformly on the range of d .

Theorem (Kirk JMAA03)

(X , d) complete metric space, f : X → X continuous asymptotic

contraction with some orbit bounded. Then f has a unique fixed point

p ∈ X and (f n(x0)) converges to p for each x0 ∈ X .

(Proof uses ultrapower structures and hence the axiom of choice!)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 77: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

By proof mining P. Gerhardy (JMAA 2006, communicated by Kirk)

obtained a fully elementary proof of Kirk’s theorem with some

quantitative information.

Using Gerhardy’s result, E.M.Briseid (JMAA 2007) constructed an

effective full rate of convergence.

As a consequence of his analysis E.M.Briseid showed that the

(f n(x0)) is redundant to assume: rate of convergence using only

b ≥ d(x , f (x)) (Fixed Point Theory 2007, Int. J. Math. Stat. 2010).

E.M.Briseid showed that for bounded metric spaces the existence of

a x0-uniform rate of convergence implies that f is asymptotically

contractive (JMAA 2007). Also: new uniformity results generalizing

Reich et al (2007).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 78: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

By proof mining P. Gerhardy (JMAA 2006, communicated by Kirk)

obtained a fully elementary proof of Kirk’s theorem with some

quantitative information.

Using Gerhardy’s result, E.M.Briseid (JMAA 2007) constructed an

effective full rate of convergence.

As a consequence of his analysis E.M.Briseid showed that the

(f n(x0)) is redundant to assume: rate of convergence using only

b ≥ d(x , f (x)) (Fixed Point Theory 2007, Int. J. Math. Stat. 2010).

E.M.Briseid showed that for bounded metric spaces the existence of

a x0-uniform rate of convergence implies that f is asymptotically

contractive (JMAA 2007). Also: new uniformity results generalizing

Reich et al (2007).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 79: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

By proof mining P. Gerhardy (JMAA 2006, communicated by Kirk)

obtained a fully elementary proof of Kirk’s theorem with some

quantitative information.

Using Gerhardy’s result, E.M.Briseid (JMAA 2007) constructed an

effective full rate of convergence.

As a consequence of his analysis E.M.Briseid showed that the

(f n(x0)) is redundant to assume: rate of convergence using only

b ≥ d(x , f (x)) (Fixed Point Theory 2007, Int. J. Math. Stat. 2010).

E.M.Briseid showed that for bounded metric spaces the existence of

a x0-uniform rate of convergence implies that f is asymptotically

contractive (JMAA 2007). Also: new uniformity results generalizing

Reich et al (2007).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 80: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

By proof mining P. Gerhardy (JMAA 2006, communicated by Kirk)

obtained a fully elementary proof of Kirk’s theorem with some

quantitative information.

Using Gerhardy’s result, E.M.Briseid (JMAA 2007) constructed an

effective full rate of convergence.

As a consequence of his analysis E.M.Briseid showed that the

(f n(x0)) is redundant to assume: rate of convergence using only

b ≥ d(x , f (x)) (Fixed Point Theory 2007, Int. J. Math. Stat. 2010).

E.M.Briseid showed that for bounded metric spaces the existence of

a x0-uniform rate of convergence implies that f is asymptotically

contractive (JMAA 2007). Also: new uniformity results generalizing

Reich et al (2007).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 81: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Example 2: Generalized p-contractions

Definition: [Rhoades 1977] (X , d) metric space and p ∈ IN.

f : X → X is called generalized p-contractive if

∀x, y ∈ X(x 6= y→ d(fp(x), fp(y)) < diam {x, y, fp(x), fp(y)}

).

Theorem: [Kincses/Totik 1990]

(K , d) compact metric space and f : K → K continuous and generalized

p-contractive for some p ∈ IN. Then f has a unique fixed point ξ and for

every x ∈ K limn→∞

fn(x) = ξ.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 82: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Example 2: Generalized p-contractions

Definition: [Rhoades 1977] (X , d) metric space and p ∈ IN.

f : X → X is called generalized p-contractive if

∀x, y ∈ X(x 6= y→ d(fp(x), fp(y)) < diam {x, y, fp(x), fp(y)}

).

Theorem: [Kincses/Totik 1990]

(K , d) compact metric space and f : K → K continuous and generalized

p-contractive for some p ∈ IN. Then f has a unique fixed point ξ and for

every x ∈ K limn→∞

fn(x) = ξ.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 83: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Definition: [Briseid, J. Nonlinear Convex Anal. 2008]

(X , d) metric space, p ∈ IN. f : X → X is called uniformly generalized

p-contractive with modulus η : Q∗+ → Q∗

+ if for all x , y ∈, ε ∈ Q∗+

d(x, y) > ε→ d(fp(x), fp(y)) + η(ε) < diam {x, y, fp(x), fp(y)}.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 84: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

New existence without compactness

Theorem (Briseid, J. Nonlinear Convex Anal. 2008)

(X , d) complete metric space and p ∈ IN. f : X → X be a uniformly

continuous and uniformly generalized p-contractive with moduli ω, η. Let

(f n(x0)) be bounded by b ∈ Q∗+. Then f has a unique fixed point ξ and

(f n(x0)) converges to ξ with rate of convergence Φ : Q∗+ → IN,

Φ(ε) :=

{pd(b− ε)/ρ(ε)e if b > ε,

0, otherwise

with

ρ(ε) := min

{η(ε),

ε

2, η(

1

2ωp(

ε

2))

}.

Existence of fixed point by uniform uniqueness via uniform continuity

and uniform generalized p-contractivity!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 85: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

New existence without compactness

Theorem (Briseid, J. Nonlinear Convex Anal. 2008)

(X , d) complete metric space and p ∈ IN. f : X → X be a uniformly

continuous and uniformly generalized p-contractive with moduli ω, η. Let

(f n(x0)) be bounded by b ∈ Q∗+. Then f has a unique fixed point ξ and

(f n(x0)) converges to ξ with rate of convergence Φ : Q∗+ → IN,

Φ(ε) :=

{pd(b− ε)/ρ(ε)e if b > ε,

0, otherwise

with

ρ(ε) := min

{η(ε),

ε

2, η(

1

2ωp(

ε

2))

}.

Existence of fixed point by uniform uniqueness via uniform continuity

and uniform generalized p-contractivity!Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 86: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Fluctuation Bounds

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 87: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

An Example from Ergodic Theory

X Hilbert space, f : X → X linear and ‖f(x)‖ ≤ ‖x‖ for all x ∈ X .

An(x) :=1

n + 1Sn(x), where Sn(x) :=

n∑i=0

f(i)(x) (n ≥ 0)

Theorem (von Neumann Mean Ergodic Theorem)

For every x ∈ X , the sequence (An(x))n converges.

Avigad/Gerhardy/Towsner (TAMS 2010):

in general no computable rate of convergence.

But: Prim. rec. bound on metastable version!

Theorem (Garrett Birkhoff 1939)

Mean Ergodic Theorem holds for uniformly convex Banach spaces.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 88: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

An Example from Ergodic Theory

X Hilbert space, f : X → X linear and ‖f(x)‖ ≤ ‖x‖ for all x ∈ X .

An(x) :=1

n + 1Sn(x), where Sn(x) :=

n∑i=0

f(i)(x) (n ≥ 0)

Theorem (von Neumann Mean Ergodic Theorem)

For every x ∈ X , the sequence (An(x))n converges.

Avigad/Gerhardy/Towsner (TAMS 2010):

in general no computable rate of convergence.

But: Prim. rec. bound on metastable version!

Theorem (Garrett Birkhoff 1939)

Mean Ergodic Theorem holds for uniformly convex Banach spaces.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 89: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

An Example from Ergodic Theory

X Hilbert space, f : X → X linear and ‖f(x)‖ ≤ ‖x‖ for all x ∈ X .

An(x) :=1

n + 1Sn(x), where Sn(x) :=

n∑i=0

f(i)(x) (n ≥ 0)

Theorem (von Neumann Mean Ergodic Theorem)

For every x ∈ X , the sequence (An(x))n converges.

Avigad/Gerhardy/Towsner (TAMS 2010):

in general no computable rate of convergence.

But: Prim. rec. bound on metastable version!

Theorem (Garrett Birkhoff 1939)

Mean Ergodic Theorem holds for uniformly convex Banach spaces.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 90: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

An Example from Ergodic Theory

X Hilbert space, f : X → X linear and ‖f(x)‖ ≤ ‖x‖ for all x ∈ X .

An(x) :=1

n + 1Sn(x), where Sn(x) :=

n∑i=0

f(i)(x) (n ≥ 0)

Theorem (von Neumann Mean Ergodic Theorem)

For every x ∈ X , the sequence (An(x))n converges.

Avigad/Gerhardy/Towsner (TAMS 2010):

in general no computable rate of convergence.

But: Prim. rec. bound on metastable version!

Theorem (Garrett Birkhoff 1939)

Mean Ergodic Theorem holds for uniformly convex Banach spaces.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 91: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

By logical metatheorems (K. TAMS 2005, Gerhardy/K. TAMS 2008, K.

Springer Monograph 2008):

Theorem (K./Leustean, Ergodic Theor. Dynam. Syst. 2009)

X uniformly convex Banach space, η a modulus of uniform convexity and

f : X → X as above, b > 0.

Then for all x ∈ X with ‖x‖ ≤ b, all ε > 0, all g : IN→ IN :

∃n ≤ Φ(ε, g, b, η) ∀i, j ∈ [n; n + g(n)](‖Ai(x)− Aj(x)‖ < ε

),

where

Φ(ε, g, b, η) := M · h(K)(0), with

M :=⌈

16bε

⌉, γ := ε

16η(ε

8b

), K :=

⌈bγ

⌉,

h, h : IN→ IN, h(n) := 2(Mn + g(Mn)), h(n) := maxi≤n h(i).

Computable rate of convergence iff the norm of limit is computable!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 92: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

By logical metatheorems (K. TAMS 2005, Gerhardy/K. TAMS 2008, K.

Springer Monograph 2008):

Theorem (K./Leustean, Ergodic Theor. Dynam. Syst. 2009)

X uniformly convex Banach space, η a modulus of uniform convexity and

f : X → X as above, b > 0.

Then for all x ∈ X with ‖x‖ ≤ b, all ε > 0, all g : IN→ IN :

∃n ≤ Φ(ε, g, b, η) ∀i, j ∈ [n; n + g(n)](‖Ai(x)− Aj(x)‖ < ε

),

where

Φ(ε, g, b, η) := M · h(K)(0), with

M :=⌈

16bε

⌉, γ := ε

16η(ε

8b

), K :=

⌈bγ

⌉,

h, h : IN→ IN, h(n) := 2(Mn + g(Mn)), h(n) := maxi≤n h(i).

Computable rate of convergence iff the norm of limit is computable!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 93: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Bounding the number of fluctuations

We say that (xn) admits k ε-fluctuations if there are i1 ≤ j1 ≤ . . . ik ≤ jk

s.t. ‖xjn − xin‖ ≥ ε for n = 1, . . . , k .

As a corollary to our analysis of Birkhoff’s proof, Avigad and Rute showed

Theorem (Avigad, Rute (2012))

(An(x)) admits at most

2 log(M) ·b

ε+

b

γ· 2 log(2M) ·

b

ε+

b

γ

many fluctuations.

Partly possible because Birkhoff’s proof only uses boundedly many (in

the data) instances of the law-of-excluded-middle for ∃-statements!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 94: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Bounding the number of fluctuations

We say that (xn) admits k ε-fluctuations if there are i1 ≤ j1 ≤ . . . ik ≤ jk

s.t. ‖xjn − xin‖ ≥ ε for n = 1, . . . , k .

As a corollary to our analysis of Birkhoff’s proof, Avigad and Rute showed

Theorem (Avigad, Rute (2012))

(An(x)) admits at most

2 log(M) ·b

ε+

b

γ· 2 log(2M) ·

b

ε+

b

γ

many fluctuations.

Partly possible because Birkhoff’s proof only uses boundedly many (in

the data) instances of the law-of-excluded-middle for ∃-statements!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 95: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Bounding the number of fluctuations

We say that (xn) admits k ε-fluctuations if there are i1 ≤ j1 ≤ . . . ik ≤ jk

s.t. ‖xjn − xin‖ ≥ ε for n = 1, . . . , k .

As a corollary to our analysis of Birkhoff’s proof, Avigad and Rute showed

Theorem (Avigad, Rute (2012))

(An(x)) admits at most

2 log(M) ·b

ε+

b

γ· 2 log(2M) ·

b

ε+

b

γ

many fluctuations.

Partly possible because Birkhoff’s proof only uses boundedly many (in

the data) instances of the law-of-excluded-middle for ∃-statements!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 96: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Bounds on Metastability

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 97: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Strong nonlin. ergodic theorem (Wittmann)

Halpern iterations: f : C → C nonexpansive, x0 ∈ C , αn ∈ [0, 1]

xn+1 := αn+1 x0 + (1− αn+1) f(xn).

Using weak compactness, Wittmann proved in 1992:

Theorem (R. Wittmann 1992): C ⊆ X closed and convex, x0 ∈ C and

Fix(f ) 6= ∅. Under suitable conditions on (αn) (e.g. αn := 1n+1 ) (xn)

converges strongly towards the fixed point of f that is closest to x0.

Remark: Wittmann’s theorem is a nonlinear generalization of the

Mean ergodic theorem: for αn := 1/(n + 1),C := X and linear f , the

Halpern iteration coincides with the Cesaro means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 98: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Strong nonlin. ergodic theorem (Wittmann)

Halpern iterations: f : C → C nonexpansive, x0 ∈ C , αn ∈ [0, 1]

xn+1 := αn+1 x0 + (1− αn+1) f(xn).

Using weak compactness, Wittmann proved in 1992:

Theorem (R. Wittmann 1992): C ⊆ X closed and convex, x0 ∈ C and

Fix(f ) 6= ∅. Under suitable conditions on (αn) (e.g. αn := 1n+1 ) (xn)

converges strongly towards the fixed point of f that is closest to x0.

Remark: Wittmann’s theorem is a nonlinear generalization of the

Mean ergodic theorem: for αn := 1/(n + 1),C := X and linear f , the

Halpern iteration coincides with the Cesaro means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 99: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Strong nonlin. ergodic theorem (Wittmann)

Halpern iterations: f : C → C nonexpansive, x0 ∈ C , αn ∈ [0, 1]

xn+1 := αn+1 x0 + (1− αn+1) f(xn).

Using weak compactness, Wittmann proved in 1992:

Theorem (R. Wittmann 1992): C ⊆ X closed and convex, x0 ∈ C and

Fix(f ) 6= ∅. Under suitable conditions on (αn) (e.g. αn := 1n+1 ) (xn)

converges strongly towards the fixed point of f that is closest to x0.

Remark: Wittmann’s theorem is a nonlinear generalization of the

Mean ergodic theorem: for αn := 1/(n + 1),C := X and linear f , the

Halpern iteration coincides with the Cesaro means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 100: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Strong nonlin. ergodic theorem (Wittmann)

Halpern iterations: f : C → C nonexpansive, x0 ∈ C , αn ∈ [0, 1]

xn+1 := αn+1 x0 + (1− αn+1) f(xn).

Using weak compactness, Wittmann proved in 1992:

Theorem (R. Wittmann 1992): C ⊆ X closed and convex, x0 ∈ C and

Fix(f ) 6= ∅. Under suitable conditions on (αn) (e.g. αn := 1n+1 ) (xn)

converges strongly towards the fixed point of f that is closest to x0.

Remark: Wittmann’s theorem is a nonlinear generalization of the

Mean ergodic theorem: for αn := 1/(n + 1),C := X and linear f , the

Halpern iteration coincides with the Cesaro means.

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 101: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

General features of the logical analysis of the proof due

Wittmann

In Wittmann’s proof the use of weak compactness gets in the end

eliminated via a quantitative projection argument but could be fully

effectivized (K., Adv. Math. 2011)

Wittmann’s result has been generalized to uniformly smooth

Banach spaces (Shioji-Takahashi 1997) and CAT(0)-spaces

(Saejung 2010) using Banach limits (AC).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 102: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

General features of the logical analysis of the proof due

Wittmann

In Wittmann’s proof the use of weak compactness gets in the end

eliminated via a quantitative projection argument but could be fully

effectivized (K., Adv. Math. 2011)

Wittmann’s result has been generalized to uniformly smooth

Banach spaces (Shioji-Takahashi 1997) and CAT(0)-spaces

(Saejung 2010) using Banach limits (AC).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 103: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

General features of the logical analysis of the proof due

Wittmann

In Wittmann’s proof the use of weak compactness gets in the end

eliminated via a quantitative projection argument but could be fully

effectivized (K., Adv. Math. 2011)

Wittmann’s result has been generalized to uniformly smooth

Banach spaces (Shioji-Takahashi 1997) and CAT(0)-spaces

(Saejung 2010) using Banach limits (AC).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 104: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rate of Metastability in Saejung’s Theorem

Theorem (K./Leustean, Adv. Math. 2012; improved 2013)

X CAT(0), C ⊆ X convex, diam(C ) ≤ M, (xn) as above, ε ∈ (0, 1) :

∀g : ININ∃k ≤ Σ(ε, g,M) ∀i, j ∈ [k; k + g(k)](ρ(xi, xj) ≤ ε

),

Σ(ε, g,M) :=⌈

12M2χ∗L (ε2/12)ε2

⌉, with L := h∗

(dM2/ε20e)

(0) +⌈

1ε0

⌉,

χ∗k (ε) :=⌈

12M2(k+1)ε

+ 144M4(k+1)2

ε2

⌉− 1, ε0 := ε2/24(d + 1)2,

Θk(ε) :=⌈

3M2χ∗k (ε/3)ε

⌉, ∆∗k (ε, g) := ε

3gε,k(Θk(ε)−χ∗k (ε/3))

,

gε,k(n) := n + g(n + χ∗k

(ε3

)), h(k) := max

{⌈M2

∆∗k (ε2/4,g)

⌉, k}− k,

h∗(k) := h(

k +⌈

1ε0

⌉)+⌈

1ε0

⌉, h∗(k) := k + h∗(k).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 105: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rate of Metastability in Saejung’s Theorem

Theorem (K./Leustean, Adv. Math. 2012; improved 2013)

X CAT(0), C ⊆ X convex, diam(C ) ≤ M, (xn) as above, ε ∈ (0, 1) :

∀g : ININ∃k ≤ Σ(ε, g,M) ∀i, j ∈ [k; k + g(k)](ρ(xi, xj) ≤ ε

),

Σ(ε, g,M) :=⌈

12M2χ∗L (ε2/12)ε2

⌉, with L := h∗

(dM2/ε20e)

(0) +⌈

1ε0

⌉,

χ∗k (ε) :=⌈

12M2(k+1)ε

+ 144M4(k+1)2

ε2

⌉− 1, ε0 := ε2/24(d + 1)2,

Θk(ε) :=⌈

3M2χ∗k (ε/3)ε

⌉, ∆∗k (ε, g) := ε

3gε,k(Θk(ε)−χ∗k (ε/3))

,

gε,k(n) := n + g(n + χ∗k

(ε3

)), h(k) := max

{⌈M2

∆∗k (ε2/4,g)

⌉, k}− k,

h∗(k) := h(

k +⌈

1ε0

⌉)+⌈

1ε0

⌉, h∗(k) := k + h∗(k).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 106: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rate of Metastability in Saejung’s Theorem

Theorem (K./Leustean, Adv. Math. 2012; improved 2013)

X CAT(0), C ⊆ X convex, diam(C ) ≤ M, (xn) as above, ε ∈ (0, 1) :

∀g : ININ∃k ≤ Σ(ε, g,M) ∀i, j ∈ [k; k + g(k)](ρ(xi, xj) ≤ ε

),

Σ(ε, g,M) :=⌈

12M2χ∗L (ε2/12)ε2

⌉, with L := h∗

(dM2/ε20e)

(0) +⌈

1ε0

⌉,

χ∗k (ε) :=⌈

12M2(k+1)ε

+ 144M4(k+1)2

ε2

⌉− 1, ε0 := ε2/24(d + 1)2,

Θk(ε) :=⌈

3M2χ∗k (ε/3)ε

⌉, ∆∗k (ε, g) := ε

3gε,k(Θk(ε)−χ∗k (ε/3))

,

gε,k(n) := n + g(n + χ∗k

(ε3

)), h(k) := max

{⌈M2

∆∗k (ε2/4,g)

⌉, k}− k,

h∗(k) := h(

k +⌈

1ε0

⌉)+⌈

1ε0

⌉, h∗(k) := k + h∗(k).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 107: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Further consequences of the analysis

A quadratic full rate of convergence for the asymptotic regularity

ρ(xn, f(xn))→ 0:

∀ε > 0∀n ≥4M

ε+

16M2

ε2(ρ(xn, f(xn)) < ε).

Let zk be the unique fixed point of the contraction

fk(x) :=1

kx⊕ (1−

1

k)f(x).

Then the analysis yields (essentially) polynomially in a given rate α

of convergence of the resolvent (zk) a rate of convergence of (xn).

For effective X , f , x and z := lim zk :

Computable convergence for (xn) iff ‖z − x‖ is computable.

Also unbounded C and modified Halpern iterations: M ≥ 4‖p − x0‖(Schade/K., Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2012)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 108: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Further consequences of the analysis

A quadratic full rate of convergence for the asymptotic regularity

ρ(xn, f(xn))→ 0:

∀ε > 0 ∀n ≥4M

ε+

16M2

ε2(ρ(xn, f(xn)) < ε).

Let zk be the unique fixed point of the contraction

fk(x) :=1

kx⊕ (1−

1

k)f(x).

Then the analysis yields (essentially) polynomially in a given rate α

of convergence of the resolvent (zk) a rate of convergence of (xn).

For effective X , f , x and z := lim zk :

Computable convergence for (xn) iff ‖z − x‖ is computable.

Also unbounded C and modified Halpern iterations: M ≥ 4‖p − x0‖(Schade/K., Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2012)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 109: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Further consequences of the analysis

A quadratic full rate of convergence for the asymptotic regularity

ρ(xn, f(xn))→ 0:

∀ε > 0 ∀n ≥4M

ε+

16M2

ε2(ρ(xn, f(xn)) < ε).

Let zk be the unique fixed point of the contraction

fk(x) :=1

kx⊕ (1−

1

k)f(x).

Then the analysis yields (essentially) polynomially in a given rate α

of convergence of the resolvent (zk) a rate of convergence of (xn).

For effective X , f , x and z := lim zk :

Computable convergence for (xn) iff ‖z − x‖ is computable.

Also unbounded C and modified Halpern iterations: M ≥ 4‖p − x0‖(Schade/K., Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2012)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 110: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Further consequences of the analysis

A quadratic full rate of convergence for the asymptotic regularity

ρ(xn, f(xn))→ 0:

∀ε > 0 ∀n ≥4M

ε+

16M2

ε2(ρ(xn, f(xn)) < ε).

Let zk be the unique fixed point of the contraction

fk(x) :=1

kx⊕ (1−

1

k)f(x).

Then the analysis yields (essentially) polynomially in a given rate α

of convergence of the resolvent (zk) a rate of convergence of (xn).

For effective X , f , x and z := lim zk :

Computable convergence for (xn) iff ‖z − x‖ is computable.

Also unbounded C and modified Halpern iterations: M ≥ 4‖p − x0‖(Schade/K., Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2012)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 111: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Further consequences of the analysis

A quadratic full rate of convergence for the asymptotic regularity

ρ(xn, f(xn))→ 0:

∀ε > 0 ∀n ≥4M

ε+

16M2

ε2(ρ(xn, f(xn)) < ε).

Let zk be the unique fixed point of the contraction

fk(x) :=1

kx⊕ (1−

1

k)f(x).

Then the analysis yields (essentially) polynomially in a given rate α

of convergence of the resolvent (zk) a rate of convergence of (xn).

For effective X , f , x and z := lim zk :

Computable convergence for (xn) iff ‖z − x‖ is computable.

Also unbounded C and modified Halpern iterations: M ≥ 4‖p − x0‖(Schade/K., Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2012)

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 112: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Other developments

Similar results for uniformly smooth Banach spaces (then bound

depends on modulus of smoothness):

Leustean/K., Phil. Trans. Royal Soc. A, 2012.

This involves new logical metatheorem for uniformly smooth

spaces and with uniformly continuous normalized duality map.

Another strong nonlinear ergodic theorem due to Wittmann for

mappings

‖f(x) + f(y)‖ ≤ ‖x + y‖

has been analyzed by P. Safarik, J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2012.

Effective rates of metastability for iterations of odd operators in

uniformly convex Banach spaces (K., J.Math.Anal.Appl.,2011).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 113: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Other developments

Similar results for uniformly smooth Banach spaces (then bound

depends on modulus of smoothness):

Leustean/K., Phil. Trans. Royal Soc. A, 2012.

This involves new logical metatheorem for uniformly smooth

spaces and with uniformly continuous normalized duality map.

Another strong nonlinear ergodic theorem due to Wittmann for

mappings

‖f(x) + f(y)‖ ≤ ‖x + y‖

has been analyzed by P. Safarik, J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2012.

Effective rates of metastability for iterations of odd operators in

uniformly convex Banach spaces (K., J.Math.Anal.Appl.,2011).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 114: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Other developments

Similar results for uniformly smooth Banach spaces (then bound

depends on modulus of smoothness):

Leustean/K., Phil. Trans. Royal Soc. A, 2012.

This involves new logical metatheorem for uniformly smooth

spaces and with uniformly continuous normalized duality map.

Another strong nonlinear ergodic theorem due to Wittmann for

mappings

‖f(x) + f(y)‖ ≤ ‖x + y‖

has been analyzed by P. Safarik, J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2012.

Effective rates of metastability for iterations of odd operators in

uniformly convex Banach spaces (K., J.Math.Anal.Appl.,2011).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 115: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Other developments

Similar results for uniformly smooth Banach spaces (then bound

depends on modulus of smoothness):

Leustean/K., Phil. Trans. Royal Soc. A, 2012.

This involves new logical metatheorem for uniformly smooth

spaces and with uniformly continuous normalized duality map.

Another strong nonlinear ergodic theorem due to Wittmann for

mappings

‖f(x) + f(y)‖ ≤ ‖x + y‖

has been analyzed by P. Safarik, J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2012.

Effective rates of metastability for iterations of odd operators in

uniformly convex Banach spaces (K., J.Math.Anal.Appl.,2011).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 116: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Other developments

Similar results for uniformly smooth Banach spaces (then bound

depends on modulus of smoothness):

Leustean/K., Phil. Trans. Royal Soc. A, 2012.

This involves new logical metatheorem for uniformly smooth

spaces and with uniformly continuous normalized duality map.

Another strong nonlinear ergodic theorem due to Wittmann for

mappings

‖f(x) + f(y)‖ ≤ ‖x + y‖

has been analyzed by P. Safarik, J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2012.

Effective rates of metastability for iterations of odd operators in

uniformly convex Banach spaces (K., J.Math.Anal.Appl.,2011).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 117: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rates of asmyptotic regularity and metastability for

Krasnoselski-Mann iterations in normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(K., Num.Funct.Anal.Opt.2001, K., Nonlinear Anal.2005

Leustean/K., Abstr.Appl.Anal. 2003).

Approximate fixed point property in product spaces

(Leustean/K., Nonlinear Anal.2007).

Rates of asmptotic regularity for asymptotically nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(Lambov/K., Proc. FPTA 2004, Leustean/K., JEMS 2010).

Rates of asymptotic regularity for finite families of nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex W -hyperbolic spaces

(M.A.A. Khan/K., J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2013).

Rate of asymptotic regularity for Bruck’s iteration of Lipschitzian

pseudocontractions in Hilbert space (Kornlein/K., 2013

submitted).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 118: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rates of asmyptotic regularity and metastability for

Krasnoselski-Mann iterations in normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(K., Num.Funct.Anal.Opt.2001, K., Nonlinear Anal.2005

Leustean/K., Abstr.Appl.Anal. 2003).

Approximate fixed point property in product spaces

(Leustean/K., Nonlinear Anal.2007).

Rates of asmptotic regularity for asymptotically nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(Lambov/K., Proc. FPTA 2004, Leustean/K., JEMS 2010).

Rates of asymptotic regularity for finite families of nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex W -hyperbolic spaces

(M.A.A. Khan/K., J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2013).

Rate of asymptotic regularity for Bruck’s iteration of Lipschitzian

pseudocontractions in Hilbert space (Kornlein/K., 2013

submitted).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 119: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rates of asmyptotic regularity and metastability for

Krasnoselski-Mann iterations in normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(K., Num.Funct.Anal.Opt.2001, K., Nonlinear Anal.2005

Leustean/K., Abstr.Appl.Anal. 2003).

Approximate fixed point property in product spaces

(Leustean/K., Nonlinear Anal.2007).

Rates of asmptotic regularity for asymptotically nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(Lambov/K., Proc. FPTA 2004, Leustean/K., JEMS 2010).

Rates of asymptotic regularity for finite families of nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex W -hyperbolic spaces

(M.A.A. Khan/K., J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2013).

Rate of asymptotic regularity for Bruck’s iteration of Lipschitzian

pseudocontractions in Hilbert space (Kornlein/K., 2013

submitted).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 120: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rates of asmyptotic regularity and metastability for

Krasnoselski-Mann iterations in normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(K., Num.Funct.Anal.Opt.2001, K., Nonlinear Anal.2005

Leustean/K., Abstr.Appl.Anal. 2003).

Approximate fixed point property in product spaces

(Leustean/K., Nonlinear Anal.2007).

Rates of asmptotic regularity for asymptotically nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(Lambov/K., Proc. FPTA 2004, Leustean/K., JEMS 2010).

Rates of asymptotic regularity for finite families of nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex W -hyperbolic spaces

(M.A.A. Khan/K., J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2013).

Rate of asymptotic regularity for Bruck’s iteration of Lipschitzian

pseudocontractions in Hilbert space (Kornlein/K., 2013

submitted).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 121: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Rates of asmyptotic regularity and metastability for

Krasnoselski-Mann iterations in normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(K., Num.Funct.Anal.Opt.2001, K., Nonlinear Anal.2005

Leustean/K., Abstr.Appl.Anal. 2003).

Approximate fixed point property in product spaces

(Leustean/K., Nonlinear Anal.2007).

Rates of asmptotic regularity for asymptotically nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex normed and W -hyperbolic spaces

(Lambov/K., Proc. FPTA 2004, Leustean/K., JEMS 2010).

Rates of asymptotic regularity for finite families of nonexpansive

mappings in uniformly convex W -hyperbolic spaces

(M.A.A. Khan/K., J.Math.Anal.Appl. 2013).

Rate of asymptotic regularity for Bruck’s iteration of Lipschitzian

pseudocontractions in Hilbert space (Kornlein/K., 2013

submitted).

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 122: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical conclusion from ‘proof mining’ enterprise

Rather than having ‘collapsed’ (S. Kripke), Hilbert’s program (in

the broad sense) on the possibility of elimination of ideal elements

from proofs of real statements has largely been vindicated for

ordinary mathematical practice.

To a large extent this is even true for the narrow interpretation of

the program, i.e. the reduction to strict finitism: primitive recursive

arithmetic: All bounds in this talk were primitive recursive.

Striking exceptions exist (H. Friedman) but are very rare.Why?

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 123: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical conclusion from ‘proof mining’ enterprise

Rather than having ‘collapsed’ (S. Kripke), Hilbert’s program (in

the broad sense) on the possibility of elimination of ideal elements

from proofs of real statements has largely been vindicated for

ordinary mathematical practice.

To a large extent this is even true for the narrow interpretation of

the program, i.e. the reduction to strict finitism: primitive recursive

arithmetic: All bounds in this talk were primitive recursive.

Striking exceptions exist (H. Friedman) but are very rare.Why?

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 124: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical conclusion from ‘proof mining’ enterprise

Rather than having ‘collapsed’ (S. Kripke), Hilbert’s program (in

the broad sense) on the possibility of elimination of ideal elements

from proofs of real statements has largely been vindicated for

ordinary mathematical practice.

To a large extent this is even true for the narrow interpretation of

the program, i.e. the reduction to strict finitism: primitive recursive

arithmetic:

All bounds in this talk were primitive recursive.

Striking exceptions exist (H. Friedman) but are very rare.Why?

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 125: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical conclusion from ‘proof mining’ enterprise

Rather than having ‘collapsed’ (S. Kripke), Hilbert’s program (in

the broad sense) on the possibility of elimination of ideal elements

from proofs of real statements has largely been vindicated for

ordinary mathematical practice.

To a large extent this is even true for the narrow interpretation of

the program, i.e. the reduction to strict finitism: primitive recursive

arithmetic: All bounds in this talk were primitive recursive.

Striking exceptions exist (H. Friedman) but are very rare.Why?

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 126: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical conclusion from ‘proof mining’ enterprise

Rather than having ‘collapsed’ (S. Kripke), Hilbert’s program (in

the broad sense) on the possibility of elimination of ideal elements

from proofs of real statements has largely been vindicated for

ordinary mathematical practice.

To a large extent this is even true for the narrow interpretation of

the program, i.e. the reduction to strict finitism: primitive recursive

arithmetic: All bounds in this talk were primitive recursive.

Striking exceptions exist (H. Friedman) but are very rare.

Why?

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 127: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Philosophical conclusion from ‘proof mining’ enterprise

Rather than having ‘collapsed’ (S. Kripke), Hilbert’s program (in

the broad sense) on the possibility of elimination of ideal elements

from proofs of real statements has largely been vindicated for

ordinary mathematical practice.

To a large extent this is even true for the narrow interpretation of

the program, i.e. the reduction to strict finitism: primitive recursive

arithmetic: All bounds in this talk were primitive recursive.

Striking exceptions exist (H. Friedman) but are very rare.Why?

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 128: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Two advertisements

Tokyo-Darmstadt International PhD Schoolon Mathematical Fluid Dynamics.

Likely to get a 2nd 4.5 year funding period including

Proof Mining/Reverse Math. Projects.

Modulo final approval in May:

Announcement of PhD positions forproof-theorists in this project this summer!

WoLLIC 2013 in Darmstadt, August 20-23!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 129: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Two advertisements

Tokyo-Darmstadt International PhD Schoolon Mathematical Fluid Dynamics.

Likely to get a 2nd 4.5 year funding period including

Proof Mining/Reverse Math. Projects.

Modulo final approval in May:

Announcement of PhD positions forproof-theorists in this project this summer!

WoLLIC 2013 in Darmstadt, August 20-23!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 130: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

Two advertisements

Tokyo-Darmstadt International PhD Schoolon Mathematical Fluid Dynamics.

Likely to get a 2nd 4.5 year funding period including

Proof Mining/Reverse Math. Projects.

Modulo final approval in May:

Announcement of PhD positions forproof-theorists in this project this summer!

WoLLIC 2013 in Darmstadt, August 20-23!

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications

Page 131: Proof Theory: From the Foundations of Mathematics to Applications

1 23 Sprin

ger M

onog

raph

s in

Mat

hem

atic

s

SMM ulrich kohlenbach

ko

hle

nb

ac

h

u. kohlenbach

Applied Proof Theory: Proof Interpretations and their Use in Mathematics

Ulrich Kohlenbach presents an applied form of proof theory that has led in recent years to new results in number theory, approxi-mation theory, nonlinear analysis, geodesic geometry and ergodic theory (among others). This applied approach is based on logical transformations (so-called proof interpretations) and concerns the extraction of effective data (such as bounds) from prima facie ineffective proofs as well as new qualitative results such as inde-pendence of solutions from certain parameters, generalizations of proofs by elimination of premises.The book first develops the necessary logical machinery empha-sizing novel forms of Gödel‘s famous functional (‚Dialectica‘) interpretation. It then establishes general logical metatheorems that connect these techniques with concrete mathematics. Finally, two extended case studies (one in approximation theory and one in fixed point theory) show in detail how this machinery can be applied to concrete proofs in different areas of mathematics.

1

Applied Proof Theory: Proof Interpretations and their Use in M

athematics

Applied Proof Theory: Proof Interpretations and their Use in M

athematics

54205 WMX

Design G

mbH

Heidelberg – Bender 06.12.07

D

ieser pdf-file gibt nur annähernd das endgültige Druckergebnis w

ieder !

issn 1439-7382

› springer.com

ISBN 978-3-540-77532-4

Applied Proof Theory: Proof Interpretations and their Use in Mathematics

Applied Proof Theory: Proof Interpretations and their Use in Mathematics

Proof Theory: From Foundations to Applications