Problem Consciousness

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    1/279

    THE PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS:MENTAL APPEARANCE AND MENTAL REALITY

    by

    JOSH WEISBERG

    A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty inPhilosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements forthe degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City

    University of New York

    2007

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    2/279

    - ii -

    2007

    JOSH WEISBERG

    All Rights Reserved

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    3/279

    - iii -

    This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty inPhilosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor

    of Philosophy.

    _________Michael Levin____________

    ________________ ________________________________Date Chair of Examining Committee

    _______John D. Greenwood_________

    ________________ ________________________________Date Executive Officer

    ____David M. Rosenthal________________

    ____Michael Devitt_____________________

    ____Douglas Lackey___________________Supervisory Committee

    THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    4/279

    - iv -

    Abstract

    THE PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS: MENTAL APPEARANCE AND

    MENTAL REALITY

    by

    Josh Weisberg

    Adviser: Professor David M. Rosenthal

    Consciousness is widely seen as posing a special explanatory problem for

    science. The problem is rooted in the apparent gulf between consciousness as it

    appears from the first-person perspective and consciousness as it is

    characterized in scientific theory. From the first-person perspective it seems that

    we directly access intrinsic qualities of conscious experience, qualities

    immediately known, but isolated and indescribable. But scientific theory seems

    ill-equipped to explain such qualities.

    That is how things appear from the first-person perspective. However, in

    this dissertation I argue that we have no reason to accept that these

    appearances reflect the underlying nature of the conscious mind. I begin by

    examining attempts by David Chalmers, Joseph Levine, and Ned Block to

    characterize the problem of consciousness. I argue that all three fail to establish

    anything more than the claim that consciousness appears to have intrinsic

    qualities. If we can explain these appearances without endorsing the reality of

    intrinsic qualities, the way is open to a satisfying materialist theory of

    consciousness.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    5/279

    - v -

    The key, I argue, is to provide a feasible model of first-person access. I

    consider a popular model of first-person access, the "phenomenal concepts"

    approach, but I argue that this model either fails to explain the appearances or it

    posits an undischarged mysterious element, undermining the proposed

    explanation. I then defend a model of first-person access that avoids these

    pitfalls. I propose that we access our conscious states by way of an

    automatically applied nonconscious theory. We are unaware of the theory's

    application, so the access seems direct. Further, we are unaware of the rich

    relational descriptions the theory employs. It therefore seems to us that we are

    accessing intrinsic, indescribable qualities. I then present empirical evidence for

    my model, including the phenomenon of "expert perception" in chess, music,

    wine tasting, and the appreciation of beauty; and a range of data suggesting that

    introspection is not a reliable guide to the underlying nature of the conscious

    mind. I conclude by countering the knowledge argument with a version of the

    "ability hypothesis," in order to close off any lingering philosophical worries

    concerning the problem of consciousness.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    6/279

    - vi -

    Acknowledgments:

    Portions of this dissertation were presented at the Association for the Scientific

    Study of Consciousness, Towards a Science of Consciousness, The Society for

    Philosophy and Psychology, The New Jersey Regional Philosophy Association,

    and the CUNY Graduate Center Cognitive Science Symposium and Discussion

    Group. My sincere thanks to audiences at those venues for helpful feedback and

    comments.

    This work has benefited from the help and support of a number of people.

    First, my fellow students and colleagues who offered helpful and constructive

    criticism throughout: Jared Blank, Gregg Caruso, Jim Hitt, Uriah Kriegel, Pete

    Mandik, Roblin Meeks, Doug Meehan, Bill Seeley, and Liz Vlahos. Thanks also

    to a number of professors who gave time and effort in support of this project:

    Martin Davies, Michael Devitt, John Greenwood, Doug Lackey, Michael Levin,

    and Barbara Montero. Special thanks to my thesis adviser, David Rosenthal.

    Without his help and effort throughout my time in graduate school, I would not be

    the philosopher I am today. Finally, thanks and love to my friends and family

    who stuck with me through the long years, especially my wife Ashley Hope.

    Without her wise counsel and timely motivation this project would never have

    seen completion.

    This dissertation is dedicated to my loving parents, Bob and Judy Weisberg.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    7/279

    - vii -

    THE PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS: MENTAL APPEARANCE ANDMENTAL REALITY

    Table of Contents

    CHAPTER 1: FIXING THE DATA, AND CHALMERS'SHARD PROBLEM.........................................................................................11.1 Fixing the Data ...........................................................................................4

    1.1.1 The Need for a Neutral Method ...........................................................41.1.2 Does the Commonsense Approach Really Capture the Data?..........11

    1.2 Chalmers's Hard Problem of Consciousness ...........................................241.2.1 A Model of Reductive Explanation .....................................................241.2.2 The Hard Problem .............................................................................331.2.3 Criticisms of Chalmers's view ............................................................41

    CHAPTER 2: LEVINE AND BLOCK.................................................................52

    2.1 Levine's Explanatory Gap.........................................................................522.1.1 Levine's Defense of Materialism........................................................522.1.2 The Explanatory Gap.........................................................................57

    2.2 Block's Phenomenal Consciousness........................................................692.2.1 Kinds of Consciousness.....................................................................692.2.2 Block's Identity Thesis and the Harder Problem of Consciousness ...842.2.3 Block and Levine ...............................................................................89

    2.3 Conclusion: What's the Problem?............................................................96

    CHAPTER 3: THE APPEARANCES TO BE EXPLAINED AND THEPHENOMENAL CONCEPTS APPROACH ................................................99

    3.1 What are the Appearances?.....................................................................993.1.1 Three Features of Conscious Experience..........................................993.1.2 Immediacy .......................................................................................1023.1.3 Independence..................................................................................1053.1.4 Indescribability .................................................................................1093.1.5 Are These Really the Appearances that Create the Problem? ........112

    3.2 The Phenomenal Concepts Approach....................................................1153.2.1 What is the Approach?.....................................................................1153.2.2 Loar's Recognitional Concepts of Experience .................................1233.2.3 Papineau's Quotation Model............................................................1283.2.4 Perry's Humean Ideas .....................................................................133

    3.3 Criticisms of the P-concepts Approach...................................................139

    CHAPTER 4: A MODEL OF FIRST-PERSON ACCESS ................................1534.1 Descriptions and the Doctrine of Cartesian Modes of Presentation .......153

    4.1.1 What are Descriptive Concepts? .....................................................1534.1.2 The Doctrine of Cartesian Modes of Presentation ...........................156

    4.2 Expert Perception...................................................................................1664.2.1 Chess and Chunking .......................................................................167

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    8/279

    - viii -

    4.2.2 Music, Wine, Chick Sexing, and Attractiveness...............................1714.2.3 Expert Qualia and Dreyfus...............................................................180

    4.3..A Descriptivist Model of First-Person Access.........................................1844.3.1 Conditions of Adequacy...................................................................1844.3.2 Characterizing the Model .................................................................186

    4.3.3 Empirical Evidence ..........................................................................199

    CHAPTER 5: EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE, AND THEKNOWLEDGE ARGUMENT.....................................................................202

    5.1 Evidence Against the Accuracy of Introspection.....................................2035.1.1 Common Sense and the Accuracy of Introspection .........................2035.1.2 Accepting the Evidence ...................................................................2105.1.3 The Empirical Results......................................................................2145.1.4 The Effect of the Empirical Results..................................................228

    5.2 Empirical Evidence for a Descriptivist Model of First-Person Access.....2335.2.1 Chess Expertise...............................................................................233

    5.2.2 Wine Tasting Expertise....................................................................2425.3 The Knowledge Argument......................................................................250

    REFERENCES .................................................................................................259

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    9/279

    -1-

    CHAPTER 1: FIXING THE DATA, AND CHALMERS'S HARD PROBLEM

    It is widely accepted that consciousness poses a special explanatory problem for

    science. In the 17th century, near the dawn of modern era, John Locke

    expressed what has become a well-entrenched sentiment concerning the

    mysterious nature of the conscious mind. He wrote

    'Tis evident that the bulk, figure, and motion of several Bodies about us,

    produce in us several Sensations, as of Colours, Sounds, Tastes, Smells,

    Pleasure and Pain, etc. These mechanical Affections of Bodies, having

    no affinity at all with those Ideas, they produce in us, ... we can have no

    distinct knowledge of such Operations beyond our Experience; and can

    reason no otherwise about them, then as effects produced by the

    appointment of an infinitely Wise Agent, which perfectly surpasses our

    Comprehensions.1

    The quantifiable features of reality (bulk, figure, motion) seem utterly distinct from

    the conscious ideas we experience. Locke despaired of ever grasping their

    interconnection. Locke's contemporary Samuel Johnson concurred, writing,

    "Matter can differ from matter only in form, bulk, density, motion and direction of

    motion: to which of these, however varied or combined, can consciousness be

    annexed?"2 In the latter part of the 19th century, even as modern science moved

    from triumph to triumph, biologist Thomas Huxley wrote

    1Locke, Essay, IV, iii, 28, 558-559.

    2Quoted in Minsky 1985, 19.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    10/279

    2

    How it is that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness comes

    about as a result of irritating nerve tissue, is just as unaccountable as the

    appearance of Djin when Aladdin rubbed his lamp (quoted in Tye 1995,

    15).

    While other facets of nature were illuminated, consciousness remained in the

    dark.

    The 150 years since Huxley have seen the establishment of scientific

    psychology and neuroscience, of relativity theory and quantum mechanics, and

    the advent of biochemistry and molecular genetics. But consciousness

    apparently remains as perplexing as ever. In a recent work, David Chalmers

    writes that

    Consciousness is the biggest mystery. It may be the last outstanding

    obstacle to our quest for a scientific understanding of the universe. ... We

    have good reason to believe that consciousness arises from physical

    systems such as brains, but we have little idea how it arises or why it

    exists at all. ... We do not just lack a detailed theory; we are entirely in the

    dark about how consciousness fits into the natural order (Chalmers 1996,

    xi).

    In a similar vein, Colin McGinn writes

    We know that brains are the de facto causal basis of consciousness, but

    we have, it seems, no understanding whatever of how this can be so. It

    strikes us as miraculous, eerie, even faintly comic. Somehow, we feel,

    the water of the physical brain is turned into the wine of consciousness,

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    11/279

    3

    but we draw a total blank on the nature of this conversion (McGinn 1989,

    529).

    And with characteristic bluntness Jerry Fodor adds, "Nobody has the slightest

    idea how anything material could be conscious. Nobody even knows what it

    would be like to have the slightest idea about how anything material could be

    conscious" (Fodor 1992, 5).

    What is it that inspires such pessimism about explaining consciousness,

    despite the impressive scientific progress of the last half-millennium? Perhaps

    we are too close to the subject matter to see it clearly. It seems that we know

    our conscious minds differently then we know everything else. Our conscious

    minds are directly and immediately available to us--nothing seems nearer to us,

    or better known. Furthermore, consciousness makes up the experiential bedrock

    of our world. Everything else is known through it, by reasoning from the

    evidence that it brings. Descartes went so far as to hold that we cease to exist

    without consciousness. There is seemingly no way to step back and peer at the

    conscious mind from an objective distance.

    But such distance is apparently required by science. Modern science

    employs quantitative, mechanistic theories whose precision, scope, and

    predictive power leave little doubt about their primacy in explaining our world. To

    the extent that a phenomenon is brought under scientific theory, we count it as

    explained. But consciousness seems to evade the systematic web of science.

    From the inside, consciousness appears basic, indivisible, and unquantifiable.

    We grasp consciousness more directly and with a greater feeling of certainty

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    12/279

    4

    than we grasp anything else. But what we grasp doesn't seem to fit into the

    orderly world of science.

    This is how things appear. But what reason is there to accept this radical

    dichotomy? Is it really so obvious that consciousness cannot fit into our scientific

    world view? And can argument and evidence be brought to bear on this issue, or

    are we simply at the mercy of brute intuition? Recently, a number of researchers

    have worked to clearly demarcate the problem of consciousness, and to defend

    the idea that there is more to the problem then mere intuition-mongering. In what

    follows, I will present and criticize the efforts of David Chalmers, Joseph Levine,

    and Ned Block, with the aim of distilling out the core of what must be explained

    by a theory of consciousness. Then I will develop and defend a theory of the

    access that we have to our conscious states, a theory fully amenable to a

    scientific explanation of consciousness. But to begin, I will make some important

    claims concerning how we should go about pinning-down the data that a theory

    of consciousness must explain. This preliminary step is crucial if we are to avoid

    the temptation to either operationalize away the alleged problem or to cloak the

    explanatory data in unnecessary mystery.

    1.1 Fixing the Data

    1.1.1 The Need for a Neutral Method

    Many important issues concerning the possibility of an explanation of

    consciousness turn on how we pick out the phenomenon we are trying to explain.

    Therefore, it is of utmost importance that we find a neutral way to fix the data a

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    13/279

    5

    theory of consciousness must explain, one that both accurately captures just

    what we wish to elucidate and avoids cloaking consciousness in terms that

    antecedently beg the question against one view or another. There are difficulties

    inherent in this process, however. On the one hand, we run the risk of defining

    away our problem, of characterizing consciousness illicitly in terms that aid

    scientific explanation at the expense of the very features that first attracted our

    interest. On the other, we are in danger of characterizing consciousness as that

    which is by nature inexplicable and beyond our intellectual reach. While this may

    become apparent at the end of our inquiry, building it into the definition of the

    phenomenon eliminates the possibility of progress at the outset. To paraphrase

    David Chalmers, we could define "world peace" as a ham sandwich, and it would

    be much easier to achieve world peace, though perhaps less than satisfying in a

    geopolitical sense. But by the same token, we could define "ham sandwich" as

    world peace, and go unnecessarily hungry at lunchtime. The trick, therefore, is

    to find a way to fix the data in neutral terms, and to avoid prejudicial

    misdescription of our subject matter.

    A neutral method of data fixing has several requirements. One, it must

    accurately capture the phenomenon in question. Two, it must do so in language

    that is as neutral as possible, to avoid begging important theoretical questions.

    And three, it must refrain, as much as possible, from delivering pronouncements

    on the underlying nature of the phenomenon in question. What we desire is a

    characterization of that which must be explained, not of the underlying processes

    or materials that account for the explanandum. The last constraint should be

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    14/279

    6

    handled with care in order to skirt the problem of operationalizing away the

    subject in pursuit of scientific theory. But it also important to keep in mind that

    what we want is a cataloging of how things appear at the outset of theorizing--

    how things seem to be before we apply this or that theory to explain the data.

    This requirement dictates that claims about the underlying nature of the

    phenomenon should come at the end of a chain of reasoning, not at the

    beginning. If the subject matter really does defy scientific explanation, this will

    become apparent in the course of theory-building and empirical research.

    Thus, as much as possible, we want a pretheoretic characterization of the

    data, a description of how things appear prior to explicit theorizing. This is the

    initial step in scientific theorizing generally. Among other things, Galileo's

    principle of inertia explains why, pretheoretically, it appears that we and the

    objects around us are not in rapid motion, despite the fact that the earth is

    moving rapidly. This requires establishing how things appear at the start of

    theorizing. In long-established scientific research programs, the data to be

    explained is often explicitly the product of prior scientific theory. But at the outset

    (and often in the final analysis as well) we require an explanation of the

    pretheoretic appearances. How should we go about pinning down the

    appearances? Mental state terms owe their meaning to their place in our

    everyday practices of predicting and explaining each other's (and our own)

    behavior. We all employ the terms "conscious," "sensation," "thought," etc. in

    everyday discourse, and we recognize how to apply the terms to ourselves and

    others. This is where our mental terms get their initial life, and this is where the

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    15/279

    7

    factors fixing our intuitions about the subject-matter are ensconced and codified.

    Indeed, employing terms like "thought" and "sensation" outside of common usage

    invokes the very confusion that the proponents of a problem of consciousness

    warn against. The sort of "bait and switch" they deride arguably involves starting

    with the folk-meaning of a term, and offering a theory of something else. Thus,

    we should look to our common, everyday usage of mental state terms in order to

    pin down the data that must be explained.

    David Lewis defends the idea that we should look to our commonsense

    characterization to fix the initial data. He writes,

    We have a very extensive shared understanding of how we work mentally.

    Think of it as a theory: folk psychology... Folk psychology has evolved

    over thousands of years of close observation of one another. It is not the

    last word on psychology, but we should be confident that so far as it goes-

    -and it does go far--it is largely right (1994, 298).

    Folk psychology has the virtue of being free from abstract or technical language;

    it is in everyday terms which are unlikely to carry heavy-duty metaphysical

    commitments and presuppositions. For the same reason, it will not present a

    characterization of the data in language tilted towards a particular scientific view,

    or in terms operationalized to fit a specific research agenda. Finally, it arguably

    respects our first-person access to the mind. Folk psychology certainly allows

    that we know our own minds in a different way from which we know the mind's of

    others. Further, it allows that we have introspective access to our conscious

    states, and that this is part of what fixes our commonsense terms for the mind.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    16/279

    8

    That is not to say that folk psychology endorses an infallibility claim about the

    mind; arguably, this is much stronger than the dictates of commonsense (see

    below). But there is no barrier to including introspective data in a folk

    characterization of the mental, and to granting that we know our own minds in a

    distinctive way.

    But haven't I already gone back on my claim that we need a pretheoretic

    characterization of the data? If folk psychology itself is a theory, as Lewis urges,

    won't its "hidden presuppositions" infect the data as much as any other theory? I

    will address this point in more detail below, when I consider worries along these

    lines presented by Paul Churchland. But already a case can be made that this is

    the most neutral characterization we are going to get. Saying that folk beliefs

    about a particular domain make up a theory is to say that the beliefs are geared

    towards explaining a limited domain of facts, and that they provide the

    background framework that lets us see certain types of claims as explanatory.

    Saying that Mary went to the fridge because she wanted a beer is explanatory

    because it falls under the general rule that people who want beer and believe

    there is beer in the fridge will usually get a beer. The key point is that these are

    everyday beliefs, and not the product of an abstract philosophical or scientific

    theory. These beliefs constitute what people think about the mind in everyday

    contexts. And what's more, there seems to be no better place to go for the

    desired neutrality. Even careful attempts to "bracket" off the contributions of folk

    psychology from the way mental phenomena appear to us require a

    characterization of just what folk psychology adds, so that we appropriately

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    17/279

    9

    cordon off its influence. Further, such a characterization requires a prior theory

    about how the mind works, in order to justify the claim that we can bracket things

    in this manner at all. But that is precisely what is at issue here. This sort of

    justifying explanation will have to say what the mind is, what consciousness is,

    etc. such that it could be bracketed. And how is that to be done, prior to

    bracketing? Common sense may involve theory in the mild way sketched by

    Lewis, but it does not make such substantial claims about the underlying

    workings of the mind. Thus, it is neutral in the sense we require. In what follows,

    I will at times use the term "pretheoretic," but it will always refer to our folk-

    psychological characterization of the mind.

    The commonsense approach does have the advantage over pure

    introspective approaches of being publicly checkable, after a fashion. A pure

    introspective method is one where a subject simply "peers" inward, and

    characterizes the data according to what they introspect. However, if there is

    disagreement over what is introspected, there is no higher court of appeal; we

    are stuck with the contradictory results, and can't proceed further (witness the

    disagreements by the early introspective psychologists over "imageless

    thoughts"). The commonsense approach, on the other hand, requires at least

    that the characterization fit with what most people would assent to if prompted.

    Thus, the other members of the folk community provide a check upon the

    characterization: if the claim is too controversial, it will not make it into the

    common usage that defines folk psychology.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    18/279

    10

    Furthermore, folk psychology allows for third-person correction of first

    person ascriptions, at least in certain cases. For example, it occasionally

    happens that we may be in a mental state, perhaps a desire or emotional state,

    and fail to recognize it ourselves. We may in fact deny that we are that state.

    But it may be apparent to others that we desire X or are angry about Y, despite

    our protestations. And we may later come to agree. There are even times when

    we can be corrected about our self-attributions of sensations, like pain. This is

    most obvious when we suggest to a frightened child that they are not hurt,

    despite the presence of blood or because of a scary fall. As adults, we are open

    to the suggestions of doctors or dentists (at least on occasion!) when they assure

    us that a procedure really doesn't hurt, and instead, in our anxious state, we've

    misinterpreted a stimulus as painful. This may not happen often, but it is familiar

    enough, and it certainly does not elicit a sense that such scenarios are

    impossible or contradictory. Thus, folk psychology disavows Cartesian infallibility

    and transparency concerning the mind. Again, this is not to rule such claims out

    of bounds; instead, it suggests that, according to the commonsense approach,

    such claims require further argument.

    Thus, the commonsense approach provides a neutral means of fixing the

    data, one that captures our "pretheoretic" intuitions concerning the mind, but also

    allows for a degree of crosschecking and public correction. Further, it delivers

    mental terms in language that is as independent of theoretical commitment as

    possible. It is not (at least overtly) weighed down with metaphysical claims and

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    19/279

    11

    presuppositions, and it does not operationalize terms illicitly in the service of a

    particular theory.

    1.1.2 Does the Commonsense Approach Really Capture the Data?

    However, the commonsense approach as I have laid it out already is open to

    criticism, from more than one direction. The first line of criticism holds that the

    approach does not take the first-person perspective seriously enough and

    thereby fails to properly characterize the conscious mind. The second line of

    complaint holds that the view privileges the prejudices and confusions of

    common sense, and thereby limits the possibility of a scientific theory of

    consciousness. I will address the concerns in turn.

    The first worry holds that the commonsense approach puts too much

    weight on third-person prediction and explanation of behavior. After all, the main

    role of folk psychology in our lives as social animals is to predict and explain the

    behaviors of our conspecifics. This accounts for the utility and ubiquity of folk

    psychology; however, it seems to downplay our first-person access to the "feel"

    of conscious states. Indeed, one of the main defenders of the approach, David

    Lewis, argues the folk psychology generally defines mental states in functional

    terms. Some argue that this leaves no room for consciousness.3

    Furthermore, the approach has a close affinity with the method prescribed

    by Daniel Dennett for fixing the data, the "heterophenomenological approach"

    (Dennett 1991, chapter 4). That view dictates that we consider the reports of

    3See Lewis 1972, 1980. See Block 1978 for the criticism of the view. But see also Lewis 1983a

    for a response.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    20/279

    12

    subjects as part of the data; further, if we can explain why they make these

    reports, we have provided an adequate explanation of the phenomenon. They

    may make the reports because they are accurately describing their mental

    states. But they may make the reports for other reasons, and therefore we are

    not committed to accept the veracity of the reports, no matter what. Dennett

    likens the task of the consciousness researcher to a field anthropologist

    collecting data on a forest religion: we take the indigenous subjects' reports as

    canonical on what they take the religion to be, but we withhold judgment on the

    truth of their reports of gods and spirits. They are certainly correct that this is

    how their religion is practiced, but it may well turn out that there is no omnipotent

    forest god, despite the sincere reports and beliefs of the subjects. The situation

    is the same in the case of the conscious mind. All reports must be independently

    corroborated before they are accepted as indications of real phenomena.

    Objectors to Dennett's view contend that it unfairly begs the question

    against the existence of phenomenal consciousness (Block 1992; Chalmers,

    website). If a phenomenon cannot be establish without third-person

    confirmation, it will fail to qualify as a legitimate object of scientific study and its

    very existence will be called into doubt. Furthermore, the view takes subject's

    reports as the data to be explained, rather than taking the reports as evidence for

    conscious states which are to be explained. Chalmers, in responding to a piece

    of Dennett's, argues instead for a method of data fixing defended by Max

    Velmans (1996, 2000). Velmans argues for what Chalmers terms a "critical

    phenomenology" in which we

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    21/279

    13

    accept verbal reports as a prima facie guide to a subject's conscious

    experience, except where there are specific reasons to doubt their

    reliability... On this view, we're not interested so much in reports as data to

    be explained in their own rights (though we might be in part interested in

    that). Rather, we are interested in them as a (fallible) guide to the first-

    person data about consciousness that we really want to be explained

    (Chalmers, website).

    A similar complaint is lodged by Charles Siewert against Dennett's

    position (Siewert 1998). He argues that first-person reports have a "distinctive

    warrant" which renders them, as it were, innocent until proven guilty. He runs

    through a number of cases that many take as empirical evidence that we are

    often wrong about the contents of our minds. He considers work in social

    psychology championed by Nisbett and others (e.g. Nisbett and Wilson 1977),

    and argues that it fails to show systematic error concerning the contents of our

    minds. Rather, it shows errors concerning the antecedent causes of our

    occurent beliefs. But this indicates a lack of causal knowledge instead of a lack

    of knowledge concerning our current mental states. He concludes that

    since we have no adequate reason to deny what we pre-epistemologically

    would judge about our knowledge of our minds, we are entitled to proceed

    on the assumption that we do have a distinctively first-person knowledge

    of our mind, and to rely on such knowledge in our inquiries about

    ourselves, in lieu of the discovery of some compelling reason not to do so

    (Siewert 1998, 23).

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    22/279

    14

    Thus, first-person reports require no independent corroboration in the absence of

    a compelling challenge, contrary to Dennett's approach.

    For my purposes, it is important to note that both Chalmers and Siewert

    take first-person reports as fallible, though prima facie acceptable in the absence

    of good counterevidence. Also, both seem committed to a pretheoretic or "pre-

    epistemological" status for our data-fixing claims. This is in line with the

    commonsense approach, which holds that folk-theoretic claims fix the data. It is

    clear that by "pretheoretic" and "pre-epistemological," neither theorist wishes to

    rule out folk psychology in Lewis's sense. But to address their central worry,

    there is no reason that to deny that reports are evidence for inner states or to

    accept that they are the sole and exclusive data a theory must explain. Indeed,

    folk psychology licenses this very evidential link: we take our reports and the

    reports of other to indicate what mental states we are in. And the folk

    characterizations that fix the data for a theory of consciousness are

    characterizations of mental states themselves, not of reports.

    But arguably the conflict between Dennett's heterophenomenology and

    the views of Chalmers and Siewert is illusory. Dennett's view also allows that

    reports are evidence of real states; he simply puts stress upon the idea that such

    reports are fallible and require some kind of independent means of confirmation if

    we are to step out of the trap that plagued introspectionist psychology. Later in

    his 1991 book, Dennett does reject the notion of consciousness defended by

    Chalmers, Block, and others, and this leads him to hold that all that remains to be

    explained is subject's reports of such states. But this is an application of the

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    23/279

    15

    method that can be challenged. In fact, one might argue that Dennett is too

    quick to dismiss the possibility of additional evidence for the presence of a more

    richly characterized phenomenon (See Rosenthal 1995; Akins 1996). Still, even

    if one establishes that heterophenomenology begs the question against

    phenomenal consciousness, I have argued that the commonsense approach is

    free of that bias.

    Finally, the commonsense method is defended by one of the early

    defenders of a nonreductive view of consciousness, Frank Jackson.4 Jackson in

    his 1998 book and in a work with David Braddon-Mitchell (1996) argues for the

    commonsense approach to fixing the data, while contending that other

    approaches that look more directly to the sciences fail to adequately capture

    what we wish to explain. Such approaches tend to ignore specific difficulties

    inherent in the subject matter, and operationalize away important phenomena.

    While there are responses to this claim, I only wish to stress that Jackson did not

    feel that such a method shortchanged consciousness or the first-person point of

    view. Indeed, he collaborates with Chalmers on a piece that dovetails well with

    the overall view (Chalmers and Jackson 2001). And it is arguable that Chalmers

    himself employs the commonsense approach in the first chapter of his 1996

    book, where he characterizes a number of concepts of consciousness and mind.

    4Jackson has since rejected his anti-reductionist stance, and now holds that reduction is in

    principle possible, despite his earlier worries. See Chalmers and Jackson 2001; Jackson 2003.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    24/279

    16

    If the method is acceptable to Jackson and Chalmers, it is hard to argue that it is

    not able to take the phenomenon of consciousness seriously.5

    However, this may appear to open up the commonsense approach to a

    charge from the opposite direction, that the method overvalues the view of the

    folk at the expense of a scientific approach to the mind. Why think the folk have

    any real insight on the nature of the mind, or have anything useful to say about

    fixing the data for scientific theory of consciousness? All we get from folk

    psychology is a collection of loosely related intuitions, intuitions that are shaped

    by ignorance about the real workings of the mind. Further, the method may

    seem committed to a priori analyses of mental phenomenon, and such analyses

    have proven a failure at grounding a science of the mind. Indeed, it may appear

    that the commonsense approach endorses the idea that there are analytic truths

    about the mind which trump scientific claims. Why think a method apparently

    committed to these dubious notions has any role to play?

    Block and Stalnaker (1999) present a multifaceted attack on the idea that

    a priori conceptual analysis has any role to play in reductive scientific

    explanation. They argue that the requisite analyses are never actually

    5There is an additional position on fixing the data which I have bypassed. The phenomenological

    tradition holds that we must be trained in taking a specialized kind of attitude towards our ownmental states; only then can we "bracket" the elements of our naive conception of mind and get atits true nature. Further, this view holds that mind is irreducibly subjective and distinct from theobjective. Thus, commonsense would have no real insight into the proper objects of study for a

    theory of the mind. However, this approach has its troubles. One, it is not clear to me how wejustify the ability to bracket. Why not think that the bracketing is theory laden, and therefore, theresults of the investigation simply show us what we already believed? Further, the view suffersfrom a great difficulty in cross-checking and confirming its investigation. If the phenomena ofstudy are irreducible in this sense, is there any reliable intersubjective check on theoreticalclaims? Finally, the attitude or intuition that is taken towards introspection is questionable. Whythink our "inner eye" has the ability to see into the nature of the mind at all, particularly in thisunfettered manner? My discussion of this issue is prompted by Francisco Varela's interesting1996 piece "Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy for the Hard Problem."

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    25/279

    17

    forthcoming; further, even the sketchiest attempts at place-holders fall prey to

    counterexamples. In addition, they argue that a number of theoretical constraints

    which they lump under the heading of "simplicity" demonstrate that empirical

    considerations are always present in data fixing, even in the simplest cases. The

    real reason, they argue, that we posit theoretical identities is to simplify our

    theories and increase their range of prediction and explanation. Further, this

    shapes our decisions about the extension of the terms in question. We cannot

    tell which moves will achieve these theoretical goals until we have empirical data.

    Thus, empirical considerations are always at play in data fixing, undermining the

    possibility of a priori analyses.

    But, contrary to the views of some of its proponents, the commonsense

    approach is not committed to a priori analyses or analytic truths. Instead, the

    view is committed only to analyses that characterize phenomena relative to the

    principles and assumptions of folk psychology. Given that our folk beliefs shift

    over time in the face of new data, there is no reason to believe that we know in

    principle that a term's meaning is fixed come what may. Even our everyday

    terms for mental states are open to revision, and therefore are not analytic.

    While at present it may seem just obvious that a particular change in the use of a

    term would represent a change in its meaning, we cannot know beforehand how

    we will react to new empirical data, especially when we take into account the

    holistic nature of theory confirmation (Quine 1951). We may choose to alter our

    weighting of the various factors that fix the meaning of a term, in order to

    preserve some other aspect of our folk theory. It proves to be arbitrary whether

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    26/279

    18

    to view this shift as a change in meaning or the falsification of certain empirical

    beliefs. There is no further source of data to decide this question in a principled

    manner. Thus, there is no supportable analytic/synthetic distinction, and it

    cannot be invoked here. The meanings of our folk psychological terms are not

    knowable independently of experience, and the process of ascertaining those

    meanings is not disconnected from the rest of what we believe, both about the

    mind and in other domains. However, this does not rob folk psychology of its role

    in fixing the data. Instead, we must take into account that we are engaged in an

    empirical study and that our data is only interpretable against the background of

    the rest of our beliefs and theories. Still, the relatively stable common knowledge

    of folk psychology provides the best place to fix the data for a scientific theory of

    consciousness.

    However, it may seem that our folk analyses are worked out "in the

    armchair" and thus are plausibly counted as a priori in the relevant sense. They

    appear to require no empirical support for justification. To access our folk theory,

    all we need to do is reflect on our own beliefs, and this requires no outside help.

    But why think that just because such a theory is active in our predictions and

    explanations of behavior that it is evident upon private reflection just what the

    principles of the theory are? Some may be better than others at unpacking the

    principles implicit in the folk views, and the process of investigation generates

    disagreement about the shape of the commonsense view. When difference over

    interpretations occurs, it is reasonably settled by canvassing a variety of

    subjects, and this is an empirical matter. The justification for such claims comes

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    27/279

    19

    from how well they agree with the attitudes and response of the folk, not from a

    nonexperiential source.6

    Furthermore, our commonsense theory evolves and shifts under pressure

    from a variety of sources, including changing cultural fashions and customs, and

    scientific theories and opinions that get folded back into everyday knowledge.

    While the rate of alteration may be slow, it does occur over time, undermining the

    idea that all of our folk views on the mind are accessible a priori. Consider the

    case of unconscious thought. Locke, in his Essay, holds that nonconscious

    thought is impossible; indeed, it seems to him almost a contradiction in terms

    (Locke 1979/1689). In these passages, he is in part appealing to a

    commonsense use of the terms he has in mind; he presents little in the way of

    argument, and instead appeals to the seeming absurdity of the claim. This

    provides an indication that the idea of nonconscious thought may not have fit

    particularly well with commonsense views in Locke's day. But with the

    widespread popularity of the works of Sigmund Freud, the idea of nonconscious

    thoughts and desires driving our behavior became commonplace. Freud's

    theories, inspired by the goal of a scientific psychology, altered the folk view of

    the mind. For my purposes, the main point is that these attitudes about the mind

    fail to display the stability needed for a priori access. Such views are thus

    learned, and therefore must be investigated from an empirical standpoint. Our

    justification for the use of these terms traces back to a learnt public theory about

    6In fact, this seems to correspond well to Block's approach to characterizing consciousness. He

    employs a "pre-theoretic" paradigm, and then considers a variety of thought experiments tosharpen that conception. Finally, he argues that the empirical evidence for his characterization isnot conclusive, but provides a number of weak but potential lines of evidence, when taken as agroup and viewed in light of general theoretical principles (Block 2001). See chapter 2, below.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    28/279

    20

    whose principles we can be in error. A priori reflection provides no justification

    for such claims.

    The commonsense approach therefore is not committed to a priori

    analyses or analytic truths. Instead, it relies on an empirical investigation of the

    principles of an acquired public theory, one that is stable enough and accessible

    enough to be termed common knowledge, but not one that is beyond revision

    and known independent of experience. In this manner, the considerations that

    Block and Stalnaker term "simplicity" are a central part of the method. We

    develop our best interpretations of the folk theory, and in order to confirm our

    picture, we run it up against folk responses and attitudes. But in adjudicating

    between rival interpretations, considerations of simplicity and the like will always

    be at play. Sometimes, this may be the only way to really decide between two

    views: one view fits in with theoretical and empirical considerations better than

    the other, despite the fact that both make plausible cases concerning

    commonsense theory.

    Still, this may seem to miss the force of the initial criticism. Why think that

    folk psychology is a useful guide to the mind, at all? Paul Churchland (1981) has

    argued that folk psychology is a relatively weak theory, when held up to the

    promise of an advanced neuroscientific approach. He argues that over time we

    will reject folk theory because it will be replaced by a better theoretical approach

    to the mind. Clumsy folk notions like "belief" and "desire" will fade away in the

    face of more precise and more informative neuroscientific replacements.

    Therefore, the practice of mining the folk view for data is of no value. We are

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    29/279

    21

    simply making precise terms in dying theory, like diehard vitalists making clear

    what they mean by "lan vital."

    But this criticism is wide of the mark. First, there is an intermediate

    position between blind acceptance of folk psychology and its elimination.

    Instead, it is reasonable to assume that the discoveries of a future neuroscience

    will inform and sharpen our folk conceptions like "belief" and "desire." The mere

    fact that certain commonsense characterizations are in error does not remove

    the possibility that they may be revised in the face of new data. As noted in with

    the case of nonconscious mental states, the folk view is certainly revisable as

    new theoretical information disseminates into the common view. Further, to put

    the point more directly, we need not think that when the ancients talked about

    stars, they were referring to something different from what we do, despite a belief

    that stars were holes in the sky (Rosenthal 1980; Stich 1996). Folk beliefs have

    a malleable quality in the face of new evidence; this is plausibly the case

    regarding beliefs about the mind.

    However, this is not to say that the folk view is inviolate. If there is truly

    compelling evidence that folk belief is radically incorrect about the mind, such a

    belief should be rejected. But the prior option of revision must be ruled out first,

    on the general theoretical principles that one should save the appearances and

    minimize damage to our preexisting beliefs, if possible. Further, the strong track

    record of folk psychology in predicting and explaining the actions of ourselves

    and others supports the idea that the commonsense theory must accurately

    capture aspects of our mental functioning. If not, what explains its success? So

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    30/279

    22

    it is much more likely that a revisionary, rather than an eliminativist, strategy will

    be appropriate.

    In addition, if there is no plausible connection between the folk view and a

    new theoretical claim, lingering open questions and doubts will pervade. To the

    extent that a theory both respects neuroscientific results and explains folk

    intuitions, it is to be favored. And one cannot forge this connection without a

    clear idea of the phenomena as viewed from the folk perspective. In the final

    analysis, we may be compelled to reject closely held folk principles in the face of

    scientific progress; nothing rules out this possibility beforehand. But we should

    certainly aim, at this point in inquiry, at a view that both respects and explains

    folk-theoretic claims and incorporates modern neuroscientific results. Indeed,

    one wouldn't know how to begin to evaluate the mind, from a neuroscientific or

    any other point of view, without a clear delineation of our uses of folk

    terminology. Interpreting an fMRI or a PET scan requires a background theory to

    underwrite the interpretation. Folk psychology, either explicitly or implicitly,

    provides that theory.

    Taken together, all of these considerations suggest that the

    commonsense approach is the best option for fixing that data and determining

    the conditions of adequacy on a theory of consciousness. It respects the

    importance of our commonsense notions in providing the initial meaning of our

    mentalistic terms, it is in a position to "take phenomenology seriously," and it is

    open to experimental input and theoretical change. The approach provides a

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    31/279

    23

    stable enough platform to characterize consciousness in a non-question-begging

    way, while leaving the door open to scientific explanation.

    In the following three sections of the dissertation I will examine the

    attempts of David Chalmers, Joseph Levine, and Ned Block to capture what is

    distinctively problematic about consciousness. In light of my commonsense

    approach to fixing the data, if a characterization deviates from our folk-

    psychological conception, the burden is on the theorist offering the

    characterization to support that proposal. If such support is lacking, the claim will

    be rejected as begging the question. In particular, I will focus on the distinction

    between the way the conscious mind appears to us from a commonsense point-

    of-view, and the conscious mind's underlying nature. As I stressed above, folk

    psychology does not license any sort of infallible access to the nature of the

    mind--what we are aware of from a commonsense point of view is simply how

    things appear to us. This is appropriate: what we desire is a characterization of

    the everyday appearances. To the extent that a theorist, in fixing the initial data

    to be explained, moves from these appearances to the underlying reality

    substantial argument is required. This, of course, is not to claim that no such

    argument can be made; rather, it is to highlight the burden of proof regarding

    claims about the underlying nature of consciousness.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    32/279

    24

    1.2 Chalmers's Hard Problem of Consciousness

    1.2.1 A Model of Reductive Explanation

    In his 1996 book The Conscious Mind and in a series of related papers (1995,

    1999, 2003), David Chalmers argues that consciousness poses a problem

    different in kind from other scientific challenges. According to Chalmers,

    consciousness cannot be explained in physical terms, and therefore fails to find

    location in a materialist ontology. It is a brute and inexplicable feature of the

    world. In Chalmers's terms, consciousness poses a "hard problem" for science.

    Chalmers begins with an alleged folk-characterization of consciousness and then

    argues that, given the nature of our concepts generally, we can conclude that

    consciousness is explanatorily problematic. In what follows, I will reject

    Chalmers's concept-based argument and I will question his initial characterization

    of the data as well. However, at the end of the chapter I will isolate an important

    element that any theory of consciousness must account for. Though I argue that

    Chalmers is premature in proclaiming a hard problem of consciousness, his work

    does help to clarify the burdens on any materialist theory. But to begin I will lay

    out Chalmers's model of reductive explanation, which is central to his

    antimaterialist project.

    Materialism is the ontological thesis that holds that all things are ultimately

    physical or made up of physical parts. The position matches up well with the

    scientific worldview: according to the materialist picture, the basic constituents of

    reality are fixed by our best scientific theory, and given that our best theory deals

    in basic physical elements, materialism holds that at root, the universe is

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    33/279

    25

    physical. To put the point in possible worlds talk, according to materialism, any

    possible world that is physically just like ours is just like ours simpliciter.

    Of course, there are numerous entities in the world that are not explicitly

    mentioned in the physical sciences. To gain legitimacy in a materialist ontology,

    it must be shown that such entities are ultimately nothing over and above the

    arrangement of basic physical parts. According to Chalmers (following work by

    David Lewis and Frank Jackson), this is achieved by showing that statements

    about the presence of the entity in question are entailed by statements about

    physical facts, where entailment means that "it is logically impossible for the first

    [statement] to hold without the second" (Chalmers 1996, 36). Establishing this

    entailment provides what Chalmers calls a reductive explanation of the entity in

    question. A reductive explanation demonstrates how the presence of certain

    physical conditions fully settles questions about the presence of the phenomenon

    in question. This shows that, ontologically speaking, there is nothing more to the

    phenomenon than the presence of the relevant physical conditions. If no such

    entailment can be demonstrated, the phenomenon is not reductively explainable,

    and thus can't be located in a materialist ontology. It either must be eliminated,

    or it must, pace materialism, be accepted as a brute feature of reality.7

    According to Chalmers, reductive explanations are available in principle

    for most macroscopic phenomena. He writes

    7The term "location" is taken from Jackson 1998. Jackson argues that the "location problem" can

    only be solved by showing how a complete description of a "macro-level" entity is entailed by thephysical description of the world. See also Lewis 1983b, 1994; Horgan 1984; Kim 1998.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    34/279

    26

    For almost every natural phenomenon above the level of microscopic

    physics, there seems in principle to exist a reductive explanation: that is,

    an explanation wholly in terms of simpler entities. In these cases, when

    we are given an appropriate account of lower-level processes, an

    explanation of the higher-level phenomenon falls out (1996, 42, emphasis

    in original).

    Paradigm examples of reductive explanation are the explanation of the properties

    of water in terms of the properties of H2O molecules and the explanation of

    heredity in terms of the properties of DNA molecules. These explanations show

    how complex macro-level phenomena can be explained in terms of simpler

    entities that ultimately connect with basic physics.

    Chalmers argues (again in accordance with Lewis and Jackson) that a

    crucial step in reductive explanation is providing a conceptual analysis of the

    explanandum. Conceptual analysis supplies the bridge that links facts presented

    in one vocabulary to facts presented in another. In reductive explanation, we first

    conceptually analyze the target, and then show how the lower-level facts satisfy

    the analysis. In this way, we can deduce the existence of the target from a

    description of the lower-level facts.

    For example, consider the case of water. Chalmers argues that there is in

    principle an analysis of water in terms of the way water looks and behaves, in

    terms of the role, broadly conceived, that it plays in our lives. A rough sketch of

    this analysis is "the clear, drinkable liquid that fills our lakes and rivers, comes out

    of the tap, freezes at 0 degrees C, etc." Chalmers offers "the watery role" as a

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    35/279

    27

    stand-in for a completed analysis. Chalmers holds that this sort of analysis is

    available a priori to competent speakers of a language. We arrive at the analysis

    by considering a variety of possible scenarios and seeing how we would apply

    the term in question. We do not need to perform any empirical investigation to

    arrive at the analysis; instead, we reason how the term applies from our

    armchair.

    Further, the analysis need not deliver strict necessary and sufficient

    conditions for the application of the term. Instead, all that's required is a "rough

    and ready" analysis that delivers the extension of a term in a variety of cases. In

    fact, Chalmers allows that people would be hard pressed to come up with a

    workable list to fill out the analysis for "the watery role." But the fact that people

    make reasonably stable judgments over a range of cases shows that they grasp

    the term's "intension," according to Chalmers. The intension of a term is a

    function that delivers a term's extension in various situations. That we can

    reliably make such judgments is evidence of our grasp of the intension.8

    The analysis delivers a rough and ready set of conditions that allow us to

    see, a priori, how various lower-level conditions might realize or constitute the

    target phenomenon. For example, we can reason that, if H2O fills the watery

    role, then water is H2O. Or, if XYZ fills the water role, then water is XYZ. This

    specifies how a phenomenon might be reductively explained. The final step in

    8Chalmers (and Jackson) hold that a term actually possess two intentions, one fixed by

    application at the actual world, the other fixed by considering "other worlds as actual." Chalmerscalls these primary and secondary intensions; Jackson calls them A and C intensions. We arehere concerned with primary or A intensions, which are knowable a priori, according to bothChalmers and Jackson. See Chalmers 1996, chapter 2; Jackson 2003.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    36/279

    28

    reductive explanation is to discover empirically which lower-level stuff actually

    fills the analysis in question. As it turns out, H2O fills the watery role. Thus,

    water is H2O, and water gains acceptance in a materialist ontology by being

    properly located with respect to physical phenomenon. H2O fits into atomic

    chemistry, and thus can be unpacked in principle in terms of the most basic

    elements of physics.9

    The completed reductive explanation has the form of a deductive

    entailment. The water case is reconstructed as follows:

    1. Water is whatever fills the watery role (by analysis)

    2. H2O fills the watery role (by empirical investigation)

    3. Therefore, Water is H2O (by transitivity of identity)

    It follows on this model that if materialism is true, all statements of macro-level

    fact must be entailed by statements of what Chalmers calls the "microphysical

    facts," facts stated in terms of "the fundamental entities and properties of

    physics, in the language of a completed physics" (Chalmers and Jackson 2001,

    2). The only way for entities above the microphysical level to gain legitimacy in a

    materialist ontology is to be reductively explained in this manner.

    It can be argued that Chalmers model does not yield explanations,

    because deductive arguments are not in and of themselves explanatory.10

    9Throughout this dissertation, I will be referring to this style of explanation as "reduction." I will

    not address the issue of bridge laws and intertheoretic reduction, because the issue of reductiveexplanation has largely supplanted intertheoretic reduction as the focus of debate concerningconsciousness. See Kim, 1998, for a review of these issues, and a defense of a similar model ofreductive explanation.

    10See, for example, criticisms of the deductive-nomological model of explanation, i.e. Achinstein

    1981; Salmon 1989.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    37/279

    29

    Chalmers acknowledges the worry, and argues that, although reductive

    explanations are not "illuminating explanations," they are "mystery-removing

    explanations," that reduce "the bruteness and arbitrariness of the phenomenon in

    question to the bruteness and arbitrariness of lower-level processes" (1996, 48-

    49). In essence, such explanations show how an explanatory target connects

    with more basic facts in a way that closes off certain ontological questions. We

    can no longer meaningfully ask how water could be H2O: it just is H2O, because

    water is characterized as the watery role, and H2O actually fills that role.11

    Consequently, according to Chalmers, reductive explanation is a two step

    process. The first is an a priori conceptual analysis of the explanandum. The

    second is an empirical investigation to determine which lower-level entities

    satisfy the analysis, and therefore realize the phenomenon in question. We are

    left at the end with a description providing an entailment of the target by the

    lower-level facts. Chalmers further argues that crucial elements in this process

    are a priori. First, as noted, the conceptual analysis is a priori. The analysis

    proceeds by considering various possible scenarios, and determining how a term

    would be applied. This does not require any knowledge of which world we are

    actually in. Therefore, the justification for the analysis is not empirical. Secondly,

    the reductive explanation itself turns on a priori conditionals like "if H2O is the

    watery stuff, then water is H2O." Chalmers calls these "supervenience

    conditionals" (1996, 53). Our analysis delivers sets of these conditionals, and

    they are the crucial linking premises in reductive explanations. Finally, once the

    11Chalmers does not endorse a model of "illuminating explanation." See Chalmers 1996, 48-49.

    The explication of this sort of explanation is vexed, and I will not address the issue here.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    38/279

    30

    empirical information is supplied telling us which antecedent of a supervenience

    conditional is true in this world, the resulting argument is deductive, and requires

    no further empirical justification. Therefore, Chalmers concludes that we are at

    times in a position to determine a priori when a phenomenon is not reductively

    explainable. If we cannot secure the requisite analysis, or if we cannot produce a

    legitimate deductive argument, then we can conclude that a phenomenon is not

    reductively explainable. This, according to Chalmers, is the case with

    consciousness.

    Chalmers spells out the relationship between the epistemology of

    reductive explanation and ontology of materialism by introducing a

    supervenience framework. Supervenience is a dependence relation between

    two sets of properties or facts.12 Roughly, supervenience occurs when one set of

    facts A fully determines another set of facts B. There are a number of ways to

    unpack the dependence relations, yielding a variety of types of supervenience.13

    Chalmers argues that for a phenomenon to gain location in a materialist

    ontology, it must logically supervene on the physical. According to Chalmers, "B-

    properties supervene logically on A-properties if no two logically possible

    situations are identical with respect to their A-properties but distinct with respect

    to their B-properties" (1996, 35, emphasis in original).

    12Chalmers moves back and forth between talk of properties and talk of facts (and sometimes

    talk of truths, i.e., in Chalmers and Jackson, 2001), but at bottom he sees the relationship asholding between properties. "The appeal to facts makes the discussion less awkward, but all talkof facts and their relations can ultimately be cashed out in terms of patterns of co-instantiations ofproperties..."(1996, 361n2). Arguably, the same ideas can be expressed using talk of predicatesinstead of properties. See Klagge 1988.

    13See Kim 1993 for a detailed discussion of the varieties of supervenience.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    39/279

    31

    For Chalmers, a logically possible situation is one that is conceivable,

    where the constraints on conceivability include not only the rules of formal logic,

    but also conceptual or meaning constraints. Chalmers informally presents the

    notion in the following way:

    One can think of [logical possibility] loosely as possibility in the broadest

    sense, corresponding roughly to conceivability, quite unconstrained by the

    laws of our world. It is useful to think of a logically possible world as a

    world that it would have been in God's power (hypothetically!) to create if

    he had so chosen. God could not have created a world with male vixens,

    but he could have created a world with flying telephones. In determining

    whether it is logically possible that some statement is true, the constraints

    are largely conceptual. The notion of a male vixen is contradictory, so a

    male vixen is logically impossible; the notion of a flying telephone is

    conceptually coherent, if a little out of the ordinary, so a flying telephone is

    logically possible (1996, 35).

    If two conceivable situations are the same with respect to the A-properties, but

    differ with respect to the B-properties, B-properties do not logically supervene on

    A-properties. If B-properties logically supervene on A-properties, all God has to

    do to fix the B-properties is fix the A-properties. There is no extra work for her to

    do. If logical supervenience does not hold, God has additional work to do to fix

    the B-properties.

    The precise relationship between logical supervenience and reductive

    explanation is complex. Chalmers holds that logical supervenience is a

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    40/279

    32

    necessary condition for reductive explanation. We evaluate claims of logical

    supervenience by considering possible situations. If we can conceive of

    situations that are microphysically identical, yet distinct with respect to the target

    phenomenon, logical supervenience fails. The presence of this conceivable

    situation means that the microphysical conditions do not decisively fix the

    presence of the target. We can still meaningfully ask if the macro-phenomenon

    is present, even when we know the microphysical conditions. It's thus not

    entailed by the microphysical facts. If logical supervenience fails, there is no

    entailment from the microphysical facts to the facts about the target

    phenomenon. The a priori conditional required for reductive explanation on

    Chalmers's model is absent. Thus, logical supervenience is necessary for

    reductive explanation.

    However, we evaluate claims of logical supervenience by considering if

    there are residual meaningful ontological questions that remain open even when

    we are given the microphysical facts. And this just is to consider if a reductive

    explanation is available in principle for the phenomenon in question. So the

    order of priority is not clear, and in fact, our intuitions concerning the failure of

    supervenience seem to track our intuitions about the failure of reductive

    explanation. With this in mind, Chalmers writes, "in areas where there are

    epistemological problems, there is an accompanying failure of logical

    supervenience, and ... conversely, in areas where logical supervenience fails,

    there are accompanying epistemological problems" (1996, 74, emphasis in

    original). Chalmers claims to argue from the failure of logical supervenience to

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    41/279

    33

    the failure of reductive explanation for consciousness, but the same set of

    intuitions is in play. In any event, the appearance of a gap between

    consciousness and the physical blocks both possibilities, on Chalmers's view. It

    is beside the point whether we view this as a move from the ontology of

    supervenience to the epistemology of reductive explanation, or vice versa. The

    same set of intuitions determines our conclusion in either case.

    1.2.2 The Hard Problem

    We are now in a position to detail Chalmers's argument for the "hard problem" of

    consciousness. The first step involves a conceptual analysis of "consciousness."

    Chalmers argues that we possess two distinct kinds of concepts that characterize

    the mind, psychological concepts and phenomenal concepts. "On the

    phenomenal concept, mind is characterized by the way it feels; on the

    psychological concept, mind is characterized by what it does" (1996, 11,

    emphasis in original). Psychological concepts characterize mental states in

    functional terms, in terms of perceptual inputs, behavioral outputs, and relations

    to other mental states. Phenomenal concepts characterize mental states in

    terms of subjective experience, in terms of what it is like for the subject to be in

    that state.14 Chalmers grants that many states can be characterized in both

    ways, but he argues that reflection on hypothetical cases delivers distinct

    psychological and phenomenal analyses. A typical psychological concept is

    14See Nagel 1974, for the introduction of this locution into contemporary philosophical

    discussions of consciousness.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    42/279

    34

    "learning."15 Learning can be characterized as a functional process wherein an

    organism adapts its behavior over time in the face of environmental stimuli. This

    characterization makes no mention of what it's like for the organism to undergo

    the process. If an organism adapts its behavior over time in response to stimuli,

    we would say it learned, even if there is nothing it's like for the organism to

    undergo this process.

    A typical phenomenal concept is "pain," understood as the state that feels

    a particular way, namely painful. If an organism felt that particular painful feeling,

    we would consider it in pain, even if it lacked the various behavioral responses

    ordinarily associated with pain. Desire arguably is a mixed state, involving a

    functional response profile, and a particular compelling feel. Note that "pain" can

    also receive a psychological characterization, as a state that underwrites

    aversion and avoidance behavior. Chalmers holds that this does not create a

    conflict; rather, there are two concepts of pain, both of them valid, and both of

    them licensed by analysis (Ibid. 16ff).

    It is the phenomenally characterized mind that presents special problems

    for explanation. To the extent that a mental state can be psychologically

    characterized, it can be reductively explained, because psychological

    characterizations provide the functional analyses necessary for reductive

    explanation. According to Chalmers, there is no special problem in explaining

    how a material being could learn, for example. Given that "learning" can be

    analyzed as "the learning role," all we need to do is discover what physical

    15Here, the quotes pick out a concept as opposed to a term. I will occasionally use quotes to

    pick out concepts. The usage should be clear from the context.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    43/279

    35

    processes realize the learning role. There is no prima facie problem with this

    project, and once we find what actually fills the learning role, we have an a priori

    entailment to the claim that the role-filler is learning.

    However, Chalmers claims the phenomenal cannot be fully captured in a

    functional characterization. "The phenomenal element in the concept prevents

    an analysis in purely functional terms" (1996, 23). This is demonstrated by

    reflection on cases where the phenomenal feel of a particular mental state is

    present, but the functional profile is absent. Again, consider pain. We can,

    according to Chalmers, imagine a state that feels painful to a subject, but never

    leads to any distinct behavioral responses. Chalmers holds that in such a case,

    we would consider the state an example of pain, despite its lack of connection to

    any functional role in the behavior of the organism. But this shows that the

    intension of "pain" is independent of functional considerations, and thus the

    phenomenal concept of "pain" is distinct from the psychological concept of "pain,"

    which is characterized in functional terms of avoidance behavior and indication of

    bodily damage.

    Chalmers likewise argues that we possess a psychological and a

    phenomenal concept of consciousness. "Consciousness" in the psychological

    sense refers to various sorts of awareness and attention that can be given

    functional role characterizations. "Consciousness" in the phenomenal sense

    refers generally to states that there is something it is like for the subject to be in,

    states with a distinct phenomenal feel or character. Chalmers calls the latter

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    44/279

    36

    "phenomenal consciousness;" it is phenomenal consciousness that creates the

    special problem of consciousness.16

    Armed with this analysis, Chalmers presents five separate (though

    arguably related) cases to demonstrate that phenomenal consciousness fails to

    logically supervene on the microphysical, or even on the functional, makeup of

    the organism. His first case involves the conceivability of "zombies," creatures

    physically identical to us that nonetheless lack phenomenal consciousness.

    Chalmers argues that zombies are conceivable because nothing in the zombie

    case seems contradictory or incoherent. He writes,

    I confess that the logical possibility of zombies seems... obvious to me. A

    zombie is just something physically identical to me, but which has no

    conscious experience--all is dark inside. While this is probably empirically

    impossible, it certainly seems that a coherent situation is described; I can

    discern no contradiction in the description (1996, 96).

    If zombies are conceivable, then they are logically possible in Chalmers's sense.

    If zombies are logically possible, then the phenomenal does not logically

    supervene on the physical, because fixing the physical facts fails to fix the

    phenomenal facts. And if it does not logically supervene, it is not reductively

    explainable. Furthermore, Chalmers argues that parallel considerations show

    that phenomenal consciousness does not supervene on the chemical, the

    biological, or even the psychological facts, functionally construed, because fixing

    16Block defines a parallel notion of "phenomenal consciousness," though he uses a different

    method to characterize the concepts. See chapter 2 below, sections 2.2.1-2.2.3.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    45/279

    37

    those facts does not close off the conceivability of zombies. Thus, phenomenal

    consciousness is not reductively explainable.

    Chalmers second argument focuses on the possibility of the "inverted

    spectrum." The inverted spectrum is the possibility that two creatures can be

    physically identical, and yet have systematically inverted phenomenal

    experiences. Chalmers claims that it is conceivable that there could be physical

    duplicates, one that experienced phenomenal red when stimulated by an apple

    while the other experienced phenomenal green, despite the fact that the

    stimulations and the perceivers were physically identical. If this is conceivable,

    then by Chalmers's definition, it is logically possible. But, again, if it is logically

    possible, then logical supervenience fails. Holding the physical facts steady does

    not entail that the phenomenal facts are the same. And again, Chalmers claims

    that it is likewise conceivable that the phenomenal can vary despite holding the

    chemical, biological or the psycho-functional facts fixed. Thus, phenomenal

    consciousness cannot be reductively explained.

    The third case is somewhat different than the first two. Chalmers argues

    that there is an epistemic asymmetry between our knowledge of consciousness

    and our knowledge of other things, an asymmetry that is absent with reductively

    explainable phenomena. We know consciousness in an apparently direct and

    unmediated way. We don't seem to reason to its existence; it's simply given to

    us. But we do not know the conscious minds of other creatures in this way, and

    furthermore, we can reasonably wonder if they are conscious at all. The

    asymmetry is reflected in the so-called problem of other minds. Chalmers writes,

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    46/279

    38

    "Even when we know everything physical about other creatures, we do not know

    for certain that they are conscious, or what their experiences are..." (1996, 102).

    There is no parallel problem of "other lives" or "other economies." The physical

    facts close off these possibilities. Chalmers argues that this shows that

    consciousness does not logically supervene on the physical. If it did, there would

    be no such asymmetry present; we would be able to infer the presence of other

    minds from the physical facts. But there is no such logical entailment, logical

    supervenience fails, and thus consciousness is not reductively explainable.

    The fourth case involves the so-called "knowledge argument" against

    physicalism (Nagel 1974; Jackson 1982). The argument features Mary, the

    color-deprived super-scientist. By hypothesis, Mary knows all the facts of a

    completed science, but has never seen red. Eventually, she gets her first

    glimpse of red. The question is, does she learn anything new? Chalmers

    argues that even though she has all the physical facts, Mary lacks the facts about

    what it is like to see red. She learns these facts upon her release. Thus, the

    physical facts do not entail facts about what it is like to see red. But these are

    just the phenomenal facts about red. So the physical facts do not entail the

    phenomenal facts, logical supervenience fails, and thus phenomenal

    consciousness is not reductively explainable.

    Finally, Chalmers argues that the absence of an analysis that seems in

    any way amenable to reduction directly undermines logical supervenience. He

    contends,

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    47/279

    39

    For consciousness to be entailed by a set of physical facts, one would

    need some kind of analysis of the notion of consciousness--the kind of

    analysis whose satisfaction physical facts could imply--and there is no

    such analysis to be had (1996, 104).

    The natural candidate for a reductive analysis is a functional analysis. But

    Chalmers argues that functional analyses of phenomenal consciousness all miss

    the phenomenon, and so in effect change the subject. He notes that functional

    analyses have the implausible effect of dissolving the problem of consciousness.

    Indeed, if a functional analysis is correct, why did we think there was a problem

    at all? Further, Chalmers argues that simply adopting a functional analysis for

    the sake of avoiding the problem is ad hoc. He writes, "One might well define

    'world peace' as 'a ham sandwich.' Achieving world peace becomes much

    easier, but it is a hollow achievement" (1996, 105).

    He also notes that functional analyses possess a degree of indeterminacy

    that seems lacking in the phenomenal case. While there may be vague borders

    for the extension of the functionally analyzable concept "life," for example,

    Chalmers claims that phenomenal consciousness is plausibly an all or nothing

    affair. To the extent that he is correct, functional analyses cannot capture the

    phenomenal. Finally, Chalmers argues that it is unclear what other sort of

    analysis could provide the needed link to the physical facts. Consciousness may

    in fact be correlated with some biochemical property in us, but this fact does not

    underwrite an analysis of "consciousness," nor does it illuminate how the

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    48/279

    40

    physical might entail the phenomenal. Thus, consciousness does not logically

    supervene on the physical, and thus cannot be reductively explained.

    The failure of phenomenal consciousness to logically supervene on the

    physical (or the chemical, biological, functional, etc.) leaves us with an

    explanatory problem. No matter what we find out about the physical and

    functional basis of the mind, we are still left with an open question: why are

    these processes accompanied by phenomenal experience? There is an

    explanatory gap between the physical and functional, and the phenomenal

    (Levine 1983, 1993, 2001). Many features of the mind succumb to the kind of

    reductive explanation detailed by Chalmers. Belief, desire, learning, and memory

    are all arguably amenable to functional analysis and reductive explanation, when

    considered as psychological concepts. However, phenomenal consciousness

    can't be so explained. Therefore, Chalmers concludes that consciousness poses

    a "hard problem" for scientific explanation. And, given the failure of

    supervenience, it follows that consciousness cannot be located in a materialist

    ontology.

  • 7/30/2019 Problem Consciousness

    49/279

    41

    1.2.3 Criticisms of Chalmers's view17

    Chalmers argues that materialism is committed to the claim that all the macro-

    level facts are a priori entailed by the microphysical facts. Thus, when presented

    with a possible microphysical description of the world, and armed with analyses

    of the relevant concepts, we should be able to a priori deduce the macro-level

    facts about that possible world. But any description in microphysical terms will

    be unreadable in practice. It will be far too long and complex to be of any use as

    a guide for us in deriving the relevant facts. Thus, Chalmers holds that such a

    priori reasoning is idealized: an ideal rational observer, with unlimited time and

    mental resources, could perform the derivation. This does not require any

    additional rational abilities; it requires only additional computing power and

    memory (Chalmers 1996, 68; Chalmers and Jackson 2001, 11).

    Furthermore, Chalmers holds that the relevant physical description need

    not be restricted to micro-level language. It can include

    information about the structure and dynamics of the world at the

    macroscopic level, at least insofar as this structure and dynamics can be

    17I will not here address Kripke-style counterarguments from a posteriori necessities, nor

    Chalmers's response employing 2-D modal logic. My criticisms are, I believe, independent ofthese issues, and apply even if Chalmers is correct about 2-D semantics. To briefly put thingsinto 2-D terms, I shall argue that the meaning of mental state terms like "consciousness" are opento revision, potentially altering the primary intension of those terms, This undermines theargument against reductive explanation, which relies on the primary intension of "consciousness"

    being stable in the face of empirical results. Further, I shall challenge the particular interpretationof "consciousness" offered by Chalmers. It is not, pace Chalmers, a term possessing the sameprimary and secondary intension; instead, it functions in much the same way as otherfunctionally-defined terms. There is a large and ever growing literature on the topic of 2-D modalsemantics. See Chalmers 1999, and commentaries; Block and Stalnaker 1999; and the 2004Philosophical Studies on 2-Dimensionalism, edited by Davies and Stoljar, for a start. See alsoLevin 1995. My thanks to Michael Levin for help in clarifying these points, and for helpfulcomm