1
LANDSAT/NASA Mark Buchanan W hen someone makes a ‘prediction’, he or she usually contends that a specific event will take place at some point in the future: it will rain tomorrow morning; an earthquake will shake the San Francisco area next Thursday. This is ‘prediction’ as we usu- ally define it. But in modern science, the idea of prediction has evolved subtler interpreta- tions, and the concept continues to develop today, as scientists grapple with phenomena of ever-greater complexity. By 700 BC, the Babylonians had devel- oped skill in predicting lunar eclipses; they understood their world better and feared it less, presumably, than earlier peoples did. Over the ensuing 2,500 years, science honed its ability to make accurate predictions, with Galileo, Kepler and finally Newton bringing the world’s mechanistic pre- dictability to centre stage. In the newtonian Universe, as Pierre-Simon Laplace pointed out, a being of sufficient intelligence could predict the future in detail by knowing the positions and velocities of all particles at any moment. Today, we casually use the term ‘predic- tion’ in a slightly more general sense. One might predict that a new material will be superconducting below 40 K, or that a mouse that lacks a certain gene will show a particu- lar trait. Such predictions always precede their experimental test, yet aim less to foretell the future than to explore scientific under- standing. Prediction in this sense is the engine of science: we design the present (the experiment) and observe the future (the result) so as to compare our theories to empirical reality. A more interesting twist to the idea arises when forecasting in the newtonian sense is impossible. No one can solve the equations of motion for the 10 24 particles in a bucket of water, nor would such a solution be useful. For this reason, Boltzmann, Maxwell and other physicists of the nineteenth century executed a strategic retreat to ‘prediction’ in a weaker sense. One can predict the statistical distribution of molecular velocities in the bucket. Foregoing exact knowledge, statisti- cal mechanics also predicts the likelihood of the 10 24 molecules being in any particular microscopic state. Strikingly, acquiescence to probabilities at this level yields definite predictions at the higher collective level — we can predict that the water will be solid below 0 7C, for example. More recently, quantum physics has taken statistical prediction as a fundamental concept, and the idea has also entered the study of chaotic systems, for which detailed prediction is impossible over long periods. Climate scientists refrain from making pre- cise predictions, instead exploring ‘scenar- ios’, which effectively project a probable increase in global mean temperature of 1.4–5.8 7C by the year 2100. Earth scientists similarly find it useful to communicate their knowledge to the public by predicting the probability of an earthquake in a given window of space, time and magnitude. Today we are so used to statistical predictions that it is difficult to appreciate the profundity of this retreat into probabilities. Yet a retreat into statistics does not imply an abandonment of the search for meaning- ful regularities. Indeed, this search lies at the heart of recent studies of ‘complex systems’. Such systems frequently involve many inter- acting parts that achieved their current orga- nization through a process of evolution. We might think, for example, of a food web, or the intricate tree-like network of streams and tributaries that make up the drainage basin of a great river. In each case, accidental events — such as the chance extinction of a species — have lasting consequences for the system. As with biological evolution, one might replay the ‘tape of history’ many times and never twice obtain the same result, as the outcome depends on innumerable fine details that lie beyond scientific scrutiny. For such systems, one might sensibly wonder whether there is anything to pre- dict. Yet for river drainage basins, studies have identified a well-defined fractal struc- ture — in a statistical sense, river networks exhibit a degree of self-similarity, with small portions of the network being rough copies of larger portions. All drainage basins appear to be alike in this respect, regardless of differences in geography and the many accidents of history that deter- mined their precise structure. Moreover, this ‘law-like’ feature seems to emerge as the inevitable result of a dynamic process that minimizes the dissipation of energy. Given this theoretical understanding, it is possible to predict the expected fractal char- acter of any newly discovered basin. An ero- sion basin recently identified on the surface of Mars appears to validate this prediction. For complex systems, many macroscopic details may indeed be unpredictable; yet predictable statistical regularities may lie hidden behind these details. Recent work on complex net- works underlines this point, illuminating deep similarities between the structure of sys- tems as diverse as social networks, the Inter- net and the biochemistry of the cell. The idea of prediction may have still fur- ther implications for the study of evolution. As the physicist Giorgio Parisi has argued, it may be that for some systems of biological interest — cells, or even large proteins — it will never be possible to predict the proper- ties of individual systems. Science may instead retreat further, making predictions that can be confirmed only by studying the statistics of many cells or proteins, for exam- ple. Such an approach may seem to under- mine the search for detailed understanding, yet freedom in interpreting the concept of ‘prediction’ will continue to broaden the scope and power of science. Mark Buchanan is a science writer based in the United Kingdom. FURTHER READING Rodríguez-Iturbe, I. & Rinaldo, A. Fractal River Basins (Cambridge Univ. Press, 1999). Albert, R. & Barabási, A.-L. Rev. Mod. Phys. 74, 47 (2002). Caldarelli, G., De Los Rios, P. & Montuori, M. Published online at http://xxx.arxiv.cornell.edu/abs/cond-mat/ 0107228 Parisi, G. Physica A 263, 557–564 (1999). A game of chance concepts NATURE | VOL 419 | 24 OCTOBER 2002 | www.nature.com/nature 787 Prediction Today we are so used to statistical predictions that it is difficult to appreciate the profundity of this retreat into probabilities. Twisting tail: the delta of the Lena River in Russia reveals its intricate and convoluted structure. © 2002 Nature Publishing Group

Prediction: A game of chance

  • Upload
    mark

  • View
    213

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Prediction: A game of chance

LAN

DSA

T/N

ASA

Mark Buchanan

When someone makes a ‘prediction’, heor she usually contends that a specificevent will take place at some point in

the future: it will rain tomorrow morning; anearthquake will shake the San Francisco areanext Thursday. This is ‘prediction’ as we usu-ally define it. But in modern science, the ideaof prediction has evolved subtler interpreta-tions, and the concept continues to developtoday, as scientists grapple with phenomenaof ever-greater complexity.

By 700 BC, the Babylonians had devel-oped skill in predicting lunar eclipses; theyunderstood their world better and feared itless, presumably, than earlier peoples did.Over the ensuing 2,500 years, science honedits ability to make accurate predictions,with Galileo, Kepler and finally Newtonbringing the world’s mechanistic pre-dictability to centre stage. In the newtonianUniverse, as Pierre-Simon Laplace pointedout, a being of sufficient intelligence couldpredict the future in detail by knowing thepositions and velocities of all particles atany moment.

Today, we casually use the term ‘predic-tion’ in a slightly more general sense. Onemight predict that a new material will be

superconducting below 40 K, or that a mousethat lacks a certain gene will show a particu-lar trait. Such predictions always precedetheir experimental test, yet aim less to foretellthe future than to explore scientific under-standing. Prediction in this sense is theengine of science: we design the present (theexperiment) and observe the future (theresult) so as to compare our theories toempirical reality.

A more interesting twist to the idea ariseswhen forecasting in the newtonian sense isimpossible. No one can solve the equationsof motion for the 1024 particles in a bucket ofwater, nor would such a solution be useful.For this reason, Boltzmann, Maxwell andother physicists of the nineteenth centuryexecuted a strategic retreat to ‘prediction’ in aweaker sense. One can predict the statisticaldistribution of molecular velocities in thebucket. Foregoing exact knowledge, statisti-cal mechanics also predicts the likelihood ofthe 1024 molecules being in any particularmicroscopic state. Strikingly, acquiescenceto probabilities at this level yields definitepredictions at the higher collective level —we can predict that the water will be solidbelow 0 7C, for example.

More recently, quantum physics hastaken statistical prediction as a fundamentalconcept, and the idea has also entered thestudy of chaotic systems, for which detailedprediction is impossible over long periods.Climate scientists refrain from making pre-cise predictions, instead exploring ‘scenar-ios’, which effectively project a probableincrease in global mean temperature of1.4–5.8 7C by the year 2100. Earth scientistssimilarly find it useful to communicate theirknowledge to the public by predicting theprobability of an earthquake in a given window of space, time and magnitude.Today we are so used to statistical predictionsthat it is difficult to appreciate the profundityof this retreat into probabilities.

Yet a retreat into statistics does not implyan abandonment of the search for meaning-ful regularities. Indeed, this search lies at theheart of recent studies of ‘complex systems’.Such systems frequently involve many inter-acting parts that achieved their current orga-nization through a process of evolution. Wemight think, for example, of a food web, orthe intricate tree-like network of streams andtributaries that make up the drainage basinof a great river. In each case, accidental events— such as the chance extinction of a species— have lasting consequences for the system.As with biological evolution, one mightreplay the ‘tape of history’ many times andnever twice obtain the same result, as theoutcome depends on innumerable fine

details that lie beyond scientific scrutiny. For such systems, one might sensibly

wonder whether there is anything to pre-dict. Yet for river drainage basins, studieshave identified a well-defined fractal struc-ture — in a statistical sense, river networksexhibit a degree of self-similarity, withsmall portions of the network being roughcopies of larger portions. All drainagebasins appear to be alike in this respect,regardless of differences in geography andthe many accidents of history that deter-mined their precise structure. Moreover,this ‘law-like’ feature seems to emerge as theinevitable result of a dynamic process thatminimizes the dissipation of energy.

Given this theoretical understanding, it ispossible to predict the expected fractal char-acter of any newly discovered basin. An ero-sion basin recently identified on the surface ofMars appears to validate this prediction. Forcomplex systems, many macroscopic detailsmay indeed be unpredictable; yet predictablestatistical regularities may lie hidden behindthese details. Recent work on complex net-works underlines this point, illuminatingdeep similarities between the structure of sys-tems as diverse as social networks, the Inter-net and the biochemistry of the cell.

The idea of prediction may have still fur-ther implications for the study of evolution.As the physicist Giorgio Parisi has argued, itmay be that for some systems of biologicalinterest — cells, or even large proteins — itwill never be possible to predict the proper-ties of individual systems. Science mayinstead retreat further, making predictionsthat can be confirmed only by studying thestatistics of many cells or proteins, for exam-ple. Such an approach may seem to under-mine the search for detailed understanding,yet freedom in interpreting the concept of‘prediction’ will continue to broaden thescope and power of science. ■

Mark Buchanan is a science writer based in theUnited Kingdom.

FURTHER READINGRodríguez-Iturbe, I. & Rinaldo, A. Fractal River Basins(Cambridge Univ. Press, 1999).Albert, R. & Barabási, A.-L. Rev. Mod. Phys. 74,47 (2002).Caldarelli, G., De Los Rios, P. & Montuori, M. Publishedonline at http://xxx.arxiv.cornell.edu/abs/cond-mat/0107228Parisi, G. Physica A 263, 557–564 (1999).

A game of chanceconcepts

NATURE | VOL 419 | 24 OCTOBER 2002 | www.nature.com/nature 787

PredictionToday we are so used to statisticalpredictions that it is difficult toappreciate the profundity of thisretreat into probabilities.

Twisting tail: the delta of the Lena River in Russiareveals its intricate and convoluted structure.

© 2002 Nature Publishing Group