17
[T] Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015 Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 1 [I] Aspectos políticos na filosofia de Hans Blumenberg [I] Felix Heidenreich * Universität Stuttgart, Internationales Zentrum für Kultur und Technikforschung (IZKT), Stuttgart, Germany [R] Abstract The scientific community in the humanities agrees that the work of the German post- -war philosopher Hans Blumenberg is fascinating, compelling and inspiring, although the texts remain to some extent hard to understand. His extensive exchange with au- thors like Carl Schmitt, Jacob Taubes or Hannah Arendt show the often forgotten and so- metimes systematically hidden political aspects of his philosophy. The theory of moder- nity, the theory of myth and of course his metaphorology are the main areas of debate 1 This paper is meant to be a first presentation of the political implications of Blumenberg’s writings and has been formulated for the general academic reader who is not necessarily a specialist on Blumenberg. It is based on publications in German which tackled the question of Blumenberg’s political thought in different contexts. The constant dialogue with Angus Nicholls has played a very important role concerning my views; our common interpretations are explored in more detail in the “Nachwort” of our common edition of “Präfiguration”. * FH: PhD, e-mail: [email protected] DOI: 10.7213/aurora.27.041.DS06 ISSN 0104-4443 Licenciado sob uma Licença Creative Commons

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    3

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

[T]

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

[I]Aspectos políticos na filosofia de Hans Blumenberg

[I]

Felix Heidenreich*

Universität Stuttgart, Internationales Zentrum für Kultur und Technikforschung (IZKT), Stuttgart, Germany

[R]Abstract

The scientific community in the humanities agrees that the work of the German post-

-war philosopher Hans Blumenberg is fascinating, compelling and inspiring, although

the texts remain to some extent hard to understand. His extensive exchange with au-

thors like Carl Schmitt, Jacob Taubes or Hannah Arendt show the often forgotten and so-

metimes systematically hidden political aspects of his philosophy. The theory of moder-

nity, the theory of myth and of course his metaphorology are the main areas of debate

1 This paper is meant to be a first presentation of the political implications of Blumenberg’s writings and has been formulated for the general academic reader who is not necessarily a specialist on Blumenberg. It is based on publications in German which tackled the question of Blumenberg’s political thought in different contexts. The constant dialogue with Angus Nicholls has played a very important role concerning my views; our common interpretations are explored in more detail in the “Nachwort” of our common edition of “Präfiguration”.

* FH: PhD, e-mail: [email protected]

DOI: 10.7213/aurora.27.041.DS06 ISSN 0104-4443Licenciado sob uma Licença Creative Commons

Page 2: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

HEIDENREICH, F.524

which can be checked for their political implications and ramifications. However, the a

priori exclusion of republican arguments and ideas points to a systematic problem in

Blumenberg’s thought. All his thinking remains in the framework of what has been cal-

led “subject-philosophy”, it seems. While his early publications allowed a certain critique

of ideology (from the perspective of metaphorology), this gesture almost disappears in

his later writings. It is basically the single subject which works on myth, which seems

to project “significance” (Bedeutsamkeit) into the world, which makes sense of his life in

anecdotes. However, human self-assertion is always a common project, an inherited te-

chnique which creates not only myths but also institutions and law. The political aspects

in Blumenberg’s work therefore also make transparent the limitations of his thought.[P]

Keywords: Modernity. Self-assertion. Legitimacy. Metaphors. Political myth.[B]

Resumo

A comunidade científica no contexto das humanidades concorda que o trabalho do filósofo do

pós-guerra Hans Blumenberg é fascinante, convincente e inspirador, mesmo seus textos sendo,

de certa forma, difíceis de compreender. Seu extenso diálogo com autores como Carl Schmitt,

Jacob Taubes ou Hannah Arendt mostra o quão frequentemente os aspectos políticos de sua

filosofia são esquecidos, ou mesmo sistematicamente ocultados. A teoria da modernidade, a

teoria do mito e, claro, sua metaforologia são as principais áreas de debate que podem ser

avaliadas por suas implicações e ramificações políticas. No entanto, a exclusão a priori dos ar-

gumentos e das ideias republicanas aponta para um problema sistemático no pensamento de

Blumenberg. Parece que todo o seu pensamento permanece no quadro daquela que foi apeli-

dada de “filosofia do sujeito”. Embora suas primeiras publicações permitam uma certa crítica

da ideologia (na perspectiva da metaforologia), esse gesto quase desaparece das obras mais

tardias. É essencialmente apenas o sujeito singular que trabalha no mito, que parece projetar

“significância” (Bedeutsamkeit) no mundo, que dá sentido a sua vida em anedotas. No entan-

to, a autoafirmação humana é sempre um projeto comum, uma técnica herdada que cria não

apenas mitos, mas também instituições e leis. Por conseguinte, os aspetos políticos no trabalho

de Blumenberg também tornam transparentes as limitações de seu pensamento. [K]Palavras-chave: Modernidade. Autoafirmação. Legitimidade. Metáfora. Mito político.

Page 3: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 525

Introduction: Blumenberg and Politics?

The work of the German philosopher Hans Blumenberg is today intensely read in German academia, translated into English, French and Spanish, discussed in books, articles and in conferences from Berlin, Heidelberg and Paris to Jerusalem. The scientific community in the humanities seems to agree that his thought is fascinating, compelling and inspiring, although the texts remain to some extent hard to under-stand. The theory of modernity, the theory of myth and of course his metaphorology are the main areas of debate which his books continue to influence. Many scholars from all over the world seek to put his arguments in dialogue with these contemporary discussions concern-ing the self-understanding of philosophy in the age of technology. As the publications from his archives are expected to continue for years, the research illuminating his controversies with extraordinary figures such as Carl Schmitt, Hans Jonas, Jacob Taubes or Hannah Arendt will be fed continuously. This philological work is sometimes wrongfully accused of being mere “Blumenbergology”; however it produces im-portant insights of philosophical relevance.

It is however often forgotten that Blumenberg’s work has been considered, in the late 1960s, to be of highly political ambition. As Anselm Haverkamp outlined in a debate in Heidelberg in September 2013, Blumenberg’s defense of Modernity — a direct attack on catholic anti-modern mainstream in Adenauer’s Germany — was seen as a left-wing project fitting perfectly well with the ideas of the other heroes of the early “Suhrkamp-culture” such as Jürgen Habermas. However, Blumenberg’s following books made clear that his work did not at all address contemporary political issues. While Habermas was discuss-ing the reform of the German university system, the possible collapse of capitalism, the ramifications of technological progress, Blumenberg seemed to focus on the history of Modernity in general (with a special interest in William of Ockham). His enormous work includes only one article which directly treats a political topic, a brief text on the concept of state (cf. BLUMENBERG, 1968). While Habermas constantly put into dialogue Political Theory and politics and gained a role as a leading

Page 4: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

HEIDENREICH, F.526

political intellectual, Blumenberg seemed to retreat into the almost private life of theological erudition, strict phenomenological research and philosophical interpretation of literature and anecdotes. Although he held a chair denominated for “Practical Philosophy”, he was, as Barbara Recki recently pointed out, known for claiming that “morality is what does not need to be discussed” (RECKI, 2015). In the German context in particular, this thought seems to express a hope, not to state a fact. Nowhere had it become more evident that morality cannot be simply taken for granted, as Blumenberg’s saying suggests. It is not a surprise, therefore, that Blumenberg is often considered to avoid the political dimensions of his topics.

However, as the research on Blumenberg continues and our pic-ture of his thinking is more and more nuanced, it becomes clear, that he approaches political issues in a very indirect, sometimes almost hidden way. In this paper I would like to outline in what way these political aspects of his work can be detected, where they are hidden and whom they contradict implicitly. I shall first of all recall the political dimen-sion of his thinking, beginning with his theory of modernity (2), to his theory of Myth (3), to his conception of rhetorics and anthropology (4). I will than conclude by sketching his thought as a liberalism of distance and discuss the questions un-answered in his work (5). The exclusion of the sphere of law in his thought proves to be a decisive indicator for the limitations of his philosophy, I claim.

The way modernity produces legitimacy

The book on the Legitimacy of the Modern Age today appears to be fighting a battle which seems to be over. Today, the legitimacy of mo-dernity is rejected only by actors and schools of thought which seem to be beyond the limits of reasonable disagreement: Islamic wahabites and salafists, Russian nationalists, minor catholic groups such as the Brotherhood of Pius continue to fight modernization, but in intellectu-al discourse they do not appear at all, not even as objects of philosophi-cal scrutiny, thereby forming a kind of “toxic other”. Today, we could

Page 5: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 527

state, anti-modernism is “not even wrong”. Re-reading Blumenberg’s classic of German post-war thought hence quickly makes clear that his first great book is not just a historical theory of the genesis of mo-dernity. All the decisive terms of this book have a political dimension: legitimacy, secularization, absolutism, self-assertion. Blumenberg not only reconstructs the way in which modern functionalist rationality arose from a specific development in scholastic philosophy. He also empha-sizes the self-foundational character of modern thought, its truly post-gnostic “grammar” (in the sense of Witttgenstein’s later thought).

In the early 1960s Blumenberg’s defense of modernity faced two opposed schools of thought which attacked modernity from two dif-ferent angles. On the one hand, a whole series of conservative, even reactionary thinkers claimed that modernity should be considered a failure — at least if evaluated in total. Modern individualism, modern moral pluralism, modern science, modern self-referential law: all these core-elements of modernization, from their point of view, had guided mankind into apocalyptical disaster of world-wara, genocide and the narcissism of Western mass-consumption culture. Martin Heidegger and Carl Schmitt were probably the most evident examples of this line of thought. Whereas in the case of Carl Schmitt the anti-democratic and anti-semitic elements of his world-view were evident from the start, in the case of Martin Heidegger only the recent publication of the “Black Notebooks” made any attempt to defend him vain.

Heidegger had presented himself with elaborated means of self-mystification as a guardian of an ancient, pre-Socratic wisdom. Blumenberg had already in his “Habilitationsschrift” formulated a convincing critique of Heidegger’s “History of Being” 2. Heidegger had attributed the two main stances a human mind could take in relation to the world to different authors and epochs in the history of Being: a) “Being-in” or “In-ständigkeit”, referring to a self-forgotten involve-ment into the world experienced for example in concentrated work, on the one hand, and b) “Calculating thought” or “Gegen-ständigkeit” on

2 Die ontologische Distanz, unpublished manuscript finished in Kiel in 1950, accessible through the system of German university-libraries.

Page 6: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

HEIDENREICH, F.528

the other hand, naming a objectifying attitude aiming at the world as pure object of manipulation and exploitation. While some pre-Socratic thinkers, the scholastic heretic Master Eckhart and the romantic poet Friedrich Holderlin were qualified as acceptable predecessors of the master-philosopher himself, Plato, Descartes and at a specific moment in his thinking even Husserl were qualified as purely objectifying think-ers who had forgotten about Being and thereby expressed the deeper fate of the European history of power-seeking thought. The anti-Semtic elements of this crude history of European thought have only recently become public by the publication of Heidegger’s “black notebooks”.

Blumenberg rejected this view and claimed that the two pos-sible stances should be considered as two possible modes that could and actually are taken by all humans depending on their situation and its constraints. When Blumenberg tried to show that self-assertion is a legitimate reaction of man facing a world of contingeny and dan-ger, this argument therefore indirectly addressed Heidegger’s roman-tic celebration of the pre-modern world: Modern technology, we can conclude, is not just a sign of a modern egocentrism but the legitimate answer of a creature forced to defend itself against a merciless Nature. Heidegger’s attack on modernity therefore looks like a regression into a gnostic pattern–an interpretation Hans Jonas had developed early on and which Blumenberg, a close friend of Jonas’, had outlined in the chapters on Heidegger in his book “Cave Exits” (Höhlenausgänge)3.

Whereas Heidegger always strengthened the difference between pre-modern and modern thought — in his bizarre view, modernity actually begins with Plato and his re-interpretation of truth (a-letheia) as correctness (orthotês)4 — Carl Schmitt criticized modernity for hav-ing occupied an illegitimate pre-modern heritage. Modernity can only pretend to be modern, he claimed. The term “secularization” is conse-quently loaded with a very specific meaning: Carl Schmitt considered modern state-law to be the result of a process of transformation (and

3 I propose a more detailed interpretation of Blumenberg’s view on Gnosis in an article entitled “Unvermittelte Gegensätze: Blumenbergs Analyse des gnostischen Denkens”, to be published in a volume edited by Melanie Möller.

4 See his article on the conception of truth in Plato.

Page 7: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 529

perversion) of catholic theology. Where theology attributed “sover-eignty” to the one God capable of a creation ex nihilo, modern state-law has to hide by all kinds of strategies the inevitable foundation of its system in the sovereign, voluntaristic act of a person willing to take power. These strategies make modern political thought a kind of a zombie of catholic theology, pretending to be something (self-founda-tional, democratic, “fair”, rational etc.) which it can never really be. The foundation of politics will always be an irrational act, expressing a will to power, Schmitt argued. Authority creates truth and “reason”, not the other way around. He consequently openly had declared and explained his hate and disgust towards modern parliamentarianism which he considered to be an attempt to sidestep the necessity of deci-sion. His engagement for National-Socialism was just the logical con-sequence of his anti-liberalism and anti-modernism.

Blumenberg opposed this view with a theory of concepts which contradicted the essentialist idea of a given meaning (e.g. “sovereig-nity”). Referring to Cassirer and his idea of “functionalist concepts” (Funktionsbegriff), he claims that in the new context of modernity, old terms can take a truly new meaning: modern political thought may sound like catholic theology; but all the terms follow a completely new logic, because they now a part of a different language-game. Legitimacy e.g. is attributed by evaluating the results, not by considering the origin (of a person, an institution or an idea): Whereas in pre-modern societ-ies may ask a stranger “Where do you come from?” or “Who are you?”, in modern societies a typical question would be “What do you do in Life?”, thereby addressing a performance. Not where you come from defines your essence, but what you do, what you achieve, how you perform. In that sense, Modernity is not only legitimate, as the title of Blumenberg’s book claims, but it also produces a new kind of (func-tionalist) legitimacy which could be summed up: Whatever works! Pragmatism therefore is genuinely modern and Modernity genuinely an Age of pragmatism.

The letters exchanged between Carl Schmitt and Hans Blumenberg may, on the surface, appear to be a friendly dialogue be-tween two well-educated German professors, full of allusions to their

Page 8: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

HEIDENREICH, F.530

enormous erudition. A closer look shows, I think, that these letters con-stitute a calibrated dance of two radical opponents, a dance in which Blumenberg fires strong ammunition against Schmitt while hiding this aggression in a very fine irony which is hard to detect.

Whereas his book on modernity highlights the authentic charac-ter of modernity, its autonomy and truly innovative logic, Blumenberg’s book Work on Myth from 1979 seems to take another perspective. His most important opponent here seems to be a self-interpretation of mo-dernity which claim the overcoming of pre-modern myth in a once-and-for-all-manner. From Myth to Logos — a formular used by the famous specialist of Greek thought Wilhelm Nestle — is the scheme which needs to be contradicted, Blumenberg argues. Myth can never be completely overcome, he claims.

Myth, Polytheism and Tolerance

The debates in the group Poetik und Hermeneutik had already in the late 1960s focused on myth and terror; ten years before publishing Work on Myth Blumenberg had defended myth as a polytheistic and therefore more tolerant version of pre-modern ways of dealing with contingency (BLUMENBERG, 1971). Already back then, Blumenberg’s paper had provoked passionate contradiction, which shouldn’t sur-prise us since the mythical character of National-Socialism was far too obvious (cf. NICHOLLS, 2015)5. In 1979 Blumenberg makes almost the same claims about the tolerant character of myth, excluding almost completely the intense debates he had with Jacob Taubes concern-ing the intolerant myth of Gnostic thought and — more importantly maybe, from the point of view of Jacob Taubes, who was also a Rabbi — the tolerant and rational character of monotheism, and Judaism in particular. Praising polytheism for its absence of moral bigotry was a Nietzschean gesture which had to look suspicious.

5 Angus Nicholls shows in detail in what way these questions played an outstanding role in Blumenberg’s life and intellectual biography.

Page 9: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 531

It is evident that as Blumenberg emphasizes the tolerant char-acter of polytheistic myth, his defense of a “separation of powers” at the same time takes the side of a liberal, power-taming conception of a modern state. This state would have to limit its capacities to rule the citizens, and have all his activities counter-checked in a system of a balance of power. Looking back at this debate, it is however astonish-ing that Blumenberg never really discusses possible objections to his view, Taubes being the author of the most important ones. In Work on Myth Blumenberg claims “Everything the dogma demands, myth will do without”. When taking into account the case of the dogmatic myth as it can be observed in the Gnostic texts, one could wonder if Blumenberg’s statement can be defended. If we re-interpret the term of myth as a kind of collective imaginary, the binding power of the imagi-nary — as Castoriadis had shown at great length — cannot be denied.

The discussion on the excluded dimension of political myth — a subject almost absent in the published version of Work on Myth — has been boosted by the publication of a chapter entitled “Prefiguration” which Blumenberg apparently had written for the book and than excluded (BLUMENBERG, 2014). As the chapter discusses mainly Hitler’s mythical thinking, it can be suggested that Blumenberg final-ly decided that he did not want to give room to Hitler in a book main-ly talking about Goethe, the deeply adored hero of the German intel-lectual class in general and Blumenberg in particular. In this chapter, Blumenberg describes Goebbels’ and Hitler’s thinking as deeply rooted in mythical, almost magical ideas of providence and fulfill-ment: Hitler thought of himself as the promised savior of the German people who came to fulfill what has been announced in the deeds of Alexander the Great, Napoleon or Frederick II of Prussia. The case of this excluded chapter, destined to be part of Work on Myth, then hidden in the archives for reasons hard to figure out, appears to be emblematic of the way Blumenberg bypasses political topics or even political aspects of his subjects.

Whereas “prefiguration” seems to argue that mythical thought will always have fatal consequences in politics, Blumenberg’s re-marks on Hannah Arendt and her analysis of Adolf Eichmann take

Page 10: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

HEIDENREICH, F.532

the opposite position (BLUMENBERG, 2015). Arendt had argued that the kidnapping of Eichmann in Argentina by the Israeli secret service, his trial in Jerusalem and finally his execution operated as a political myth, a deceptive personification of evil, a mythical foundation of the Nation of Israel. In her view, Eichmann was not the mastermind, the evil murderer of the Jewish people, but an astonishingly stupid person, following his orders, not capable of understanding what he was doing. “Eichman was breath-takingly stupid” (ARENDT; FEST, 2011), she wrote to a friend in Germany. The research undertaken by Elisabeth Stangneth allows us today to see that Arendt was fundamen-tally wrong about Eichmann (cf. STANGNETH, 2014). He had system-atically planned how to present himself in the event that he were to be caught, preparing to play the role of a stupid bureaucrat. Moreover, he had continued to be a hateful anti-Semite after 1945 and tried system-atically to build a network of Nazis in Latin America. Eichmann was all but stupid; in contrast to Arendt’s analysis we now have good reasons to consider him a vicious murderer and liar.

However, Blumenberg’s critique of Arendt could not, in the 1960’s, take into account what we know today. His most important argument is the following: Even if the trial in Jerusalem and the con-demnation of Eichmann were to be considered to be a political myth, the young state of Israel would have all the right to produce and use this myth. Exposed to imminent threat, questioned by many states in the region, desperately trying to integrate Jews coming from all the corners of the earth, the young nation of Israel needed a political myth, Blumenberg claims. Arendt’s ignorance of this existential need dis-closes a fundamental lack of political prudence, an absence of politi-cal “faculty to judgement” (“Urteilksraft”), he argues. Arendt’s abstract critique of political myth might be right in general, but in this case her misunderstanding of the situation in Israel is rude, arrogant, unaccept-able. This perspective may today look like a harsh attack on an intel-lectual of great merit-back in the early 1960s this defense of Israel’s per-spective was — in the USA more so than in Germany — a mainstream position, based however on a specific theory of myth.

Page 11: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 533

Rhetorics and political anthropology

The case of the critique of Arendt (unpublished in his lifetime due to the respect he had for Arendt’s close friend Hans Jonas) makes it clear that Blumenberg was following daily politics very closely. It is known that he was a passionate reader of newspapers; we find many traces of this daily reading in his Archives and in some of his publica-tions. His political views can however only be detected very rarely in his publications. Two brief essays show in what way Blumenberg op-posed Carl Schmitt’s conception of politics — defined as the distinction between friend and enemy — by defending the liberal idea of second-best solutions, rhetorical exchange instead of ultimate decisions, de-escalation instead of escalation. Blumenberg’s article about the genesis of the concept of the state (“Staatsbegriff”) and finds its climax when Blumenberg argues that the art of politics today is defined by the skill to delay decisions and moderate conflict by the means of rhetorical pat-terns (cf. BLUMENBERG, 1968, p. 144).

It seems obvious that this conception of politics has its particularly persuasive power if we take into account the situation in Germany at the end of the 1960s: as the conflict between the Soviet Union and the West could escalate at any given moment, keeping the Cold War under control was the major task of the hour. In addition to this international horizon even internally escalation seemed to threaten the young democracy of Western Germany: after 1968 the students’ movement which had started out as a wave of protest against the war in Vietnam now continued to make life in universities difficult. Defending the art of a time request-ing rhetoric which uses specific techniques and topologies was therefore meant to contradict a political movement which tried to operate mainly with “happenings”, sit-ins, demonstrations, action.

His theory of rhetoric as an art of delaying final decisions and civilizing discourse (by making it more sophisticated, maybe even boring) is put into a larger context of a philosophical anthropol-ogy in a later article: In his essay “Anthropologische Annäherung an die Aktualität der Rhetorik” (1971) he tries to show that man, by his

Page 12: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

HEIDENREICH, F.534

nature-given condition, is condemned to compensate his weakness by means of ‘technique’ (in a larger sense) — such as rhetoric. Referring to the anthropological thesis of Arnold Gehlen — not an author to be quoted without reserve, to put it politely — Blumenberg explains that rhetoric can be considered not as an art of deception, but, as long as the listeners are well educated in rhetoric, as a medium of getting to terms even in case of conflict. This conception is not only a far more humble version of Habermas’ “communicative reason”, but quite in contrast it expresses the idea that human reason will always continue to be a compensating tool, a way of dealing with a complex world uninter-ested in the survival of Man and Mankind. Blumenberg’s conception of reason therefore could be described as a theory of muddling-through, using analogies, metaphors, rhetoric, whatever helps in order to get to terms with life. In contrast to Habermas’ conception of deliberative reasoning, Blumenberg’s concept of rhetorical reason does not imply the necessity of a consensus. Habermas’ “public reasoning” has a coer-cive dimension; it produces at least the impression to have a telos, even if it does not actually have a telos in the Hegelian sense. Blumenberg in contrast to Habermas insists on the importance of replacing action with word. From his point of view, the major task can be described as follows: How to do nothing with words6.

The anthropological dimension of Blumenberg’s philosophy is obvious in all his publications, and although it is very present in Work on Myth, it is the book entitled “Beschreibung des Menschen” (Description of Man) which makes clear in what way anthropology (in the very specific sense of German philosophische Anthropologie) and politics are linked7. It is mainly in the second part of the book that Blumenberg outlines two elements of the human condition of extraordinary importance. His first argument consists in strengthening the idea of the “undefinedness” of Man — an intuition present in German philosophical anthropology from the 1920s on. The human being, Blumenberg claims, is paradoxi-cally determined by the fact that nature does not really determine him:

6 Blumenberg of course alludes to the famous book by J. L., How to do things with words. 7 The context is made perfectly transparent in Angus Nicholls’ book (2015).

Page 13: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 535

in contrast to animals he can choose and has to choose what to do in Life. Therefore all “naïve” philosophical anthropology which claims to conceive an “essence of man” is to be rejected. Blumenberg at least in this regard subscribes to the objections against Gehlen formulated in particular from the Frankfurt School. Adorno and Habermas had both contradicted authors like Gehlen by showing that Man cannot be reduced to a “natural essence” without excluding all the social and his-torical context so important from a Marxist point of view: workers or capitalists are different beings insofar as they are co-defined by their inclusion into a social class. Philosophical anthropology therefore runs the risk of producing pre-modern naturalizations.

Blumenberg however adds a special twist to this argument. He emphasizes the fact that humans strive towards very different goals in life. The openness or “undefinedness” of man renders comprehensible why the conceptions of the good life are so fundamentally different. This appears to be a rather trivial thesis; but Blumenberg gives this idea a po-litical spin: It is, he argues, this variety of goals in life which allows peo-ple to live together peacefully. If we were all seeking the same goals in life, civil war would break out. Only if our desires, dreams and aspirations are dispersed to a multitude of objects, careers and conceptions of success, mankind can avoid an escalation of concurrence. This idea implies a strik-ingly Anti-Aristotelean line of attack: If there is — hopefully — no common idea of euzên the polis does not play the same role as in antiquity and man is not a zoôn politikón. The contrast to neo-republican thinking often attributed to Arendt is obvious: Politics is not about acting together, but about protecting the mechanisms of distance.

The second important line of thought renders the consequences of this approach more transparent. After having formulated severe doubt concerning the possibility of a definition of the “essence of Man”, Blumenberg nevertheless gives a hint about what he considers to be a major difference between men and animals: man is, he states, a “being of distance” (Distanzwesen). In contrast to animals, Man can use stones, sticks, all kinds of means of intervention by distance, e.g. language, scripture etc. Whereas animals do not in the same way have the need and the capability to secure their life by instruments of prevention,

Page 14: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

HEIDENREICH, F.536

Men can bridge both special and temporal distance. The book of Paul Alsberg, The Puzzle of Humanity, serves Blumenberg as an important source of inspiration in this regard, as Angus Nicholls (2015, p. 11-121) has shown clearly. In Blumenberg’s descriptions man is sketched as an animal constantly seeking distance: distance from danger that might hit him out of the blue. Even his primitive weapons such as stones or sticks have their advantage in allowing to attack without being at-tacked at the same time.

Although this scenario looks plausible at first sight, one objec-tion is evident: Blumenberg does not refer to the fact that Man at the same time systematically longs for proximity, yes even intimacy. The erotic drive disappears in his conception and an evident plea could be to stress the simple fact that Man is also a “being of proximity”, pro-ducing great parts of his culture not to protect his distance form the world or from others but quite in contrast in order to bridge this dis-tance, to produce “resonance” (Hartmut Rosa) or gain “recognition” (Axel Honneth).

Let’s briefly focus more thoroughly on the political dimension of this anthropological argument: What exactly follows on the political level from a conception of man as a “Being of distance”? To put it as blunt as possible: only a liberal conception of a minimal community seems to fit with this idea of Man. Only a liberal framework (which secures the distance amongst the citizens and between the citizen and his state) will make sure that escalation can be prevented. Every citizen may strive for his individual conception of happiness — and help his fellow citizens by not intervening into their plans. The exclusion of all the erotic striving in man therefore produces an implicit rejection of all republican ideas: There is no res publica, Blumenberg lets us know, because there is no common idea of happiness. Rousseau’s volonté gé-nerale therefore must have looked like a fatal misconception of modern politics to Blumenberg, it seems. The best we can achieve is a politi-cal framework which allows everybody to follow their private aims as peacefully and distanced from the others as possible. Blumenberg’s po-litical thought can therefore be qualified as a “liberalism of distance”, I claim (cf. HEIDENREICH, 2011).

Page 15: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 537

The limitation in Blumenberg’s philosophy: From rhetorics to law

It is not hard to see that Blumenberg’s theory of man and culture has specific limitations. From the historical point of view of a German post-war situation, a liberal conception of the State seems perfectly convincing and rather typical for what has been called the “skepti-cal generation” (including such important figures as Odo Marquard). If we take into account what the contemporary options of political thought actually were in early post-war Germany — the range rank-ing from right-wing anti-liberalism of Heidegger, Carl Schmitt, Arnold Gehlen and Helmut Schelsky on the one hand radical anti-parliamen-tarist left of early Habermas and the Marxist left on the other hand — Blumenberg’s liberalism proves to be a brave defense of the rule of law, the civilizing effect of rhetorics, the thorough reflection of mythical ele-ments in politics and the fact of pluralism, to put it in Rawls’ terms.

However, the a priori exclusion of republican arguments and ideas at the same time points to a systematic problem in Blumenberg’s thought. All his thinking remains in the framework of what has been called “subject-philosophy”, it seems. While in his early publications concepts like “Concept of Reality” (Wirklichkeitsbegriff) seemed to allow a certain critique of ideology, this gesture almost disappears in his later writings. It is basically the single subject which works on myth, which seems to project “significance” (Bedeutsamkeit) into the world, which makes sense of his life in anecdotes. However, human self-assertion is always already (“toujours déjà”, Derrida would say) a common project, an inherited technique. And it has not only taken the form of myth and dogma, but also the form of Law.

It is, I have argued, astonishing that the question of law never really is discussed by Blumenberg (cf. HEIDENREICH, 2005). From a Hegelian point of view, law is the most obvious example of what he calls “objective spirit” (objektiver Geist), common cultural tools taking the form of a nature-like, undisputable being. Law, although a human product, addresses man as if it had a perfect objective character: al-though it is “constructed” and “produced”, it doesn’t disappear simply, because we do not believe in it anymore. It is “real” and therefore more

Page 16: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

HEIDENREICH, F.538

than just a myth, a metaphor or a “figure of significance”. The same is true, of course, of our institutions, namely the state. It is therefore sur-prising, that Blumenberg taught Hegel’s “Elements of the Philosophy of Right” while at the same time excluding the dimension of “objective spirit” almost completely from his books — “Prefiguration” being one important but unpublished example.

The exclusion of the dimension of law has severe consequences. Jürgen Habermas and Robert Brandom have — in very different theo-retical frameworks — showed the binding character of speech-acts. We would not have to agree with their very ambitious theories about the nature of reason to see that the production of myths, metaphors or rhe-torical arguments is not sufficiently understood if it is mistaken for an exclusively art-like activity. In this regard, Blumenberg remains very much in the Nietzschean tradition (an author extensively cited by the young Blumenberg, then more and more absent in his writings). As a defender of Modernity and a critic of positivism this is a strength, concerning the political dimension of his philosophy, it is a limitation.

References

ARENDT, H.; FEST, J. Eichmann war von empörender Dummheit: Gespräche und Briefe. München: Piper, 2011.

BLUMENBERG, H. Wirklichkeitsbegriff und Staatstheorie. Schweizer Monatshefte, n. 48, p. 121-146, 1968.

BLUMENBERG, H. Wirklichkeitsbegriff und Wirkungspotential des Mythos. In: FUHRMANN, M. (Hrsg.). Terror und Spiel: Probleme der Mythenrezeption. Munich: Fink, 1971.

BLUMENBERG, H. Präfiguration: Arbeit am politischen Mythos. Angus Nicholls and Felix Heidenreich [Hrsg]. Berlin: Suhrkamp, 2014.

BLUMENBERG, H. Rigorismus der Wahrheit: “Moses der Ägypter” und weitere Texte zu Freud und Arendt. Hrsg., kommentiert und mit einem Nachw. von Ahlrich Meyer. Berlin: Suhrkamp, 2015.

Page 17: Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy1

Rev. Filos., Aurora, Curitiba, v. 27, n. 41, p. 523-539, maio/ago. 2015

Political aspects in Hans Blumenberg’s philosophy 539

HEIDENREICH, F. Mensch und Moderne bei Hans Blumenberg. München: Fink, 2005.

HEIDENREICH, F. Ein Liberalismus der Distanz. Zu den ideenpolitischen Aspekten der phänomenologischen Anthropologie Blumenbergs. Journal Phänomenologie, n. 35, p. 52-65, 2011.

NICHOLLS, A. Myth and the Human Sciences: Hans Blumenberg’s Theory of Myth. New York; London: Routledge, 2015.

RECKI, B. Blumenbergs Absolutismen der Wirklichkeit. Merkur, n. 792, p. 28-41, 2015.

STANGNETH, B. Eichmann vor Jerusalem: Das unbehelligte Leben eines Massenmörders. Reinbek: Rowohlt, 2014.

Received: 06/05/2015Recebido: 05/06/2015

Approved: 06/28/2015Aprovado: 28/06/2015