PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    1/36

    SpecialIssue

    TheManyFatesofLegalPositivism

    CommentonPetroskiOnMacCormicksPostPositivismByThomasBustamante

    *

    A. Introduction

    In her thoughtprovoking paper Is PostPositivism Possible?, Karen Petroski argues thattherearecertaininstitutionalconditionsinthemodernsettingofscholarlyactivitythatmakepositivismtheinevitable(ornearlyinevitable)formoftheoreticalthinkingaboutthelaw. Furthermore, she also claims that there is nothing in Neil MacCormicks post

    positivismthatshouldleadustobelievethathislegaltheoryisqualitativelydifferentfrompositivism,whichaccording toPetroskiconstitutesthemainstreamAngloAmerican legalphilosophy. Herargument isthatthere isaparallelbetweenthecharacteristicsof lawand thecharacteristicsof the theoreticaldiscourseabout law.

    1 Law,as theobjectof

    legal theory,shareswith legaltheoretical inquiry (or,morebroadly,withmostacademicdiscoursesinthemodernsociety)someinstitutionalconditionsthatmakelegalpositivismnot merely a defensible mode of theorizing about the law, but an irresistible orinescapableone.

    2

    Even though thereareother interesting topics inPetroskispaper, Iwill concentrateondiscussingthesetwoclaims. Although Iamwell impressedbysomeofthearguments inPetroskispaper,Icannotshareherthesisthatlegaltheoryisconstrainedbysomesortof

    institutionalcontext,

    which

    rules

    out

    the

    possibility

    of

    post

    positivism

    (Petroskis

    first

    thesis),andIalsodoubtherclaimthatNeilMacCormickfailstoprovidearealalternativeto the current versions of legal positivism (Petroskis second thesis). In the followingsections Iarguethatthe firstthesisderivesbothfromtoostrictanunderstandingoftheroles of philosophy and legal scholarship and from a questionable description of thenecessary features of law. Moreover, I attempt to highlight some of the features ofMacCormicks latest legal theory that demonstrate that he moves beyond the limitedhorizonsofpositivism.

    *AdjunctProfessor,FederalUniversityofMinasGerais,Brazil.Email: [email protected]. Theauthorwouldlike to thankMtys Bdig, Tams Gyrfi, Scott Styles, Zenon Bakowski, Andrs Jakab, Karen Petroski, and

    AntonioCavalcantiMaiafortheirvaluablecommentsonpreviousdraftsofthispaper.

    1KarenPetroski,IsPostpositivismPossible?,12GERM.L.J.670(2011).

    2Id.at673.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    2/36

    [Vol.12No.02694 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lMyanalysisisstructuredinthefollowingway. Inthefirstpartofthepaper,dividedintwo

    sections, I summarize Petroskis main arguments for the alleged predominance ofpositivism in theAngloAmericancontextand for theclaim thatpostpositivism isnotarealalternativetothecontemporaryeffortsinthefieldoflegaltheory. InsectionB.I,Itryto determine the best interpretation of Petroskis argument to explain the connectionbetweenthefeaturesoflegaltheoryandthefeaturesoflegalpractice,whichaccordingtoherexplanationmakepositivismthemostattractivetypeoflegaltheory. InsectionB.II,Icriticizethisviewandattempttoelucidatethenatureoftheargumentsthatwecanfindinlegalphilosophy,aswellastherelationshipbetweensuchargumentsandthepracticeoflaw. InPartC, in turn, I focuson the specific criticisms thatPetroski addresses toNeilMacCormickspostpositivism. ThefirstsubsectionrestatesPetroskispointsagainstthelateversionofMacCormicksinstitutionaltheoryoflaw,andtheremainingofthepaperisdedicated to showing what answers in MacCormicks legal theory we could find to

    Petroskis

    criticisms.

    B. LegalScholarshipandLegalDiscourse

    I. PetroskisArgumentforthePredominanceofPositivism

    Petroski starts her argument for the first thesis by referring to an emerging literaturewhichargues that, sinceearlymoderndays, theacademicdomainhasbeenmoreandmore characterized by the policing of membership through extensive discursiveindoctrinationandtheevaluationofvariousformsofdiscursiveperformance.

    3 Sheclaims

    thatthemodernuniversityhassomedistinctivematerialandformalfeaturesthatimposeasetofconstraintsintheformsofknowledgeproducedwithinitsboundaries. Thoseactingwithin the institution of the modern university are depicted as depending on some

    externalsupportwhichcanonlybeachievedbytherecognitionofaspecialexpertisethatjustifies their activities to social actors outside the institutions. At the same time, theinstitutionalstructureisdescribedaslargelyselfreproducing,andsuchselfreproductionoccursprimarilythroughaspecialtypeofdiscourse.

    4 Thesefeaturesmakethestructure

    a competitive arena, and the resulting competition encourages academics to drawdistinctionsbetween theirpositionsand thoseof their forebearsandcontemporaries.

    5

    Thetypicalstrategyofacademicsinthesocialsciences,andinlawinparticular,wouldbetomakefractaldistinctionswhichencouragerhetoricalinnovationevenwhenatheoristisnottrulymakinganovelpoint.

    6

    3Id.at677.

    4Id.at678.

    5Id.at678.

    6Id.at678.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    3/36

    2011] 695CommentonPetroski

    Inasimilarway,thepracticallegaldiscourseismarkedbythesametypeofindoctrination.

    Liketheacademy,theargumentgoes,thesetoflegalinstitutionsisbothmateriallyandconceptually selfperpetuating. Materially,lawyersexpertise in thediscourseused tonavigatetheinstitutionsregulatingstatepowersensurestheircontinuedsupportbynonlawyers.

    7 On the formal level, in turn, lawyers adopt a theoretical perspectivewhich

    helpsthemtoexcludecertainreasonsforactionfromthesetofmaterialsavailableinlegalreasoning. Asintheacademicdomain,thisselfreferentialcharacteroflawtakesafractalform and creates a status hierarchy for the experts that master the nuances of legallanguage.

    Inmy reading Petroski argues that both the academic discourse and themodern legaldomain are selfreferential; dependant on some sort of indoctrination and fractaldistinctions;inneedofmasteringaspecialdiscoursewhichjustifytheiractivitiestoactors

    outside

    their

    realm;

    exclusive

    or

    certain

    reasons;

    and

    self

    perpetuating.

    But

    why

    are

    these

    common features relevant for the debate over postpositivism? How do these parallelfeaturesofeachoftheseintellectualdomainsinfluencetheother?

    Ifweacceptthatthereismorethanasimplehistoricalcoincidencebetweenthecharacterof legal theoretical inquiry and the features of legal discourse, then there are twoalternative interpretationsavailableforthisparallelbetween legalpracticeandacademicscholarship.

    Thefirst interpretationexplainsthedominanceofpositivismonthebasisofthefeaturesthat Petroski attributes to the legal practice. At first sight, the author appears to befollowingthisroute inthebeginningofthesecondsectionofherpaper. Nevertheless,ifwe look closely enoughwe can see that any attempt to explain the features of legal

    theorysacademicdiscourseon thebasisof the features thatPetroski attributes to thelegalpracticewillbeveryfragile. This lineofargumentpresupposesfromtheoutsetthecorrectionofpositivism,whichispreciselywhatitintendstodemonstrate. Theargumentwouldbecircular,sincethedescriptionofthe legaldomainasnecessarilyselfreferentialandexclusiveofanynonlegalreasonsalreadycoincideswiththekeyassumptionsoflegalpositivism. If we define positivism as the theory according to which the law is selfreferential(inthesensethatitregulatestheprocessofitsowncreationandsetsatestforclearly distinguishing between legal and nonlegal rules) and exclusionary of certainreasons (whether this feature is interpreted in a strict sense according to which thesources of law are to be found in social facts alone or in a broader sense thatwouldexcludeonlythesetofreasonswhicharenotincorporatedbytheruleofrecognition),thenit becomes obvious that this interpretation of the relationship between law and legal

    scholarship

    simply

    begs

    the

    question,

    for

    the

    features

    that

    are

    attributed

    to

    law

    or

    legal

    practice coincide with some of the theoretical theses about the law held by most

    7Id.at679.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    4/36

    [Vol.12No.02696 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lcontemporarypositivists. To follow this strategywouldbe saying something like legal

    theory defines the law as selfreferential and exclusionary because the law is selfreferentialandexclusionary,which seems like a tautology. It isquestionable, thus, toclaimthatlegaltheoriststendtobepositivistsbecauseofanyempiricalfeatureofthelegalsystems.

    Nevertheless,torefutethisfirstinterpretationisnotenoughtodismantlePetroskispoint.OnecanseefromhertextthatPetroskiisawareofthisproblemwhenshesaysthatsheisnotactuallyadvocatingthatlegaltheoryislogicallyconstrainedtobepositivistduetotheempiricalfeaturessheattributestolegaldiscourse:

    My point is not that legal theory inevitably adoptsthese features because it is impelled to take on the

    features

    of

    the

    subject

    matter

    it

    is

    explaining

    (either

    becausethisisnecessaryforthecompleteexplanationorbecause it isakindof irresistibletemptation). It is,rather,thatbecauseoftheparallelsocialfunctionsandhistorical paths of these two practiceslegal practiceand theoretical inquirythey in fact share certainfeatures, at least when they are regarded from acertainperspective.

    8

    Thisquotation shows that thebestway to read the thesisof theparallelbetween legalpracticeandacademicdiscourseisbyacceptingnotthatthefeaturesoflawinfluencethetheoretical understanding of legal theorists, but rather that the features of academicdiscourseareprojected in thewayscholarsdescribethe law. Therewouldstillbesome

    sortofirresistible temptation forpositivism,but itscausewouldnotbeany featureoftheobjectofinquiryoflegaltheorists(thelaw),butratherasetoffeaturesoftheinquiryitself. This is the second interpretation of the connection between the character ofpractical legaldiscourseand thatof legaltheoretical inquiry. Ican find support for thissecond reading in Petroskis own words, when she holds that the institutional andconceptualdynamicswithineachdomainprovide strong incentives for thoseworking ineachtofixateonjustthesefeatures.

    9 Thesamephenomenonwouldthusoccurinboth

    institutionalcontexts: On theonehand, lawyers tend to interpretthe law ina legalisticwaybecauselegalreasoningisembeddedinanexclusivistdiscursivepattern;ontheotherhand, theorists tend todescribe thenatureof law inapositivisticwaybecauseof someinstitutional restraints over the sphere in which they operate. Does this secondinterpretationoftheparallelconnectionsbetweenlegaldiscourseandlegalpracticemake

    Petroskis

    thesis

    more

    acceptable

    than

    the

    first

    one?

    8Id.at680.

    9Id.at680(emphasisadded).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    5/36

    2011] 697CommentonPetroski

    Anargumentforthesecondinterpretationcouldbeplausibleifpositivismweretheonlyortheoverwhelminglydominantwayofthinkingaboutthenatureoflaw. Nonetheless,theimpactofsuchinstitutionalandconceptualdynamicsincontemporarylegaltheoryisnotthatevident. Nonaturallawyer,pragmatistornonpositivist ingeneralwoulddefinethelawasentirelyselfreferentialandexclusionaryofallnonlegalreasonsinastrictsense.

    10

    Nocompellinginstitutionalfactorinthestructureofthemodernuniversitiesseemstoberequiringsuch theoriststodoso. Furthermore, Ibelieve thatPetroskis ideasabout thesocial functions of law and legal theory are unconvincing, for at least two correlatedreasons. Ontheonehand,theonlysocialfunctiononecanidentifyforlegalpracticeinherparadigmistoexerciseanaristocraticdominationoverthemassofnonlawyersbymeansofanobscurediscoursewhich isclosedwithinitself. Thisseemstobemoreapathologythanagenuinesocialfunction. Ontheotherhand,ifthisdescriptionoflegaltheorywere

    correct,

    then

    the

    theoretical

    inquiry

    about

    law

    would

    suffer

    from

    self

    imposed

    limitations

    whichwouldkeepitawayfromanyinterestingreallifeproblem. Legaltheorywouldnotbeable toachievewhat itpurports todo, since itwouldneitherbeable toexplain thenormativityoflawnorcontributetojustifyrelevantdecisionsaboutthenatureoflaw. Aswe will see in the next section, legal philosophy itself would lose one of its centralfunctions.

    II. TheCriticalDimensionofLegalTheory

    Although Petroski intends to explain positivism in sociological terms, I believe that thedebatebetweenpositivistsandnonpositivistsisaphilosophicalone,andthatitcannotberesolvedwithoutaproperunderstandingofthenatureof legalphilosophy. WecanseefromPetroskisdescriptionof thecharacterof legaltheoreticaldiscourses that she sees

    legal theorists as (at least in part) strategic actors who operate within a competitiveenvironmentthatisclosedwithinitselfandexcludesallthereasonsthatfalloutsideofthescopeofitsowndiscursivepattern. Insteadofactingcriticallyagainstthisframework,legaltheoristscultivateitandreproduceitbecausetheycanonlyachievestatus,authorityandexpertisebystickingtosuchdiscourseanddifferentiatingitfromthecompetingdiscoursesbymeansoffractaldistinctions. Tomoveoutofthiscontextwouldbeagainsttheinterestsofthetheoristherself.

    10Anatural lawyerwouldhavetosaythatthenormativityof lawis justifiedbysomeobjectivemoralprinciples

    which cannotbeentirelyexcluded frompractical legal reasoning. Seegenerally JOHN FINNIS,NATURAL LAW ANDNATURALRIGHTS (1979). Apragmatistwouldneverdeny that reasonsofpolicyandarguments fromothernonstrictly institutionalizedmaterialsplayanimportantpart in legalargumentation,althoughshewouldtendtobe

    skeptical about the role ofmoral principles in legal practice. See generally RICHARD POSNER, THE PROBLEMS OF

    JURISPRUDENCE (1993). A nonpositivist like Dworkin or Alexy, finally, would argue that the key principles ofpoliticalmoralityare inanycasepartofthematerialsthat lawyersuse intheirpracticalactivity. SeegenerallyROBERT ALEXY, THE ARGUMENT FROM INJUSTICE: A REPLY TO LEGAL POSITIVISM (2002); RONALDDWORKIN, LAWS EMPIRE(1986).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    6/36

    [Vol.12No.02698 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lIfPetroskisanalysisoflawandoftheoreticalthinkingiscorrect,boththelegalsystemand

    legal philosophy could be described in the sameway that Jrgen Habermas describedNiklasLuhmannssociologyoflaw.

    Assodescribed,thelegalsystemisarecursivelyclosedcircuitofcommunicationthatselfreferentiallydelimitsitself from itsenvironment,withwhich ithas contactonly through observations....[T]he system describesits own components in legal categories and employsthese selfthematizations for the purposes ofconstituting and reproducing legal acts by its ownmeans.

    11

    The

    problem

    of

    Luhmanns

    12

    autopoietic

    theory

    of

    law,

    Habermas

    argues,

    is

    that

    its

    empiricist interpretationofthe legalsystemassumesthat it isdetached fromall internalrelations tomorality and politics. The law is reduced to the special function of theadministrationof law,and the interpreteror the theorist loses sightof theconnectionbetween law and the constitutional organization of the origin, acquisition, and use ofpoliticalpower.

    13 If the law isunderstoodasanautopoietic socialsystem,onecannot

    account for its social normativity and its proper social functions in the context of apluralisticand secularsocietywhichcanno longer relyonmetaphysicalarguments fromnaturallaw. Stripedofitsnormativeconnotationsthatoncewerebackedbymetaphysicalnatural law,butwhichcanno longer findany roomwhen the law isobserved from theoutside and characterized as an entirely autonomous social system, the law becomesnarcissisticallymarginalizedandcanonlyreactto itsownproblems. Inshort,amutualindifferencebetweenthelawandallothersocialsystemsisassumedbytheinterpreter.

    14

    Thismutual indifference,Habermaswouldsay,hastheconsequencethatthe lawcannolongerfindaproperjustification,foritsnormativityisheavilycompromised.

    Whoeverisrightinthispoint,HabermasorLuhmann,itmustbestressedthatthisdebateismorefruitfulasadebateaboutthelawthanasoneaboutthecharacteroftheoreticalinquiryover itsnature. In fact,onecanmakeverygoodarguments to support,againstHabermas, the claim that the law is a closed and selfreferential systemwhich can beidentifiedbymeansofa strictlyempiricalanalysis,withoutanyconsiderationabout theroleplayedbypoliticsormorality in itscreationandadministration. This is, infact,how

    11 JRGENHABERMAS,BETWEEN FACTS ANDNORMSCONTRIBUTIONS TO ADISCOURSE THEORYOF LAW ANDDEMOCRACY49

    (1996).

    12SeegenerallyNIKLASLUHMANN,LAWASASOCIALSYSTEM(2008).

    13HABERMAS,supranote11,at50.

    14Id.at51.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    7/36

    2011] 699CommentonPetroski

    one of the most powerful legal theories of our time explains the validity of a law.

    AccordingtoJosephRaz,thevalidlawshouldnecessarilybeidentifiedinawaythatisfreefromanypoliticalormoralconnotations,sinceitssourcescomefromsocialfactsalone. Toincludemoralprinciplesoranytypeofnonauthoritativeconsiderations inthetestsusedto distinguish legal rules from other social norms would undermine the authoritativecharacteroflegalnorms,whichisitsdistinctivefeature. Whenlegalofficialsaresetouttoapplythelaw,theyareguidedbypositiveauthoritativeconsiderationswhoseexistenceand content can be assertedwithout resort tomoral judgment.

    15 Law, in this theory,

    consistsonlyof suchpositive authoritative considerations. When stateofficials identifyand apply the law, their personal action is situated not on the deliberative stage ofpracticalreasoning,butratherontheexecutivestage,inwhichthequestionwhatoughttobedone isansweredwithout resort toany typeofmoralorpoliticalargument.

    16 As in

    Luhmann,wecannoticeinRazastressonanintrinsicformofrationalityinlegalreasoning,

    which

    is

    conducted

    in

    an

    entirely

    autonomous

    practical

    context.

    If

    that

    is

    the

    case,

    one

    mightaskwhetherthisautonomyappliesalsotothetheoreticalinquiryaboutthenatureof law,asPetroski suggests. Canweconceiveof legal theoryas strictly separated fromother fieldsof inquiry suchaspoliticsandmorality? Do legal theoristsneed toconfinethemselvestoanyparticulartypeofreason?

    Myviewisthatbothofthesequestionsshouldbeansweredinthenegative. Evenwithintherealmoflegalpositivism,fewarethetheoristswhounequivocallyagreewithPetroskionthispoint. Austin,Kelsen,andHartarepossiblythebestexamplesofthisapproach,butthey seem to be in a minority (even though they are prominent thinkers within thepositivisttradition),andIdonotthinkthattheyarerightinthis. Theyseemtobelievethattheoretical inquiry shouldbeentirelyneutral. Nomoral,ethicalorpragmaticargumentshould be used to back up a particular theoretical conception of law. In Kelsens

    perspective, for instance, science is theonly formof knowledgeworth pursuing, and itmust proceed either by means of empirical observation or by strict logical andmathematical analysis. The theorist ismotivated solelybyher faith in science and thepursuit of the truth. She has no ideological ambitions and is determined to free heranalysisfromtheprejudicesandpreconceptionsthatareusuallyfoundinethics,morality,politics,psychology,biology,andreligion. AsKelsenwritesintheopeningpageofthePureTheoryofLaw,legaltheoryisatheoryofpositivelaw,andassuchitaimssolelyatthecognitionof its subjectmatter; that is to say: Legal theory is legal science,not legalpolicy.

    17 Bythesametoken,Austins imperativetheoryof law isstronglycommittedto

    anempiricistapproach,asisvisibleinoneofhismostfamouspassages,whereheargues

    15JOSEPHRAZ,ETHICSINTHEPUBLICDOMAIN: ESSAYSINMORALITYOFLAWANDPOLITICS189(1994).

    16Id.at190.

    17HANSKELSEN,INTRODUCTIONTOTHEPROBLEMSOFLEGALTHEORY7(1992).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    8/36

    [Vol.12No.02700 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lthatthematterof jurisprudence ispositive law,simplyandstrictlysocalled.

    18 Finally,

    Harts view of jurisprudence as a form of descriptive sociology19 is even morecharacteristicofthisneutralmethodologicalpointofview.

    Inmyview,Petroskiseemstobelievethatit isfeasibletoanalyzethe legalphenomenonwith the kind of neutrality that is advocated by the strand of descriptive positivismmentioned justabove. If thatwere the case, itwouldappear reasonable toargue thatlegaltheoryisboundtobepositivistbecauseofthemethodologicalattitudeofthemajorlegal theorists,whoby large excludepolitical, pragmatic, andmoral reasons from theirtheoretical inquiry about the nature of law. This is, in fact, the root of my deepestdisagreementwithPetroski. Iamnotconvincedthatanyserioustheoreticalaccountofthelegalphenomenoncanfreeitselffromthekindofreasonsthatarefoundinpolitics,ethicsor morality. As a matter of fact, I can think of no AngloAmerican positivist whose

    arguments

    in

    support

    of

    his

    or

    her

    own

    theory

    are

    neither

    moral

    nor

    political

    in

    nature.

    In

    these matters, I think that Dworkin is right when he claims that any theory of law,includingpositivism,isbased intheendonsomeparticularnormativepoliticaltheory.

    20

    Lawisacontestedpoliticalconceptwhichtakesitssensefromitsuse,fromthecontextsof debates aboutwhat the law is, and fromwhat turns onwhich view is accepted.

    21

    According to Dworkin, positivists who claim that their theories are merely a sort oflinguistic study or descriptive sociology potentially do not understand their ownarguments.

    22 Everythesisaboutthenatureof law ispartlygrounded inanargumentof

    politicalmorality.

    IfonelooksatthefiveauthorsthatPetroskiquotesinsupportofherargumentthatlegaltheoryisboundtoremainpositivistbecauseofthekeyfeaturesofjurisprudentialinquiry,one should be able to see that none of them excludedmoral and political reasons in

    supportofhistheory. Inmyopinion,neitherHobbesnorBentham,Austin,Hart,orRazhasproduced a legal theorywith all the features pointed out by Petrosky. None of thesetheoriesisselfreferentialorexclusiveofallmoralandpoliticalconsiderations.

    Hobbes,forinstance,isasmuchanaturallawyerasheisoneofthefoundersofpositivism.Thelawsofnaturearedescried in theLeviathanasimmutableandeternal,and thescienceofthese laws isthetrueandonlymoralphilosophy.

    23 Althoughheisskeptical

    18JOHNAUSTIN,THEPROVINCEOFJURISPRUDENCEDETERMINED1(1832).

    19H.L.A.HART,THECONCEPTOFLAW(2ded.1994).

    20RonaldDworkin,AReply,inRONALDDWORKINANDCONTEMPORARYJURISPRUDENCE254(MarshallCohened.,1984).

    21Id.at256.

    22Id.at255.

    23THOMASHOBBES,LEVIATHANpara.,I.15(1651).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    9/36

    2011] 701CommentonPetroski

    aboutanynatural inclinationofmankindtowardsthese laws,for inthestateofnature

    the laws of nature cannot determine human action, he shareswith classical naturallawyerstheviewthatpeopleareabletodiscoverwhattheselawsofnaturearebyusingtheirpractical reason. Whenhumansdo that,Hobbesargues, theyare likely to formacommonwealthinwhichmenarenolongerapttoactonthesocalledrightofnatureorthelibertyeachmanhathtousehisownpowerashewillhimselfforthepreservationofhis own nature...or his own life.

    24 These views are more than enough to classify

    Hobbesasanaturallawyer,forheadmitsboththatthereisanaturallawtheexistenceofwhich does not depend on any positive or institutional act and that the positive lawscreatedbythecivilsocietyfindtheirjustificationinsuchnaturallaws. Hence,Hobbescanonlybereadasapositivist ifoneunderstandsthis labelasnotnecessarilyantagonisttowhat natural lawyers have to say. Moreover, Petroskis belief thatHobbeswas undersome sortofconstraintbecauseof thebasicconceptualvocabulary thatheusesdoes

    not

    seem

    to

    me

    entirely

    accurate

    from

    a

    historical

    point

    of

    view,

    since

    it

    misses

    the

    point

    aboutHobbespoliticalmotivations for the kindof theoryhe advocated. Hobbes livedthroughoneofthemostvolatilemomentsinBritishhistory,andhewrotewithaviewtoprovide a practical and political justification for absolute Monarchy, which was in hisopiniontheonlywayoutoftheEnglishCivilWar. Hence,althoughPetroskiisrightwhenshe argues that Hobbes and other positivists described the legal system as onewhichsuspends the operation of certain reasons for action and that has selfreferentialfeatures,

    25thesamecannotbesaidabouttheinquiryortheresearchthatthesetheorists

    undertook. Despite the initial appearances, the actual inquiry of Hobbes and hissuccessorsisneitherselfreferentialnorexclusive.

    Toillustratethatpoint,onecanthinkofthecaseofBentham. Eventhoughsomescholarsas important as Hart interpret his theory as a predominantly descriptive or neutral

    theoreticalenterprise,26thebest readingofhis ideas istheonethat recognizesthattherole of his analytical jurisprudence is subservient to what he called the art oflegislation.

    27 Benthamspositivismhasmoralroots. Hedefinesalawinapositivisticway

    becausehebelievesthat indoingsohe isfollowingtheprincipleofutility. Asaformofutilitarianpositivism,Benthamsconceptualtheoryisbasedonaparticularviewabouttheproperfunctionoflaw,afunctionwhichcannotbeunderstoodinpurelylegalterms.

    28

    24Id.,para.,I.14.

    25Petroski,supranote1,at682.

    26H.L.A.HART,ESSAYSONBENTHAM: JURISPRUDENCEANDPOLITICALPHILOSOPHY2139(1982).

    27PhilipSchofield,JeremyBenthamandnineteenthcenturyEnglishjurisprudence12J.LEGALHIST.58,60(1991).

    28ThebestdefenseofthisinterpretationofBenthamcanbefoundinGERALDPOSTEMA,BENTHAMANDTHECOMMON

    LAWTRADITION(1986).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    10/36

    [Vol.12No.02702 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lEven Austin, who concentrated his legal theory on the socalled expository

    jurisprudence,asopposedtothecensorial jurisprudence,mayhavehiddenmoralandpolitical reasons for his allegedly descriptive positivism. Benthams reformativeutilitarianism can be contrasted with Austins conservative use of the same principle.Whilst Bentham sees the principle of utility as a device for criticizing government andchanging the law into something better, Austin adopted a theological utilitarianismwhich presumed that itwas thewill ofGod that his creatures should be happy, andthereforethetheoryofutilityandthewillofGod...coincided.

    29 UnlikeBentham,Austin

    seemed to assume that the principle of utility had in practice commonly guided thelegislator. AsSchofieldnotices, whereasBenthams scientificversionofutilitarianismsubjectedexistingpracticesand institutions to thescrutinyof theprincipleofutility...,Austins theologicalutilitarianism tended tosee those samepracticesand institutionsas[already] embodying utility.

    30 We can see, thus, that despite Austins claim that his

    theory

    was

    neutral

    and

    purely

    descriptive,

    his

    jurisprudence

    could

    not

    be

    separated

    from

    theconservativemoralpoliticalcontextinwhichitwasinitiallyproposed.

    Hart,likewise,regardlessofhisfirmconvictionthathisaccountisdescriptiveinthatitismorallyneutralandhasno justificatoryaims,

    31hasnotmanagedto freehis theoretical

    inquiry from arguments of political morality. I can think of two of his most centralargumentsasgenuineexamplesof themoralpoliticalcommitmentsofhistheory,whichwillbeanalyzedinthefollowingparagraphs.

    The first argumentwhichexemplifiesHartsmoralpolitical commitments appears in hisreply toRadbruchs postwar papers against positivism. In one of hismost celebratedessays, Hart heavily criticizes Radbruch and the German Constitutional Court for thedecisionsthatappliedthesocalledRadbruchsFormulaandthusdeniedlegalcharacter

    toasetofNaziLawswhichimposedracistmeasuresonpeopleoftheJewishreligion. Inparticular,HartwasnotsatisfiedwiththereasoningprovidedbytheConstitutionalCourtto justify, ina setofcriminalcases, theconclusion that somestatutesare toounjust todeserveany formofobedience. Insteadof saying that the lawswhich legalizedmurderagainsttheJews lacked legalvaliditybecauseoftheirextreme injustice,Hartargues,thecourtshouldhaveadmittedthatthesestatuteshad indeed legalcharacter,althoughthelawinthatcasewastoowickedtobeobeyed. Inordertocorrectlyjustifyitsdecisions,thecourtshouldhaverecognizedthelegalcharacteroftheoldstatuteswhilecreatinganewlegalrulewithretrospectiveeffects. InHartsownwords:

    29Schofield,supranote27,at63.

    30Id.

    31HART,THECONCEPTOFLAW,supranote19,at240(emphasisinoriginal).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    11/36

    2011] 703CommentonPetroski

    Odious as retrospective criminal legislation and

    punishmentmaybe, tohavepursued itopenly in thiscase would at least have the merits of candour. Itwouldhavemadeplainthatinpunishingthewomanachoice had to be made between two evils, that ofleaving her unpunished and that of sacrificing a verypreciousprincipleofmoralityendorsedbymost legalsystems. Surely ifwehave learnedanything fromthehistoryofmoralsitisthatthethingtodowithamoralquandaryisnottohideit.

    32

    Itisclear,therefore,thatoneofHartsmostfamousargumentsinreplytononpositivismisagenuinelymoralargument,whichhasverylittleneutralityinit. Apositivistdefinition

    of

    law

    should

    be

    preferred

    to

    a

    non

    positivist

    one

    because

    it

    would

    make

    plain

    the

    sacrificesandthechoicesthatonehastomake inorderto impose legalobligationswithretrospectiveeffect.

    Thesecondargument,ontheotherhand,isevenmoreexpressiveofthemoralorpoliticalpreferences of the author, for it clearly demonstrates that the allegedly descriptivetheoretical accountproposed inTheConceptof Lawhas importantnormativeelementsbuiltintoit. Hartscentralargumentinsupportoftheideathatalegalsystemmusthavenotonlyprimary rulesaccording towhichhumansare required todoorabstain fromcertain actions, but also secondary ruleswhich are concernedwith the primary rulesthemselves, isgroundedona reductioadabsurdum thatexposes the inadequaciesofapoliticalorganizationwhichusesonlytheformertypeofrules. Animaginarysocietywherethereareonlyprimaryrulesofobligationwouldsufferfromtheproblemsofuncertainty,

    for therewouldbenoprocedure for settling any doubt about the validityof a rule; ofhavinga static character, for therewouldbenomeans, in such society, fordeliberatelyadaptingtheserulestonovelcircumstances;andof inefficiency,sincetherewouldbenoprocedure to keep the diffused social pressure by which rules are enforced andmaintained.

    33 Itisbecauseofthisthatweneedsecondaryrulestoprovidearemedyfor

    these three serious problems for any legal society. Nevertheless, asDworkin correctlyargues,suchconstructionisfarfrombeingneutralorpurelydescriptive,asHartclaimsittobe. Dworkinswordsaboutthispointareparticularlyilluminating:

    He [Hart] develops his own account of the mainelements of law by showing how the device of asecondary rule of recognition responds to these

    32H.L.A.Hart,PositivismandtheSeparationofLawandMorals,inTHEPHILOSOPHYOFLAW33(RonaldDworkined.,

    1977).

    33HART,supranote19,at9293.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    12/36

    [Vol.12No.02704 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lparticulardefectsbymakingpossibleanewsetofrules

    thatare flexible,efficient,andcertain. This, Ibelieve,doessupportmysuggestionaboutthepoliticalbasisofpositivism.

    34

    If Dworkin is right about this, then Harts advocacy of neutrality in jurisprudence isinconsistent with his own theory, for the choice of his theoretical position is entirelydeterminedbypoliticalconsiderations. AsithappenswithHobbes,BenthamandAustin,Hartstheoreticalinquiryisfarfromexcludingallmoralandpoliticalreasons.

    Lastbutnotleast,Razsphilosophyoflawappearstomeasanythingbutneutral. Firstofall,hehasneverattemptedtoavoidmoralreasonsinhistheoreticalproject. Althoughheholdsthatthelawconsistsonlyofpositiveauthoritativeconsiderations,whichimpliesthat

    one

    cannot

    appeal

    to

    moral

    or

    political

    arguments

    in

    order

    to

    answer

    questions

    about

    the

    validity of a particular rule, he does not deny that there is some sort of connectionbetweenlawandmoralityandthatthenormativityofalegalsystemshouldbeexplainedbymeansofmoral reasons. TheSeparabilityThesis, for instance, isexpresslydeniedbyRaz: [I]tisverylikelythatthereissomenecessaryconnectionbetweenlawandmorality,thateverylegalsysteminforcehassomemoralmeritordoessomemoralgoodevenifitisalsothecauseofagreatdealofmoralevil.

    35 PerhapsoneofthekeystounderstandRazs

    theory that the law is a system of authoritative rules is to look at the example ofarbitration,whichisoneofhismostfamous. Inthatscenario,eachofthepartieshasherownfirstorderreasonstodeterminehercourseofaction,butthesereasonsmayconflict.Whentwopersonshaveconflictingviewsaboutaparticulardecision,theymayagreetorefer the dispute to an arbitrator. If they do that, two features stand out: (1) Thearbitratorsdecisionisinitselfareasonforaction;and(2)Thearbitratorsdecisionmustbe

    based on a set of firstorder reasons which apply to the disputants (or, in Razsterminology,dependentreasons). InRazsperspective,thearbitratorhasauthorityoverthedisputantsbecausehis judgmentover the reasons thatapply to them replaces theirown balancing of reasons. In agreeing to obey the decision [of the arbitrator], thedisputants agreed to follow his judgment of the balance of reasons rather than theirown.

    36 Thisiswhathappensinthecaseoflegalsystems. Whenpeoplejointogetherto

    formalegalcommunity,theyagreetoacceptanauthoritywhosejudgmentreplacesthatofthe individualactorsthemselves. Atthisstage,wecanseeclearlythepoliticalrootofRazsphilosophyoflaw. Peopleaccepttheauthorityoflawforprudentialreasons. Oneofthe central ideas to explain the normativity of law is what Raz calls the normaljustificationthesis,whichcanbestatedinthefollowingterms:

    34Dworkin,supranote20,at255.

    35RAZ,supranote15,at211.

    36Id.at196.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    13/36

    2011] 705CommentonPetroski

    [T]he normal way to establish that a person hasauthority over another person involves showing thatthe alleged subject is likely better to comply withreasons which apply to him...if he accepts thedirectives of the alleged authority as authoritativelybinding,andtriestofollowthem,ratherthanbytryingtofollowthereasonswhichapplytohimdirectly.

    37

    Lawsvalidityandbindingness canonlybe justifiedbymeansofprudential,political,ormoralreasons. Theauthorityoflawisjustifiedwhenpeoplearebetteroffwiththelawsjudgmentratherthanwiththeirown. Thewholeargument,thus,isconductedbypracticalreasons. Furthermore,oneofRazsbasicideasisthatthelawclaimslegitimateauthority,

    and

    such

    legitimacy

    means

    that

    the

    authority

    of

    every

    legal

    agent

    must

    seek

    for

    a

    kind

    of

    moraljustification. ToeliminateanydoubtsabouttheuseofpoliticalandmoralreasonsinRazstheoryoflegalauthority,wecanquotehisownwordsaboutit. Whentalkingabouthisownwritings,Razhasrecentlysaid: Imaintainthatnecessarilythelawclaimstohavelegitimateauthority,andthatthatclaimisamoralclaim.

    38 Wecansee,thus,thatRazs

    philosophyoflawalsodiffersfromPetroskischaracterizationoflegaltheoreticalinquiryasanentirelyneutralenterprise. This isenoughtoclaim,contrarytowhatPetroskithinks,that jurisprudence as a philosophical discipline neither is selfreferential nor excludesmoralandpoliticalconsiderations. Eveninthecaseofthosewhothinkthatthelawisanautonomous social system, theoretical inquiryover the law is hardly ever autonomous.Jurisprudence is philosophy applied to the law, and it plays a similar role to that ofphilosophyingeneral.

    Oneofthemostinterestingquestionsaboutlegalphilosophyistounderstandthekindofstatements we find in it. Although one can think of many different methodologicalapproaches to legalphilosophy,whichcannotbeanalyzedhere, thatwhich seemsmostinteresting tome is theoneadvocatedbyRobertAlexy. Forhim, [l]egalphilosophy isargumentation about the nature of law, and any reflection about legal philosophy is,therefore,areflectionaboutthenatureofargumentsaboutthenatureoflaw.

    39 Before

    weunderstandthenatureofsuchreflection,however,weneedsomeclarificationaboutphilosophy itself. Howcanwedefinephilosophy? Again,this isoneofthemostdifficulttasks of philosophical discourse. Alexys answer is this: Philosophy is general andsystematic reflectionaboutwhat there is [ontology],whatought tobedoneor isgood

    37JosephRAZ,THEMORALITYOFFREEDOM53(1986)(emphasisremoved).

    38JOSEPHRAZ,THEAUTHORITYOFLAW: ESSAYSONLAWANDMORALITY315(2ded.2009).

    39RobertAlexy,Thenatureof theargumentsabout thenatureof law, inRIGHTS,CULTUREANDTHELAWTHEMES

    FROMTHELEGALANDPOLITICALPHILOSOPHYOFJOSEPHRAZ4(L.H.Meyeretal.eds.,2003).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    14/36

    [Vol.12No.02706 Ge rman L aw J ou rna l[ethics], and how knowledge about both is possible [epistemology].

    40 This definition,

    according to Alexy, has three corollaries of capital importance: Firstly, the fact thatphilosophy is a reflection presupposes a critical aspect that constitutes a normativedimension for philosophical inquiry; Philosophy as a necessarily reflective enterprisethereforenecessarilyhasanormativedimension.

    41 Secondly,thegeneralandsystematic

    characterofphilosophicalreflectionleadstoananalyticaldimension(whichisdefinedbytheattempttoidentifyandtomakeexplicitthefundamentalstructuresofthenaturalandsocialworld inwhichwe liveand the fundamentalconceptsandprinciplesbymeansofwhich we can grasp both worlds)

    42 and, thirdly, to a synthetic dimension (which is

    definedbytheattempttouniteallofthisintoacoherentwhole).43

    We are now in a position to define legal philosophy. Legal philosophical inquiry is aphilosophical inquiry about the nature of law. Its differentia specifica consists in its

    subject.

    It

    is,

    thus,

    a

    general

    and

    systematic

    reflection

    about

    what

    there

    is,

    what

    ought

    to

    be,andwhatcanbeknown,butwithspecificreferencetolaw.

    Of course this conceptof legalphilosophy isdifferent from thatof some legal theoristswho might restrict its scope to what Alexy has called the analytical dimension.Nevertheless, this is not how most contemporary philosophers (as opposed to legalphilosophers)understandtheirowndiscipline,andthefactthattheconceptsandtheoriesdevelopedby legalphilosophyarequiteoftenused inpractice,at leastwhenitcomestopivotalcases, isan indicatorthatthe legaltheoreticalaccountsthatrestrictthescopeoflegalphilosophytoanalyticalorempiricalproblemstendtomisrepresentthefunctionofthetheoreticalinquiryaboutthelaw.

    44

    MymainreasonsfordisagreementwithPetroskiarethatifherdescriptionoflegaltheory

    is correct, then jurisprudence lacks what I consider to be one of its crucial functions

    40RobertAlexy,TheNatureofLegalPhilosophy17RATIOJURIS156,157(2004).

    41Id.at158. ThesameargumentisfoundinALEXY,supranote39,at3.

    42Alexy,supranote40,at158.

    43Id.

    44ThisispreciselywhatDworkinmeans,forinstance,whenheholdsthatinanylegaldisputethereisalwaysthe

    possibilityofatheoreticaldisagreementaboutthe law. Inhardcases, judgesand lawyersmaydisagreenotonly about whether or not a particular act falls within the scope of a master rule such as Harts rule ofrecognition,butratheraboutthecontentofthemasterruleitself. Thecriteriononwhichonereliestoidentifythe law in a given casemaydependon the theory oneupholds to develop his conception of law. See,e.g.,

    DWORKIN,supra

    note10,at45. Topickupanexample, inadditiontothecasesquotedbyDworkin inthefirsttwochaptersofhisLAWSEMPIRE,wecanmentionthedecisionoftheHouseofLordsinJacksonv.HerMajestysAttorneyGeneral[2005]UKHL56. Inthiscase,theLawLordsdisagreednotonlyaboutthevalidityofaparticularrule,butabouttheruleofrecognitionitself. Fortheparticularsofthiscase,seeMichaelPlaxton,Theconceptoflegislation: JacksonandOthersvHerMajesty'sAttorneyGeneral,69MOD.L.REV.249,24961(2006).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    15/36

    2011] 707CommentonPetroski

    accordingtoAlexysaccount,whichisthenormativeorcriticalone. WhateverdefectsNeil

    MacCormicks legal theorymay have, the lack of a critical or normative standpoint forjurisprudential inquiry is not one of them. Inmy reading, his conception of law as aninstitutionalnormativeorderincludestheideathattheproperpurposeofsuchanorderistherealizationofjustice,andoneoftheconsequencesofthisconceptionisthatitjustifiesacriticalattitudetowardsactualinstitutionsoflawandstate.

    45

    C. MacCormicksPostPositivismandtheNatureofLegalArgumentation

    I. PetroskisCriticismonMacCormicksPostPositivism

    AccordingtoPetroski,NeilMacCormickistheonlylegaltheoristtohaveappliedtohimselfthelabelpostpositivistortohaveexplainedwhatthislabelactuallymeans. Sheclaims

    that

    the

    use

    of

    the

    prefix

    post

    implies

    that

    the

    root

    tradition

    is

    no

    longer

    viable

    in

    its

    original form, and that this is the sense inwhichMacCormick uses the term.46 After

    saying that, she explainswhy she thinks that a legal theoristmight conclude that thetraditionof legalpositivism isno longer viable. She claims that there are two typesofreasonsonecanadduceforapostpositivistposition: conceptualandprudentialreasons.On the one hand, the former could include either (1) a dissatisfaction with theincreasingly narrow questions addressed by positivists and their apparently increasinglytrivialconclusionsor (2)aconclusion thatoneormoreofthepremisesormethodsoflegalpositivismhavebeendiscreditedorareirreconcilable. Thelatter,ontheotherhand,could include (3) adesire to free the theoristswork from thepejorative connotationsassociatedwithpositivism; (4)exhaustionwiththevolumeofmaterialproducedunderthepositivist rubric;or (5)adesire tomark the theoristsworkasoriginal rather thanderivative.

    47 With this classification in mind, she claims that MacCormicks chief

    motivationsforhispostpositivistpositioncanonlybeprudentialinnature.

    Petroskiargues,firstly,thatMacCormickdoesnottakethepositionthatthepremisesoflegalpositivismhavebeendiscredited,

    48 and attempts to show thisbymentioninghis

    assertion that lawandmoralityare conceptuallydistinct.49 Secondly, she claims that

    neitherisMacCormicktroubledbythenitpickingdetailsoflegalpositivistcontroversies,sinceheengages inandacknowledges the relevanceofmanyof thesequarrels.

    50 And

    45NEILMACCORMICK,INSTITUTIONSOFLAW:ANESSAYINLEGALTHEORY264(2007).

    46Petroski,supranote1,at672.

    47Id.at6723.

    48Id.at674.

    49Id.,at674,note47.

    50Id.at674.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    16/36

    [Vol.12No.02708 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lthirdly, she says that although MacCormick claims to be a postpositivist because he

    believesthatthelaw isnecessarilygearedtosomeconceptionofjustice,heconcedesthat it isonly the more austereand rigorous formsof legalpositivism that absolutelyexcludethepossibilitythatthereisanymoralminimumthatisnecessarytotheexistenceoflawassuch.

    51

    TheconclusionsPetroskidrawsarethat(1)noneofthedetailsofMacCormickspositionin Institutionsof Law,his final summationofhis theoreticalcommitments, distinguishesthosecommitmentsfromthecore legalpositivistcommitments,and(2)thattheauthorcan only be using the postpositivist label for some of the prudential purposes sheidentifies, that is, as a device for avoiding unwanted negative connotations or forassertingthathisintellectualpositionisdistinguishablefromothers.

    52

    In

    the

    following

    I

    am

    going

    to

    attempt

    to

    defend

    MacCormick

    against

    these

    criticisms.

    My

    reasonsare twofold. Firstly,my readingdiffers fromPetroskiswhen she suggests thatMacCormick does not hold that the premises of legal positivism are discredited orincorrect,andwhenshestatesthattheMacCormicksbeliefthatlawandmoralityareconceptuallydistinctimpliesanyagreementwithpositivism. Someofthecentralthesesofpositivismarethat(1)thereisnonecessaryconnectionbetweenlawandmoralityand(2)itispossiblethatvalidlawscanbeidentifiedwithoutresorttomoraljudgments.

    53 Asa

    postpositivist,MacCormick accepts neither of these claims. This fact does not entail,however, that law andmorality should be confused or are not conceptually distinct.Evenanorthodoxnaturallawyeroranenthusiasticnonpositivistwillhavetoconcedethatlaw and morality are not conceptually equivalent, no matter how many necessaryconnections she finds between these two normative orders. Secondly, MacCormicksassertionthatthe law isnecessarilygearedto justiceseemstometobeverydifferent

    fromtheclaimthatthereisamoralminimumwhichisnecessaryfortheexistenceoflawassuch. Whiletheformerimpliesthatthereisanargumentativeconnectionbetweenlawand morality, so that moral arguments are embedded in any legal discourse andnecessarilyplayapart inthe interpretationandapplicationof law,the lattermeansonlythatalegalsystemwhichdoesnotcomplywithsomeminimummoralstandardscannotbelegallyvalid. EvenifPetroskiisrightwhenshesaysthattheformerthesiscanbeacceptedbynonorthodoxpositivists,thisfactalonedoesnotmakeNeilMacCormickoneofthem.We can see, thus, that even thoughMacCormick retains some ideas derived from the

    51Id.at675.

    52Id.at676.

    53

    Acontemporarypositivistmightreplythatpositivismno longeradvocatesthe firstthesis (Separability). Thiskind of argument ispartof a general attempt tonarrowdownpositivism inorder toescape fromobjectionsraisedbyDworkinandotherpostpositivistssuchasMacCormick. Nonetheless,Ibelievethisdoesnotaffectmyargumenthere,foritsufficestoprovethatMacCormickrejectsthesocalledSourcesThesisinordertoclaimthathistheoryisverydifferentfrompositivism.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    17/36

    2011] 709CommentonPetroski

    positivist tradition, he departs from the most distinctive theses of such tradition.

    DifferentlyfromPetroski,IthinkthatMacCormickstheorygenuinelytranscendstheframeof thoughtwhich is common to legal positivists. In the following section,my job is toprovideafewexamplestodemonstratethispoint.

    II. Law,MoralityandArgumentation: TheNatureofMacCormicksPostPositivism

    AlthoughMacCormickhadnotadoptedforhimselfthe labelpostpositivistuntil late inhis career, his relationshipwith positivism has never been unproblematic. Even in hisearliestworkshewasnotentirelysatisfiedwiththemainstreampositivistpositionaboutthenatureof law. In spiteof the great influenceofHerbertHart, therewere relevantdisagreementswiththesupposedneutralityofHartianandKelsenianpositivisms. Perhapsthe most expressive of these disagreements concerns the issue of the justification of

    decisions

    about

    the

    validity

    of

    a

    norm,

    considered

    from

    theinternal

    point

    of

    view.

    As

    MacCormickhasstressedseveraltimes, legaltheoristsshouldpressHarts insightsaboutthe internal point of view further than he did in his own theoretical project.

    54 Once

    theorists take into consideration all the implications of the internal point of view, theproblemofthejustificationoflegaldecisionsbecomesacentralone,aswecanseeinthefollowingexcerptfromMacCormicksLegalReasoningandLegalTheory:

    [A]positivisticdescriptionofthesystemas itoperatescannotansweraparticularkindofquestionwhichmayberaisedinternallytoalegalsystem: thequestionasitmightberaisedforajudgeinahardcase: Whyoughtwe to treat every decision in accordancewith a rulevalid by our criteria of validity as being sufficiently

    justified? and that is a question which can be, andfrom time to time is, raised. Nor can it answer thequestionyetmorefrequentlyraised for judges: Howought we to justify decisions concerning theinterpretation and application of our criteria ofvalidity?

    55

    54Toillustratethispoint,wecanquotethefollowingexcerptfromaninterviewthatMacCormickgavetoManuel

    AtienzaontheoccasionofthepublicationofhisInstitutionsofLaw: ThemostilluminatingandlastingaspectofHartswritingshastodowiththeneedtounderstandanyconductregulatedbyrulesfromtheinternalpointofview. Thisisessentiallytodevelopaclearandconvincingtheoryofnorms. Butrulesarejustonetypeofnorm.

    The analysis of Law as a system of primary and secondary rules, although a valuable intuition, is at the endincomplete and unsatisfactory. A fresh start is needed. Manuel Atienza, Entrevista aNeilMacCormick 29DOXACUADERNOSDEFILOSOFADELDERECHO479,482(2006)(trans.unknown).

    55NEILMACCORMICK,LEGALREASONINGANDLEGALTHEORY63(1978).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    18/36

    [Vol.12No.02710 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lThispassageshowsthatMacCormickisworriedaboutsomethingthatisusuallyneglected

    by contemporary positivists: the problem of the justification of legal decisions. He isespeciallyconcernedwith the justificationof legaldecisionsbecausehe isawareof thesubjectiveelement that isalwayspresent, ingreateror lesserextent, in theactivitiesofinterpretationandapplicationof law. Furthermore,heassumesthepointofviewofthenormuserwhenhe takesup the taskofconstructinga theoreticalexplanationof thenatureoflaw.

    Although the institutional theory of law,which isMacCormicks legal theory in a strictsense, presupposes some sort of detachment from the part of the theorist, suchtheoreticalinquiryremain[s]neverthelessvalueorientedinthedescriptionsitmakesofthe legal institutions.

    56 According toMacCormick,acoherentaccountof thenatureof

    law,andacoherentaccountof thecharacterofanymodern legal system,have to take

    seriously

    the

    very

    general

    values

    that

    are

    inherent

    in

    the

    character

    of

    the

    legal

    enterprise.

    Theconceptsthatalegaltheoristusestoexplainthenatureoflawarethusinterpretativeconcepts in the sense of Ronald Dworkin, for the theoristmust adopt a hermeneuticapproachwhichseek[s]tounderstandthepracticesand institutionsofhumanbeings intermsofwhatmakesthemintelligibleandworthwhile...totheirhumanparticipants.

    57

    Although the theorist has a certain degree of detachment when contrasted with thefrontlineactorsofthelegalpractice,shemusthave,asasecondlineactor,arelativelyhighdegreeofengagementbycontrastwithpurelyexternalobservers.

    58 Inspiteofthe

    fact that MacCormick claims that his jurisprudence is not aimed at the solution ofparticular current practical problems,

    59 the understanding which it provides for the

    practicalcategoryoflawpresupposesarationalreconstructionofthe legal institutionsthatyieldsacriticalaccountofthegoverningrulesinthelightoftheprinciplesandvalues

    whichunderpinthem. Suchacriticalaccount,MacCormickproceeds,may indicatethescopeforfutureinterpretationsoflawthatwillrectifyanomaliesincurrentunderstanding,includingcurrentjudicialpractice.

    60

    Theunderstandingof legal theoretical inquiryaspredominantlycriticalandvalueladen,adoptedbyMacCormick, iscoupledwithaviewofthepracticeoflegalargumentationas

    56MACCORMICK,supranote45,at301.

    57Id.at295.

    58Id.at6.

    59Id.at302.

    60Id.at292. LikeAlexy,MacCormickclaimsthatlegaldoctrinehasnotonlyempiricalandanalyticaldimensions,

    butalsoanormativeone.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    19/36

    2011] 711CommentonPetroski

    alsoanecessarilyconstructiveorhermeneuticprocess,whichseemstobeatoddswiththe

    empiricalessentialismthatpermeatesmostofthecontemporarypositivists.

    Formanypositivists the law is some kindof real entity that is there to be knownordiscovered by the theorist. Theorists very rarely engage in an interpretative orhermeneutic activitywhen they attempt to identify the law. The law has a factualessencewhichcanbeobservedordescribed fromtheoutside. Thetheorist looksatthelaw fromanexternalpointofview,andsheseesastaticsystemofnormswhichcanbetheorizedinasortofPlatonicway,sinceitscontentsarealreadyfixedandtheirmeaningdoesnotdependonthesubjectivitiesoftheinterpreter. Thistypeofpositivism,whichiswidely spread in AngloAmerican jurisprudence, holds that there is a clear separationbetween the creation and the applicationof law. One can identifyquiteeasily thevalidlawinanygivensociety,althoughalegalofficialmayeventuallycreatenewlaws

    when

    she

    is

    not

    satisfied

    with

    the

    solution

    provided

    by

    the

    legal

    order

    or,

    more

    frequently,

    whensheisdealingwithacasenotyetresolvedbythesetofvalidlaws. Forthisstrandofpositivism,itispossibletoapplythelawwithoutanybalancingofreasons. Thesocalledapplicationoflawismerelytheexecutivestageofpracticalreasoning. Allofthelawcanbefoundinitssocialsources,andthemajortaskofthejurististoidentifythesesources,sincetheygiveheranorientationaboutwhatone is legallyrequiredtodo inaparticularcase.

    Suchcleardistinctionbetweenthecreationandtheapplicationoflawleadstoanotherdistinctionwhich is typical of contemporaryAngloAmerican positivism: the distinctionbetweentheoriesof lawandtheoriesofadjudication. Theoriesof lawaregenerallyconcernedwiththeidentificationoflaw. Theyanswertothequestionofwhatthelawis,notwhat itought tobe. Theremustbeasingle test fordifferentiating legal rules from

    other type of social norms, and such testnormally has to dowith the pedigree or theprocessbymeansofwhichtherulesarecreated(inotherwords,withitssources). Inthisperspective,thelawisselfreferentialbecauseitregulatestheprocessthroughwhichlegalnorms are created. This distinction between theories of law and theories ofadjudicationpresupposessomegrainofpositivism. Infact,itishardlypossibletofindanonpositivistwhowouldbewillingtoacceptthisseparation.

    Thedifferentiationbetweenatheoryoflawandatheoryofadjudicationiscrucialforthedebate about contemporary positivism, since it illustrates how this kind of theorycharacterizesthefunctionofjurisprudenceasatheoreticaldiscipline. Oncejurisprudenceisclassifiedasatheoryoflaw,asopposedtoatheoryofadjudication,onecannoticeanincreasing gap between theory and practice, which are conceived as autonomous

    discursive

    contexts

    which

    very

    rarely

    communicate

    with

    each

    other.

    It

    is

    not

    the

    task

    of

    a

    theorist to justifyanypracticeorparticulardecisionor toprovide anyguidance for theproperinterpretationandapplicationoflaw. Thepropertaskoflegaltheoryismerelytoexplainthelaw,ratherthantodeveloporreviseit. Agoodlegaltheoristmust,therefore,

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    20/36

    [Vol.12No.02712 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lleave theobjectofher inquiryuntouched. Legal theoryand legalpracticeare separate

    domains,whichshouldremainseparateiftheyaretocomplywiththeirsocialfunctions.

    IhavenodoubtthatthisishowPetroskiconceivesthetaskoflegaltheory: Legaltheoristsandjudgesoperatewithindifferentinstitutionalcontexts. Hence,itseemspuzzlingtocallapractitionerpositivistor toapply tohim theconceptsandpositionsadvanced in thejurisprudentialdiscourse. ForPetroski,whenoneclassifiesa judgeasapositivist, thiscan onlymean one of these two things: (1) that the judge speaks from an academicdomaindespitehisorherroleasajudge,or(2)thatthejudgeadoptstherhetoricoftheacademicdomain.

    61 Inbothcases,however,theuseofthevocabularyoflegaltheoryby

    judges or other members of the legal profession is perceived as unnatural, if notillegitimate. Forexample,whenanallegedlypositivist judge like JusticeScalia classifieshimself as a positivist, Petroski thinks thatwhat he is doing ismerely deploying some

    interactive

    expertise

    in

    order

    to

    adopt

    a

    rhetoric

    which

    would

    allow

    him

    to

    stress

    on

    statutoryandconstitutionaltextandprecedentastheonly legitimatereasonstooffer insupport of a judicial decision and to disavow any reliance on policy or moralconsiderations.

    62 This interactive expertise, however, is considered to be anomalous

    and interstitial, since the speaker is actually master[ing] the language of a specialistdomainintheabsenceofpracticalcompetencefordoingit.

    63 Whenwefindarguments

    from jurisprudence in a particular judicial opinion, this is explained not as somethingnatural and immanent to the activityofadjudication,asDworkin claimedwhenhe saidthatjurisprudenceisthegeneralpartofadjudication,

    64butratherasanintrusionintoa

    differentdomain.

    Thisway of conceiving the spheres of jurisprudence and legal practice, however, onlybecomes plausible if one presupposes a positivistic conception of legal theory. Hence,

    Petroski is perhaps giving way to certain positivist prejudices when analysing a nonpositivist theory such as that ofNeilMacCormick. She assumes that the functions ofMacCormickstheoryof lawandthemotivesthathehastoundertakehis jurisprudentialinquiryarethesameasthoseoftheparticulartypeofpositivismwithwhichsheimpliedlyidentifiesherself. WeshouldalsobearinmindthatMacCormickisattemptingtoconstructalegaltheorywhichmakessensetotheparticipantsinthelegalpractice,evenifitisnotprimarilyaimeddirectlyatsolvingindividualproblems. Whenwesetoutforourselvesthetaskofunderstandingalegalsystem,thisinvolvesbothadescriptionandareconstructionofthelegalpracticeandtheprincipleswhichunderlieit,andthisisnotsimplyamatterof

    61Petroski,supranote1,at686.

    62Id.at6867.

    63Id.at687.

    64DWORKIN,supranote10,at90.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    21/36

    2011] 713CommentonPetroski

    detachedunderstandingfromanobserversviewpoint. Itisalsoapracticalunderstanding

    fromaparticipantsviewpoint.65

    IfonetakesadifferentviewofMacCormicksrecenttheoryoflaw,withoutpresupposingthepositivistseparationbetweentheoriesoflawandtheoriesofadjudication,oneislikelytoseemanypointswherehedefinitivelybreaksdownwithpositivism. ThiswouldbemyreadingofMacCormick,whichIshallconsiderinthefollowingtopics.

    1. TheArguableCharacterofLaw

    The first point about Neil MacCormicks institutional theory of law is that the lawcomprisesmore than just a set of institutional factswhich do not require any furtherinterpretation. Asanormativeorder,andasapracticalone,the law isincontinuous

    need

    of

    adaptation

    to

    current

    practical

    problems.

    66

    In

    this

    particular,

    MacCormick

    acceptsKelsens idea that the lawpresentsahierarchical structure inwhich thehigherlevelnormsarespecifiedorconcretizedintheprocessesoflegislationandadjudication. InEuropeanLaw,forinstance,thetranspositionprocessfromthelevelofsupranationallawtothemunicipallegalordersisapartoftheStufenbau,thatis,thestepbystepprocessfrom abstract general enactment to particular decisions in concrete cases.

    67 As

    MacCormick puts it with particular clarity, he sees the law as an argumentativediscipline,ratherthananexactscience. Hisfirstcommonplaceaboutthelawisthatitisalwaysarguable innature.

    68 Unlike thepositivistswhoplace legalcertaintyas theonly

    value secured by the Rule of Law, MacCormick believes that the proclaimedargumentativecharacteroflawissomethingtobecelebratedindemocraticsocieties,foritisdeeplyentrenchedintheidealoftheRuleofLaw. TherecognitionoftheRuleofLawas a political ideal implies the recognition of laws domain as the locus of

    argumentation.69 AlthoughtheprincipleoftheRuleofLawisorientedtowardsthevalueoflegalcertainty,thisvalueisnottheonlyone. RationalityandjusticealsofigureamongstthebasicvalueswhichformthebasicidealoftheRuleofLaw.

    65NEILMACCORMICK,RHETORIC AND THERULEOF LAW: ATHEORYOF LEGALREASONING6 (2005). It isnot a surprise,

    therefore, that MacCormick has recently confessed that his interest in legal philosophy developed from anattempttoreconcilephilosophyand legalpractice. WhenaskedbyManuelAtienzaabouttherootsofhis legalphilosophy,MacCormick answered in the followingway: M. A.: Why have you become interested in legalphilosophy? N.M.: BecauseIwasfascinatedaboutphilosophy,butwantedtodedicatemyselftothepracticeoflaw. Atienza,supranote54,at480.

    66MACCORMICK,supranote65,at6.

    67Id.at10.

    68Id.at1415.

    69Id.at13(emphasisadded).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    22/36

    [Vol.12No.02714 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lInthisinterpretation,theindeterminacyoflawisnotalwayssomethingtobedeplored. It

    hastodowiththeidealoftheRuleofLawandwiththeproceduralrulesofargumentationthat are presupposed in the institutional structure that it provides. The ideals ofimpartialityandequalitybetweenthepartiesinalegaldispute,aswellasthefundamentalprincipleaudiaturetalterapars,arenecessarilyconnectedtothebasicideaoftheRuleofLawandtothearguablecharacterofthelegalsystem. Inthissense,itisworthreferringtoMacCormicks words in the introductory chapter to his updated theory of legalargumentation:

    I do believe in the argumentative quality of law, andfinditadmirableinanopensociety. Weshouldlookateverysideofeveryimportantquestion,notcomedownatonceonthesideofprejudiceorapparentcertainty.

    We

    must

    listen

    to

    every

    argument,

    and

    celebrate,

    not

    deplore, the arguable quality that seems built in tolaw.

    70

    TheRuleofLawitself,MacCormickwouldsay,impliesacertaindegreeofindeterminacyinthelegalsystem. Suchindeterminacy,accordingtotheauthor,isnotmerelyaresultofthefactthatstatescommunicatetheirlegalmaterialsinnatural(official)language,andthat these are afflictedwith ambiguity, vagueness and open texture, like Hartwouldsay.

    71 Italso results fromthedue recognitionof the rightsof thedefense inevery

    settingofcriminalprosecutionandcivillitigation.72 Inshort,theRuleofLawimpliesand

    inawaymagnifiesthearguablecharacteroflaw.

    IfthisinterpretationofthepoliticalidealoftheRuleofLawiscorrect,thentraditionallegal

    theoristsarewrongwhentheypresentthevalueoflegalcertaintyastheonlysubstanceoftheRuleofLaw. Moreover,theoristsarealsomistaken iftheyclaim, likeRazdoes inhispositivist legal theory, that the law is to be found in apreviouslydeterminate set ofsocialsources,bymeansofanentirelyempiricalreasoning. Thevalidityofalawcannotbemerelyaquestionoffact,butratherneedstobeatleastinasignificantpartamatterofargument. In MacCormicks view, the law is hardly ever settled and its rules arenecessarilydefeasible, for they are inevitably subjected to a constructive interpretationthat might lead to revisions, reinterpretations, and even exceptions to their operativeconditions. Legal rules are regarded as stating only ordinarily necessary andpresumptively sufficient conditions for the arrangements they regulate, since theunderlyingprinciplesthatprovideageneraljustificationforthelegalsysteminteractswith

    70Id.at16.

    71Id.at26.

    72Id.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    23/36

    2011] 715CommentonPetroski

    themorespecificprovisions thatare found instatutes,precedentsand inthesecondary

    legislation.73 Such interaction may activate some background factor covered by thejustifyingprinciple,which islikelytoamounttotherecognitionofunstatedexceptionstothe rule initially considered by the interpreter. To put it inMacCormicks ownwords,[t]hepresenceofunstatedelementsappearstobeageneralfeatureoflaw.

    74

    2. TheInterpretativeReadingoftheSourcesofLaw

    At this stage, one can see why MacCormicks interpretative theory of law and legaladjudication,whichisinanimportantmeasureinfluencedbyDworkinsconceptionoflawas integrity, is one step aheadof thepositivistic formulationof the socalled SourcesThesis,whichseemstobetheonlycommonpointtoallpositivists.

    It

    is

    a

    common

    assumption

    of

    positivists

    that

    the

    decisive

    criterion

    to

    determine

    the

    validityofalegalnorm,andthereforeitsdistinctivelegalcharacter,isthepedigreeorthesourceofthatparticularlegalnorm. Whenarulecanbetracedbacktoasourcewhichislegallyrecognized, juristscan identify itwithareasonabledegreeofcertainty. EventhenonorthodoxformsofpositivismsuchastheinclusivetheoriesofColeman,Waluchow,andthelateHerbertHarthavetoagreethatwhatevercomesoutofavalidsourceoflawhas a proper legal character, provided that it satisfies themaster rule established in aparticularlegalsystemasatestforthevalidityofitsnorms.

    75

    MacCormicksrecognitionoftheimmanentlyarguablecharacteroflaw, inturn,seemstoimplyacompletelydifferentdoctrineof the sourcesof law. Thematerials found in thesourcesoflaw,suchasstatutes,precedents,treaties,andadministrativeactsarenotselfinterpreting and selfapplying.

    76 Properly considered, they are law only in a pre

    interpretative sense.77 PerhapsMacCormicksviewson the theoriesofprecedentareagoodexampleto illustratethispoint. MacCormickarguesthatthetheoriesofprecedentbased on natural law and on positivism have contributed not only to alternative

    73Id.at241.

    74Id.at244.

    75Inthisparticular,aninclusiveorsoftpositivistwouldhavetoconcedethatitisatleasttheoreticallypossible

    toconceiveaperfectlyvalidlegalsystemthatdoesnotincorporateanymoralprinciplestoitsruleofrecognition.Whateverconnectionsonecanfindbetweenlawandmoralitywillbecontingent,asopposedtonecessary. Seegenerally JulesColeman,NegativeandPositive Positivism, inRONALDDWORKINANDCONTEMPORARY JURISPRUDENCE(MarshallCohened.,1984);WILLWALUCHOW,INCLUSIVELEGALPOSITIVISM(1994).

    76

    MACCORMICK,supranote65,at23.

    77NeilMacCormick,PrecedentasaSourceofLaw, inSOURCESOF LAWAND LEGISLATION: PROCEEDINGSOFTHE17TH

    WORLDCONGRESSOFPHILOSOPHYOFLAWANDSOCIALPHILOSOPHY,BOLOGNA, JUNE16211995,ARSPBEIHEFT177,183(1998).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    24/36

    [Vol.12No.02716 Ge rman L aw J ou rna linterpretationsofthedoctrineofstaredecisisintheUnitedKingdom,butalsotodifferent

    practical uses and applications of the case law. On the one hand, the socalleddeclaratory theoryofadjudicationwhichpresents itselfas compatiblewithanaturallawviewpointanddominatedtheBritishsceneuntilearly inthe18

    thCenturysupports

    hostility to any doctrine of absolutely binding precedent, and tends towards a view ofprecedents as atmost defeasibly binding, on the grounds thatmistakes about law arelogicallypossible,andprecedentsonlydeclaratoryorevidentiary,notstrictlyconstitutiveof law.

    78 On the other hand, positivism,which stresses the human character of law,

    necessarilydeniesthepremisesofthedeclaratorytheory:79

    There isnoessenceof lawbeyondorbehindwhat isdecided as law by some competent decision maker.From this it follows obviously that, if precedents are

    evidence

    of

    the

    law,

    they

    can

    be

    so

    only

    because

    judges

    explicitlyor implicitlyaccordedauthority tomake lawthrough their decisions. Conversely, the veryrecognition of precedent as evidence of the lawamounts to recognitionof thepowerof thecourts tomakelaw.

    80

    Wecansee,thus,thatthesetheoriesproduceseriousnormativeconsequencesinthewaya judicial precedent is received and applied in legal practice. It is because of suchconsequences thatMacCormick, in his approach to precedents, holds that we need atheory that canovercome thedichotomy natural lawversuspositivism, for this is theonlywaytotranscendthelimitsofthedeclaratorytheoryanditspositivistcounterpart:

    Itisnolongerpossible...torestcontentwithasimplecontrastofnaturallawandpositivisminthetreatmentofprecedent. Forthis,particulartribute isduetothework of Ronald Dworkin, which has subverted thesimple dichotomy of positivism versus natural lawtheory. Inplaceofamodeloflawasasystemofrulesderived from predetermined sources, Dworkin invitesus to reconceive law as an essentially interpretiveconcept. Thewhole body of decisions by legislatureand judges and others that positivism hasconceptualizedasmakingupa legalsystemDworkin

    78Id.at182.

    79Id.at182.

    80Id.at183.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    25/36

    2011] 717CommentonPetroski

    tells us to acknowledge as law only in a pre

    interpretiveway.81

    AsMacCormickexplains,accordingtothisconceptiontheverynotionofsourcesoflawneedstoberevised: ForafollowerofDworkinsview, ifwetreatprecedent,or indeedParliamentaryorExecutiveenactment,asa sourceof law,theconceptionof source inplaymust be radicallydifferent from that assumed in the positivisticmodel....

    82 By

    followingthereasoningofDworkin,MacCormickendsupwithatheoryofthesourcesoflaw according towhich statutory provisions, precedents, case reports, and other legalmaterialsarenotreallythemselves law,butratheraresourcematerials fromwhichthelawmaking taskof themomentmustwork. The specificationof themeaningofa lawdependsonaninterpretiveprocessguidedbytheideaofintegrity,inDworkinssense,

    83

    ornormativecoherence,whichisthesameideainMacCormicksvocabulary.84 Insuch

    constructive

    interpretation,

    the

    interpreter

    makes

    the

    law

    operative

    by

    applying

    these

    legalmaterialsaccordingtothemoralprinciplesimplicitinthelaw,andthishermeneuticprocess isalwaysguidedbythe idea toachieve thebestpossible interpretationofthesepreinterpretivematerials. We can see, thus, thatMacCormick advocates a theory ofsourcesoflawandatheoryofprecedentsthatareincompatiblewithlegalpositivismandwiththeviewthattheauthorityofasourceistheonlyfactorthatisrelevanttodeterminethe validity of the rulewhich can be extracted from a judicial precedent. The normsderivedfromprecedentwillbefixedinaninterpretativediscoursewhereargumentsbasedonauthorityandargumentsbasedonpracticalreasonarebalancedinaproperway.

    3. MacCormicksTheoryofLegalArgumentation

    Thearguablecharacterof lawandtheconceptionofsourcesof lawaspreinterpretive

    materialsratherthandefinitiveanswerstothequestionofthevalidityofarulearedeeplyconsistentwithMacCormicksambitionstoprovideanormativetheoryoflegalreasoning.If the law necessarily refers to some conception of justice and if its ultimate contentsdepend on constructive interpretations in the context of disputable validity claims tosupport the individual norms produced in the process of application of law, then it isreasonable toargue thatoneof the tasksof legal theory shouldbe toprovidea setofdirectivestohelp lawyersdiscriminatebetweenbetterandworsearguments,moreandlessrationallypersuasiveones.

    85 Inthissense,partofMacCormicksstrategytoreconcile

    81Id.

    82Id.

    83DWORKIN,supranote10,at9596.

    84SeegenerallyMACCORMICK,supranote55;MACCORMICK,supranote65.

    85MACCORMICK,supranote65,atvi.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    26/36

    [Vol.12No.02718 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lthe argumentative dimension of law with the value of certaintywhich are both

    presupposedandimpliedbythepoliticalideaoftheRuleofLawistoelaborateatheoryof legal argumentation that claims to be capable of acknowledging the best criteria ofrationality for legal decisions and the fundamental constraints on the process of legalreasoning.

    AlthoughmuchcouldbesaidaboutMacCormickspenetratingtheoryoflegalreasoning,itis enough for our purposes to make reference to the Kantian universalism which isaccepted in the latest version of his theoretical project. For MacCormick, any legaldecisioncannotbe justifiedunless itpassesatestofuniversalizability. Thisfollowsfromtheveryideaofjustification: Tojustifyistoshowthatitisright,andtoshowthatitisright istoshowthat,uponanyobjectiveviewofthematter,theactoughttohavebeendone, or even had to be done, given the characteristics and the circumstances of the

    case.

    86

    There

    is

    no

    justification

    without

    universalization

    in

    MacCormicks

    theory

    of

    legal

    reasoning: Forparticularfactsorparticularmotivestobejustifyingreasonstheyhaveto be subsumable under a relevant principle of action universally stated, even if theuniversal is acknowledged to be defeasible. This applies to practical reasoning quitegenerally, and to legal reasoning as one department of practical reasoning.

    87 This is

    enough to show us that MacCormicks theory of argumentation strives towards someuniversalitytestinthespiritofKantscategoricalimperative,evenifthistestisadaptedtotheformofPerelmansidealoftheuniversalaudience

    88orHabermasregulativeideaof

    theidealspeechsituation.89

    In any case,MacCormick is very clear about the importance of themoral principle ofuniversalizabilitywhenheexpresslyrecognizesthatthelatestversionofhistheoryoflegalreasoninghasdepartedfromtheHumeannoncognitivismfoundinhisearliestwritingsin

    favor of a Kantian universalistic moral philosophy.90 In this particular, MacCormickstheoryoflegalargumentationhastoincorporatetwothesesputforwardbyRobertAlexyin order to vindicate his claim that the principles of Kantian universalisticmorality arerelevantforlegalreasoning: thethesisoftheclaimtocorrectnessandthespecialcasethesis. If the law isa specialcaseofpracticaldiscourseand,as such, raisesaclaim tocorrectness,thenthebasicrulesofargumentationwhichapplytopracticaldiscoursesare

    86Id.at98.

    87Id.at99.

    88 Seee.g.,CHAIMPERELMAN and LUCIEOLBRECHTSTYTECA,THENEWRHETORIC: ATREATISEONARGUMENTATION3135

    (1969).

    89

    JrgenHabermas,Teorasde laVerdad, inTEORADELAACCINCOMUNICATIVA: COMPLEMENTOSYESTUDIOSPREVIOS11358 (1997). For a comprehensive analysisofHabermasdiscourse theory in English, see generally THOMASMCCARTHY,THECRITICALTHEORYOFJRGENHABERMAS(1978).

    90MACCORMICK,supranote65,at30.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    27/36

    2011] 719CommentonPetroski

    alsovalidforlegaldiscourse. ThesameprinciplesofdiscoursethatonecanfindinKantian

    moralphilosophyarealsovalidforlegaldiscourse,sincethelatterisnothingbutacaseoftheformerwithasetofinstitutionalconstraints.

    91 Withoutthesetwotheses,MacCormick

    wouldnotbeabletovindicatehisclaim,whichiscommontoAlexy,thattheprinciplesofmoralargumentationproposedbythinkerslikeKantandHabermasareapplicabletolegalreasoning. Hence, it is not difficult to notice that MacCormicks theory of legalargumentationat least in its latest formpresupposesabreakdownwith thepositivisttradition. AsIintendtodemonstrateinthefinalsectionsofthispaper,thethesesofthespecial case thesis and of the claim to correctness, in the form that MacCormickinterpretsthem,cannotbereconciledwithanyformofpositivism.

    4. TheThesisoftheClaimtoCorrectness

    One

    of

    the

    points

    in

    which

    MacCormick

    departs

    from

    positivism

    is

    when

    he

    claims

    that

    the

    lawraisesanimplicitpretensiontojustice. Infact,MacCormickholdsthatlegaldiscourseischaracterizedbythepresenceofcertainimplicitclaimswhicharenecessarilyboundupwith theperformanceof the interactive rolesof the lawmaking, judicial,andexecutiveinstitutionsoragenciesofthestate.

    92 Everyspeechactwhichintroducesalegalnormor

    exercisessomesortof legalauthority isconnectedwiththe illocutionaryactofassertingthecorrectnessofthegeneralorindividualnormwhichisproducedthereby. Anyspeechact performed in the context of legal argumentation involves certain backgroundassumptionsor implicitclaims,and inparticularaclaimto legalandmoralcorrectness.

    93

    Consideredasan institutionalnormativeorder, the lawstrives to justiceandnecessarilypurportstoresolvepracticalconflictsinamorallyacceptableway: [A]certainpretensiontojustice,thatis,apurportedaspirationtobeachievingjustice(evenifthisbethemaskofamorepartisanorsinister intent) isnecessarilyevinced intheveryactof lawmaking in

    thecontextofalawstate.94

    The claim to correctness includes, although it is not satisfied with, a claim to moralcorrectness,andnotonlyaclaimtocorrectnessaccordingtothepositive lawsofagivenstate. Suchaclaim,whichplaysacentralroleinAlexystheoryoflegalargumentationandnowseemstoperformananalogousfunctionwithregardstoMacCormickslatestversionofhistheoryoflegalreasoning,isintimatelyconnectedwiththeideathatthelawhasan

    91 This obviously does notmean, however, that law andmorality are notdistinguishable. The fact that legal

    discourseoperateswithinasetofinstitutionalconstraintsimpliesthatlegaldecisionsarelimitedbytheexigencytorespectthestatutes,precedents,andotherauthoritativematerialsfoundinalegalsystem. Itisthisconstraintinpracticallegalreasoningthatmakesitaspecialcaseofpracticalgeneraldiscourse.

    92MACCORMICK,supranote45,at274.

    93Id.at275.

    94Id.at276.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    28/36

    [Vol.12No.02720 Ge rman L aw J ou rna largumentative character. The foundations of this thesis can be found in Habermas

    philosophyof language. Inhis famousessayTheoriesofTruth,originallypublished inGerman in theearly1970s,Habermascriticizes thephilosophical theorieswhichdefinethetruthofanassertionasthecorrespondencewithacertainthingorstateofaffairsthat is proved to be existent in theworld of physical objects.

    95 In contrast to these

    theories,Habermasadvocatesaconceptionoftruthasrationalconsensus,whichcanbesummarizedinthefollowingexcerpt:

    Icanpredicatesomethingtoanobjectif,andonlyif,alltheindividualsthatcouldenterinadiscoursewithmewould predicate the same thing to the same object.Hence, to distinguish the truth from the falsity of anassertion I make reference to the judgment of the

    othersin

    fact,

    to

    the

    judgment

    of

    all

    of

    those

    with

    whom Icouldeventuallyenter inadiscussion (amongwhich I counterfactually include all the hearers that Icouldmeet ifmy lifetimewere coextensivewith thehistory of mankind). The truthcondition of astatement is the potential consensus of all theparticipantsinthediscourse.

    96

    Withthisidealdiscourse,Habermasseeksforthecriterionoftruthwhichheclaimstobeabsent intheepistemologicaltheoriesthat identifythetruthofanassertionwithamerecorrespondence,mediatedbysensorialexperience,toacertainstateofaffairs. Sinceweallhavedifferentexperiences,aconceptionoftruthbasedsolelyonsensorialperceptionwouldprovetobemistakenbecauseitcannotguaranteetheobjectivityoftheknowledge

    itprovides. Sincethereisnorealityobjectivelyaccessibletooursenses,therationalityofthe expressions used by A or B can only be assessed in terms of the discursiveredeemability of the validity claims contained in the speech acts performed by eachspeaker. Inotherwords,byunderstandingthediscourseasanargumentativeprocedure,HabermasisclaimingthatinthelinguisticinteractionsbetweenAandBbothraiseclaimswith their symbolic expressions, claims that can be criticized and argued for, that is,grounded.

    97 A judgmentabout the truth, in the caseof constatative speech acts, or

    aboutthecorrectness,inregulativespeechacts,wherewhatisatstakeisnottheassertionofafact,butratherthevalidityofanorm

    98canonlybeobjectiveifitisundertakenon

    thebasisofatranssubjectivevalidityclaim, insuchawaythattheassertionsandgoal

    95Habermas,supranote89.

    96Id.at171.

    97JRGENHABERMAS,1THETHEORYOFCOMMUNICATIVEACTION: REASONANDTHERATIONALIZATIONOFSOCIETY9(1984).

    98Habermas,supranote89,at130.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    29/36

    2011] 721CommentonPetroski

    directedactionsarethemorerationalthebettertheclaimthatisconnectedwiththemcan

    be defended against criticism.99 Hence, Habermas needs to adopt a concept ofcommunicative rationality which is based on a discourse whose formal properties arecapableofgeneratinganunconstrainedandunifyingconsensus.

    100

    Like assertions about facts, normatively regulated actions also contain signifyingexpressionswhichareconnectedtocriticizablevalidityclaims. Thenormstowhichtheseactionsreferalsocanbeintersubjectivelyrecognized,andthediscursiveredeemabilityofthevalidityclaims raised for thesenorms iswhatconstitutes their rationality.

    101 In the

    field of ethics, Habermas adopts a cognitivist position according to which practical ornormative questions can be resolved bymeans of an argumentation put forward in apractical discourse where the correctness of the norm is scrutinized.

    102 This type of

    discourse is a communicative process that can only be rational if it approaches the

    following

    ideal

    conditions:

    (1)

    the

    speakers

    must

    be

    in

    an

    ideal

    speech

    situation

    which

    isbasicallycharacterizedbythegeneralsymmetryofconditions,sothateachparticipantinthediscoursecanstructurehisspeechactsinawaythatthereisnocoercionotherthatthe rational force of the better arguments;

    103 (2) the argumentation, as a process of

    communication, must be understood as a a form of interaction subjected to specialrules;and (3) theargumentationhasas itsaim toproducecogentarguments thatareconvincing in virtue of their intrinsic properties andwith which validity claims can beredeemedorrejected.

    104

    SinceIcannotmoveanydeeperintothistheoryofrationaldiscourse,Iwilllimitmyselftostressoneof thepointswhichappear tobecentral toAlexyandMacCormick: the ideathatregulativespeechactsalwaysraiseaclaimtonormativecorrectness. ItisonthebasisofthispremisethatAlexyarguesthatineveryactofcreationandapplicationoflawaclaim

    thatsuchactiscorrectisimplicitlyraised. Inthecoreofthisclaimtherewouldbe: (1)Theassertionthatthe legalact issubstantiallyandprocedurallycorrect;(2)Theclaim (whichgenerates a guarantee) of justifiability of this assertion; and (3) The expectation ofacceptanceofcorrectnessbyalladdresseesofthelegalnorm.

    105 ButhowcanAlexyjustify

    this thesis? Heanswers thisquestion in the followingway: [A]n implicitclaim canbe

    99HABERMAS,supranote97,at9.

    100Id.at10.

    101Id.at1516.

    102Id.at19.

    103Id.at25.

    104Id.at25.

    105RobertAlexy,LawandCorrectness,51CURRENTLEGALPROBLEMS205,208(1998).

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    30/36

    [Vol.12No.02722 Ge rman L aw J ou rna lmade explicit by showing that its express negation is absurd.

    106 He follows, thus, a

    formalpragmaticstrategyofshowingthattheexplicitnegationoftheclaimtocorrectnessentails a contradiction between the content of the legal act (be it a statute, a judicialdecisionetc.)andthecontentoftheclaimimplicitinitsenactment. Alexycallsthiskindofcontradictionaperformativecontradiction.

    107 Everyparticipant in legaldiscoursewho

    expresslydeniestheclaimtocorrectnesscommitsacontradictionofthiskind. Itwouldbeaperformativecontradiction, for instance, if in theenactmentofaconstitution the firstarticleexpresslyassertedthatX isanunjustState. Thesamewouldhappen ifa judgepronouncedasentencestatingsomethinglikeXisherebyconvictedtolifeimprisonment,although this isan incorrect interpretationofvalid law. This judgesdecision couldbeclassifiedasabsurdbecauseitwouldcontainbothanimplicitassertionthatitisacorrectdecisionandanexplicitassertionwhichcontradictstheimplicitpart.

    Alexy

    argues,

    in

    one

    of

    the

    main

    points

    of

    his

    argument

    to

    justify

    his

    definition

    of

    law,

    that

    theclaimtocorrectnesshasthefunctionofestablishinganecessaryconnectionbetweenlawandmorality,whichisdescribedasacomplexconnectionthathasatthesametimeaqualifying and a conceptually necessary character: It is a necessary character becauseeverylegalsystemnecessarilyraisesaclaimtocorrectness(andthustherecanbenolegalsystemthatdoesnotraisetheclaim),but it isaqualifyingcharacter (unlikeaclassifyingcharacter)becausethe legalsystemsand legalnormsthatdonot fulfilltheexigenciesofthe claim to correctnessmay remain valid in a legal sense, despite being conceptuallyflawed.

    108 Theclaimtocorrectnessgeneratesaweakdutytodojusticeaccordingtothe

    law,notanabsoluteone.

    Butapositivistjuristcouldstillask: Whatistherelevanceofaclaimtocorrectness,ifithasonly a qualifying character? Alexy contests this question by arguing that the claim to

    correctness is not only a moral claim, but also a legal claim. And this legal claimcorrespondswithalegalobligationnecessarilyconnectedwithjudicialjudgmentstohanddown correct decisions.

    109 It attributes to law an ideal character that is especially

    relevantforthosewhoanalyzelawfromthepointofviewoftheparticipants. Thus,whenapplication of the law results in an injustice (and thereforedoes not fulfill the state ofaffairsrequiredbytheclaimtocorrectness),wearefacingnotonlyamoralfault,butalsoalegalfault. InAlexysownwords,[t]heclaimtocorrectnesstransformsmoralfaultinessinto legalfaultiness. Andthis isbynomeanstrivial. It istheconversionofpositivismto

    106RobertAlexy,DerechoyMoral,inLAINSTITUCIONALIZACINDELAJUSTICIA21(2005).

    107Alexy,supranote105,at210.

    108SeegenerallyALEXY,supranote10.

    109Alexy,supranote105,at216.

  • 8/7/2019 PDF Vol 12 No 02 693-728 Positivism Special Bust Am Ante FINAL

    31/36

    2011] 723CommentonPetroski

    nonpositivism. Laws claim to correctness isonno account identicalwith the claim to

    moralcorrectness,butitincludesaclaimtomoralcorrectness.110

    Theclaimtocorrectnessattributesto lawan idealcharacterthatwasnotpresent inthepositivisticaccounts thatdefined the legal system asmere facticityor the resultof theexerciseofauthority. Thisidealdimensionoflawsupportsageneralprincipleofmoralitywhich isvalidasa legalnorm implicit inevery legalsystem. Alongwiththisclaim,Alexyrecognizesanormpragmaticallypresupposedthatcontainsadutyofcorrectlyinterpretingandapplyingthelegalnorms. Asaconsequenceoftheclaimtocorrectness,onecanarguethat there is amethodological argumentative connection between law andmorality

    111

    which impliesthat legalofficialshaveaprimafacie legaldutytodojusticeaccordingtothe law. This is precisely what MacCormick means when he holds that the law isnecessarily geared to justice, and such claim is obviously at odds with any form of

    positivism.

    To

    say

    the

    least,

    it

    attaches

    to

    law

    an

    aspirational

    character

    and

    introduces

    a

    distinctionbetweentheactualpositive lawandtheidealpositive law,112

    aswellasadiscursive obligation for legal agents to attempt to reconcile the two of them in theirconstructiveinterpretations.

    5. TheSpecialCaseThesis

    Furthermore,afewwordscanbesaidaboutthethesisthatthelegalreasoningisaspecialcase ofpractical discourse. The special case thesis is relevant for the theories of legalargumentationbecause itmakes iteasiertoseethe formalpragmaticpresuppositionsoflegaldiscourse. Whenwesaythatlegaldiscourse isaspecialcaseofpracticaldiscourse,we commit ourselves to the view that there are some discursive obligations for theparticipants in this type of discourse. Whatever constraints are applicable to general

    practicaldiscoursesarealsovalid for legaldiscourse,albeitwiththeadditionalconditionthat the speakers have to complywith the positive lawswithwhich they operate. AsMacCormickwrites toexpresshisagreementwithRobertAlexysoriginal formulationofthethesis,legalargumentationmustbeacknowledgedtobeonespecialcaseofgeneralpracticalreasoning,andmustthusconformtoconditionsofrationalityandreasonablenessthatapplytoallsortsofpracticalreasoning.

    113

    110RobertAlexy,OntheNecessaryConnectionbetweenLawandMorality: BulyginsCritique,13RATIOJURIS138,