numinous approachin.pdf

  • Upload
    jessica

  • View
    223

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    1/11

     

    Approaching the Numinous: Rudolf Otto and Tibetan TantraAuthor(s): Donald S. Lopez, Jr.Source: Philosophy East and West , Vol. 29, No. 4 (Oct., 1979), pp. 467-476Published by: University of Hawai'i PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1398815

    Accessed: 25-04-2016 17:54 UTC 

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

    http://about.jstor.org/terms

     

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted

    digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about

    JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toPhilosophy East and West 

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    2/11

     Donald S. Lopez, Jr. Approaching the numinous: Rudolf Otto and

     Tibetan tantra

     In Oriental art there may be no more evocative portrayal of what Rudolf Otto

     calls the mysterium tremendum than the wrathful deities of Tibetan Tantric

     Buddhism. Fearful in form, wreathed in flames, adorned with garlands of

     human heads, and brandishing dagger and skull-cup, their painted images

     conjure the feelings of dread and fascination which Otto describes in The Idea

     of the Holy. In this seminal work, he sets out to describe the central element

     of religious experience such that there is no religion in which it does not live

     as the real innermost core, and without it no religion would be worthy of the

     name. 1

     This article will be an inquiry into whether the holy, described as mys-

     terium tremendum, does indeed stand as the core of the tantric path of

     Tibetan Buddhism and will be a comparison of the methods of approaching

     the holy or numinous as set forth by Otto and Tibetan scholars. The

     presentation of tantra given here will follow that of the Gelukba order of

     Tibetan Buddhism, relying especially on the writings of Tsong-ka-pa

     (1357-1419), its founder.

     In The Idea of the Holy Otto rejects the views held by many psychologists,

     historians of religion, philosophers, and anthropologists that religion is a

     fact in nature and, to be understood, must be seen as a product of the same

     laws of nature that determine other natural phenomena. 2 Nor does he see

     religion, as does Clifford Geertz, as a system of conceptions formulated by

     man in response to ignorance, pain, and injustice.3

     Rather, Otto sees religion as a sui generis category, which stands above all

     natural processes and whose essence is irreducible and unevolvable. He writes

     that if there is any single domain of human experience that presents us with

     something unmistakably specific and unique, peculiar to itself, assuredly it is

     that of religious life. 4 This essence he calls the numinous, which is the

     object of religious experience, and which we cannot but feel 5 for it eludes

     the conceptual way of thinking. 6

     Throughout Otto draws sharp distinctions between the natural and the

     supernatural and between the rational and the nonrational. The numinous

    is not a natural phenomenon and our knowledge of it cannot be gained

     empirically; instead, it issues from the deepest foundation of cognitive

     apprehension that the soul possesses, and though it of course comes into

     being in and amid sensory data and empirical material of the natural world

     and cannot anticipate or dispense with those, yet it does not arise out of them,

     but only by their means. 7 Further, the numinous is nonrational and com-

     pletely eludes apprehension in terms of concepts 8 and can only be sugges-

     ted by means of the special way in which it is reflected in the mind in terms of

     feeling. 9

     Donald S. Lopez, Jr. is a doctoral candidate in Buddhist Studies and an instructor in the Department

     of Religious Studies, University of Virginia.

     Philosophy East and West 29, no. 4 (October, 1979) ( by The University Press of Hawaii. All rights reserved.

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    3/11

     468 Lopez

     It is Otto's view that religion cannot be fully understood through reason

     and rational thought. To support his claim, he looks not to scripture or

     theological treatise, but instead finds his affinity in the words of the mystics,

     Weber's religious virtuosos, because they stress the non-rational or supra-

     rational elements in religion. 10

     The numinous cannot be known through ratiocination; awareness of it

     comes only through the feelings it evokes. Consequently, Otto devotes a great

     part of The Idea of the Holy to a description of these feelings, the first of

     which centers in the subject's sense of creature-consciousness, the emotion of

     a creature, submerged and overwhelmed by its own nothingness in contrast to

     that which is supreme above all creatures. 1 It is a recognition of one's

     insignificance in the face of the absolute, exemplified by Arjuna's response to

     the theophany in the eleventh chapter of the Bhagavad-g£ta.

     Next Otto considers the experience of the mysterium tremendum, which

     carries with it a complex of feelings, with mysterium denoting that which is

     hidden and esoteric, that which is beyond conception or understanding,

     extraordinary and unfamiliar. 12 Tremendum evokes a peculiar dread of

     something uncanny, aweful, weird, eerie, and absolutely unapproachable,

     causing the flesh to creep. Throughout his description, Otto stresses that

     although these feelings may have analogs among natural moments of

     consciousness, there is a qualitative difference between them. For example, he

     characterizes the dread of the tremendum as something other than natural

     fear, a terror fraught with an inward shuddering such as not even the most

     menacing and overpowering created thing can instil. 13

     As the object of these feelings, the numinous is endowed with might,

     power, transcendence, absolute overpoweringness, majesty, and a plenitude

     of being surpassing any created thing. It has urgency, energy, passion, and

     emotional temper. Because it is that which is quite beyond the sphere of the

     usual, the intelligible, and the familiar, 14 it is called the wholly other

    which brings forth feelings of wonder, amazement, and astonishment. The

     numinous produces a captivating attraction in one sensitive to it-the

     element of fascination. Otto finds these feeling-responses to be common to all

     forms of mysticism.

     Not only does he enumerate these various reactions to the numinous, he

     also emphatically contends that these feelings are the only media through

     which the numinous, or reality, can be known. Words, concepts, reasoning,

     and rational thought are incapable of producing true experience of the wholly

     other, which can only be firmly grasped, thoroughly understood, and

     profoundly appreciated, purely in, with, and from the feeling itself. 15

     Otto traces these experiences of the numinous to the most primitive

     religious consciousness, where the feeling-response was one of daemonic

     dread. This crude consciousness of the numinous evolved over the centuries

     to a more elevated and noble experience. Throughout this process of religious

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    4/11

     469

     evolution, however, the object of these feelings remains the nonrational

     numinous, and the element of dread felt by the primitive savage, though

     superseded by other responses, does not disappear on the highest level of all,

     where the worship of God is at its purest. 16 And although this process of

     evolution has occurred in all the great religions, it has reached its culmination

     in Christianity, which stands out in complete superiority over its sister

     religions. 7 Thus, against all those who would see the rise of religion

     emanating from any number of natural factors, Otto holds the numinous to

     be the basic factor and basic impulse underlying the entire process of

     religious evolution. 18

     Although Otto discounts reason as having any relation to the numinous

     whatsoever, he discovers a close relationship between the feeling of the

     numinous and aesthetic experience. He finds the feelings of the sublime, the

     beautiful, and the experience of music to be nonconceptual, nonrational, and

     wholly other, much like that of the numinous.

     Weber also notes such a similarity between religion and art. However,

     Weber observes that for the mystic the indubitable psychological affinity of

     profoundly shaking experience in art and religion can only be a symptom of

     the diabolical nature of art. 19 The mystic is seeking to transcend all form in

     order to achieve union with a reality that is beyond form. Weber perceives a

     contradiction between religion and art, with the result that the more religion

     has emphasized either the supra-worldliness of its God or the other-

     worldliness of salvation, the more harshly has art been refuted. 20

     Otto on the other hand, far from refuting art, suggests that aesthetic

     feelings reveal the transcendent reality, that in great art the point is reached

     at which we may no longer speak of the 'magical,' but rather are confronted

     with the numinous itself, with all its impelling power, transcending reason,

     expressed in sweeping lines and rhythm. 21

     Nonetheless, the numinous is a purely a priori category, underivable and

     irreducible. It cannot be explained but only presupposed. This numinous

     undergoes a process of development whereby it becomes moralized, gaining

     ethical meaning through being endowed with rational qualities of absolute-

     ness, completeness, morality, purpose, justice, goodness, and love. The wholly

     other numinous, having become completely permeated and saturated by

     these rational qualities, becomes what Otto calls the holy. He finds these

     rational qualities also to be a priori and not to be 'evolved' from any sort of

     sense perception. 22 Further, the connection of the numinous to these ethical

     qualities, the relation of the nonrational to the rational, is not to be derived

     from reasoning, but is also a priori.23

     Finally, our capacity for experience of the numinous is a priori as well. The

     object of religious experience is the numinous, of which we are aware through

     numinous feelings. Objectively, the numinous seems to act as a stimulus for

     these feelings. However, from the subject's side there exists an a priori

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    5/11

     470 Lopez

     potency which allows the numinous to be experienced. This Otto calls a

     hidden, substantive source, from which the religious ideas and feelings are

     formed, which lies in the mind independently of sense-experience. 24 It is a

      primal element of our psychical nature that needs to be grasped in its

     uniqueness and cannot itself be explained by anything else. 25

     Despite philosophical problems that may inhere in such a wholesale

     attribution of the a priori category to all things religious,26 it is important to

     consider Otto's purpose at this point. The Idea of the Holy is not intended as a

     philosophical treatise proving the existence of the numinous; rather it is an

     apology for the intuitive element of religious experience. Otto does not intend

     to persuade the unconvinced with his arguments. His words are offered only

     to kindred spirits, those whose innate capacity for the numinous has been

     awakened, for whom he eloquently verbalizes the experience of the holy, the

     feeling which remains where the concept fails. 27 At the very outset, Otto

     invites the reader to direct his mind to a moment of deeply-felt religious

     experience, as little as possible qualified by other forms of consciousness.

     Whoever cannot do this, whoever knows no such moments in his experience,

     is requested to read no further. 28 It is his purpose then, to suggest this

     unnamed Something to the reader as far as we may, so that he may himself

     feel it. 29

     Thus, having stressed the intuitive aspect of religious experience, having

     presented numinous feeling for the sake of awakening that feeling, Otto in the

     end makes his appeal to feeling. The numinous is something which the

     'natural' man cannot, as such, know or even imagine, 30 and no intellectual,

     dialectical dissection or justification of such intuition is possible, nor indeed

     should any be attempted, for the essence most peculiar to it would be

     destroyed thereby. 31 Rather, the numinous must be directly experienced to

     be understood.

     Once experienced, there need not be doubt concerning the validity of these

     numinous feelings for they are a priori by which Otto means that as soon as

     an assertion has been clearly expressed and understood, knowledge of its

     truth comes into the mind with the certitude of first-hand insight. 32 In short,

     religious experience is autonomous, self-validating, and infallible. When the

     numinous feelings that Otto describes are experienced, there is immediate

     certainty that this is a realization of the deepest truth; religious experience

      represents a perception which provides its own evidence. 33

     It is Otto's contention that the numinous and the feelings it evokes are

     common to all religions. To test this claim in the case of Tibetan tantra, it is

     first necessary to identify the numinous element in Buddhism.

     According to the Prasangika-Madhyamika school, the highest system of

     tenets in Tibet, every object of knowledge, permanent or impermanent, is a

     phenomenon (dharma). Even the highest nature of an object, its emptiness, is

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    6/11

     4 71

     a phenomenon. Taking phenomena in this sense, there are no noumena apart

     from phenomena in Buddhism, and our inquiry is cut short.

     However, if we take the view found in Western metaphysics that pheno-

     mena refer to sense objects and that behind the phenomena which present

     themselves in everyday experience, there lie realities whose existence and

     properties can be established only by the use of the intellect and which can

     hence be described as noumena, 34 we then have a distinction between

     noumena and phenomena that can be applied to the Prasangika-

     Madhyamika view. That is, impermanent things or products (samskrta), the

     appearing objects of direct perception (pratyaksa), are phenomena and those

     objects which initially must be known through relying on inference (anumdana)

     are noumena.35 For the purpose of comparison with Otto, we may consider

     only the most important of such objects-emptinesses (sunyatd)-the ul-

     timate truths (paramdrthasatya) of the Prasangika-Madhyamika system, the

     realization of which leads to liberation from cyclic existence (samsdra). Otto

     identifies emptiness as the numinous element in Buddhism, writing that the

     'void' [emptiness] of the eastern, like the 'nothing' of the western, mystic is a

     numinous ideogram of the 'wholly other.' 36

     An emptiness, according to Prasangika, is an object's lack of inherent

     existence (svabhava-siddhi); and when it is realized what appears to the mind

     is a clear vacuity accompanied by the mere thought, 'These concrete things as

     they now appear to our minds do not exist at all.' 37 In the direct realization

     of emptiness, the mind and emptiness are said to be mixed like fresh water

     poured into fresh water.38

     Since Buddhism is an atheistic religion in the sense that it denies the

     existence of a preexistent creator deity, the experience of the numinous does

     not carry with it the feeling of creature-consciousness which Otto describes.39

     Emptiness is a mere negative, a lack of a falsely conceived predicate of

     existence.40

     Reference is made in Prasafigika to a fear which arises in the practice of

     emptiness. It is said that a person with a slight understanding of emptiness

     becomes fearful because the phenomenon suddenly appears to his mind as

     not existing at all. 41 When emptiness is realized directly, however, all fear is

     dispelled because the source of fear-the conception of true existence-has

     disappeared. This fear bears little resemblance to the dread and terror that

     Otto describes which produces creeping flesh and which never disappears,

     even at the highest level of mystical experience.

     Emptiness is neither shrouded in mystery, nor is it a numinous ideogram

     of the wholly other. 42 An emptiness is not other than the phenomenon it

     qualifies in that they are of the same entity. Through the practice of the path,

     emptiness can be realized in a direct, nonconceptual, nondualistic experience

     free of doubt and mystery.43

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    7/11

     472 Lopez

     Otto holds the mysterious to be an essential attribute of religious ex-

     perience and for support points to a mode of manifestation that in every

     religion occupies a foremost and extraordinary place, 44 namely, miracle.

     Although the settings and circumstances of many Buddhist suitras, especially

     in the Mahayana, may be termed magical or miraculous, miracles are not a

     central teaching technique of Buddha.

     Buddhas neither wash sins away with water

     Nor remove beings' suffering with their hands

     Nor transfer their realizations to others; beings

     Are freed through the teaching of the truth, the nature of things.45

     Regarding miracles, it is noteworthy to compare the reactions of Christ and

     Buddha in a similar situation-being request to restore the life of a dead

     child. Christ resurrected Jairus' daughter,46 while Buddha, in the Parable of

     the Mustard Seed,47 used the opportunity to teach the mother of the child the

     all-pervasive nature of suffering. In both cases, it can be assumed that one

     result was that witnesses were inspired to follow the teaching, although the

     techniques of the two teachers were quite different.

     Weber notes a more general difference in the style of teaching of Buddha as

     compared to those of Jesus and Muhammad:

     Neither the short parable, the ironic dismissal, or the pathetic penitential

     sermon of the Galilean prophet, nor the address resting on visions of the

     Arabic holy leader find any sort of parallels to the lectures and conversations

     which seem to have constituted the true form of Buddha's activity. They

     address themselves purely to the intellect and affected the quiet, sober

     judgement detached from all internal excitement; their factual manner

     exhausts the topic always in systematic dialectical fashion.48

     The emphasis on reason and analysis which Weber observes in the

     Theravada sutttas is also an essential element in the tantric path. In Tsofig-

     kha-pa's major work on tantra, The Great Exposition of Secret Mantra, he

     explains that before beginning practice one must have firm conviction that the

     system one has chosen to follow is correct. A choice between two systems is

     not an act of partisanship but should be based on reasoned analysis.

     Specifically, the scriptures of the two systems are what are to be analysed to

     find which does or does not bear the truth; thus, it would not be suitable to

     cite them as proof (of their own truth). Only reason distinguishes what is or is

     not true. 49

     Citation of scripture, mere belief, or respect are not suitable bases for

     strong conviction in a system of practice, as is evident in this quotation from

     the Buddha:

     Monks and scholars should

     Well analyze my words,

     Like gold (to be tested) through melting, cutting, and polishing,

     And then adopt them, but not for the sake of showing me respect.50

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    8/11

     473

     Reasoning is also essential to the practice of emptiness, through which the

     wisdom is generated which bestows liberation from suffering. According to

     Tsong-kha-pa's Ge-lug-pa order, it is a basic tenet of all three Buddhist

     vehicles-Hinayana, Perfection, and Mantra (or Tantra)-that direct re-

     alization of emptiness is gained through an initial acquaintance with an

     inferential realization of emptiness gained through reasoning, the basis of

     which is empirical. The fourteenth Dalai Lama, the current leader of the

     Gelukba order, states that the generation of a conceptual consciousness

     realizing emptiness must depend solely on a correct reasoning.

     Fundamentally, therefore, the process traces back solely to a reasoning, which

     itself must fundamentally trace back to valid experiences common to our-

     selves and others. 51 Such reasonings are those set forth by Nagarjuna in his

     Treatise on the Middle Way (Madhyamakasdstra).

     According to Ge-lug-pa, the many reasonings presented by Nagarjuna are

     explicitly intended for the purpose of destroying the conception of inherent

     existence, the root cause of suffering. As far as this false conception forms the

     basis of philosophical systems, it can be said that Nagarjuna's arguments

     refute the positions of those systems. Nevertheless, the fundamental purpose

     of reasoning in Prasafigika-Madhyamika is to generate the wisdom which

     eradicates suffering and its causes. Refutations of opposing tenet systems are

     subsidiary.

     A number of differences are thus evident between Otto and the Buddhist

     Ge-lug-pa position regarding the numinous element of religious experience.

     Otto's observations are astute when applied to the Abrahamic religions and

     theistic Hinduism. Yet the strength of his argument often relies on the

     existence of a creator deity endowed with the qualities of transcendence,

     majesty, and power, from whom man seeks atonement, which Otto sees as a

     longing to transcend this sundering unworthiness, given with the self's

     existence as 'creature' and profane natural being. 52

     It is difficult to construe a parallel with Buddhism, which lacks such a

     creator god of whom we are creatures. The religious impulsion in Buddhism

     is not a priori, but a natural reaction to suffering and the practice of a

     prescribed set of teachings to escape that suffering, for the sake of oneself in

     Hlnayana, for others in Mahayana.53 The dharma is not an end in itself but,

     like a raft, is to be discarded upon reaching the further shore.54

     According to Malinowski's distinction between magic and religion, one is

     then forced to assign Buddhism to the category of magic, which he defines as

      a practical art consisting of acts which are only means to a definite end

     expected to follow later on 55 and which are not ends in themselves. This is

     not to suggest that Buddhism is indeed magic, but rather to point out the

     difficulty, also encountered in Otto, in making general statements which are

     intended to hold true for all religions.

     Returning to Otto, the more important point, however, is his contention

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    9/11

     474 Lopez

     that reasoning has no part in religious experience, where coercion by proof

     and demonstration and the mistaken application of logical and juridical

     processes should be excluded. 56 For him, the absolute exceeds our power

     to comprehend; the mysterious wholly eludes. 57 The nonconceptual, non-

     rational numinous cannot be approached with conceptuality and reason;

      mysticism has nothing to do with 'reason' and 'rationality.' 58

     According to the Ge-lug-pa position, the direct experience of emptiness, in

     both the sutra and tantra systems, is nonconceptual. Yet without relying on

     reasoning and analysis, such an experience is impossible. In answer to how

     analysis and thought can serve as a cause for nonconceptuality, the fifth Dalai

     Lama (1617-1682) cites the Kasyapa Chapter Sutra (Kdayapa-parivarta):

      Kashyapa, it is thus: For example, fire arises when the wind rubs two

     branches together. Once the fire has arisen, the two branches are burned. Just

     so Kashyapa, if you have the correct analytical intellect, a superior's faculty

     of wisdom is generated. Through its generation, the correct analytical intellect

     is consumed. 59 That is, conceptual thought can lead to experience of the

     nonconceptual, that which is beyond thought.

     Reasoning alone, however, is not sufficient; the process of insight is not

     merely an intellectual exercise. Reasoning is an essential element of wisdom,

     the third element in the triad of ethics (sTla), meditative stabilization (sam-

     ddhi), and wisdom (prajida), all of which are necessary for realization of

     emptiness. For example, a bodhisattva of the suitra system must engage in

     limitless forms of the six perfections (paramita)-giving, ethics, patience,

     effort, concentration, and wisdom-over many aeons in order to accumulate

     the merit which will empower his mind to penetrate emptiness and eventually

     overcome all obstructions.60 In the tantra system, a special technique-deity

     yoga-is taught which allows this accumulation of merit to proceed more

     quickly.61 Thus, the process of reasoning must be conjoined with ethical and

     meditative practices to yield realization of emptiness.

     Reasoning must be used because emptiness is a hidden phenomenon

     (paroksa), unable to appear to direct perception without initially depending

     on reasoning.62 For Otto too, the numinous is hidden in the sense that it is

     something which has no place in our scheme of reality but belongs to an

     absolutely different one, and which at the same time arouses an irrepressible

     interest in the mind. 63 For him, reasoning cannot be the key to the

     experience of the numinous because our knowledge has certain irremovable

     limits. 64

     We find then, two different approaches to this hidden numinous, in-

     accessible to ordinary sense perception. For the Ge-lug-pas, the process of

     reasoning and analysis leads to the experience of reality. For Rudolf Otto,

     reasoning must be discarded, for reality-the holy-is only to be known

     through feeling.

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    10/11

     4 75

     NOTES

     1. Rudolf Otto, The Idea of the Holy, trans. John W. Harvey (London: Oxford University

     Press, 1976), p. 6.

     2. Anthony F. C. Wallace, Religion. An Anthropological View (New York: Random House,

     1966), p. vi.

     3. Clifford Geertz, Religion as a Cultural System, in Reader in Comparative Religion: An

     Anthropological Approach, ed. William A. Lessa and Evon Z. Vogt, 3d ed. (New York: Harper

     and Row, 1972), pp. 171-174.

     4. Otto, p. 4.

     5. Ibid., p. 5.

     6. Ibid., p. 2.

     7. Ibid., p. 113.

     8. Ibid., p. 5.

     9. Ibid., p. 12.

     10. Ibid., p. 22.

     11. Ibid., p. 10.

     12. Ibid., p. 13.

     13. Ibid., p. 14.

     14. Ibid., p. 26.

     15. Ibid., p. 34.

     16. Ibid., p. 17.

     17. Ibid., p. 142.

     18. Ibid., p. 15.

     19. Max Weber, Religious Rejections of the World and their Directions, in From Max

     Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans. Hans H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (New York:

     Oxford University Press, 1976), p. 342.

     20. Ibid., p. 343.

     21. Otto, p. 67.

     22. Ibid., p. 112.

     23. Wach notes that critics have found this to be the weakest element in Otto's presentation.

     See Joachim Wach, Types of Religious Experience Christian and Non-Christian (Chicago, Illinois:

     University of Chicago Press, 1951), p. 222. For an analysis of this relationship between the

     numinous and morality and of the process of schematization whereby the numinous becomes

     endowed with rational qualities see John P. Reeder, The Relation of the Moral and the

     Numinous in Otto's Notion of the Holy, in Religion and Morality: A Collection of Essays, ed.

     Gene Outka and John P. Reeder, Jr. (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor Books, 1973), pp. 255-292.

     24. Ibid., p. 114.

     25. Ibid., p. 124.

     26. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, s.v. Otto, Rudolf, by William J. Wainwright.

     27. Ibid., p. xxi.

     28. Ibid., p. 8.

     29. Ibid., p. 6.

     30. Ibid., p. 51.

     31. Ibid., p. 147.

     32. Ibid., p. 137.

     33. Joachim Wach, Understanding and Believing: Essays by Joachim Wach, edited with an

     Introduction by Joseph M. Kitagawa (Boston, Massachusetts: Harper and Row, 1968), p. 8.

     34. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, s.v. Metaphysics, Nature of, by W. H. Walsh.

     35. Geshe Lhundup Sopa and Jeffrey Hopkins, Practice and Theory of Tibetan Buddhism

     (Rider: London, 1976), p. 134.

     36. Otto, p. 30.

     37. Tenzin Gyatso, The Buddhism of Tibet and the Key to the Middle Way (New York: Harper

     and Row, 1975), p. 77.

    This content downloaded from 140.192.113.143 on Mon, 25 Apr 2016 17:54:13 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 numinous approachin.pdf

    11/11

     476 Lopez

     38. Tsong-ka-pa, Tantra in Tibet: The Great Exposition of Secret Mantra (London: Allen and

     Unwin, 1978), p. 191.

     39. Ninian Smart criticizes Otto on this point using the example of Theravada Buddhism. See

     Ninian Smart, Philosophers and Religious Truth (London: SCM Press Ltd., 1969), p. 113.

     40. Tenzin Gyatso, p. 77.

     41. Ten-dar-hla-ram-pa (bsTan-dar-lha-ram-pa), A Presentation of the Lack of One and Many,

     an Elimination of Error Collected from the Ocean of Good Explanations (Gcig du bral gyi rnam

     gzhag legs bshad rgya mtsho las btus pa'i 'khrul spong bdud rtsi'i gzegs ma) (Lhasa: Great Press at

     the base of the Potala, Fire Dog Male year of the sixteenth cycle), blockprint of 43 folios, pp.

     3a-3b.

     42. Otto, p. 30.

     43. Tsoiig-kha-pa, pp. 191-192.

     44. Otto, p. 63.

     45. Kensur Lekden, Meditations of a Tibetan Tantric Abbot, trans. and ed. Jeffrey Hopkins

     (Dharamsala, India: Library of Tibetan Works and Archives, 1974), p. 109.

     46. Mark 5:21-43.

     47. Sutta Nipdta, trans. V. Fausb6ll, in Sacred Books of the East (Oxford, 1881), Vol. 10, pt. 2,

     pp. 11-15.

     48. Max Weber, The Religion of India: The Sociology of Hinduism and Buddhism, trans. and ed.

     Hans H. Gerth and Don Martindale (New York: The Free Press, 1967), p. 225.

     49. Tsofig-kha-po, p. 87.

     50. Tenzin Gyatso, p. 55.

     51. Ibid., pp. 55-56.

     52. Otto, p. 55.

     53. Tenzin Gyatso, pp. 28-29.

     54. Middle Length Sayings (Majjhima-Nikdya), trans. I. B. Horner, Pali Text Society

     Translation Series, No. 29 (London: The Pali Text Society, 1976), 1:173-74.

     55. Bronislaw Malinowski, Magic, Science and Religion and Other Essays (New York: Anchor

     Books, 1954), p. 88.

     56. Otto, p. 145.

     57. Ibid., p. 141.

     58. Ibid., p. 4.

     59. The Fifth Salai Lama, The Practice of Emptiness, trans. Jeffrey Hopkins (Dharamsala,

     India: Library of Tibetan Works and Archives, 1974), p. 21.

     60. Na-wang-pel-den (Ngag-dbang-dpal-ldan), Presentation of the Grounds and Paths of the

     Four Great Secret Tantra Sets (gSang chen rgyud sde bzhi'i sa lam gyi rnam gzhag rgyud gzhung

     gsal byed) (modern blockprint, rGyud smad par khang, date and place of publication not given),

     pp. 7a3-8al.

     61. Tsoiig-kha-pa, p. 60.

     62. Ibid., p. 32.

     63. Otto, p. 29.

     64. Ibid., p. 59.