Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    1/27

    The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality DecisionsAuthor(s): Linda Novak

    Source: Columbia Law Review, Vol. 80, No. 4 (May, 1980), pp. 756-781

    Published by: Columbia Law Review Association, Inc.

    Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1122139Accessed: 09-06-2016 14:58 UTC

    R F R N S

    Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:

    http://www.jstor.org/stable/1122139?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents

    You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

    http://about.jstor.org/terms

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted

    digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about

    JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    Columbia Law Review Association, Inc.is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extendaccess to Columbia Law Review

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    2/27

    NOTES

    The Precedential Value of Supreme

    Court Plurality Decisions

    The number of Supreme Court plurality decisions' has increased

    dramatically in recent years.2 Because they do not provide any single

    line of reasoning supported by a clear majority of the Court, these deci-

    sions pose substantial difficulties for lower courts attempting to ascertain

    their precedential value, difficulties compounded by the variety of forms

    that plurality decisions can take.3 With the benefit of only spotty guid-

    ance from the Supreme Court,4 lower courts have relied largely on intu-

    ition and common sense in handling plurality decisions. Neither they

    nor legal scholars have articulated a more systematic and principled ap-

    proach to the problem.5

    This Note first examines the values underlying the precedential system

    of judicial decisionmaking and the role plurality opinions play in this

    system. The Note then identifies approaches commonly used by courts

    to deal with plurality decisions, analyzing their theoretical soundness and

    practical utility. Finally, the Note suggests normative standards to pro-

    mote a more rational treatment of plurality decisions.

    1. Plurality decisions, also called no-clear-majority decisions, are those in which a

    majority of the Court agrees upon the judgment but not upon a single rationale to support

    the result. Thus, there is no opinion of the Court in the ordinary sense. Plurality

    decisions are to be distinguished from affirmances by an equally divided Court, when there

    is no majority agreement even on the result, and from per curiam opinions, in which a

    majority of Justices expresses at least summary agreement on the reasoning. This Note

    uses the term plurality opinion or the plurality to refer to the opinion designated as the

    lead opinion of the Court, which is not always the opinion subscribed to by the largest

    number of Justices. Other opinions that join the judgment are designated as concurrences,

    even if they receive more votes than the lead opinion.

    2. The Supreme Court issued 45 plurality opinions from the early 1800's, when Chief

    Justice Marshall discarded the practice of issuing individual opinions seriatim and began

    issuing opinions of the Court, to 1956. For an exhaustive survey of the plurality decisions

    issued during that period and their treatment by lower courts, see Comment, Supreme Court

    No-Clear-Majority Decisions: A Study in Stare Decisis, 24 U. Chi. L. Rev. 99 (1956)

    [hereinafter cited as Chicago Comment]. Since the 1955 Term the Court has issued 101

    plurality decisions.

    3. Plurality decisions can be typed according to the exact alignment of the Justices

    and the relationships between the lines of reasoning employed. Each type of opinion poses

    distinct problems of interpretation. See generally Chicago Comment, supra note 2, suggesting

    that there is a pattern to the treatment courts have given to different types of opinions.

    4. See Marks v. United States, 430 U.S. 188 (1977); Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153

    (1976), discussed in notes 30-31 and accompanying text infra.

    5. Several commentators have discussed the problems posed by plurality opinions without

    specifically considering how such opinions should be interpreted by the lower courts. See,

    e.g., Davis & Reynolds, Juridical Cripples: Plurality Opinions in the Supreme Court, 1974

    Duke L.J. 59 [hereinafter cited as Juridical Cripples] (examining reasons for increase in

    plurality opinions, noting adverse effects of such decisions, and suggesting alternatives);

    Comment, A Suggestion for the Prevention of No-Clear-Majority Judicial Decisions, 46

    Tex. L. Rev. 370 (1968) [hereinafter cited as Texas Comment]; Note, Lower Court Disavowal

    of Supreme Court Precedent, 60 Va. L. Rev. 494 (1974) [hereinafter cited as Lower Court

    Disavowal]; Chicago Comment, supra note 2.

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    3/27

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    4/27

    758 COLUMBIA LAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    conduct and decisions of the bench, bar, and general public, and can

    facilitate decisions whether to litigate, settle, or not to act at all. More-

    over, articulation of the legal principles underlying a particular decision,

    and adherence to those principles in subsequent cases, serves as a check

    on judicial bias and arbitrariness. Just as importantly, it creates an appear-

    ance of impersonality, fairness, and consistency that fosters public faith

    in the judicial process.8 Our system's emphasis on reasoning suggests that

    the objectives of the precedential system-certainty, reliance, equality, and

    efficiency9-are ultimately best served not by blind adherence to particular

    judgments deemed to be controlling, but by the orderly development of

    well-reasoned legal principles that build logically upon each other and can

    survive testing over time and in a variety of situations.'0

    The traditional notion of the ratio decidendi was that the judgment

    and reasoning components of judicial decisions should be fused into one

    cohesive whole. The recent increase in plurality decisions, however, in-

    dicates a departure from this theoretical ideal, because plurality decisions

    frequently advance different rationales to support the same judgment.

    Although the lack of a supporting majority rationale impairs neither the

    effect of the judgment in the particular case nor its precedential value in

    identical cases, it clearly undermines the precedential value for dissimilar

    cases. Faced with ambivalent signals and discrete, often contradictory

    rationales, lower courts feel compelled to guess how a majority of Justices

    would resolve the particular legal issue presented, and at least one court

    has thrown up its hands in frustration, refusing to accord a plurality deci-

    sion any weight whatsoever.12

    8. See generally Hardisty, Reflections on Stare Decisis, 55 Ind. L.J. 41 (1979).

    9. The goal of certainty refers primarily to the possibility of predicting judicial decisions,

    and is grounded in the belief that it is important that individuals be able to predict the legal

    consequences of their actions. The goal of reliance reflects the view that, having induced a

    person to act in a certain manner, our legal system assumes an obligation not to thwart that

    person's expectation of legality. Equality refers to the fundamental expectation of our

    system of justice, that similarly situated individuals will be treated equally. Finally, adherence

    to precedent promotes judicial efficiency, by providing courts with a ready source of justifica-

    tion for reaching a particular decision. For a more detailed discussion of the major justifica-

    tions for the doctrine of precedent, see R. Wasserstrom, The Judicial Decision 60-73 (1961).

    10. One commentator has expressed this distinction in terms of rule stare decisis,

    where a court adheres to the general rule of law promulgated by a prior court in support

    of its judgment, and result stare decisis, where a court is free to adopt a new justifying

    rule so long as the result reached is consistent with the result in the earlier case. Hardisty,

    supra note 8, at 52-57. Consistency in this context does not mean that the court must reach

    an identical result, but rather that any difference in result must be justified by a material

    difference in the facts of the later case. Result stare decisis may imply a less restrictive

    use of precedent, for it provides subsequent courts with greater leeway to modify the rule of

    law proposed in the prior decision. The choice of whether to follow result stare decisis

    or rule stare decisis depends in large measure on the clarity, specificity, and definiteness

    with which the court establishing the precedent articulated its grounds of decision. Id.

    This distinction between rule and result stare decisis provides a useful conceptual

    framework for analyzing lower court treatment of plurality decisions.

    11. According to the strict classical theory of precedent, the lack of a clear majority

    rationale in support of the judgment deprived the judgment of all precedential value, and the

    decision was considered authority for the result only. See generally H. Black, Law of

    Judicial Precedents 10 (1912); E. Wambaugh, The Study of Cases 98 (2d. ed. 1894).

    12. See, e.g., Baker v. State, 15 Md. App. 73, 289 A.2d 348 (1972), cert. denied,

    411 U.S. 951 (1973), discussed in notes 80-84 and accompanying text infra.

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    5/27

    1980] PLURALITY OPINONS 759

    Commentators have sought to explain this apparent breakdown in the

    judicial decisionmaking process by pointing to a number of factors.'3 In-

    stitutional pressures are one possible cause. The increasingly heavy

    Supreme Court workload may render the process of hammering out in-

    dividual differences and articulating a clear common ground of agreement

    simply too time-consuming and difficult.'4 Another likely factor is the

    Court's more frequent involvement in controversial, emotionally charged

    areas of the law, such as obscenity, capital punishment, and affirmative

    action, where efforts at compromise are likely to founder in the face of

    strongly held personal convictions.'- Aggravating the effects of involve-

    ment in these more volatile or undeveloped areas of the law are ideolog-

    ical splits and personality differences among the Justices.'6 Yet another

    important factor is the quality of leadership provided by the Chief Justice,

    in terms of his desire and ability to promote compromise and to persuade

    other Justices to subordinate individual differences.'7

    Whatever its root causes, the proliferation of plurality decisions has

    far-reaching implications. The bulk of commentary on the subject has

    unequivocally condemned the practice, stressing the erosion of Supreme

    Court credibility and authority as a source of moral and legal leadership.'8

    Commentators have also criticized plurality decisions because they en-

    gender confusion in the lower courts, causing instability and uncertainty

    in critical areas of the law, which in turn produces wasteful and repeti-

    tious litigation.19

    13. See generally Juridical Cripples, supra note 5; McWhinney, Judicial Concurrences

    and Dissents: A Comparative View of Opinion-writing in Final Appellate Tribunals, 31 Can.

    B.R. 595 (1953); Texas Comment, supra note 5.

    14. One commentator has suggested that although a reduced workload might facilitate

    the resolution of internal controversies in some cases, the lack of time is not by itself an

    adequate answer, and that even extended opportunities for collegial negotiation will not

    result in compromise when Justices hold sharply differing views. See Juridical Cripples,

    supra note 5, at 77-80.

    15. In exercising its selective jurisdiction, the Court increasingly has devoted its

    attention to areas of constitutional law involving basic policy issues, and thus has gradually

    been converted into essentially a constitutional tribunal. McWhinney, supra note 13, at

    617. Efforts to obtain majority agreement in these more perplexing areas of the law will

    often fail, since the more a decision turns on a question of basic political beliefs

    rather than on the construction of precedent, . . . the more likely it is that each justice

    will insist on insuring that his voice is heard. Juridical Cripples, supra note 5, at 81.

    16. See, e.g., B. Woodward & S. Armstrong, The Brethren (1979) (detailed accout

    of conflicts on Burger Court).

    17. See generally B. Woodward & S. Armstrong, supra note 16; McWhinney, supra

    note 13, at 617-19.

    18. See, e.g., Juridical Cripples, supra note 5; White, supra note 7; Texas Comment,

    supra note 5.

    19. One commentator has condemned the individualistic trend of judicial opinions

    because it demonstrates reluctance to submerge minor differences at the expense of the

    values of certainty *and uniformity. Ballantine, The Supreme Court: Principles and

    Personalities, 31 A.B.A.J. 113 (1945). Another critic, recognizing that coherence is

    particularly difficult to attain in still-developing and controversial areas of law, condemns

    plurality opinions that agree only on the result because they do not fulfill the Court's

    responsibility to respond to social change. He also argues that the recent resort to

    individual pronouncements frustrates the need for public information and understanding of

    the issues involved. White, supra note 7, at 301. For some suggestions of ways to reduce the

    number of plurality opinions, see Juridical Cripples, supra note 5, at 81-85 (per curiam

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    6/27

    760 COLUMBALAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    In denouncing the Supreme Court for abdicating its essential function

    and promulgating juridical cripples, 20 however, the commentators have

    generally overlooked the positive effects that plurality decisions may have,

    most notably on judicial freedom and flexibility. When there is a funda-

    mental disagreement among the members of the Court on a particular

    legal principle, it is arguably more valuable for the sound development of

    the law to have the Justices articulate their individual positions than to

    insist on superficial agreement.2' Plurality opinions are often more

    thoughtful and of generally higher quality than short per curiam opinions,22

    because a minority opinion must be particularly convincing to command

    respect. The writer of a minority opinion need not water down or restrict

    his views to muster majority support, and thus plurality decisions may

    free the Justices to engage in more innovative and creative analyses and

    to tackle more controversial and unsettled issues, with the knowledge that

    their tentative views will not be considered binding on lower courts.

    Multiple opinions can also mitigate the stranglehold of a strict precedent

    system by affording lower courts increased opportunities to distinguish

    future cases, and by providing theories from which alternative lines of

    reasoning can be derived in future cases.23 Thus, plurality decisions allow

    lower courts an extra measure of freedom to adapt to changing condi-

    tions and to achieve equitable results within the logical boundaries of

    Supreme Court mandates.

    In attempting to extract meaningful guidance from Supreme Court

    plurality decisions, lower courts have generally recognized that different

    types of plurality decisions may pose significantly different problems of

    interpretation and may require different analytical approaches.24 The

    Supreme Court itself, however, has provided guidance on how to interpret

    only one type of plurality decision, that in which the opinions offered in

    support of the result appear to be of varying scope or breadth. In such

    a situation, the Supreme Court has indicated that the opinion concurring

    in the judgment on the narrowest grounds represents the highest com-

    opinion expressing highest common denominator of agreement, or alternatively division of

    each opinion into discrete sections to indicate which Justices agree on each particular

    issue); Texas Comment, supra note 5, at 376-78 (plurality opinion as binding precedent, to

    be issued in conjunction with separate individual opinions).

    20. See Juridical Cripples, supra note 5.

    21. Multiple opinions do tend to impair clarity and certainty in the law, but it is worth

    noting that the need for tidiness in Supreme Court decisions may be less pressing in the

    United States, where the Court plays a relatively limited role in promoting uniformity, than

    in countries such as Canada, where the Supreme Court is the general appellate tribunal

    for the provincial courts in the private law sphere, or Switzerland, where most areas of the

    law are delegated to the central government. See generally McWhinney, supra note 13, at

    619-25. This does not mean that confusion and instability are negligible problems, but

    rather that in particular areas of the law the values of certainty and predictability may be less

    important than the need for carefully considered legal principles.

    22. Contrast the per curiam opinion in a recent death penalty case, Green v. Georgia,

    442 U.S. 95 (1979), with the lengthy and elaborately reasoned opinions in Gregg v.

    Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976) discussed in notes 30-31 and accompanying text infra.

    23. See generally McWhinney, supra note 13, at 623.

    24. See Part II infra.

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    7/27

    1980] PLURALITY OPINONS 761

    mon denominator of majority agreement,25 and thus should be regarded

    as authoritative for future cases.26

    B. The Narrowest Grounds Approach

    The Supreme Court first enunciated the narrowest grounds approach

    in its decisions concerning the constitutionality of capital punishment. In

    Furman v. Georgia,27 a plurality decision, the Court held the imposition

    of the death sentence in that particular case unconstitutional. The five

    Justices supporting the judgment issued five separate opinions. Two

    Justices concluded that capital punishment was unconstitutional per se,28

    and three Justices concurred on the ground that Georgia's statutory pro-

    cedures governing the death penalty were constitutionally defective. These

    latter three Justices declined to reach the question whether capital punish-

    ment might be constitutionally permissible under other circumstances.29

    In Gregg v. Georgia 0 the Court was again called upon to determine

    the constitutionality of Georgia's capital punishment scheme, which the

    state had revised in light of Furman. Thus, Gregg presented the task of

    determining the precedential effect of Furman's nine opinions. The Gregg

    plurality interpreted the holding in Furman as that position taken by

    those Members who concurred in the judgments on the narrowest

    grounds-Mr. Justice Stewart and Mr. Justice White. 3' The Court there-

    fore concluded that because the new statutory procedures were free of

    the constitutional defects noted by Justices Sitewart and White in Furman,

    the imposition of the death penalty pursuant to the new statute was con-

    situtionally permissible.

    The Court did not explain, however, why the views of Justices

    Stewart and White should be regarded as narrower than the views of

    the other Justices, or why the narrowest view should automatically be

    regarded as authoritative. The only plausible explanation is that the views

    of Justices Stewart and White were more restricted in scope and more

    closely tailored to the priecise facts in Fuirman, whereas the views of the

    other majority Justices were grounded in more general principles sus-

    ceptible to wider application.

    The Supreme Court reiterated the narrowest grounds approach, again

    without explanation, in attempting to formulate standards to govern ob-

    25. Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 169 n.15 (1976) (plurality opinion).

    26. This highest common denominator effect occurs, for example, because there may be

    an overlap between the reasoning underlying the plurality and concurring opinions, with

    the narrower of the two opinions in effect telescoped within the broader one. See Chicago

    Comment, supra note 2, at 140-50.

    27. 408 U.S. 238 (1972).

    28. Id. at 257 (opinion of Brennan, J.); id. at 314 (opinion of Marshall, J.).

    29. Id. at 306 (opinion of Stewart, J.); id. at 310 (opinion of White, J.); id. at 240

    (opinion of Douglas, J.).

    30. 428 U.S. 153 (1976). Gregg itself was a 3-2-1-1-(2) plurality decision.

    31. Id. at 169 n.15 (plurality opinion).

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    8/27

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    9/27

    1980] PLURALITY OPINONS 763

    has indicated that legal principles should be developed in decisions

    tailored to the issues actually before the Court, and that sweeping state-

    ments and expansive pronouncements on social policy lie beyond the prov-

    ince of the judiciary.43

    In some circumstances-for example, when a narrowest ground that

    would apparently be subscribed to by a majority of the Court is readily

    ascertainable-the narrowest grounds approach may be an important

    means of promoting values of certainty and reliability. An alter-

    native approach allowing lower courts to limit the precedential value

    of the decision to its specific result or to disavow it entirely may lead

    to inconsistent results and confusion, and ultimately necessitate Supreme

    Court review. While forcing the Court in this manner to provide a

    definitive pronouncement is sometimes desirable, Supreme Court review

    might also be premature, and possibly counterproductive if further disa-

    greement ensues. The formulation of sound, enduring principles in com-

    plex or controversial areas of the law may require more time and

    opportunity to draw on the experience and reflection of lower courts.

    On the other hand, however, the narrowest grounds approach is open

    to serious criticism. Determining whether there is in fact a narrowest ground

    in any given case and, if there is, the precise nature and extent of the over-

    lap in various concurring opinions, is a task posing substantial difficulties

    in itself. It is easy to isolate the narrowest ground in those situations

    where the plurality relies on rationale A in support of the result, and the

    concurrence clearly agrees on the applicability of that rationale, but also

    goes a step further and espouses rationale B as well. In such cases the

    plurality rationale may fairly be regarded as the narrowest ground em-

    bodying the reasoning of a majority of the Court, and that rationale should

    be binding on lower courts for future cases.

    More often, however, there is no clear and explicit agreement on the

    reasoning supporting the result; instead, two essentially distinct rationales

    are proposed, and the overlap, if any, is merely implicit. In such cases,

    there is no magical formula for determining which of the rationales in-

    volved is the narrower. Indeed, the term narrow may bear various

    meanings, but the Court has not clarified its use of the word. In one

    context, for example, decisions based on statutory grounds have tradi-

    tionally been regarded as narrower than ones based on constitutional

    grounds. In other cases, the narrowest opinion may be the one most

    clearly tailored to the specific fact situation before the Court and thus

    applicable to the fewest cases, in contrast to an opinion that takes a more

    absolutist position or suggests more general rules. Under this approach,

    43. See, e.g., Ashwander v. TVA, 297 U.S. 288, 324 (1936) ( The judicial power

    does not extend to the determination of abstract questions. ).

    44. See, e.g., Spector Motor Service, Inc. v. McLaughlin, 323 U.S. 101, 105 (1944);

    Ashwander v. TVA, 297 U.S. 288, 347-48 (1936) (Brandeis, J., concurring).

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    10/27

    764 COLUMBIA LAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    the truly narrowest ground of decision is the specific result itself. A

    third possibility would regard the narrowest opinion as the one that de-

    parts the least from the status quo. This approach would interpret nar-

    rowness as an aspect of judicial conservatism, in the sense not only of

    conformity to precedent and tradition in the law, but also to established

    social, moral, or political values.

    These different definitions of narrow have different implications and

    may lead to different results. The first is in essence a prudential rule,

    arising out of firmly established judicial policies. The second suggests a

    more logical-analytical approach, but it might operate to curtail the Su-

    preme Court's role of providing general guidance on the law. The third

    definition will often require subjective value judgments, a practice that

    many would find disturbing in light of the ideal of judicial neutrality and

    objectivity.

    The Supreme Court itself has generally regarded the narrowest ground

    as the rationale offered in support of the result that would affect or con-

    trol the fewest cases in the future.45 The problem with this approach is that

    while the narrower result does in fact represent an area of majority agree-

    ment that safely can be followed, the general reasoning supporting that

    result may reflect the views of only a minority of the Court, and thus

    should not be binding on lower courts.46

    In Furman, for example, the narrowest result is apparently that capi-

    tal punishment is unconstitutional when imposed pursuant to arbitrary and

    capricious procedures. This proposition represents the highest common

    denominator of majority agreement, because in any future case where the

    Justices who concurred on the arbitrary procedure rationale would find

    the death penalty unconstitutional, the more absolutist Furman plurality

    would also find it unconstitutional. Conversely, in any case where those

    who concurred in Furman would find the death penalty constitutionally

    permissible, the Justices who dissented in Furman would align themselves

    with the concurrence. The two lines of reasoning leading to these results,

    however, are significantly different. Adherence to the concurring rationale

    would make the nature of the statutory procedures involved the determin-

    45. See, e.g., the Gregg Court's treatment of Furman, discussed in text accompanying

    note 31 supra.

    46. This difficulty with the narrowest grounds approach was recognized by one court in

    its discussion of Elrod v. Burns, 427 U.S. 347 (1976), a 3-2-(3) plurality decision. In Finkel v.

    Branti, 457 F. Supp. 1284, 1289 (S.D.N.Y. 1978), aff'd without opinion, 598 F.2d 609 (2d

    Cir.), aff'd, 48 U.S.L.W. 4331 (Mar. 31, 1980), the district court noted that under the

    narrowest grounds approach it would have to regard the concurring opinion in Elrod as

    authoritative, but it declined to read Elrod so narrowly as the 'least common denomi-

    nator' test would suggest .... Since three of the five Justices constituting the majority in

    Elrod had joined in the broader plurality opinion, the court reasoned that [e]ven if it

    is conceded that the particular language of the concurring opinion must be taken as con-

    trolling, it is clear that the analysis and reasoning of the pluraity is relevant to an

    elucidation of the holding of the concurring opinion. Id. at 1289 n.9. But cf. Ramey v.

    Harber, 431 F. Supp. 657, 662 (W.D. Va. 1977) (applying narrowest grounds approach to

    find concurring opinion authoritative), modified, 589 F.2d 753 (4th Cir. 1978), cert.

    denied, 442 U.S. 910 (1979).

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    11/27

    1980] PLURALITY OPINONS 765

    ative issue, whereas under the plurality rationale, such an inquiry would

    be extraneous. Thus, the reasoning contained in the Furman concurrence,

    although narrower than the more absolutist per se principle espoused by

    the plurality, does not in any meaningful way reflect a majority viewpoint.

    Consequently, there is no reason automatically to regard that rationale as

    binding on lower courts in future cases.

    In Fanny Hill the problems caused by the narrowest grounds ap-

    proach are even more apparent. The decision proposes three separate

    lines of analysis in support of the result reached, and a fourth is proposed

    by the dissenters. The choice of the plurality's utterly without redeeming

    social value test as the narrowest is once more based not on any

    meaningful overlap in the reasoning underlying the various analyses, but

    on the fact that adherence to the plurality test will yield the right

    results. In other words, any book that a court would find not to be

    obscene under that standard would presumably not be obscene under the

    two tests proposed by the concurring Justices.

    Another drawback of the narrowest grounds approach is that it may

    unduly hamper development of the law. By ensuring that the Justice who

    aligns himself with a majority of the Court on the narrowest grounds will

    prevail, the approach may encourage the Justices to limit their opinions

    as closely as possible to the specific facts, and to avoid more general dis-

    cussion of the broader issues involved. In effect, then, the narrowest

    grounds approach tends to promote a conservative process of judicial

    development.

    The Supreme Court's treatment of Furman and Fanny Hill suggests

    yet another serious drawback to the narrowest grounds approach-it tends

    to vest disproportionate power in the swing Justice or Justices by ac-

    cording their narrow opinion controlling weight, even though the reason-

    ing expressed does not reflect a true consensus of the Court.

    Indeed, in recent years, a significant number of decisions in critical

    areas of constitutional law have been dictated, in effect, by the views of

    a single swing Justice.47 For example, Justice Powell's concurring opin-

    47. A notable example is Justice Black's opinion in Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U.S.

    112 (1970), a case in which several states challenged the provision of the Voting Rights

    Act Amendments of 1970, Pub. L. No. 91-285, ?? 301, 302, 84 Stat. 318 (1970), lowering

    the voting age in federal and state elections to eighteen. Justices Douglas, Brennan, White

    and Marshall found the provision constitutional as a legitimate exercise of Congress's power

    to enforce equal protection. 400 U.S. at 143-44 (opinion of Douglas, J.); id. at 240

    (opinion of Brennan, White, and Marshall, JJ.). Justices Harlan, Stewart, Burger, and

    Blackmun found it unconstitutional. Id. at 213 (opinion of Harlan, J.); id. at 296 (opinion

    of Stewart and Blackmun, JJ., and Burger, C.J.). Justice Black, writing the opinion of the

    Court, found the voting age provision constitutional for federal elections, id. at 122-24, 130,

    but not for state elections, id. at 130. He reasoned that the fourteenth amendment, aimed

    primarily at racial discrimination, was inapposite to Congress's determination to lower the

    voting age, because Congress made no finding that an age differential had a racial impact.

    Id. at 129-30. Instead, Justice Black held that Congress's power to supervise national

    elections, U.S. Const., art. I, ?? 2, 4, justified the provision relating to federal elections, id.

    at 119-24; Congress, however, has no such authority over state elections, thus rendering the

    remainder of the provision unconstitutional, id. at 124-30. No other member of the Court

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    12/27

    766 COLUMBALAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    ion in Regents of the University of California v. Bakke,48 a case involving

    the constitutionality of race-preferential school admissions programs, has

    been regarded as the authoritative source of guidance by several lower

    courts.49 Although under some definitions Justice Powell's opinion repre-

    sents the narrowest ground, most of the principles he espoused were

    not clearly adopted by the other Justices hearing the case, and thus his

    views cannot be considered authoritative.50 Bakke illustrates the ambiguity

    of the term narrowest grounds and the resulting difficulty in applying

    the narrowest grounds approach. For that part of the Court's decision

    holding fixed quota systems illegal under title VI, Justice Powell's view

    may be regarded as narrower than the view of Chief Justice Burger

    and Justices Stevens, Stewart, and Rehnquist, which would prohibit any

    racial preference in cases arising under title VI. The Stevens group, how-

    ever, is narrower insofar as it rests on statutory, rather than constitu-

    tional, grounds. With regard to the second issue in the case, involving

    the constitutionality of some form of racial preference, Justice Powell's

    view that some degree of racial preference is acceptable in certain situa-

    tions is arguably narrower than the position of Justices Brennan, Marshall,

    Blackmun, and White, who would approve the use of racial preferences in

    a broader range of situations. Justice Powell's opinion, however, is also

    broader than necessary to resolve the particular case, because he analyzed

    accepted Justice Black's reasoning, but, because he was the key swing vote in different

    5-(4) majorities sustaining the statute for federal elections and striking it down for state

    elections, his isolated views dictated the result.

    48. 438 U.S. 265 (1978).

    49. See, e.g., Uzzell v. Friday, 591 F.2d 997 (4th Cir. 1979); Fullilove v. Kreps, 584

    F.2d 600 (2d Cir. 1978), cert. granted, 441 U.S. 960 (1979); Morrow v. Dillard, 580 F.2d

    1284 (5th Cir. 1978). But see K. Greenawalt, The Unresolved Problems of Reverse

    Discrimination, 67 Calif. L. Rev. 87, 91-92 (1979).

    50. In Bakke, the Court voted 5-4 to affirm that part of the lower court's judgment

    ordering the Medical School at the University of California at Davis to admit Allan Bakke.

    Also by a 5-4 vote, the Court declared the Davis admissions program, which reserved a

    fixed number of spaces in each entering class for black students, illegal. Finally, it reversed

    that part of the lower court judgment prohibiting any consideration of race whatsoever

    in the admissions process. These results were supported by two different majorities, however,

    with Justice Powell serving as the bridge between the two groups. Chief Justice Burger

    and Justices Stevens, Stewart and Rehnquist declined to reach the constitutional question.

    They decided the case on statutory grounds, arguing that title VI bars any form of racial

    preference and mandates a color-blind policy. 438 U.S. at 408-21 (opinion of Stevens,

    Stewart, and Rehnquist, JJ., and Burger, C.J.). Justices Brennan, Marshall, Blackmun, and

    White, on the other hand, reached the constitutional issue because they regarded title VI

    as coextensive with the equal protection clause. This group would have found virtually all

    race-conscious admissions programs constitutional because they are designed to remedy the

    unequal opportunity caused by past discrimination. Thus, they found that the rigid Davis

    quota did not violate equal protection. Id. at 324-79 (opinion of Brennan, Marshall,

    Blackmun, and White, JJ.).

    Justice Powell agreed with the Brennan group that title VI is coextensive with the equal

    protection clause, thus establishing a majority on this issue. Id. at 281-87 (opinion of

    Powell, J.). His view on the constitutionality of race-conscious admissions programs fell

    somewhere between the views of the Brennan group and those of the Stevens group. He

    regarded rigid quota systems as unconstitutional but would have allowed certain types of racial

    preference in appropriate circumstances. Id. at 287-320 (opinion of Powell, J.). Thus, in

    future cases arising under title VI Justice Powell's vote should be determinative. Any

    preferential program acceptable to him would clearly be acceptable to the Brennan group.

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    13/27

    1980] PLURALITY OPINONS 767

    the merits of affirmative action admissions programs that were not before

    the Court.

    Although the narrowest grounds approach may be a useful tool in

    interpreting certain types of plurality opinions, it is a doctrine of limited

    applicability. It is only useful in those cases where the plurality and

    concurring opinions stand in a broader-narrower relation to each other.

    Many of the most troublesome plurality opinions, however, do not fit into

    this mold, and lower courts have been left to their own devices to deter-

    mine the precedential value of most plurality opinions.

    II. OTHER APPROACHES TO INTERPRETING PLURALITY OPINIONS

    In interpreting plurality opinions, lower courts have primarily looked

    to the alignment of the Justices and the extent of agreement, the com-

    patibility of different lines of reasoning, the persuasiveness of the various

    rationales, and the relative stature of the opinion writers.

    A. Dual Majority Cases

    In some plurality decisions the concurring and dissenting opinions

    share a common line of reasoning, but differ in their application of the

    law to the facts. In such cases there are in effect two majorities: the

    plurality and concurrence agreeing on the result, and the concurrence and

    dissent agreeing on the fundamental legal principles involved.5l

    A recent decision of this type is Arnett v. Kennedy,52 in which the

    Court held by a 3-3-(3) vote that a nonprobationary government em-

    ployee, employed under a statute authorizing removal only for cause, was

    not constitutionally entitled to a trial-type evidentiary hearing prior to the

    termination of his employment. The plurality reasoned that the substan-

    tive rights conferred by the statute were conditioned by the removal pro-

    cedures specified within it. Under this analysis, constitutional standards

    of due process were inapplicable, and all that was necessary to protect

    the employee's rights was compliance with the statutory procedures.53 The

    concurring Justices explicitly rejected the plurality view. They found in-

    stead that the statute created an expectation of continued employment that

    amounted to a legally cognizable property interest under the fifth amend-

    ment, and thus could be terminated only in accordance with constitutional

    standards of due process.54 They concluded, however, that the employ-

    ment statute at issue, which provided for notice and an opportunity to

    51. For a more detailed discussion of dual majority opinions see Chicago Comment,

    supra note 2, at 115-24.

    52. 416 U.S. 134 (1974).

    53. Id. at 155 (opinion of Rehnquist and Stewart, JJ., and Burger, C.J.).

    54. Id. at 167 (Powell and Blackmun, JJ., concurring); id. at 185 (White, J., con-

    curring).

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    14/27

    768 COLUMBALAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    respond to the charges prior to discharge and for a full trial-type hearing

    after discharge, did in fact satisfy due process requirements.55 The dis-

    senters agreed with the concurring Justices that the statute conferred an

    entitlement that could not be terminated without satisfying constitutional

    standards of due process. They construed due process standards, how-

    ever, to require a full hearing prior to discharge, and thus they found the

    statutory procedures followed in Arnett's case unconstitutional.56

    Arnett has engendered some confusion among lower courts and in the

    Supreme Court itself, particularly when constitutional entitlements are

    claimed under other employment statutes.57 Although some courts have

    apparently followed the reasoning expressed in the plurality opinion,58

    others have regarded as authoritative the view of the concurring and dis-

    senting Justices that constitutional scrutiny of termination procedures is

    required.59 This approach seems sound, since the notion that a plurality

    opinion is inherently more authoritative than a dissenting opinion-pre-

    sumably because the dissenting opinion does not support the result actually

    reached-is not persuasive when the plurality's reasoning has been clearly

    rejected by a majority of the Court. Similarly, the fact that the one line

    of reasoning to garner a majority is supported by three Justices who dis-

    sented from the judgment should not undermine the precedential value of

    that rationale. In this context, the technical alignment of the Justices is

    irrelevant; what is important is the presence of agreement by an actual

    majority of the Court.

    Further scrutiny of the concurring and dissenting opinions is neces-

    sary, however, in order to determine the exact degree of constitutional due

    process required after Arnett. To resolve this issue some courts have

    resorted to the narrowest grounds approach, regarding the concurring

    position that a post-termination hearing is sufficient as authoritative.60

    This is in fact a choice of narrowest result, rather than narrowest reason-

    ing, and, as in Gregg and Marks, reliance on the concurrence standard is

    based on the assumption that the concurring Justices will cast the deter-

    minative votes in future cases involving the constitutionality of termina-

    tion procedures. It is important to remember, however, that the concur-

    ring position is still a minority one, because the plurality never addressed

    the question of the procedures that would be required if constitutional

    55. Id. at 171, 195-96.

    56. Id. at 226-27 (Marshall, Douglas, and Brennan, JJ., dissenting).

    57. See, e.g., Bishop v. Wood, 426 U.S. 341 (1976); Mazaleski v. Treusdell, 562 F.2d 701

    (D.C. Cir. 1977); Mattern v. Weinberger, 519 F.2d 150 (3d Cir. 1975), vacated and

    remanded, 425 U.S. 987 (1976).

    58. See, e.g., Ring v. Schlesinger, 502 F.2d 479, 485-87 (D.C. Cir. 1974); Sexton v.

    Kennedy, 523 F.2d 1311, 1314-15 (6th Cir. 1975), cert. denied, 425 U.S. 973 (1976).

    59. See, e.g., Peacock v. Board of Regents, 510 F.2d 1324, 1328 (9th Cir. 1975), cert.

    denied, 422 U.S. 1049 (1975); Lake Michigan College Fed'n of Teachers v. Lake Michigan

    Community College, 518 F.2d 1091, 1095 (6th Cir. 1975), cert. denied, 427 U.S. 904 (1976);

    Christie v. United States, 518 F.2d 584, 588-89 (Ct. Cl. 1975).

    60. Peacock v. Board of Regents, 510 F.2d 1324 (9th Cir. 1975), cert. denied, 422

    U.S. 1049 (1975).

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    15/27

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    16/27

    770 COLUMBALAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    of 3-3-(3) that a woman who had been denied admission to medical

    school could bring a civil rights suit for alleged sex discrimination under

    title IX of the Education Amendments Act of 1972. Lower courts have

    regarded Cannon's determination that title IX impliedly creates a pri-

    vate right of action as authoritative, even though the Court reached this

    result on the basis of several different rationales.67

    What Glidden and Cannon have in common, and what makes them

    amenable to the specific result approach, is that they involve threshold

    issues, such as a party's right to be in court and the type of judicial pro-

    ceeding required, rather than more individualized determinations of the

    substantive merits of a claim. These cases, which involved areas of law

    that may be characterized as procedural, yielded specific results that

    were not dependent on or limited to individual factual circumstances. The

    results can thus stand as independent rules of decision for subsequent

    cases. On the other hand, cases involving individual claims of constitu-

    tional right, such as Arnett, are more likely to produce results that can-

    not be divorced from the underlying reasoning on the issue of entitlement.

    Thus, the reasoning underlying the result is less important in the former

    class of cases than in the latter group, where the analytical underpinnings

    of each decision may have profound implications for subsequent decisions

    in many areas of the law.

    Lower courts may also choose citation for specific result not because

    they regard the reasoning as unimportant for precedential purposes, but

    simply because they find it impossible to discern a coherent majority ra-

    tionale. One example of a plurality decision that seems to defy all

    reasoned attempts at interpretation is National Mutual Insurance Co. v.

    Tidewater Transfer Co.,68 a 3-2-(2)-(2) decision upholding a statute con-

    ferring federal diversity jurisdiction over actions between citizens of the

    District of Columbia and citizens of other states.69

    The statute was upheld through a combination of two minority ra-

    tionales, each of which was rejected by a majority of the Justices.70

    67. See, e.g., NAACP v. Medical Center, Inc., 599 F.2d 1247, 1256-57 (3d Cir. 1979);

    Clark v. Louisa County School Bd., 472 F. Supp. 321 (E.D. Va. 1979); National Super

    Spuds, Inc. v. New York Mercantile Exch., 470 F. Supp. 1256, 1262 (S.D.N.Y. 1979).

    The rationales in Cannon are relevant for resolving the question of implication under

    other statutes. Cf. Siegel, The Implication Doctrine and the Foreign Corrupt Practices Act,

    79 Colum. L. Rev. 1085, 1088-1104 (1979) (discussing Cannon's effect on the implication

    doctrine generally).

    68. 337 U.S. 582 (1949).

    69. 28 U.S.C.A. ? 1332 (1949).

    70. The three Justices in the plurality reasoned that although the District of Columbia

    was not a state within the meaning of article III for purposes of diversity jurisdiction, the

    statute was a constitutional exercise of Congress's power under article I, section 17, to legislate

    for the District of Columbia. 337 U.S. 582, 604 (opinion of Jackson, Black, and Burton,

    JJ.). The concurring Justices, flatly rejecting this invocation of legislative jurisdiction under

    article I, upheld the statute on the ground that cases defining the word state in article III

    to exclude the District of Columbia were wrongly decided and should be overruled. Id. at

    604 (Rutledge and Murphy, JJ., concurring). There were two separate dissenting opinions,

    and each essentially repudiated both of these rationales and would have found the statute

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    17/27

    1980] PLURALITY OPINONS 771

    Courts have taken a variety of approaches to the interpretation and ap-

    plication of Tidewater. Some courts have regarded the specific result of

    Tidewater as controlling in future cases presenting similar facts, without

    worrying about the rationale.7' At least one court has disavowed the

    decision entirely as precedent for future cases.72

    There seems to be no easy way to extract any coherent precedential

    principles from a case like Tidewater. Total disavowal of the decision

    does not seem advisable, since the Supreme Court would presumably de-

    cide similar cases in a similar fashion in the future. On the other hand,

    there is no basis for according one of two minority rationales, each re-

    jected by a majority of the Justices, controlling weight. Despite the

    absence of a principled majority rationale, however, considerations of

    uniformity and predictability militate in favor of adherence to result

    stare decisis. Where, as in Tidewater, there is clear agreement on the

    specific result, that result should be regarded as binding on the lower

    courts, regardless of whether any rationale can fairly be considered author-

    itative.

    Yet another situation in which citation for specific result may be the

    only interpretive option for lower courts arises when the Court is equally

    divided on the broader legal principles underlying a particular holding.

    A particularly troublesome case of this type is Gosa v. Mayden,3 a

    4-1-1-(3) decision involving the retroactivity of the holding in O'Callahan

    unconstitutional. Id. at 626 (Douglas, J., and Vinson, C.J., dissenting); id. at 644 (Frankfurter

    and Reed, JJ., dissenting).

    Justice Frankfurter noted this anomalous result in his dissenting opinion:

    A substantial majority of the Court agrees that each of the two grounds urged

    in support of the attempt by Congress to extend diversity jurisdiction to cases

    involving citizens of the District of Columbia must be rejected-but not the same

    majority. And so, conflicting minorities in combination bring to pass a result-

    paradoxical as it may appear-which differing majorities of the Court find insup-

    portable.

    Id. at 655.

    71. One such court suggested, not without a touch of irony, that 'the conclusion to be

    drawn from [Tidewater] is that precedent is established by the votes of the justices, not by

    the reasons given for their votes. Greene v. Teffeteller, 90 F. Supp. 387, 388 (E.D. Tenn.

    1950).

    72. Detres v. Lions Building Corp., 136 F. Supp. 699 (N.D. Ill. 1955), rev'd, 234 F.2d

    596 (5th Cir. 1956).

    Detres presented the issue of whether the same statute conferred diversity jurisdiction

    over an action between a citizen of Puerto Rico and citizens of a state. The district court

    indicated that Tidewater had not put the issue of the statute's constitutionality to rest,

    and concluded that [p]robably the most that the Tidewater case settled was that for purposes

    of that proceeding a citizen of the District of Columbia could maintain a diversity action

    in the federal courts. 136 F. Supp. at 705. The court of appeals in Detres rejected the

    district court's disavowal of Tidewater, however. 234 F.2d at 603. But, by applying Tidewater

    to a case involving citizens of Puerto Rico, this court was extending its precedential effect

    to a case that was at least arguably distinguishable. Rather than analyzing any distinctions

    between the District of Columbia and Puerto Rico, the court of appeals based its decision

    on the analysis of Tidewater in Siegmund v. General Commodities Corp., 175 F.2d 952 (9th

    Cir. 1949). In this case the ninth circuit interpreted Tideivater as conferring jurisdiction

    over suits involving citizens of the territory of Hawaii, apparently finding that both the

    plurality and concurring rationales were somehow applicable to cases involving territories.

    73. 413 U.S. 665 (1973).

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    18/27

    772 COLUMBIA LAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    v. Parker,74 which severely restricted the jurisdiction of courts-martial over

    military personnel charged with offenses that there were not service-con-

    nected. The petitioner in Gosa had committed such an offense prior to

    the ruling in O'Callahan, but once it came down he challenged the military

    court's authority to try him.

    Six Justices agreed on the specific result that O'Callahan should not be

    applied to the facts of Gosa, but they reached this result on the basis of three

    distinct rationales.75 On the issue of O'Callahan's retroactivity, however, the

    Court was equally divided: the four plurality Justices found it not to be

    retroactive; Justice Rehnquist voted for the plurality result because he thought

    O'Callahan was wrongly decided, but he was aligned with the three dissenters

    in favor of retroactivity; and Justice Douglas did not deal with the retro-

    activity issue.

    Gosa has caused considerable confusion among the lower courts. Some

    courts have recognized that it does not provide a determinative ruling on the

    retroactivity issue, and have looked to other precedents in the area 76 or have

    simply adopted the rationale deemed most convincing.77 No court has directly

    contradicted the result in Gosa by according O'Callahan retroactive effect.

    At least one court has relied on Gosa as a purported precedent for a rule of

    decision that can be divorced from the underlying reasoning on the retro-

    activity issue.78 This court, in deciding not to apply O'Callahan retroactively,

    concluded that it was immaterial that less than a majority of the Court

    upheld the legal proposition that O'Callahan should not be applied retro-

    actively ; it was dispositive that a majority voted that O'Callahan should

    not control cases like the present one. 79

    It seems somewhat disingenuous to recognize that Gosa failed to uphold

    the legal proposition that O'Callahan should not be applied retroactively,

    and in the same breath to indicate that Gosa authoritatively determines that

    O'Callahan should not be applied to pre-O'Callahan cases. The question

    74. 395 U.S. 258 (1969).

    75. Four Justices in Gosa held that O'Callahan should not apply because the decision

    had no retroactive effect. 413 U.S. 685 (opinion of Blackmun, White, and Powell, J.J., and

    Burger, C.J.). The dissenters argued that O'Callahan should apply retroactively and they

    would have found as a result that the exercise of nilitary jurisdiction over Gosa had been

    improper. Id. at 700 (Stewart, Marshall, and Brennan, JJ., dissenting). Justice Rehnquist

    concurred in the plurality judgment not to apply O'Callahan, but he did so on the ground

    that the case had been wrongly decided and should be overruled. He clearly indicated,

    however, that if O'Callahan was valid, it should be given retroactive effect. Id. at 692

    (Rehnquist, J., concurring). Justice Douglas concurred separately on a theory entirely

    unrelated to the retroactivity issue. He suggested that res judicata barred petitioner's right

    to contest the jurisdiction of the military court because he had failed to object in timely

    fashion. Id. at 691 (Douglas, J., concurring).

    76. See, e.g., Brown v. United States, 508 F.2d 618 (3d Cir. 1974). Cf. id. at 636

    ( While the precise application of Gosa ... is uncertain, [its] result.. . is manifest. Based on

    considerations either of non-retroactivity or res judicata, a majority of the Supreme Court held

    that Gosa would remain in prison despite the constitutional shortcomings of his court-martial. )

    (Adams, J., concurring).

    77. See, e.g., Lichtenstein v. Schlesinger, 495 F.2d 1382 (9th Cir. 1974).

    78. Augenblick v. United States, 509 F.2d 1157 (Ct. Cl. 1975).

    79. Id. at 1159 (citing Glidden and Tidewater).

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    19/27

    19801 PLURALITY OPNONS 773

    confronting lower courts is essentially whether or not to apply O'Callahan

    retroactively, no matter how they phrase the issue. In resolving this question,

    the Court's basic division is an inescapable fact. True stability and clarity

    in this area will not be achieved until the question of O'Callahan's validity is

    disentangled from the question of whether, unless and until it is overruled,

    it requires retroactive application. Thus, it seems advisable to view Gosa as

    failing to establish any general rule that must control future cases. Lower

    courts should use their discretion in dealing with such cases until the Supreme

    Court provides a true resolution of the retroactivity issue. This approach

    would better serve the goals of certainty and reliability in the long run than

    attempts to build enduring legal principles an the basis of an illusory con-

    sensus.

    It is rare for a lower court, faced with a plurality decision presenting

    clear majority agreement on the result, to choose instead to follow the dis-

    senting rationale and come to a contradictory result on similar facts. Such

    total disavowal was attempted by a state court 80 in its treatment of the

    plurality decision in United States v. Jorn.81 Jorn, a 4-2-(3) decision, held

    that the double jeopardy clause prohibited reprosecution following a mistrial

    declared sua sponte by the judge without the defendant's consent.82 In State

    v. Baker, a Maryland court faced with essentially the identical issue concluded

    that because there was no opinion of the Court, the various opinions in

    Jorn were of persuasive value only.83 After an independent scrutiny of those

    opinions, the court concluded that the dissenters' analysis was the most con-

    vincing and accordingly dismissed the defendant's double jeopardy claim.

    A Federal district court subsequently granted habeas corpus relief to the

    defendant,84 criticizing the Baker court for adopting a position clearly con-

    80. State v. Baker, 15 Md. App. 73, 289 A.2d 348 (1972).

    81. 400 U.S. 470 (1971).

    82. The six Justices supporting this specific result did so on the basis of two separate

    rationales. The plurality reasoned that in the absence of manifest necessity to declare a

    mistrial, the trial judge's actions amounted to an abuse of discretion and double jeopardy

    would attach. Id. at 487 (opinion of Harlan, Douglas, and Marshall, JJ., and Burger, C.J.).

    The concurrence reasoned that the trial judge's actions amounted to an acquittal of the

    appellee, so that the Court lacked jurisdiction to hear the case; but in view of the majority's

    decision to reach the merits, the concurring Justices elected to join in the judgment. Id. at

    488 (Black and Brennan, JJ., concurring). The dissenters argued that a showing of prejudice

    to the accused was necessary in order to invoke double jeopardy. Id. at 492. (Stewart, White,

    and Blackmun, JJ., dissenting).

    83. State v. Baker, 15 Md. App. at 82, 289 A.2d at 353-54.

    84. Whitfield v. Warden, 355 F. Supp. 972 (1973), rev'd on related grounds, 486 F.2d

    1119 (4th Cir. 1973). After examining the Maryland court's interpretation of Jorn, the

    federal court declined to rule on the question of [w]hether that construction of the effect

    of a plurality opinion is a construction which a state court is free to adopt in general, or may

    adopt with regard to Jorn .... 355 F. Supp. at 976. After indicating that it was bound by

    fourth circuit precedents assigning controlling weight to the plurality opinion, however, the

    court went on to criticize the Baker court's approach:

    While in Jorn, Mr. Justices Black and Brennan joined only the judgment

    of the Court, they stated that the action of the trial judge amounted to an

    acquittal of appellee, and thus clearly rejected the Jorn dissenters' approval of the

    trial judge's actions. . . . Thus, six of nine Justices who sat in Jorn disagreed

    with the dissenting views of Mr. Justice Stewart which Judge Orth elected to follow

    in denying Whitfield's appeal.

    355 F. Supp. at 976-77.

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    20/27

    774 COLUMBIA LAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    trary to that adopted by six of the Justices. The criticism seems apt. While

    the Baker court was arguably correct in refusing to give the rationales ex-

    pressed in either the plurality opinion or the concurring opinion controlling

    weight, since neither rationale received majority support, six Justices in Jorn

    did agree on the specific result that double jeopardy barred reprosecution

    under similar facts. In light of this consensus, the Baker court should not

    have embraced a rationale that led to a contrary result.

    C. Adopting One Opinion as Authoritative

    In some instances, lower courts have regarded as authoritative a rule

    of decision that has not received majority support, perhaps because the opin-

    ion is particularly persuasive or is written by a prestigious Justice. Some-

    times, however, there is no apparent justification for choosing one rationale

    over another other than the fact that it was contained in the plurality opinion.

    An example is the treatment by lower courts of the inadvertence require-

    ment for evidence obtained through warrantless searches endorsed by a four-

    Justice plurality in Coolidge v. New Hampshire.85 Even though the require-

    ment did not command majority support, it has generally been regarded as

    authoritative.86 Courts have divided, however, as to the proper scope and

    application of the doctrine. Some have simply cited Coolidge as authority

    for the inadvertence requirement without recognizing that there was no ma-

    jority to support it.87 Other courts have explicitly noted the lack of majority

    support for the rule but have nonetheless felt constrained to apply it.88 Ap-

    parently only one court 89 has expressly declined to follow the inadvertence

    5 403US 4431971

    The Court voted 5-(4) to reverse a conviction on the ground that it was based on

    evidence seized without a warrant in violation of the fourth amendment. In explaining why

    the evidence did not fall within the plain view exception to the warrant requirement,

    Justice Stewart, writing for himself and three other Justices, stated that the plain view

    doctrine applied only when the discovery of the evidence was inadvertent ; that is, when

    the police had not expected to discover the evidence. 403 U.S. at 464-73 (opinion of Stewart,

    J., joined by Douglas, Brennan, and Marshall, JJ.). This qualification of the plain view

    doctrine was not accepted by Justice Harlan, who concurred in certain portions of Justice

    Stewart's opinion and in the judgment. The inadvertence requirement was expressly rejected

    in the concurring and dissenting opinions of the four remaining Justices.

    86. It is interesting to note that the dissenting Justices in Coolidge at various points

    referred to the plurality's inadvertence requirement as the majority rule. See, e.g., 403 U.S.

    at 508 (Black, J., dissenting), 518 (White, J., dissenting).

    87. See, e.g., United States v. Berenguer, 562 F.2d 206 (2d Cir. 1977); United States v.

    Cushnie, 488 F.2d 81 (5th Cir. 1973).

    Lower courts that have adopted the inadvertence requirement may have relied on the

    fact that the rule was contained in an opinion labelled the Opinion of the Court, even though

    that opinion was subscribed to by only four Justices. Such reliance is misguided, however; a

    rule supported by a plurality of four Justices is still a minority rule, and thus should not be

    considered authoritative.

    88. In United States v. Liberti, No. 79-1127 (2d Cir. Jan. 25, 1980), the Court relied on

    a somewhat strained interpretation of the inadvertence requirement, indicating that a discovery

    is inadvertent when the police lack probable cause to search for and seize the items.

    Judge Newman, concurring in the result, suggested that in view of the uncertain status of

    the inadvertence requirement, he would not deem it the law of the land and would decide

    the case on other grounds. Slip op. at 5938. See also United States v. Griffith, 537 F.2d 900

    (7th.Cir. 1976); United States v. Gray, 484 F.2d 352 (6th Cir. 1973).

    89. United States v. Bradshaw, 490 F.2d 1097 (4th Cir. 1974), cert. denied, 419 U.S.

    895 (1974).

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    21/27

    1980] PLURALITY OPINONS 775

    rule, resting a decision of inadmissibility on other grounds. In doing so, this

    court stressed the uncertain status of the rule and noted that recent changes

    in the composition of the Court might result in a new majority opposed to it.90

    In some plurality decisions, one or two Justices write concurring opin-

    ions that purport to interpret or limit the absolute implications of the lead

    opinion. Some lower courts have looked to the reasoning of these self-pro-

    claimed interpreters of the court as authoritative guidance for future cases.

    They may find these opinions, which often explain and clarify the Court's

    decision, easier to apply, or they may find the concurring rationale more

    persuasive or more compatible with precedent. In Branzburg v. Hayes,9,

    for example, Justice Powell was the swing Justice who offered a clarifying

    interpretation of the main opinion. In Branzburg the Court decided by a

    4-1-(4) vote 92 that the first amendment does not protect newsmen from

    revealing to a grand jury information gathered from confidential sources.

    Justice Powell joined the majority opinion, but he also wrote a brief

    concurring opinion reiterating the majority's good faith test requiring report-

    ers claiming privilege to demonstrate that a grand jury investigation was

    conducted in bad faith.93 Justice Powell's interpretation made the test ap-

    pear more liberal than the majority formulation. He argued that the stand-

    ard actually left the Court free to balance the competing interests on their

    merits in the particular case. 94 This formulation seems to afford broader

    90. 490 F.2d at 1101 n.3. It is interesting to compare the treatment of the inadvertence

    requirement with the treatment accorded to the rule espoused by four Justices in the plurality

    decision in Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. 677 (1973), that sex should be a suspect clas-

    sification for purposes of equal protection analysis. The Court decided by a vote of 4-1-3-(1)

    that a statute automatically treating spouses of male members of the uniformed services as

    dependents for purposes of certain benefits while regarding spouses of female members as

    not dependent unless they can prove dependence for more than one-half of their support,

    violated the fifth amendment. The alignment of the Justices in Frontiero was substantially

    identical to the alignment in Coolidge: the four-Justice plurality (Brennan, joined by Douglas,

    Marshall and White) indicated that sex should be regarded as a suspect classification, 411 U.S.

    at 682-91. One Justice concurred in the judgment but expressed no view on whether sex

    constituted a suspect class. Id. at 691 (Stewart, J., concurring). Three Justices concurred

    in the judgment but concluded that, since the equal rights amendment was awaiting ratification

    by the states, it was inappropriate to decide the suLspect class issue at this time. Id. at 691-92

    (Powell and Blackman, JJ., and Burger, C.J., concurring). Justice Rehnquist dissented from

    the judgment. Id at 691.

    Neither the Supreme Court itself nor the lower courts have regarded the plurality's

    suspect classification analysis as the governing standard in gender-discrimination cases, since

    that analysis was accepted by only four Justices. See, e.g., Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190

    (1976); Stanton v. Stanton, 421 U.S. 7, 13 (1975); Schlesinger v. Ballard, 419 U.S. 498, 511

    (1975); Alma Soc'y Inc. v. Mellon, 601 F.2d 1225, 1234 (2d Cir. 1979). The ready acceptance

    of Coolidge's inadvertence requirement is therefore especially surprising.

    91. 408 U.S. 665 (1972).

    92. Although technically a routine majority decision, Justice Powell's restatement of the

    lead opinion makes this case analytically similar to no-clear-majority decisions.

    93. The majority opinion indicated that newsmen's claims of privilege should be decided

    under a good faith test. This test would permit a reporter to obtain a protective court order

    limiting grand jury questioning only when he can show that a grand jury investigation is being

    conducted not to serve a legitimate law enforcement need, but in bad faith or for the purpose

    of disrupting his relations with his confidential sources. Absent such a showing, the majority

    believed that the consequential, but uncertain, burden on news gathering created by com-

    pelling reporters to testify before a grand jury was outweighed by the public interest in the

    grand jury's role in [flair and effective law enforcement. 408 U.S. at 690.

    94. Id. at 710. Justice Powell also expanded the scope of the good faith standard to

    allow newsmen to seek motions to quash or protective orders whenever called upon to give

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    22/27

    776 COLUMBIALAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    opportunities for newsmen to obtain judicial protection from grand jury in-

    vestigations than the majority standard.95 Lower courts trying to apply

    Branzburg in subsequent cases have generally relied on the Powell concur-

    rence.96 One reason for doing so may be that Justice Powell's rule of deci-

    sion is narrower than the standard promulgated by the majority, and thus

    his vote would be the key one for future decisions involving the same issue.97

    This approach, however, gives authoritative effect to a rationale that repre-

    sents the views of only a single Justice. The other reason for relying on

    Justice Powell's opinion may be that lower courts perceive his statement as

    not proposing a standard different and independent from that proposed by

    the majority, but as simply restating and explaining the majority viewY98 This

    perception is based in part on the fact that Powell justified his statement in

    these terms.99

    In National League of Cities v. Usery 100 a single concurring Justice was

    again able to restrict the scope of a decision through the device of interpret-

    ing it. In this case the Court decided by a 4-1-(4) vote that the 1974

    amendments to the Fair Labor Standards Act extending minimum wage pro-

    visions to nearly all state and local government employees were unconstitu-

    tional.101 In the plurality opinion, four Justices held that the provisions

    would transgress tenth amendment limitations on the commerce power. This

    opinion suggested a rule that any congressional regulation based on the

    commerce clause must be overturned if it operates to directly displace the

    States' freedom to structure integral operations in areas of traditional govern-

    mental functions.'02 Justice Blackmun wrote a concurring opinion offering

    a different interpretation of the plurality view. He expressed his understand-

    ing that the Court's opinion adopted a balancing test, under which Congress

    may regulate traditional state activities if regulation is essential to protect a

    information bearing only a remote and tenuous relationship to the subject of the inves-

    tigation .... Id.

    95. In cases where a newsman can prove the remote and tenuous relationship but

    cannot demonstrate bad faith, it is conceivable that Justice Powell might break with the

    majority.

    96. See, e.g., Riley v. City of Chester, 612 F.2d 708, 715-16 (3d Cir. 1979); Reporters'

    Comm. for Freedom of the Press v. American Tel. & Tel. Co., 593 F.2d 1030 (D.C. Cir. 1978),

    cert. denied, 440 U.S. 949 (1979); Ealy v. Littlejohn, 569 F.2d 219 (5th Cir. 1978); United

    States v. Schiavo, 504 F.2d 1 (3d Cir.), cert. denied, 419 U.S. 1096 (1974); Carey v. Hume,

    492 F.2d 631 (D.C. Cir.), cert. denied, 417 U.S. 938 (1974).

    97. See, e.g., United States v. Liddy, 478 F.2d 586, 586-87 (D.C. Cir. 1972) ( the

    Branzbuirg decision is controlled in the last analysis by the concurring opinion of Justice

    Powell . . . as the fifth Justice of the majority. Powell's balancing test does not require a

    demonstration of either total lack of legitimacy or utter lack of any possible need, for it may

    be raised on a claim that the information desired of the newsman has only a 'remote' relation-

    ship to the subject of the investigation. ).

    98. See, e.g., In re Possible Violations of 18 U.S.C. ?? 371, 641, 1503, 564 F.2d 567, 571

    (D.C. Cir. 1977) (citing Powell's concurrence as controlling because it emphasize[s] and

    elaborate[s] the majority opinion).

    99. I add this brief statement to emphasize what seems to me to be the limited nature

    of the Court's holding. 408 U.S. at 709 (Powell, J., concurring).

    100. 426 U.S. 833 (1976).

    101. Id. at 852.

    102. Id.

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    23/27

    1980] PLURALITY OPINONS 777

    federal interest that is demonstrably greater than the state's interest.103 Jus-

    tice Blackmun added a caveat that he might be misinterpreting the Court's

    opinion.'04 This statement, however, seems a bit disingenuous; because of

    his key voting position, it is difficult to escape the conclusion that Justice

    Blackmun intended to limit significantly the scope of the lead opinion while

    purporting to interpret it.105

    On the assumption that Justice Blackmun's vote will be determinative

    in subsequent litigation involving Congress's authority to regulate state

    activities, lower courts have accepted his interpretation as authoritative.'06

    Accordingly, they have cited National League of Cities for the rule that when

    a federal commerce regulation supplants a state's policy choice affecting the

    structure of its governmental activities, balancing of state and federal inter-

    ests is required to determine the regulation's constitutionality.

    In some instances lower courts have regarded the opinion of a single

    Justice as authoritative not because it interprets the lead opinion, but because

    the particular Justice enjoys special status in the eyes of the profession or

    the general public. It is rare for a court to admit overtly that it is taking

    such an approach.'07 Nonetheless, considerations of a Justice's prestige

    may, consciously or unconsciously, influence a court's interpretation of a

    particular decision.

    Acceptance of the most prestigious Justice's opinion as authoritative

    may be particularly tempting when a court is confronted with a plurality

    decision that lacks a coherent majority rationale.'08 Thus, in interpreting

    Glidden Co. v. Zdanok 109 other courts, including the Supreme Court, have

    generally cited Justice Harlan's opinion, although it was joined by only two

    103. Id. at 856 (Blackmun, J., concurring).

    104. Id.

    105. The only possible justification for Justice Blackmun's interpretation is that he was

    attempting to reconcile the National League of Cities decision with the earlier case of

    Fry v. United States, 421 U.S. 542 (1975), which held that Congress had power under the

    commerce clause to include state employees within the national wage freeze authorized by the

    1970 Economic Stabilization Act.

    106. See, e.g., Peel v. Florida Dep't of Transportation, 600 F.2d 1070, 1084 (5th Cir.

    1979); Public Service Co. of N. Carolina v. Federal Energy Regulatory Comm'n, 587 F.2d

    716, 721 (5th Cir. 1979); Philadelphia v. SEC, 434 F. Supp. 281, 288 n.6 (E.D. Pa. 1977),

    appeal dismissed, 434 U.S. 1003 (1978); Usery v. Dallas Independent School Dist., 421 F.

    Supp. 111, 116 (N.D. Texas 1976).

    107. But see Doe v. Commonwealth's Att'y for City of Richmond, 403 F. Supp. 1199

    (E.D. Va. 1975), aff'd, 425 U.S. 901 (1976), where the court interpreted Griswold v. Con-

    necticut. 381 U.S. 479 (1965), by relying on Justice Harlan's dissent in Poe v. Ullman, 367

    U.S. 497, 533 (1961): At all events, the Justice's exegesis is that of a jurist of widely

    acknowledged superior stature and weighty whatever its context. With his standing, what he

    had further to say in Poe v. Ullmann . . . is worthy of high regard. 403 F. Supp. at 1201.

    108. One lower court, after acknowledging the general validity of according special

    weight to the opinions of particularly eminent judges or Justices, also recognized one of the

    weaknesses of such an approach: The opinion in Strika is entitled to more than usual

    weight, as having behind it the authority of a great judge. But even Homer nods, and the

    quoted passage, on which the opinion rests, is no less a non sequitur because it seemed con-

    vincing to Judge Hand. Gebhard v. S.S. Hawaiian Legislator, 425 F.2d 1303, 1316 (9th

    Cir. 1970).

    109. 370 U.S. 530 (1962), discussed at notes 64-65 and accompanying text supra.

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    24/27

    778 COLUMBIA LAWREVEW[Vol 80756

    other members of the Court. 10 No doubt this approach is taken not only

    because Justice Harlan was a jurist of great prestige and intellectual repute,

    but also because his opinion was a scholarly and comprehensive work.

    On balance, however, allowing considerations of a Justice's prestige to

    determine the precedential value of a decision is clearly undesirable. Such

    an approach, resting on subjective considerations, may promote uncertainty

    and inconsistency, especially since assessments of a Justice's abilities may

    vary over time. Moreover, a Justice's general reputation does not guarantee

    that any given opinion that he writes is sound or inherently better than the

    reasoning of another Justice. The merits of a particular opinion must be

    evaluated independently of the writer's other work.

    The fundamental problem with the prestigious Justice approach is

    that it focuses on the opinion-writer rather than the opinion, and thus is

    inconsistent with the values of reliability and uniformity underlying our legal

    system. The views of a single Justice, no matter how persuasive his reason-

    ing or exalted his reputation, cannot be authoritative in our precedential

    system unless they receive the support of a majority of the Court.

    III. NORMATIVE STANDARDS FOR INTERPRETING PLURALITY OPINIONS

    The practical effect of plurality decisions is to give the lower courts

    increased discretion in analyzing and applying precedent, and a more respon-

    sible role in developing the law.11' Whether such a reallocation of respon-

    sibility is desirable is open to debate; 112 but so long as the number of plurality

    decisions continues to rise, it is imperative for lower courts to develop a

    principled and effective method for handling such decisions.

    110. E.g., Palmore v. United States, 411 U.S. 389, 405-06 & n.13 (1973); Wiren v. Eide,

    542 F.2d 757, 765-66 n.10 (9th Cir. 1976); United States v. Montanez, 371 F.2d 79, 82

    (2d Cir. 1967); United States v. Allocco, 305 F.2d 704, 706 (2d Cir. 1962).

    111. The general trend toward increased lower court discretion is documented in Lower

    Court Disavowal, supra note 5. The traditional dogma was that lower courts were bound by

    the literal reading of any decision on point. Thus, any more complex evaluation of the value

    of precedents, such as attempts to distill a common principle from conflicting opinions, was

    seen to extend undue discretion to the lower courts. Id. at 496. As another scholar has

    pointed out, however, the problems of interpretation and application presented by plurality

    opinions are not qualitatively different from the problems posed by ordinary majority decisions:

    Just as mixed problems of language and political compromise permit and some-

    times force judges to make their own policy choices in interpreting statutes, semantic

    difficulties and opinion compromises within the Supreme Court often allow or require

    the exercise of lower court discretion. In addition, even where the Court has spoken

    precisely on general principles of law, the work of applying these principles to new

    and complex situations of muddled evidence and tangled pleadings may demand

    ingenuity, imagination, and the insertion of value preferences which may not conform

    to those of the Justices.

    W. Murphy, Elements of Judicial Strategy 24 (1964).

    112. The advantages of giving lower courts more leeway to act as intermediaries between

    the Supreme Court and the public, and to draw on their own sense of justice to meet changing

    times and conditions must, of course, be balanced against the needs of the bench, bar, and

    general public for stability and clarity in legal reasoning. These values are not absolutes,

    however, and their relative importance in a given situation depends on a number of factors,

    including the particular area of law involved. See notes 63-68 and accompanying text supra.

    This content downloaded from 194.47.65.106 on Thu, 09 Jun 2016 14:58:10 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 7/26/2019 Novak1980 - The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions

    25/27

    1980] PLURALTY OPNONS 779

    The foregoing discussion demonstrates the difficulty of laying down hard

    and fast interpretive rules that will be applicable to the many different types

    of plurality decisions and the myriad legal and factual settings in which they

    arise. How a particular decision should be handled depends on a variety of

    factors, including the precise nature of the issues presented and their relation

    to the broader area of law involved, the alignment of the Justices on a

    particular issue, the interrelationship between the various rationales sug-

    gested, and the degree to which a subsequent case is legally or factually

    distinguishable.

    The underlying concern in any approach to plurality decisions is how

    to effect the optimal balance between two sets of often contradictory values.

    The goals of certainty, unifolrmity, fairness, and efficiency imply a need for

    clear Supreme Court guidance. On the other hand, judicial freedom and

    flexibility are necessary for the development of well-reasoned, enduring legal

    principles. The first set of considerations militates in favor of relatively

    strict adherence to precedent, while the latter set affords lower courts con-

    siderably more leeway to minimize or even to disregard entirely the preceden-

    tial value of any plurality decision striking the judge as inherently or

    technically weak.

    In seeking to harmonize these competing values, it seems clear that

    lower courts must adhere at the minimum to the principle of result stare

    decisis,'13 which mandates that any specific result espoused by a clear ma-

    jority of the Court should be controlling in substantially identical cases. The

    absence of a clear majority rationale supporting the result may give a lower

    court some flexibility to formulate a justifying rule. It does not, however,

    justify a court in embracing a line of reasoning that will lead to a contrary

    result, as the Baker court attempted to do by adopting the position of the

    dissen