Niezen CSSH Article 2011

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    1/10

    CSSHDISCUSSION

    The Social Study of Human Rights.

    A Review Essay

    R O N A L D N I E Z E N

    Anthropology, McGill University

    The Idea of Justice, by Amartya Sen (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,

    2009).

    Surrendering to Utopia: An Anthropology of Human Rights, by Mark Goodale

    (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009).

    Prisoners of Freedom: Human Rights and the African Poor, by

    Harri Englund (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2006).

    It is noteworthyand at the same time a bit disappointing in a what-took-so-long

    sort of waythat a recent innovation in the study of human rights should involve a

    focus on the lives of the people directly affected by them. To explain this delay of

    the obvious would probably call for a review of the persistent influence of Kantian

    transcendentalism, the quasi-utopian search for ideal justice, and the inherently

    abstract nature of law in its quest for impartiality. A similar effort could be

    applied toward fully understanding the changed circumstances that encouraged

    the shift toward practical realism. It would have to take into account the surpris-

    ingly late elaboration and popularization of human rights instruments, the prolifer-ation of transnational NGOs that act on new opportunities to exercise moral and

    political influence, and the growing reach of new technologies of information

    and communication (necessary tools for the emergence of transnational NGOs).

    All of these developments have raised the prominence of legal issues and strategies

    among those once considered isolated and, in varying degrees, uncivilized. But

    whatever the dominant trends might once have been, and whatever new, enabling

    circumstances have recently emerged, there can be little doubt that over the last

    several decades a shift has taken place in the study of human rights toward prac-

    tical or applied realism, with a focus on ordinary actors.This review essay considers three recent contributions to a body of litera-

    ture on human rights that take as their starting point this very assertion of

    Comparative Studies in Society and History 2011;53(3):682691.0010-4175/11 $15.00# Society for the Comparative Study of Society and History 2011doi:10.1017/S0010417511000296

    682

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    2/10

    realism, as against established traditions of abstraction, formalism, and utopian

    imaginings. Amartya Sen, in The Idea of Justice, makes his argument in a

    general way, calling for a practical reasoning that avoids the pitfalls of the

    quest for perfect justice. He proposes a close study of the relationship

    between social institutions and actualas opposed to idealindividual behav-iour, which, he argues, cannot but be critically important for any theory of

    justice that is aimed at guiding social choice towards social justice (69).

    Here Sen departs from the failings of abstract political philosophy in much

    the same way that his 1999 book Development as Freedom pointed to the

    flaws and, ultimately, cruelties built into the abstractions of dominant,

    GDP-based economic theory. Human rights are important to this effort, as

    the expression of broadly legitimate aspirations for human improvement,

    with built in possibilities for the kind of negotiated, pluralist universalism

    that Sen sees as providing something close to an answer for the ever-problematic quest for justice.

    The other two books that I discuss here make distinct contributions to a sub-

    discipline referred to with growing frequency as legal anthropology. Mark

    Goodales Surrendering to Utopia provides an overall justification of this

    field of study, while documenting and theorizing his way around its neglect,

    particularly in the realm of human rights. The practical reality of law gets its

    closest treatment in Harri EnglundsPrisoners of Freedom, in which the distor-

    tions of universal human rights ideals are observed in interactions between the

    underclass of Malawi and their would-be advocates. There can be no better

    answer to Sens call for practical legal realism than Englunds account of the

    relationships between NGO workers and their supposed beneficiaries, with

    its seemingly limitless capacity for unintended (mostly disastrous) conse-

    quences resulting from the legal aid workersideas and attitudes: a potentially

    lethal combination of narrow legal knowledge, radical hope, and moral hubris.

    The order in which I have arranged my treatment of these books can be seen

    as something like a sliding scale of increasing distance from formal systems of

    abstract principles that reject contingency, toward an acceptance or privileging

    of the everyday uses and consequences of justice in action, which seek to

    accommodate particularism, paradox, and conflicting values. In arranging the

    reviews this way my secondary goal is to see at what point certain key assump-

    tions and perspectives fall away and are replaced by others, making it possible

    to consider the gains and losses of the various starting points and their corre-

    sponding methodological approaches to the social study of human rights.

    The first step we will take in this overview is what Amartya Sen, in The Idea

    of Justice, refers to as liberation from positional sequestering, by which he

    means the movement beyond disconnected musings or thought experiments

    about the nature of perfect justice, while orienting our search for justice

    instead toward the practical necessities of value pluralism and negotiated com-

    promise. Sen takes as his starting point a respectful critique of John Rawlss

    T H E S O C I A L S T U D Y O F H U M A N R I G H T S 683

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    3/10

    hugely influentialA Theory of Justice(1999 [1971]) and its revival of the con-

    tractarian approach to justice, which uses a hypothetical original position as a

    device for arriving at the fundamental principles of justice as fairness. The

    elegance and influence of this approach derive in good measure from the

    fact that out of a purely abstract starting pointthe imagined coming-togetherof people with diverse interests and conditions in life seeking a just constitution

    it becomes possible to envisage real-world possibilities for institutional reform.

    But in accomplishing this, as Sen points out, it fosters a kind of rational utopian-

    ism that thrives in its distance from the untidy implementation of ideals.

    In its most basic form, Sens critique has been made many times before, and

    not only with reference to Rawls. Ultimately, it has its counterpart in the

    German Enlightenment of the late eighteenth century, particularly Herders

    rejection of any philosophy of history (mainly those of Kant and Voltaire)

    inclined toward abstraction, rational ordering, and a privileging of cosmopoli-tanism. In his 1774 essay, This Too a Philosophy of History, Herder makes a

    passionate plea for the study of the actual and the real as against abstract prin-

    ciples: Have you ever taught a child to walk from the most abstracttheory

    of motion?(2002: 279). The solution was then, as now, some form of empiri-

    cism, but Herders approach was infused with now discredited (butpersistent!)

    romantic longings after the inner essence ofVlkerwho embodied historically

    distinct conditions of life.

    Despite the long history of the cause of empirically grounded realism, Sen

    takes an original approach by going outside the familiar canon of political phil-

    osophy, drawing on eastern concepts, and in the process adding to the univers-

    ality of his ideas, which, after all, have universal aspirations. Leaving the safe

    confines of closed, transcendental logic calls for an argument that in some way

    corresponds to its great ambitions, that remains globally inclusive, that still

    answers to the needs of those who hanker after universals. This Sen provides

    in part with a wide-ranging, at times entertainingly imaginative inclusion of

    the political philosophies of Eastern classics. Not only does world-embracing

    empiricism have deep roots in the Occidental imagination; the Indian

    emperor Ashoka has much to tell us about tolerance and dialogue, and

    durable universal lessons are to be found in Indian epics like the Valmiki

    Ramayana and the Mahabharata. In particular, classical Sanskrit provides

    the concept ofnyaya, the idea of justice as it is realized in the world, in its

    effects on human lives, underscoring Sens central argument thatthe subject

    of justice is not merely about trying to achieveor dreaming about achiev-

    ingsome perfectly just society or social arrangements, but about preventing

    manifestly severe injustice(21).

    While Sen should be given credit for clearly and convincingly posing the

    challenge of realism in the formulation and actualization of justice, and com-

    mended for the effort to apply some of the same empirically grounded prin-

    ciples of his welfare economics to global principles of justice, he

    684 R O N A L D N I E Z E N

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    4/10

    ultimately retreats to the safety of abstraction in thought and method. There is,

    for example, a certain hopeful defiance of realitywhile robustly arguing for

    its virtuesthat applies to his conception of human rights. These he presents as

    universal moral claims, separate and distinct from their actual origins within the

    state-centered anarchy of international law. The very real mechanisms of andimpediments to the application of human rights, which can be found in the

    workings of international agencies, the interests and policy decisions of

    states, and the often quasi-utopian ambitions of transnational NGOs, are

    nowhere to be seen in his portrayal of human rights as a moral vision. The leg-

    islative dimension of human rights and the manner of their application are sec-

    ondary to their status as ethical claims constitutively linked with the importance

    of human freedom, and the robustness of an argument that a particular claim can

    be seen as a human right has to be assessed through the scrutiny of public

    reasoning, involving open impartiality(36566).As a corollary to his emphasis on public reasoning, Sen identifies a new

    quality to justice claims that have particular relevance for the effectiveness

    of human rights: the growing significance of media and with it new possibilities

    for information and communication to mobilize social activism. Having broken

    out of the limits of transcendentalism and embraced the complexity and ambi-

    guity of human experience, a great deal hinges on media and mobilization of

    public opinion. Sens starting point here is public response to famine, in

    which greater possibilities of media coverage can make the fate of the

    victims a powerful political issue with far-reaching effects on the climate of

    media coverage and public discussion, and ultimately on the voting of others

    a potential majority(34344). This is good news as far as it goes, but it leaves

    the overall picture of the implications of media for the practical fate of justice

    largely untouched. Take, for example, the toxic effect on public reason (and

    hence democracy) of the U.S. Supreme Courts 2010 decision to allow corpor-

    ations to spend anonymously and without limits on political advertising. Or con-

    sider, more generally, the problem of the sheer volume of rights claims through

    media, which diminishes the public influence of nearly everyone with a legitimate

    need of redress from inequity or oppression, that is to say, nearly everyone other

    than those who suffer visibly and catastrophically, enough to move increasingly

    jaded distant spectators to action. Given that the reality of peoples aspirations

    and experience with justice are what human rights are all about, then more atten-

    tion can certainly be given to such uncomfortable truths, simply in the interest of

    depicting rights in action, without necessarily succumbing to the paralysis of

    hyper-criticism.

    Sen invests heavily in social choice theory as the privileged technique for

    arriving at a grounded approach to justice, and this would appear to be the ulti-

    mate source of his departure from the real-world engagement that he advocates

    with such persuasiveness. In social choice theory we find established methods

    (described but not actually applied in the book) for taking human preference

    T H E S O C I A L S T U D Y O F H U M A N R I G H T S 685

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    5/10

    into account in such all-important endeavors as formulating economic policy

    and designing voting procedures. It is, as Sen explains it, an evaluative disci-

    pline in which the outcomes take the form of ranking different states of

    affair from a social point of view, in the light of the assessments of the

    people involved (95). The central problem with this is that even in theabsence of a real demonstration of the method applied to justice issues, we

    can foresee its central failing: We can expect the key concepts of justice to

    be very different from the raw material of economics and political preferences,

    by whichlargely through Kenneth Arrows demand for clearly defined

    axioms (1950)social choice theory has proven itself. Corn, casualties, and

    pre-reified political choices lend themselves more readily to identification

    and articulation of values than do freedom, justice, democracy, and other con-

    cepts at the foundations of liberalism (another slippery idea) considered glob-

    ally and comparatively. Sens privileged method involves broadening theapplication of social choice theory to include concepts which, when applied

    to humans in social context, add the vexations of translation to their inherent

    obscurity. Expanding the methods of social choice to include a wider range

    of concepts, perspectives, and informational outputsdoes not promise a con-

    vincing answer to the need for engagement with the lived experience of policy

    decisions and institutional practice.

    Faced with the same incompatibility between formalism and experience, and

    while sharing the substance of Sens critique, Mark Goodale arrives at quite a

    different preferred solution: the long-term ethnographic perspective of anthropol-

    ogy. For Goodale, those who take a philosophical approach to rights and justice

    see problemsas either conceptual in themselves or, if not, then they believe that

    the solutions to problems should, in the best of circumstances, be conceptual

    (47). But there can be no practical answer to questions that are embedded in

    the abstracted spheres in which competing accounts of concepts clash (48).

    Rawlss deductive approach, in particular, has reinforced a philosophy of

    justice that is remote from human experience: [I]t is impossible to know

    whether there can even be empirical correspondence between the implications

    deduced from unproven first principles and the practice of everyday life(117).

    In response to this state of affairs, Goodale proposes a new discipline, or

    rather a dusted off discipline that has been sadly overlooked in the development

    of human rights. Anthropology, with its simultaneous commitments to the

    common qualities of humanity and to humanitys tremendously varied

    expressions of difference, has what it takes to make sense of the extended

    reach of transnational norms and institutions and provide a corrective to

    abstract, global normativity. Human rights, in particular, Goodale argues,

    would look different if anthropological perspectives had, from the beginning,

    been taken into account, above all through greater attention to collective

    rights. This is now the emerging trend, with the plights of ethnic minorities

    and indigenous peoples coming to the fore (and to the forums), creating not

    686 R O N A L D N I E Z E N

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    6/10

    just a challenge for the human rights movement but contributing new questions

    and material for social research.

    Goodale argues persuasively that the postnational constellationmarked

    by the growing importance of transnational norms and institutionshas

    created new conditions, in anthropology and other disciplines of socialinquiry, for the ethnographic method. These may seem unlikely circumstances

    for a method so firmly grounded in intimacy and locality. But more than ever

    before, it is possible to witness at first hand the encroachments of ideas and

    institutions with global reach. Foundationalism and universalism are them-

    selves ideas that can become particularly meaningful in social practice, and

    the anthropologist (or other researcher or cultural critic) does a valuable

    service by making their importance and power topics for close engagement

    and critical scrutiny(9). In much simpler terms, lawyers and bureaucrats are

    now among the savages of ethnological inquiry, and one of the newest researchchallenges is to observe in practice the connections between their thinking and

    the social orders they influence.

    Discussions of human rights, however, are complicated by the fact that

    certain core meanings are apprehended by people intuitively, emotionally,

    and implicitly.This observation supports the point I made earlier concerning

    the difficulties of extracting the measures that are built into Sens approach to

    social choice theory. It means, It is only through the close ethnographic

    engagement with the practice of everyday life that [alternative ways of under-

    standing the range of problems associated with relativism and human rights]

    become apparent (59). Goodale illustrates this point by citing the work of

    other anthropologists, such as Shannon Speeds (2008) study of the transna-

    tional networks that converge on the indigenous resistance movement in

    Chiapas, Mexico, and a major contribution to legal anthropology by Sally

    Engle Merry (2006), who makes her own use of comparative ethnography to

    highlight some of the moral vexations of human rights, particularly womens

    rights, when translated and applied (or in her terms vernacularized) in

    local settings with their own assemblages of custom and political interest.

    One of the core issues presented by Goodale involves a distinction between

    human rights universality and human rights universalism. Universality is based

    on the idea of common humanness, a claim that is at the core of the modern

    ideas of human rights (15). Human rights universalism, on the other hand,

    involves a kind of utopianism in action, the complicated discursive presence

    of these claims as they are acted upon within existing legal, moral and political

    practice (15). Anthropology contributes to both domains. The cause of uni-

    versality has benefited from anthropologys arguments in favor of humanity

    as a single, undifferentiated species, over and against the disorienting fact of

    human multiplicity, with anthropologists in the early history of human

    rights successfully asserting (without recognition of this accomplishment)

    the most important putative cross-cultural fact: that human beings are

    T H E S O C I A L S T U D Y O F H U M A N R I G H T S 687

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    7/10

    essentially the same and that this essential sameness entails a specific normative

    framework(18).

    Universalism is also evident in anthropology. In fact, in recent years it has

    moved front and center, particularly in more recent attempts by individual

    anthropologists and the disciplines largest professional association tore-engage with human rights as both an object of study and a vehicle for eman-

    cipatory political practice(19). And largely through its post-colonial commit-

    ments to emancipation, anthropology has become mired in the newest

    contradictions of culture. Anthropologists have shifted from the idea of

    culture as a bounded entity, often some permutation of the German Kultur

    with a K with its affinity to the idea of an inner essence orVolksgeist, to

    an idea of culture with an emphasis on process or more particularly on inter-

    subjective meanings and practices that are shifting and contested. This con-

    ceptual transformation, however, remains incomplete, in part because of theobjectifying effects of human rights advocacy, which anthropologists as an

    entirety (as would-be defenders and describers of the marginalized and forgot-

    ten) have taken up with alacrity. Universalism, with its utopian overtones, is

    reflected in the choice of anthropologists to tightly bundle their political com-

    mitments with their professional practice (121). But how is it possible to

    promote a peoples rights when their identity as a people is analytically inse-

    cure, when they represent just one of many possibilities for collective self-

    representation and rights claims? Goodales conceptual map makes it possible

    to see a fundamental contradiction in the consensual foundations of anthropol-

    ogy: it categorically rejects the notion of bounded culture, while engaged in

    advocacy premised on the cadastral orientation of the law of peoples, and

    that periodically implicates anthropologists in the boundary-enhancing fabrica-

    tions of identity construction and the politics of micro-nationalism.

    The cultural contradiction (or contradictory approach to culture) that plagues

    the agencies of global governance runs along similar lines, though its origins in

    policy are quite different. Human rights are based in a core conviction that fol-

    lowed from the experience of World War II and the era of decolonization: that

    individuals required protection from states, often from the very states of which

    they are citizens, and that human rights could serve as an ultimate check on the

    abuses of culture manifested as nationalism(75). But this went along with an

    impulse to redefine culture as a kind of property, without which individuals

    would be unable to prosper, and following from this, to codify cultures, to

    name them and to list the essential attributes that the global community

    would be committed to protect. Hence, we arrive at the cultural protection

    initiatives of UNESCO, as in the 2001 Universal Declaration of Cultural Diver-

    sity, which returns to the professionally discarded anthropological approach to

    culture as a bounded object of inquiry, appreciation, and protection.

    Also possible through the new anthropology of law are ethnographies of

    human rights networks, with NGOs as the principal actors whose behavior is

    688 R O N A L D N I E Z E N

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    8/10

    the problem of investigation. Human rights networks have hegemonic ten-

    dencies, or tendencies to become imperial, through the evacuation of

    alternative discourses on the basis of what the imperial power believesearn-

    estly or notis the correct, or morally superior, or economically more advan-

    tageous set of perspectives and practices(108). The common denominator ofGoodales critiques of the cultural conceptions of agencies of global govern-

    ance and of human rights-oriented NGOs is their shared resort to distorted con-

    ceptions of culture connected to unrealistic futurism, as captured in a

    summarizing statement: The problems that culture poses for human rights

    theory and practice will not really be solved until those who have chosen to sur-

    render to utopia come to terms with everyone else(90).

    The programmatic nature of Goodales overview necessarily introduces the

    despair of sweeping, unassailable critique based on the clarity of fact and

    reason, while calling on his readers to take his glimmerings of optimism onfaith, based as they are (as with Sen) in a methodethnographythat lies

    within his specialized competence but beyond his immediate purpose. Harri

    Englund, in Prisoners of Freedom, accomplishes what Sen and Goodale, in

    the books I have chosen to review, cannot: a critical study of human rights

    in practice dedicated to a single, tightly focused setting.

    The evidence in Englunds book advises caution with Sens admiration for

    freedom. At the intersections of NGOs and the poor of Malawi, normative

    approaches to rights often become entangled in the very rhetoric that needs

    to be scrutinized, a situation that makes salientthe perils of isolating political

    freedoms as the essence of democracy(12). The situation Englund describes

    making full use of his fluency in Chichewa and the experience of many years in

    Malawi, together with the moral authority of his ongoing commitments to

    working in the regionis at variance with the complacency of those who

    have convinced themselves of possibilities of human betterment simply by

    evangelizing the moral message of rights. In Malawi,NGOs, in effect, exercise

    a form of self-control, potentially far more insidious than any law that the gov-

    ernment can formulate. Their discourse is elitist, even though many of the self-

    proclaimed experts of freedom, democracy, and human rights do not belong to

    the elite (20). Translation of human rights instruments has taken place as a

    top down exercise, with no evidence of attempts to consult a broad cross-

    section of native speakers before launching a translation for human rights

    (48). And human rights discourseeven when asserting all individuals as

    equalscan be deprived of its democratizing potential and made to serve par-

    ticular interests in society(49). This is a setting in which well-meaning acti-

    vists believed that their knowledge of rights had not yet touched the lives of the

    grassroots. Activists sought to enlightenthe Malawians they considered as the

    grassroots, also known as the masses. They referred to this process with the Chi-

    chewa verb kuwunikira, which connotes the shedding of light. Activists saw

    themselves as the torchbearers, the ones who brought light to the darkness(71).

    T H E S O C I A L S T U D Y O F H U M A N R I G H T S 689

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    9/10

    One of Englunds more disconcerting findings is the extent to which an

    NGOs legal officers used their apparently exclusive legal knowledge to

    avoid confronting the exploitation that many Malawians endured. Under

    these circumstances, democracy and human rights were not allowed to

    exist as contested concepts, amenable to the expression and negotiation ofdiverse interests(125). Instead, contempt for the victimhood of their clients,

    made each of them appear as a saboteur of his or her own freedom(129).

    Englunds critique is accomplished not just in the manner of an expos, not

    just as an effort to bring out the real life consequences of evangelical

    approaches to human rights, but applies equally to the rethinking and reframing

    of the idea of justice, the very problem engaged in by Sen. It describes circum-

    stances in which the universalism of preconceptualized ideas of freedom and

    democracy inevitably results in their negation. Hypocrisy is built into the intel-

    lectual tool kit of Africas rights reformers from the outset. The parameters oftheir discussions with supposed beneficiaries of freedom and democracy are

    closedor perhaps open only in the way of traps, ready to spring shut on entry.

    Unexpectedly, Englunds blistering condemnation of human rights

    approached as a creed leaves room for optimism, or at least recognition of

    ongoing possibilities for the ideals of democracy, development, and freedom

    that are the driving forces of the rights movement. In contrast with the

    narrow, subject positions of rights activists, the claimants seeking legal aid,

    and the urban poor caught in the midst of moral panic consistently voiced con-

    cerns that were of general import. They demanded attention to the necessity to

    inform any realization of human rights with an understanding of the situations

    in which people live(204). Clearly enough, an alternative approach to human

    rights universalism would begin with close attention to the conceptualizations

    of the rights-related ideals of the Africans themselves, that is to say, to navigate

    the civic virtues that emerge out of explicit and inclusive negotiation (193).

    This finding would certainly appear to have wider implications than the par-

    ticular setting and circumstances of Malawi, but the necessarily tight focus of

    Englunds ethnography, which is its specific strength, at the same time leaves

    unanswered some of the comparative implications of his work. Englund

    approaches his ethnography with an unusual, perhaps unique, degree of

    honestyverging on contempt for the kind of power interests that commonly

    manage to control both the lives of the poor and the findings of researchers

    and this makes it difficult to generalize from the setting he describes. There is

    enough of a ring of truth to his account of the activistselitism and complicity

    with the attitudes and structures of extreme social inequalities to suggest that

    this is common to human rights activism almost everywhere. But there

    remain some settings where we see an everyday practice in which the subjects

    of rights are engaged in more direct, strategic use of human rights and their

    starry-eyed NGO advocates, not just engaged in futile resistance through sys-

    temically incompetent NGOs or passively venting their agency through wild

    690 R O N A L D N I E Z E N

  • 8/11/2019 Niezen CSSH Article 2011

    10/10

    rumors. The Maasai of Kenya and Tanzania, for example, have made active use

    of activists, seeking protection from state encroachments on pasturage by pur-

    suing legal claims and participating in various international forums as an indi-

    genous people and as a pastoral people (Hodgson 2004). Englund would very

    likely not deny that human rights are malleable by the particular interests of thepowerless as well as the powerful, though his emphasis is clearly on the abuses

    of states and NGOs. This strategic use of human rights networks and insti-

    tutions of course raises possibilities for new avenues to power from within

    the communities of the marginalized. At the same time, new strategies of

    rights campaigning add the complexities of cultural appeal to potentially sym-

    pathetic audiences as a rights strategy, with its built in potential for self-

    stereotyping and corruption of the goals of self-determination (Niezen 2010).

    This is simply to say that Englunds courageous ethnography raises compara-

    tive questions and possibilities, which he points to but cannot fully realize in asingle ethnography, in which the outlines of an alternative approach to human

    rights, absent the errors of elitism and imperialism, can be seen more clearly

    than ever before.

    This brings us to an important common denominator evident in all three

    approaches to the social study of human rights: none call for an outright rejec-

    tion of transnational normative systems. There are no romantic longings after

    simple, self-enclosed prosperity, just a certain Weltschmertz in response to

    the systemic suffering and indignities imposed on people who deserve better.

    Human rights are now mainstream, an unavoidable fact of life, with which

    we as scholars with critical training can either reconcile, and to which we

    can apply our skills of observation and interpretation, or which, in our

    absence, will change the world for better or worse (and probably a bit of

    both in varying degrees).

    R E F E R E N C E S

    Arrow, Kenneth. 1950. A Difficulty in the Concept of Social Welfare. Journal of Pol-itical Economy58, 4: 32846.

    Herder, Johann Gottfried. 2002. Philosophical Writings. Michael Forster, ed.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Hodgson, Dorothy. 2004. Once Intrepid Warriors: Gender, Ethnicity, and the CulturalPolitics of Maasai Development. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Merry, Sally Engle. 2006. Human Rights and Gender Violence: Translating Inter-national Law into Local Justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Niezen, Ronald. 2010. Public Justice and the Anthropology of Law. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    Rawls, John.A Theory of Justice. 1999. Rev. ed. Cambridge: Belknap Press of HarvardUniversity Press.

    Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Anchor.

    Speed, Shannon. 2008. Rights in Rebellion: Indigenous Struggle and Human Rights inChiapas. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    T H E S O C I A L S T U D Y O F H U M A N R I G H T S 691