27
Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm? Author(s): David Mendeloff Source: International Studies Review, Vol. 6, No. 3 (Sep., 2004), pp. 355-380 Published by: Wiley on behalf of The International Studies Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3699695 . Accessed: 10/11/2014 21:52 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Wiley and The International Studies Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to International Studies Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Article that casts doubts on the benefits of Truth-Seeking and Truth-Telling for Postconflict Peacebuilding

Citation preview

Page 1: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?Author(s): David MendeloffSource: International Studies Review, Vol. 6, No. 3 (Sep., 2004), pp. 355-380Published by: Wiley on behalf of The International Studies AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3699695 .

Accessed: 10/11/2014 21:52

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Wiley and The International Studies Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extendaccess to International Studies Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

International Studies Review (2004) 6, 355-380

REFLECTION, EVALUATION, INTEGRATION

Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding:

Curb the Enthusiasm?'

DAVID MENDELOFF

Norman Paterson School of International Affairs, Carleton University

This essay evaluates popular and scholarly claims about the peace- promoting benefits of formal truth-telling and truth-seeking mecha- nisms in the aftermath of civil wars. Its purpose is twofold. First, it synthesizes and clearly articulates in one place the full range of claims about the relationship between truth-telling and peacebuilding. Second, it evaluates these claims by systematically examining the core factual and theoretical assumptions on which they are based. An argument is made that many such claims-and their core assumptions-are flawed or highly contentious as well as that truth-telling advocates claim far more about the power of truth-telling than logic or evidence dictates. This is not to say that truth-telling has no role to play in preventing the re- sumption of violent conflict in postwar societies, only that proponents likely overstate its importance. Before proclaiming the necessity of truth commissions or trials in the aftermath of violent conflict, we need to better understand how truth-telling prevents the recurrence of civil war, how important it is relative to other factors and other peacebuilding strategies, and when it is likely to prove helpful, harmful, or irrelevant.

Over the past decade a general consensus has emerged on the need for states and societies to address past crimes and misdeeds in the aftermath of war and violent conflict. Scholars and practitioners of peacebuilding, as well as publics of war-torn societies, increasingly agree that some kind of formal accounting of the past is essential to achieve lasting, "self-enforcing" peace in war-torn states. Formal mech- anisms for the public accounting of wartime abuses-either in the form of criminal trials or less punitive historical commissions-are now part of the standard rep- ertoire of international peacebuilding activities and are routinely included in

negotiated peace settlements. Truth-telling (which is used interchangeably with

truth-seeking in this essay) is increasingly considered a necessary, if not vital, com-

ponent of the peacebuilding process, as important as demobilization, disarmament,

'Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the Workshop on War Memory, MIT Center for International Studies, January 25, 2003, and at the annual meeting of the International Studies Association in Portland, Oregon, March 1, 2003. The author thanks David Carment, Whan Choi, Jean Daudelin, Fen Hampson, Cynthia Irvin, Loren

King, Roy Licklider, Jennifer Lind, Roger Peterson, Benjamin Valentino, Stephen Van Evera and Inger Weibust. Sarah Noble and Francis Bedros provided valuable research assistance.

? 2004 International Studies Review. Published by Blackwell Publishing, 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA, and 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

356 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

or the holding of postwar elections.2 Recently, a major study on postconflict re- construction by the Center for Strategic and International Studies and the Asso- ciation of the United States Army proclaimed truth-telling to be one of "four pillars" of successful peacebuilding (Flournoy and Pen 2002; Hamre and Sullivan 2002). In its comprehensive handbook for international donors, nongovernmental organizations (NGOs), and postconflict governments, the International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (IDEA) (2003) includes truth-telling as one of four necessary mechanisms for achieving reconciliation, and ultimately lasting peace, after violent conflict. In the aftermath of the recent Iraq war, many have stated that a formal accounting of Baath party crimes is necessary to ease the transition to a peaceful society (Eizenstat 2003; International Center for Transi- tional Justice 2003).

But is such enthusiasm for truth-seeking warranted? How important is truth- telling in the peacebuilding process? Is it necessary or sufficient to consolidate peace in the aftermath of violent civil war? Truth-telling advocates make a number of claims about the peace-promoting effects of truth-seeking: it (1) assures justice, (2) promotes social and psychological healing, (3) fosters reconciliation, and (4) deters future crimes, all of which help consolidate peace in war-torn societies. Yet, how compelling are these claims? How sound is the causal logic? How valid are the theoretical and factual assumptions on which they are based? These are the questions this essay addresses.

The purpose of this essay is to evaluate popular and scholarly truth-telling claims advanced in the postconflict justice and peacebuilding literatures. The primary aim is to take stock of the current state of knowledge regarding the effects of truth- telling on the peacebuilding process. An argument will be made that despite claims of truth-telling advocates, we actually know very little about the impact of truth- telling or truth-seeking on peace. Claims about the peace-promoting effects of formal truth-telling mechanisms rest far more on faith than on sound logic or empirical evidence. The literature has done a poor job of specifying the logic of truth-telling arguments, defining and clarifying key concepts, operationalizing key variables, indicating the conditions under which proposed relationships hold, pro- viding compelling empirical evidence to support core assumptions, and testing claims systematically against competing explanations. Assertions are frequently presented as empirical fact when they are merely untested hypotheses. In short, truth-telling advocates claim more about the power of truth-telling than logic or evidence dictates.

This last statement is not meant to imply that truth-telling has no role to play as a conflict prevention tool in postwar societies, only that it remains unclear how sig- nificant it is. Truth-telling advocates likely overstate the case. Compelling argu- ments and limited evidence have, indeed, been offered regarding the role of chauvinist, hypernationalist mythmaking; rooted in lies and historical distortion, such myth-making has fostered certain intrastate and interstate wars (Posen 1993; Van Evera 1994; Brown 1996, 2001; Byman and Van Evera 1998; Mertus 1999; Snyder 2000; Kaufman 2001; Mendeloff 2001; Byman 2002). It follows that efforts taken to prevent such mythmaking might also prevent a return to violent conflict in certain war-torn societies. However, we still have insufficient information regarding how that can be done. It is certainly open to question how effective formal truth-seeking mechanisms-either trials or truth commissions--can be in pre- cluding the emergence of chauvinist mythmaking in the long term. The impact of truth-telling mechanisms in the short-term consolidation of peace is almost cer- tainly negligible, if not irrelevant. In short, before proclaiming the necessity of

2Broad theoretical treatments of peacebuilding, such as those by Hampson (1997) and Licklider (2001), include

truth-telling among the necessary components of a successful peace process, though they do not single it out

exclusively nor necessarily endorse its utility.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 357

truth-telling in the aftermath of violent conflict, we need to do a better job of clearly specifying how truth-telling will benefit peacebuilding, under what conditions, and after which types of conflicts as well as when it helps consolidate peace and when it does not.

Before turning to such tasks, however, five caveats are in order. First, this essay evaluates truth-telling broadly, encompassing all formal, officially sanctioned public mechanisms for examining the causes and conduct of a past war and accounting for crimes and abuses committed during wartime. This evaluation includes criminal investigations and prosecutions as well as less punitive historical fact-finding or "truth commissions." Of course, truth-telling and truth-seeking mechanisms differ in important ways-the logic of trials is different from the logic of truth commis- sions, for example. Indeed, the postconflict justice literature is dominated by a debate over alternative truth-telling mechanisms -namely, the relative merits of retributive versus restorative justice approaches. Nonetheless, advocates of both sides share the same core belief that public accounting for wartime misconduct is necessary for peace and stability. They differ only over the mechanisms by which the truth is uncovered and how that information is used-either to punish those found guilty of abuses or merely to expose such actions in the court of public opinion. It is the shared core assumptions that this essay examines.

Second, "truth-telling" speaks to three distinct, yet overlapping issues: (a) the causes and prevention of war, (b) human rights violations during peacetime, and (c) the commission of crimes during wartime. The present essay is concerned with the first issue. The others are important and may have some implications for war prevention, but they are ultimately distinct. Thus, truth-telling may play a role in preventing human rights violations during peacetime or preventing the commis- sion of crimes during wartime, but these concerns are analytically distinct from its role in preventing war. As noted below, one problem with the literature is that these issues are often conflated, for example, implicit-and contentious-assumptions are made about the causal links between human rights violations and the causes and prevention of war.

Third, the essay focuses exclusively on formal, officially sanctioned, public truth- telling mechanisms. This focus is adopted because the postconflict justice and the peacebuilding literatures are concerned with these formal mechanisms and ascribe importance to them. However, such formal institutions may not be the only, nor the most effective, way to account for past misdeeds.

Fourth, the essay focuses on the role of truth-telling after civil wars. Once again, this tack is taken not because truth-telling in the aftermath of interstate wars is unworthy of attention, but because the postconflict justice and peacebuilding literatures focus almost exclusively on the aftermath of internal conflicts. Exceptions to this last statement include the work of Catherine Lu (2002), who looks at the aftermath of World War I, and the research of William Long and Peter Brecke (2003).

Fifth, and finally, this essay draws upon the main theoretical and empirical work on truth-telling and peacebuilding. This literature is diverse in opinions and ap- proaches. However, the task here is to focus on the common claims and assump- tions that cut across the literature. As a result, the reader will note that the author occasionally will simplify subtle and complex arguments and make general state- ments for which exceptions are bound to exist. Such exceptions will be noted.

This essay consists of three sections. Section one summarizes eight main claims advanced about the peace-promoting effects of truth-telling. Section two critically examines these claims by assessing the core factual and theoretical assumptions on which they are based. An argument is made that most of these assumptions are dubious or, at a minimum, highly contentious. The third and concluding section offers thoughts about the likely value of truth-telling and proposes an agenda for future research.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

358 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

The Peace-Promoting Effects of Truth-Telling It is commonly argued that truth-telling and peace go hand in hand. Without truth- telling, writes M. Cherif Bassiouni (1996:23), "the embers of yesterday's conflict can become the fire of tomorrow's renewed conflict." 'Just as wounds fester when they are not exposed to the open air," writes Elizabeth Kiss (2000:72), "so unac- knowledged injustice can poison societies and produce the cycles of distrust, hatred, and violence we have witnessed in many parts of the world." But how exactly does truth-telling promote peace? Truth-telling advocates offer a host of reasons why exposing and publicly accounting for wartime misdeeds is an essential component of the peacebuilding process. Specifically, at least eight primary (and overlapping) claims are made about the peace-promoting effects of truth-telling. Truth-telling (1) encourages social healing and reconciliation, (2) promotes justice, (3) allows for the establishment of an official historical record, (4) serves a public education function, (5) aids institutional reform, (6) helps promote democracy, and (7) pre- empts as well as (8) deters future atrocities. Each claim and its general causal logic, summarized in Table 1, are detailed below.

TABLE 1. Eight Primary Peace-Promoting Effects of Truth-Telling (TT)

1. Social Healing and Reconciliation 1.1. TT - healing of individual victims -, group reconciliation -* peace 1.2. TT - individualized responsibility for crimes -4 group reconciliation - peace

2. Justice 2.1. TT -- justice - psychological healing of individual victims -> group reconciliation - peace 2.2. TT - justice - prevention of revenge killings -+ peace 2.3 TT -~ justice - individual criminal accountability -> peace

3. Official, Authoritative Historical Record 3.1. TT - official historical record - healing of victims -> group reconciliation -+ peace 3.2. TT - official historical record - new shared history -+ group reconciliation -* peace 3.3. TT - official historical record -+ settling of conflict over past -> power-sharing -+ peace

4. Public Education 4.1. TT ? learned lessons of the past - peace 4.2. TT - human rights education -4 human rights culture -> peace

5. Institutional Reform 5.1. TT -+ exposes institutional pathologies -- institutional reform -+ preemption --+ peace

6. Democracy 6.1. TT -+ justice -+ rule of law --+ democracy -+ peace 6.2. TT - settling of conflict over past -+ power-sharing -> strengthened democracy -+ peace

7. Preemption 7.1. TT -4 arrest/incarceration of war criminals -+ preemption of crimes -* end to human rights

abuses - peace 7.2. TT -+ public shaming/ostracism -* preemption of crimes -> end to human rights

abuses -* peace 7.3. TT --+ discrediting of old regime/elites -* preemption of return to power -* end to human

rights abuses -* peace

8. Deterrence 8.1. TT - punishment -- accountability -+ deterrence of future crimes -+ end to human rights

abuses -+ peace 8.2. TT -4 public shaming/ostracism -+ deterrence of future crimes -* end to human rights

abuses -+ peace

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 359

Social Healing and Reconciliation

One of the primary claims of the postconflict justice and peacebuilding literature is that truth-telling promotes social healing and reconciliation. A common refrain is that "after an international conflict or civil war in which grave human rights abuses have been committed the truth must be told before there can be a success- ful reconciliation" (Scharf 1997:400; also see International IDEA 2003). Reconcil- iation is especially encouraged through the psychological healing of individual victims and survivors. By exposing the truth of past crimes, victims and survivors can begin to heal from the trauma of war and receive closure. Once they have begun to heal, they can then work toward reconciling with their former adversaries. Truth-telling, in short, is therapeutic (Minow 1998:61-87; Hayner 2001:133-153). "National reconciliation and individual rehabilitation," writes Michael Scharf (1997:379), "are facilitated by acknowledging the suffering of victims and their families, helping to resolve uncertain cases, and allowing victims to tell their story, thus serving a therapeutic purpose for an entire country, and imparting to the citizenry a sense of dignity and empowerment that could help them move beyond the pain of the past." Judith Herman (1994:1) has similarly argued, "remembering and telling the truth about terrible events are prerequisites both for the restoration of the social order and for the healing of individual victims."

Indeed, the process of truth-telling is considered just as important as the truth itself (Popkin and Roht-Arriaza 1995:114). "Telling the truth about their wounds," writes Kiss (2000:72), "can heal the wounded-and perhaps listening to such sto- ries can help heal societies." This, of course, was the main premise of the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission (TRC). As the TRC's architect Arch- bishop Desmond Tutu has asserted, "there is no healing without truth" (quoted in Kiss 2000:72).

But the healing power of truth-telling is not limited to truth commissions. In making the case for criminal prosecutions, Payam Akhavan (1998:766), a former prosecutor at the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY), has contended that "truth telling will also enable victims to hear and see their stories told-either their own personal stories or stories like theirs-in an officially sanctioned forum before the international community." Thus, Richard Goldstone (1996:491), who served as chief prosecutor of the ICTY and the Inter- national Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR), notes, "the work of truth commis- sions or judicial inquiries share with criminal prosecution the ability to bring significant satisfaction to victims. If that satisfaction is sufficiently widespread within a community, it can have a soothing effect upon a whole society." The Commission Nationale Consultative des Droits de l'Homme and the International Commission of Jurists (1993:337) has similarly emphasized the common purpose of trials and truth commissions, noting "regardless of the situation, we all agree that the chief priority is to establish the facts, that is, to pursue an investigation. This is an ob- ligation owed the victims and their relatives, an obligation owed historical memory and a safeguard against forgetting."

In addition to the psychological healing of individual wounds, truth-telling encourages social healing and reconciliation by promoting individual over collective guilt. When the truths of past crimes are exposed, individuals--not en- tire ethnic, religious, or cultural groups--are singled out for blame. This helps mitigate the resumption of violence by preventing mass reprisals or revenge kill- ings, but it also allows for adversarial groups to rebuild relationships more easily. As Akhavan (1998:766) argues, "truth-telling promotes interethnic reconciliation through the individualization of guilt in hate-mongering leaders and by disabusing people of the myth that adversary ethnic groups bear collective responsibility for crimes."

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

360 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

Justice

Closely related to social healing is the claim that truth-telling leads to peace by promoting justice for victims of war crimes and their families. Exposing the truth, assigning blame to perpetrators, and either punishing them or forcing them to publicly admit their crimes, it is contended, helps achieve justice. As Goldstone (1996:491) has argued, "the public and official exposure of the truth is itself a form of justice, and it does not matter whether that exposure takes place in criminal or civil proceedings." Justice, in turn, promotes peace in a variety of ways. A sense of justice is often necessary for the personal, psychological healing that allows for reconciliation. It also dampens motives for revenge killings. And when justice comes about through criminal prosecutions, it breaks the cycle of violence by stamping out impunity. It is the latter claim in particular that is the most widely purveyed by the scholars and practitioners of international criminal law: simply put, "there can be no peace without justice."3

Official Historical Record

The third main claim is that truth-telling promotes peace by providing the basis for an official, authoritative account of past crimes and misdeeds. This account comes in the form of the official record of a criminal trial or from a report of an investigative commission and ostensibly promotes peace in at least four ways. First, it represents official acknowledgment of crimes, thereby promoting healing of victims and con- tributing to reconciliation. Second, it provides an objective accounting of the past that can be used as the basis for developing a common shared history, which in turn helps serve as the basis for reconciliation. Third, it "closes the book" on a painful history. By providing the definitive word on the past, it removes history as a point of contention among former adversaries, allowing them to work together construc- tively in new power-sharing arrangements (Goldstone 1996:494; Hayner 2001). And, fourth, an authoritative report, in the words of Michael Ignatieff (1996:113), reduces the number of permissible lies in public discourse. Demagogues and ethnic entrepreneurs will have less success inciting violence by appealing to historical dis- tortions and myths if the truth is actually known (see also Huyse 2003:30).

Public Education

The fourth major peace-promoting effect of truth-telling is its role in educating the nation about the events of the past, learning from history, and thereby preventing a resumption of violence. As Prescilla Hayner (1994:607-609) argues, creating a cred- ible account of human rights crimes "allows a society to learn from its past in order to prevent a repetition of such violence in the future." Further, truth-telling edu- cates the nation about respect for human rights. Formal truth-telling exercises become public morality plays with great educational value. "The hope is that such a record," according to Jeremy Sarkin (1999:800), "in combination with the recom- mendations made by the commission, will ensure the avoidance of such human rights violations in the future and will also further the development of a human rights culture."

Institutional Reform

Another major claim is that truth-telling encourages peace through the promotion of institutional reforms. Both trials and truth commissions, for example, reveal structural institutional pathologies that led to war or contributed to wartime abuses.

3Benjamin B. Ferencz, former Nuremberg prosecutor, quoted on the home page of the International Criminal Court at http://www.un.org/law/icc/general/overview.htm.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 8: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 361

Truth commissions, in particular, are often tasked with recommending institu- tional reforms that follow from their investigations. This serves peace largely by prevention: changing the institutions that facilitated the war or the carrying out of war crimes removes an important cause of future war and wartime abuses.

Democracy One of the most widely claimed effects of truth-telling is that it promotes and strengthens democratic institutions, practices, and values in war-torn societies. Peace results in at least two ways. By promoting justice, truth-telling helps con- solidate the rule of law, the pillar of democracy. Conflicts are then settled through political deliberation and debate, not violence. Truth-telling also strengthens de- mocracy by settling disputes over history. By bringing about a consensus on divisive historical events, political elites can focus on governing rather than on debating the past. A stronger democracy results, in which conflicts can be settled peacefully rather than through violence.

Preemption and Deterrence

Finally, it is often claimed that truth-telling advances peace through preemption and deterrence. Preemption leads to peace by removing war criminals from society or from public life so they will be unable to perpetrate violence in the future. Truth- telling encourages preemption in a number of ways. When truth-telling occurs through criminal investigation and prosecution, it leads to the arrest and incar- ceration of convicted war criminals. Physically removing them from society pre- vents them from carrying out crimes in the future. Even mere indictments of al- leged war criminals, it is argued, are enough to popularly discredit them, forcing their retreat from public life (Akhavan 2001). Truth-telling through public investigative commissions in which perpetrators are named can also have the same effect. Truth- telling can "prevent the old regime from attempting to retake control because the process would eviscerate the old authorities' ability to deny responsibility, blame others, or claim exigent circumstances. It would demystify the past and expose the previous regime's brutality and its inability to govern fairly" (Sarkin 1999:801).

Truth-telling ostensibly leads to deterrence largely, but not exclusively, through criminal prosecution. Deterrence of future war crimes is the primary claim of ad- vocates of international criminal law. Punishing war criminals sends a signal that society will not tolerate such behavior. This deters potential war criminals from acting with impunity elsewhere. Yet, even if prosecutions do not result, truth-telling still has a deterrent effect by holding perpetrators publicly accountable for their actions. If war criminals are forced to publicly admit their crimes, even in exchange for amnesty, they face public shaming and becoming ostracized by the community. Many advocates of truth commissions, for example, contend that public shaming in many cultures can be worse than criminal sanctions and thus can serve as an ef- fective deterrent (Sarkin 1999:801; Hayner 2001:107-132). As Scharf (1997:394) argues, "the very publicity of the truth about an individual's responsibility for human rights crimes exposes the perpetrator to public ignominy and is therefore a form of punishment." This, along with "the imposition of administrative sanctions can have additional deterrent effects over both the whole of society and the in- dividual subject to the penalty."

Evaluating Truth-Telling Claims

These eight claims encapsulate the most common arguments advanced about the peace-promoting benefits of truth-telling. This section evaluates the claims by as- sessing the validity of the core factual and theoretical assumptions on which they

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 9: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

362 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

are based. The validity of truth-telling claims is only as strong as the assumptions on which they are based. An argument will be made here that these assumptions are either factually or logically flawed, highly contentious, or misconstrued, raising serious questions about the proclaimed utility of truth-seeking mechanisms.

Before examining each of these assumptions, several key concepts require def- inition. Given that our task is to evaluate claims about the benefits of postconflict truth-telling on the peacebuilding process, it is essential to understand what is meant by "peacebuilding" and "peace." The definitions of these concepts are crit- ical to assessing in even a rudimentary way the validity of claims about postconflict truth-telling.

Definitions and Measurement

Peacebuilding. Though still a point of debate, a consensus on what peacebuilding is or ought to be is emerging. Peacebuilding is the process of consolidating peace in the immediate aftermath of war and involves carrying out activities that help pre- vent the recurrence of war over the long term-that is, by creating institutions and mechanisms for resolving internal conflict without resort to violence (Hampson 1997; Cousens 2001; Lund 2002). Two points about this definition should be em- phasized. First, postconflict peacebuilding has both short- and long-term elements. Distinguishing between them is critical. What is required for peace in the imme- diate aftermath of conflict is generally not the same as what is required for long- term political, social, and economic reconstruction. One of the problems with the truth-telling literature generally is that it does not always disaggregate these two phases. Even if the distinction is made, truth-telling advocates often emphasize the need to establish truth-seeking mechanisms as quickly as possible. The Interna- tional IDEA, for example, has advocated including provisions for truth-telling in all peace settlements, a move that has become increasingly common (Bloomfield 2003b:44). As the IDEA handbook argues, "the worst decision is to postpone ad- dressing the difficult issues-the pain, the guilt, the emotions-in an attempt to preserve stability and peace. The 'right time' to deal with these matters never comes: they only become more difficult to deal with as time passes" (Bloomfield 2003b:48).4 Yet, as will be argued here, evidence and logic do not support the claim that formal truth-telling mechanisms will have a discernable impact in consolidating peace in the short term. Because that period is probably the single most important determinant of long-term peace and stability (Stedman 2002), the overall impor- tance of truth-telling in the peacebuilding process is probably less important than advocates claim.

Second, the ultimate goal of peacebuilding is war prevention. If war resumes, perhaps within a decade of concerted efforts at prevention, peacebuilding has ob- viously failed. The truth-telling literature, however, often elides clear definition and measurement of goals. It conflates analytically distinct concepts-peace and de- mocracy, peace and reconciliation, war prevention and the prevention of human rights abuses during war. Although democracy, reconciliation, and human rights are intuitively related to peace, they are nonetheless analytically distinct. The problem is particularly acute with at least two of the eight claims--preemption and deterrence. Arguments about removing war criminals from society or deterring war crimes in the future are largely arguments about the prevention of war crimes, not the promotion of peacebuilding. Even though measures taken to inhibit crimes of war are worthwhile, these are not necessarily the same measures required for last- ing peace once the war has ended.

4At the same time they (see Bloomfield 2003b:32) do acknowledge "experience suggests that a rushed approach, as regularly advocated by national and international peacemakers and facilitators, will almost certainly be coun- terproductive." How they reconcile these two contradictory positions remains unclear.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 10: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 363

Peace. The previous discussion raises the larger issue of defining and measuring peace itself. One reason why truth-telling claims conflate peace and democracy, peace and reconciliation, and peace and human rights is that they implicitly (or explicitly) utilize an expansive "positive" definition of peace. Peace is not merely the absence of violent conflict and war, but the absence of "structural violence"-en- demic socioeconomic and cultural (racial, ethnic, religious) inequality (Galtung 1969). Thus, respect for human rights, the rule of law, the absence of formal or informal discrimination, intergroup harmony-in short, liberal, egalitarian, social democracy-is considered necessary for peace to exist.

To avoid conflating analytically distinct concepts, we will use a modified minimal definition of peace here: the absence of large-scale, organized violence or war and the extremely low probability of the resumption of war. This definition rests on a necessary "negative" definition of peace as the absence of war, but also recognizes the importance of certain minimal qualitative indicators of peace. The latter means that practices and institutions for the nonviolent resolution of conflicts (and the prevention of the resumption of war) have been established and are stable and functioning. However, in contrast to more expansive "positive" definitions of peace, this definition does not necessarily require social, racial, or economic equality, the absence of poverty or discrimination, intergroup harmony and cooperation, or fully functioning liberal democratic institutions. Those are valuable aims for a society, but they are not necessarily the same as peace (Byman 2002:5-9). The absence of war is, in fact, a minimum requirement for the establishment of peace. Thus, it is actually the easy test of the validity of truth-telling claims: if truth-telling cannot bring about "negative" peace in a war-torn society, it can hardly be expected to bring about "positive" peace. We can, however, debate whether or not, and to what extent, issues of socioeconomic equality, human rights, rule of law, reconciliation, and so on are necessary to prevent the resumption of war in postconflict societies. In much of the literature these concepts are often treated simultaneously as in- dependent variables, dependent variables, and measures or indicators. Thus, the burden is on truth-telling advocates to establish a clear and logical causal connec- tion between these factors. It is to this issue that we now turn.

Core Assumptions

Truth-telling claims rest on the validity of a host of factual and theoretical assump- tions about the causes of war and peace. These assumptions can be grouped into three broad categories that include seventeen total assumptions addressing various elements of the core logic of truth-telling claims. The core assumptions are presented by category in Table 2. First are psychological assumptions (that is, assumptions regarding the manipulation and effects of psychological varia- bles-fears, insecurity, trauma, feelings of injustice-in order to bring about peace). Second are assumptions about identity and its relation to war and peace (that is, assumptions about the manipulation and effects of historical beliefs and national identities). Third are institutional and normative assumptions (that is, assumptions about the creation, manipulation, and effects of new social and political institutions and norms). How valid are each of these types of assump- tions? What does this evaluation tell us about the validity of the larger truth-telling claims?

Psychological Assumptions. Table 2 indicates that many truth-telling claims rest on the validity of at least eight psychologically rooted assumptions. The first seven assumptions lie at the heart of the core claim about truth-telling--that it leads to peace through social healing and reconciliation.

Assumption 1i--the belief that individual psychology is essentially the same as group or national psychology (or that it is similar enough that we can generalize

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 11: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

364 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

TABLE 2. Core Assumptions of Truth-Telling Claims

Psychological Assumptions 1. Personal healing promotes national healing. 2. Truth-telling promotes individual healing after psychological trauma. 3. National reconciliation is peace-promoting. 4. Truth-telling promotes reconciliation. 5. Justice (or the pursuit of justice) is necessary for peace. 6. Truth-telling can promote individual over collective guilt. 7. Collective guilt is dangerous and undesirable. 8. Forgetting, suppressing, or distorting the past causes war.

Identity Assumptions 9. Divided societies are better off held together than separated.

10. Shared, collective identities are peace-promoting. 11. Historical beliefs and national identities are relatively easy to manipulate. 12. Truth-telling can serve as the basis of a new shared identity.

Institutional and Normative Assumptions 13. Democracies are less prone to civil war. 14. The truth promotes democracy. 15. Truth-telling promotes an accurate historical record. 16. Truth-telling promotes respect for human rights and the rule of law. 17. Respect for human rights and the rule of law is peace-promoting.

from individuals to societies and the nation)-is pervasive in the truth-telling and

postconflict justice literature. "What is true of individuals emerging from massive abuse and trauma," asserts Neil Kritz (1999:168), "is no less true of nations: mech- anisms are needed to confront and reckon with that past, facilitating closure rather than repression." War crimes create "social psychoses" that must be treated

through truth-telling (Cobban 2002). Tina Rosenberg (1995:26), for example, has

argued that societies, like individuals, can suffer posttraumatic stress disorder. Na- tions that repress traumatic episodes rather than confront them directly, just like traumatized individuals, are unlikely to recover from that trauma. Brandon Ham- ber (2001:134, emphasis added) concurs: "Psychologically speaking, sleeping dogs do not lie; past traumas do not simply pass or disappear with the passage of time. The past will not let itself be ignored and past traumas can always be expected to have emotional consequences for an individual and society at some later stage."

The validity of such claims, however, is questionable. First, little empirical re- search supports this logic. As Martha Minow (1998:63) has shown, "when it comes to national healing, it is simply unclear whether theories and evidence of individual

recovery from violence have much bearing." It is also problematic intuitively. As

Ignatieff (1996:110) has asked, "do nations, like individuals, have psyches? ... Can we speak of nations 'working through' a civil war or atrocity like we speak of individuals working through a traumatic memory or event?" In fact, "individuals

may be made ill by repression of their own past but it is less clear that what holds true for individuals must also hold true for societies" (Ignatieff 1996:121; see also Hamber and Wilson 2002). In short, to assume that we can generalize from in- dividual experience to the societal or national level is dubious.

Yet, even if a direct relationship between individual and societal or national

healing could be established, does truth-telling, in fact, promote individual healing after psychological trauma (Assumption 2)? Here as well, the assumption is suspect. The evidence from clinical research regarding the treatment of posttraumatic stress disorder and other psychological disorders is in actuality quite mixed. No consen- sus exists among clinical psychologists on how best to treat victims of emotional trauma. Individuals appear to be unique and to respond differently to the same

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 12: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 365

therapies. In some cases, hearing the truth is beneficial and ultimately helps in- dividuals heal; in other cases, the truth can retraumatize victims and make their suffering worse. Despite these data, a good deal of the truth-telling literature touts the "healthy catharsis" involved in testifying at trials or truth-commissions or from hearing confessions of perpetrators.5 Clinical psychologists, however, generally concur that cathartic experiences should be avoided except under highly controlled conditions because the dangers of retraumatization could be much greater than the potential benefits (Minow 1998; Allan and Allan 2000:472-473; Hayner 2001).

Moreover, great differences exist between truth-telling introduced into a pro- fessional relationship between a therapist and patient in a controlled clinical setting and public truth-telling in the aftermath of violent conflict. Very little, if any, ev- idence exists that formal truth-telling institutions actually benefit individuals' emo- tional or psychological health. No systematic studies of the psychological effects of truth-telling exist (Hamber 2001:137; Hayner 2001:135). Although some limited studies have been conducted on the psychological effects of the South African TRC, the evidence is purely anecdotal. Indeed, the truth-telling literature relies heavily on anecdotal evidence. Even some of the more balanced discussions of truth-telling are guilty of over-generalizing from isolated cases. Ignatieff (1996:121), for exam- ple, who has a critical view of truth-telling claims, nonetheless points to anecdotal evidence in arguing that "individuals can be helped to heal and to reconcile by public rituals of atonement." Although Minow (1998:57) acknowledges the "lim- itations in the therapeutic value of commissions for individuals and limitations in our knowledge of societal healing," she (Minow 1998:66), nonetheless, concludes that "anecdotal evidence suggests the healing power of speaking about trauma." However, anecdotal evidence can also speak to the dangers of truth-telling. In an analysis of the effects of the TRC, psychologists Alfred and Marietjie Allan (2000:472-473) note that "there are no empirical or other data that suggest that any long-term healing followed for witnesses who experienced catharsis while giv- ing testimony to the TRC. Anecdotal evidence is that it sometimes caused imme- diate, and maybe enduring, trauma." Yet, even they are guilty of overvaluing truth- telling benefits. Although their own study failed to determine "whether the rec- onciliation at an individual level has an effect on national reconciliation," they nonetheless conclude that "the TRC was relatively successful as a therapeutic tool" and advocate policies that promote personal psychological healing as a way to national reconciliation (Allan and Allan 2000:463-464).

None of this is to say that the psychological healing of individual victims and survivors is unimportant. Survivors of wartime violence and brutality often do suffer from lasting emotional and physical distress. Making efforts to help ease the suffering of those individuals is worthwhile. But in the absence of compelling evidence, we should be skeptical of claims that formal truth-telling mechanisms are the best way to help or that such "psychological healing" in general is somehow necessary to build and maintain peace in postconflict societies.

Even if we could establish a clear link between truth-telling and personal healing and between individual and societal or national healing, however, is it true that national reconciliation is necessarily peace-promoting (Assumption 3)? Part of the problem with this assumption is the term "reconciliation," and how it is used (Borer 2001; Tepperman 2002:134-135; Huyse 2003:19-33). Peace and reconciliation, as noted above, are frequently conflated although, in fact, they are analytically distinct. Like the term "peace," "reconciliation" has been defined "negatively" to mean "nonlethal coexistence" (Crocker 2000:99-121) or "rapprochement" (Putnam 2002:251) among former adversaries as well as "positively" to mean intergroup harmony and cooperation and a relationship free of bias, bigotry, hatred, and

5A notably more nuanced and qualified view is offered by Hayner (2001) and Freeman and Hayner (2003).

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 13: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

366 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

suspicion (Lederach 1997; Pankhurst 1999:240-241; Gutman and Thompson 2000:22-44). Both of these formulations, however, are as distinct as the competing definitions of peace. Moreover, it is not just academics, but also individual groups in postconflict societies, who often disagree over what constitutes reconciliation (van Zyl 1999; Kemali 2001:140). The ambiguity of the term makes it particularly dif- ficult to operationalize and measure. Without clear indicators, it is impossible to discern the effects of truth-telling on reconciliation (Gibson 2003).

The problem is complicated because reconciliation is often used simultaneously as a synonym for peace, as an independent cause of peace, and as an indicator or measure of peace. Interestingly, very few studies (although Andrew Rigby's 2001:183-192 is an exception) view reconciliation as a consequence of peace, al- though such a view is just as plausible as the opposite claims. Indeed, a similar argument can be made of the truth-telling literature as a whole. It is just as likely that peace (the absence of violent conflict and war and the low probability of the resumption of war) allows truth-telling to take place rather than the reverse.

Say we define peace as the absence of large-scale violent conflict and the low probability of the resumption of civil war, and we define reconciliation broadly, even then empirical evidence for a clear relationship is hardly conclusive.6 Few of the cases regularly examined in the postconflict justice and peacebuilding litera- tures-South Africa, El Salvador, Guatemala, Rwanda, the former Yugoslavia- offer clear examples of "harmony and cooperation" among former adversaries. For example, few observers of South Africa (see Wilson 2001), which has received the lion's share of academic attention, would claim that anything approximating reconciliation has taken place since the completion of the TRC. Yet, in none of these cases does there appear to be any danger of a resumption of civil war. Al- though some form of reconciliation may be important after certain kinds of internal conflicts--namely, those that have ended through negotiated settlement in which adversaries must live together, side-by-side (see comments by Henry Steiner in the Harvard Law School Human Rights Program 1997)-in the absence of a systematic comparative study of reconciliation and peace, this remains merely a hypothesis to be tested rather than an established fact. If it is true that reconciliation is necessary under these conditions, we are likely talking about a very small percentage of internal conflicts in the world given that most civil wars end through the outright victory of one side over the other, rather than through negotiated settlement (Walter 1997:335). In the remaining majority of cases, it would seem that no cor- relation exists between national reconciliation and the likelihood of the resumption of war. In nearly all these cases national reconciliation was rarely pursued. If the data confirm this observation, it would greatly limit the prescriptive claims of truth- telling advocates.

Even if we were able to establish a compelling link between reconciliation and peace, does it necessarily follow that reconciliation requires truth-telling (Assump- tion 4)? This is a core assumption of truth-telling claims. Determining the assump- tion's validity requires a clear definition of "reconciliation." But whether we accept a limited definition ("nonlethal coexistence") or a more expansive one ("intergroup harmony and cooperation"), the empirical record is inconclusive. Coexistence oc- curs in many postconflict states in which truth-telling has not taken place as well as in those in which it has. As noted above, cases of truth-telling in Central America and South Africa have not necessarily resulted in "intergroup harmony and cooperation." Given this reality, truth-telling advocates (see, for example, Kaye 1997; Kemali 2001) will often hedge and qualify their claims. They will say that truth-telling promotes reconciliation or has "put the country on the road" to

6At least one study of reconciliation and interstate war (Brecke and Long 1999) has found no clear relationship at all.

7A dissenting and methodologically sensitive view can be found in Gibson (2003).

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 14: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 367

reconciliation. Yet, it is unclear how such a proposition can be measured. It is problematic enough to operationalize reconciliation, let alone progress toward it.

Furthermore, there is no inherently logical reason why collective forgetting of painful, divisive episodes from the past might not be more conducive to harmony and cooperation than truth-telling. Truth-telling advocates generally reject official or unofficial "amnesia," saying that "it is not possible to forget the past and start completely fresh as if nothing had happened. ... The past must be addressed in order to reach the future" (Bloomfield 2003a: 15). In short, "amnesia is the enemy of reconciliation" (Huyse 2003:30). But the exact opposite lesson was learned most notably from post-Franco Spain and Mozambique, among others. Even though some scholars (for example, Freeman and Hayner 2003:122-123) may argue that the ultimate consequence of such forgetting is yet to be known, little evidence suggests that intergroup harmony and cooperation is necessarily required to pre- vent the resumption of civil war. So even if truth-telling were necessary for rec- onciliation, it is not clear that truth-telling is necessary for peace. In short, we are left with another untested hypothesis.

Similar problems affect another of the central psychological assumptions of the postconflict justice and transitional justice literatures: "There can be no peace without justice" (Assumption 5). There are several problems with this assumption. First, as with reconciliation, individual conceptions of "justice" differ from person to person, place to place, and time to time. No one definition is universally ac- cepted. In Rwanda, for example, international human rights organizations have condemned Rwandan authorities for abandoning the Western judicial approach to the punishment of war crimes in favor of an indigenous system of community tribunals, even though the latter process is widely supported by the population. In South Africa, many blacks considered the amnesty provision of the TRC, in which the accused exchanged criminal prosecution for public confession of their crimes, to be sufficient justice. Others who favored a more retributive approach con- demned the process as unjust. Without a clear, consistent definition, it is impossible to measure and reach general conclusions about the effect of justice on peace.

This dilemma is evident from existing empirical studies. The literature tends to focus on a handful of recent cases in which postconflict justice has been pursued in various ways: El Salvador, Guatemala, Rwanda, South Africa, and the former Yu- goslavia, for example. However, little agreement exists as to whether justice has or has not been realized in these cases. Hence, determining its effects on peace is problematic. Further, in each of these cases the dependent variable (peace) does not vary. Justice is pursued in various forms and with varying degrees of success, yet peace exists in all of the cases: war has not resumed and the probability of war resuming is relatively low. Peace may be more tenuous in some cases than in others (Paris 1997, 2001), but no obvious connection seems to exist between the nature or degree ofjustice and the relative strength of the peace. Guatemala, El Salvador, and South Africa pursued truth commissions with amnesties; Rwanda and Yugoslavia pursued trials without amnesties. Even though, in almost all these cases, some groups have claimed that they have been denied justice, the likelihood that war will resume remains very low in all of them.

Some advocates, however, claim that it is not necessarily achieving justice that is critical to peace, but pursuing justice (through formal truth-telling mechanisms). Hayner (1994:607) refers to this as "acknowledging the truth, rather than finding the truth." Even that formulation remains problematic. If, in fact, a justice process is necessary for peace, then how do we explain the numerous cases in which peace has been consolidated but no justice of any kind was pursued? Post-Franco Spain (but see Rigby 2001), post-Ta'if Lebanon, Namibia, Mozambique, Cambodia (but on these latter two, see Hayner 2001) serve as a few notable examples of peace being achieved without the pursuit of justice. History is replete with others; indeed the vast majority of post-civil war cases likely fit this description.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 15: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

368 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

Part of the logic of Assumption 5 is that justice through truth-telling dampens the retributive urges of victims. Justice pursued through truth-telling mechanisms re- moves any need to pursue vigilante justice. It removes incentives for revenge, thereby breaking the cycle of violence and preventing the resumption of war. The empirical support for this claim, however, is inconclusive. Jonathan Tepperman (2002:142), for example, suggests that "the fact that there have been no revenge killings in [South Africa] since the TRC started its work almost certainly says some- thing about what kind of impact the commission has had." Perhaps it says some- thing, but what that is remains unclear. Other factors almost certainly account for this outcome. Indeed, such claims are almost never accompanied by a counter- factual analysis-what would likely have happened in the absence of a TRC in South Africa?-or systematic testing of competing hypotheses. Even though Free- man and Hayner (2003:138) acknowledge some successes of the truth commis- sions-including the issuing of reparations in Chile, judicial reforms in El Salvador, and the discrediting of apartheid in South Africa-the real question is whether these outcomes would have reasonably occurred in the absence of a truth com- mission. Without clear evidence establishing a link between truth-telling and re- venge killings, this is merely a plausible hypothesis based on a simple correlation.

Moreover, this positive correlation does not seem to hold true in other cases in which we would most expect to see it. Despite an active and well-functioning re- tributive justice system in the form of the ICTY, Kosovar Albanians carried out revenge killings against Serbs in the aftermath of the NATO intervention in 1999 (Human Rights Watch 1999a; International Crisis Group 1999; Daalder and O'Hanlon 2000:177, 196). Similarly, despite the establishment of the ICTR in late- 1994, the Tutsi-dominated Rwandan army continued to carry out violent reprisals against Hutus (Amnesty International 1996a, 1996b). Although these are just two examples, they are important cases often cited by proponents (see, for instance, Akhavan 2001:23) as success stories of international criminal law and truth-telling. Given these problems, then, the question remains open as to the relative impor- tance of justice in the peacebuilding process.

Another important truth-telling claim is closely related: justice through truth- telling dampens retributive urges for communal violence by focusing on individual rather than collective guilt. As Kritz (1999:169) argues, justice through truth-telling "rejects the dangerous culture of collective guilt and retribution that often pro- duces further cycles of resentment and violence." But this argument assumes not only that individual guilt is the logical outcome of truth-telling exercises (Assumption 6), but also that collective guilt is always dangerous and undesirable (Assumption 7). Neither is necessarily true. Though the ICTY has for more than a decade inves- tigated and prosecuted war crimes in the former Yugoslavia, simply no evidence indicates that individual Bosnians, Croats, or Serbs blame individuals for crimes committed against them rather than "Bosnian Muslims," "Croats," or "Serbs." Nor is this the case in Rwanda. Indeed, the most often cited case in this regard-Nu- remberg-provides the opposite lesson. Most of the world and the Germans themselves still hold "Germans" collectively guilty for the crimes of World War II, not individual Nazis (Buruma 1994; Ignatieff 1996:117). Far from being danger- ous, it has led the German people to confront their own culpability and to make amends to victims. It is far easier for societies to shirk their collective responsibilities if they have individual scapegoats.

One other logical problem limits these claims about retribution. Cases such as Kosovo and Rwanda reveal that revenge attacks are most common and most dangerous (that is, they most threaten the integrity of a negotiated settlement) in the immediate aftermath of war (see, for example, Amnesty International 1994; Human Rights Watch 1995, 1999b). Hence it is in the short term that efforts to mitigate violent reprisals are most needed. However, it is precisely during this time that truth-telling is least likely to take place. Formal truth-telling

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 16: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 369

institutions take a good deal of time to establish. Once they are up and running, however, the threat of revenge killings is actually less acute, given that the thirst for revenge generally dies down over time.8 Justice through truth-telling, as a result, is limited in addressing revenge killings. Can justice ever dampen vigilantism? Per- haps under some circumstances, for example, when group hatred and animosity have not dissipated over time. But in the absence of compelling empirical support, the claim's general validity remains suspect.

None of this is to say that some victims of war crimes do not feel a real need for justice and that punishing war criminals would not make some feel better. The pursuit of justice is a worthy endeavor, and it should be attempted whenever pos- sible. But it remains to be fully demonstrated that successful peacebuilding requires it. Indeed, a rigorous, systematic study by Jack Snyder and Leslie Vinjamuri (2003/ 04) found little support for this claim.

The final psychological assumption is a core assumption about the causes of war upon which truth-telling claims rest. If truth-telling promotes peace, then forget- ting, suppressing, or distorting the past promotes war (Assumption 8). Is this true? A growing body of theoretical work on ethnic and nationalist conflict lends some support to this claim. The works most notably of Stephen Van Evera (1994), Mi- chael Brown (1996, 2001), Stuart Kaufman (2001), and Daniel Byman (2002) make a convincing case that in certain situations chauvinist, hegemonic nationalist ide- ologies, which are often based on historical distortions and denials of past crimes, can be used by political entrepreneurs to incite violence. However, our theorizing about the dangers of historical mythmaking is still evolving. We have yet fully to understand the mechanisms and conditions under which mythmaking leads to violence, and the evidence remains scattered and limited to only a few prominent cases. For example, Van Evera (1994) focuses primarily on Wilhelmine Germany and Imperial Japan, Kaufman (2001) on the former Yugoslavia and post-Soviet Caucasus, and the author (Mendeloff 2001) on Russia and the Baltic States. Fur- thermore, although these works in part counsel truth-telling, they call primarily for historical revision and educational reform, not the formal truth-telling mechanisms that are the focus of the peacebuilding literature. Thus, even though myth- making may indeed be a potential cause of renewed violence in postconflict societies, formal truth-telling may not necessarily be the only or the best way to address the problem.

Finally, even proponents of the mythmaking hypothesis do not claim that it has universal explanatory or predictive power. The hypothesis still remains one of a number of potential causes of internal conflicts (Byman and Van Evera 1998; Brown 2001). Thus, truth-telling remedies are not always relevant or necessary. Many postconflict states have carried out conscious policies of forgetting or sup- pressing the past and have not risked relapse into civil war: post-civil war Russia, post-civil war China, and others mentioned above (Spain, Lebanon, Namibia, Mozambique, and Cambodia).

Identity Assumptions. Many truth-telling claims also rest on the validity of factual and theoretical assumptions about the nature of national and cultural identity. These arguments are essentially about the manipulation of historical beliefs and national and cultural identity. Table 2 identifies four assumptions in particular as

8In fact, even claims by advocates of the International Criminal Court (ICC) that it will speed up the process of

punishment seem overstated and hardly undermine the larger argument. Prosecution under the ICC does not occur quickly. It is a court of last resort, and thus must wait until domestic courts have taken action and proved wanting, or failed to take action at all, before stepping in. Further, there is no reason to believe that the trial process will occur any more quickly than it currently does under ad hoc tribunals. Therefore, the ICC may speed up the

process, but only relatively, and certainly will not act quickly enough to offset the short-term problem of revenge killings.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 17: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

370 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

central to the logic of truth-telling claims; these are numbered 9 through 12 in the table.

Because many truth-telling arguments are essentially about reconciliation, they assume that divided war-torn societies are better off staying together rather than separating (Assumption 9). Sarkin (1999:821), for example, concludes that Rwanda's "history shows that ethnic violence will continue unless serious steps are taken to unite the nation." Is unity in fact preferable to separation? Little empirical or theoretical agreement exists on this point. In some cases working to foster recon- ciliation is a wise policy (assuming that reconciliation is in fact peace-promoting). But this hardly means that efforts to keep divided societies together in all circum- stances are always preferable. Indeed, as Herbert and Kanya Adam (2001:47) have observed, "where ethno-nationalist groups do not support common nationbuilding (the Balkans, Israel, Palestine) and where mutual atrocities engender divided memories, separation in independent or semi-autonomous polities would seem the only feasible solution." The benefits of reconciliation or separation, either through partition or federal autonomy, depend on the roots of the conflict, the nature of the war, particular war aims, and the geographic concentration of groups. A strong case can be made for separation after conflicts in which atrocities were carried out along largely racial, ethnic, religious, or cultural lines. Chaim Kaufmann (1996, 1999) has argued persuasively that the chances of violence resuming after such conflicts is much greater if those societies are kept together, or separated incompletely, than if they are effectively partitioned. Ultimately, though, little consensus has formed around any one set of best strategies for ethnic conflict management. Partition, power-sharing, and federalism all have their proponents and detractors. For an excellent analysis of the various possible strategies, see Byman (2002); on partition, see Kaufmann (1996, 1999), Byman (1997), Kumar (1997), Sambanis (2000), and Downes (2001); on power-sharing, see Horowitz (1990), Lijphart (1990), McCrae (1990), and Sisk (1996); and on federalism, see Lapidoth (1996) and Burmeo (2002). If conflict prevention is the goal, then we must consider the full range of options and not assume that keeping divided societies together is the best approach.

Even if unification were preferable to separation, unity is not always feasible. Many truth-telling arguments assume that creating new, shared identities is ben- eficial for long-term peace (Assumption 10) and that doing so is relatively easy-or easier than alternatives such as partition (Assumption 11). Yet, it is extremely hard to manipulate existing identities in the aftermath of massive violence and brutality, let alone create entirely new ones. Identity changes of this sort generally occur through the assimilation of minority groups who adopt the identity of the majority rather than through the creation of a new shared identity. Assimilating groups into a new national identity is not impossible, but the conditions for it to succeed are rare (Byman 2000, 2002:100-124). It requires at a minimum a single strong group willing to forge that new identity and to use coercion and bribery to bring others along. Destroying existing identities and building new ones is almost always a process imposed rather than negotiated. Thus, it is more likely to succeed in cases in which civil war ended with decisive victory and in which the balance of power has shifted decisively in favor of one side. While most civil wars end in this way, and these are also the cases in which the fighting is least likely to resume (Wagner 1993:257-263). The danger of states relapsing into civil war is most common fol- lowing negotiated settlements, which are often the result of a stalemated conflict in which the balance of power is fairly equal. Yet, in these conditions identity manip- ulation is likely to flounder. Most important, forging new identities almost always fails when groups share a history of substantial intercommunal violence (Byman 2002:220-221). Paradoxically, it is precisely in these conflicts in which truth-telling is believed to be most needed. Thus, in those cases in which identity manipulation may be most desired (in the aftermath of negotiated settlements), it is actually

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 18: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 371

hardest to achieve. And in those cases in which it is most difficult to achieve (after intercommunal violence), truth-telling may be most needed.

Moreover, manipulating identities may also be a dangerous undertaking. It can generate enormous popular resentment and further harden and radicalize com- munal identities. Most important, manipulating identities can threaten ethnic elites who are much more willing to fight than to give up power (Byman 2000). Thus, even if it eventually results in peace, the risks of violence over the generations that it takes to implement the change in identities can be great. Finally, because the proc- ess of identity manipulation takes decades, it provides few benefits in the short term (Byman 2000, 2002). Yet, it is precisely the peace that is consolidated in the im- mediate aftermath of war that is the best predictor of overall long-term success (Stedman 2002).

Even if new shared identities could be easily forged, is a common, shared identity necessarily peace-promoting (Assumption 10)? Many groups who have distinct iden- tities coexist, cooperate, work, and live together all over the world. No logical reason exists that peace requires a shared identity. More important is probably the nature of any mutual identities (are they civic or ethnic identities; hegemonic or tolerant?) and the content of the historical myths and ideas that groups purvey (are they chauvinist and other-denigrating; do they lie about and distort their own past crimes; do they exaggerate their own persecution and glorify their own victimi- zation?) (Van Evera 1994; Byman and Van Evera 1998). These are likely to be more powerful than the shared nature of the identities.

Indeed, a new shared identity may or may not be a better or more benign identity. It is assumed that truth-telling will somehow destroy old, chauvinist, cul- turally hegemonic, exclusionist identities and inexorably lead to a new civic national identity that values diversity, inclusiveness, and democracy. But civic nationalism is, in fact, relatively rare in the world today and rarely flourishes in the aftermath of violent intercommunal conflict (Snyder 2000).

If it could be established that divided societies are better off remaining integrated and that shared identities are, in reality, feasible and beneficial, should we believe that "truth" is the best glue to hold those societies together? This assumption (Assumption 12) underlies truth-telling claims. Yet, no inherently logical reason ex- ists to believe that truth should be more powerful than lies or a new set of myths based on the intentional distortion of the past. Indeed, mythmaking based on historical distortion and omission is the most common basis for national identity. In divided societies emerging from violent conflict, the truth can be a source of danger. Often legitimate truths can become fodder for dangerous hypernationalism, espe- cially for the victims of crimes. Some of the most dangerous forms of nationalist ideas are self-victimization myths (Van Evera 1994; Kiss 2000:72; Mendeloff 2001). Even if based on truth, they can be an excuse for cruelty, maltreatment, and vi- olence that can lead to war. As Charles Maier (1993:136) writes, "collective mem- ories tend to focus not on the long history of an ethnic people but on their most painful incidents of victimization." Armed with the knowledge of the genocide committed against them, is it really surprising that Tutsi have carried out bloody reprisals against Hutus in Rwanda? Are we to believe that more truth, rather than less, will moderate Tutsi animosity? Some societies that have chosen amnesia rather than truth-seeking in the aftermath of violent conflict have avoided the kind of bloodletting that has wracked Rwanda.

This is not to say, however, that truth cannot serve as the basis of national identity. Current German national identity is, in fact, based on a good deal of unadulterated, nonwhitewashed, non-self-glorifying historical truth. But Germany seems to be an exception. Nor is this to say that amnesia is always bad. German rightists and some of the victims of the Allied firebombing of German cities during World War II may consider it shameful that German society has essentially ignored their suffering and the millions of innocent German civilians who died. But most of us would have little

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 19: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

372 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

problem with the fact that German history has focused on their own crimes rather than the conduct of the allies during the war. As residents of the allies who par- ticipated in these events, we do not view this bit of amnesia as a bad thing.

What is important is not so much truth versus lies, but the purpose to which those ideas are put. Lies, distortions, or amnesia in the service of tolerant, non-self- glorifying, nonvictimizing national identities are preferable to truths that can fuel victimization myths, scapegoating, and intolerance. The truth-telling literature needs to focus more on the nature of the ideas that are involved in the truth-telling and the context of the truth-telling rather than the truth-telling itself.

Ultimately, though, identity manipulation is hard because, to have a major im- pact, it has to affect most if not all of collective society. The international IDEA handbook, for example, acknowledges that the process of reconciliation (a vital component of which is "a process of acknowledging, remembering, and learning from the past") is "a society-wide, long-term process of deep change" (Bloomfield 2003a: 14). But not only is identity change through truth-telling a Sisyphusian task, such identity change may also be unnecessary. It remains an open question whether preventing the resumption of violent conflict in war-torn societies requires such society-wide solutions. Do all members of society need to change their beliefs or just a small number of those members? After all, decisions for war and peace are ul- timately made by small groups of individuals. Thus, some may argue that it is only the actions of those few responsible individuals who need to be restrained or moderated. The goal of many truth-tellers, however, is to change the collective beliefs of all society. Such activity may be misguided.9

Institutional and Normative Assumptions. The final set of assumptions that un- derlie truth-telling claims found in Table 2 are those related to the creation and manipulation of new social and political institutions and norms. These five as- sumptions focus on the relationship between truth-telling and democracy, the his- torical record, and respect for human rights and the rule of law.

Those advocating truth-telling claims are on solid ground in assuming the do- mestic peacefulness of democracies (Assumption 13). Democracies are, in fact, much less likely to suffer civil wars than nondemocracies (Gleditsch 1999; Hegre et al. 2001). The reasons offered are numerous, but they generally have to do with norms and institutions that promote nonviolent conflict resolution. The problem here, however, is not with the validity of the assumption but rather with the re- lationship between truth-telling and democratization.

First, the ultimate goal of peacebuilding is war prevention, not democracy. Yet, many truth-telling advocates conflate the two or focus exclusively, either implicitly or explicitly, on promoting democracy. The vast majority of the undemocratic world, however, is at peace. Even though democracy is a laudable goal and may prevent the resumption of civil war in postconflict societies, it is not the exclusive guarantor of peace. It is quite possible to achieve peace in war-torn societies without democracy.

Second, although democracy may be preferable as a peacebuilding strategy, it is not necessarily the easiest or safest path to peace. Those advocating truth-telling claims tend to overlook this possibility. Indeed, important caveats must be noted in relation to the "civil-democratic peace thesis" that the truth-seeking literature elides. Truth-telling claims refer to "democracy" and "democratic institutions" in a loose, undifferentiated way, without noting the qualitative differences between de- mocracies with regard to civil peace. Democratic institutions are no guarantee of peace and stability. Even though the relationship between levels of democracy and interstate peace is fairly robust (that is, even very weak democracies are less likely to

'The author thanks Benjamin Valentino for discussions on this point.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 20: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 373

go to war with other democracies), this is not true with regard to civil war. Strong liberal democracies do not suffer civil wars; weak illiberal proto-democracies, and nondemocracies do (Henderson and Singer 2000; Hegre et al. 2001). It is relatively easy to establish a weak democracy but a lot harder to develop a robust liberal democracy that will last. Indeed, democratization is fraught with dangers for war- torn states. States that jump into the democratization process, particularly by hold- ing elections as early as possible, are much more likely to relapse into civil war (Snyder 2000; Lyons 2002).

Third, even if we assume that democracy is the best, easiest, and safest peace- building strategy, is truth-seeking helpful in bringing it about? Many truth-telling claims include the assumption that truth-seeking promotes democracy (Assumption 14). The International IDEA, for example, argues that creating "a culture of de- mocracy" and "peaceful coexistence" in war-torn societies requires truth-telling (Huyse 2003:24). Yet, the empirical support for this assumption is mixed. Given that democracy has emerged in countries where truth-telling was deliberately avoided raises the question of the relative importance of truth-telling for devel- oping democratic institutions. Indeed, it is far more plausible that the causal arrows linking truth-telling to democracy actually run in the opposite direction: truth- telling may be far more likely a consequence of democratic development, than a result of it.

Moreover, promoting truth in certain democratizing states can actually be quite dangerous. If democratic institutions are weak and developing, especially in war- torn ethnically divided societies, political entrepreneurs have great incentives to use nascent democratic institutions--free assembly, free press, electoral competi- tion-to foster extremism and ethnic hatred in a bid for power (Snyder 2000; Kaufman 2001). Truth-seekers claim that public truth-telling mechanisms can counter those ethnic appeals. But truth is just as likely to inflame passions, instill resentment, and provide grievances to be exploited as it is to moderate those appeals (Petersen 2002).

Still, it is argued, truth-telling strengthens democratic institutions by shaming and discrediting undemocratic leaders. Akhavan (2001), for example, argues that truth-telling through the ICTY led directly to the discrediting and ostracizing of extremist political elites: Milosevic in Serbia, Karadicz and Mladic in Bosnia. Tepperman (2002:141) declares that thanks to the TRC, "De Klerk's political career has been ruined and he will never return to office." But in the absence of systematic examination of competing explanations and counterfactual analysis, such claims are dubious. Milosevic's fall from power might perhaps be more readily explained by factors that had little to do with his indictment. Most Serbs, for example, reject- ed-and still reject-the authority of the ICTY, seeing it as anti-Serb and a po- litically motivated, victor's justice (even Akhavan 2001:16 acknowledges this fact). Indeed, the leader of the Serb opposition movement against Milosevic, Vojislav Kostunica, fiercely opposed extraditing Milosevic to the Hague. Serbs, it has been argued, turned on Milosevic because of his corruption and the failed prosecution of four bloody and costly wars that bankrupted the country and decimated the male population. In other words, he was discredited and ostracized not for his war crimes, but for losing Serbia's wars.10 In Bosnia, extremist political entrepreneurs may have become marginalized not because of indictments against them or other extremists, but because the United Nations (UN) authority that effectively runs Bosnia today explicitly bans extremist parties and politicians--a practice that many Western democracy activists have condemned as fundamentally undemocratic

10Observers (see Erlanger 2003:4) have also noted that it was possibly Western financial pressure on the Serb government to extradite accused war criminals (the same pressure that led to Milosevic's extradition to The Hague) that precipitated the assassination of the Serb president in 2003-a move that many saw as a grave blow to nascent Serbian democracy.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 21: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

374 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

(Chandler 1999). In South Africa, De Klerk's political career seems to have ended with the fall of apartheid. The TRC, it could be argued, had little if anything to do with forcing his retirement from public life. In short, the moderating and democ- racy-promoting influence of truth-telling remains an untested hypothesis.

Fourth, in divided societies emerging from violent conflict, the truth may actually be divisive and an impediment to cooperation. Truth-tellers claim that exposing and discussing the past actually helps foster power-sharing arrangements. Truth- telling "closes the book" on a painful past and allows governing elites to focus on the task of governing, not bickering over history. But this result, of course, rests on the questionable validity of both the psychological and identity assumptions about the benefits of truth-telling and the willingness of groups with hardened identities to merely put such episodes behind them. In fact, some groups may actually sup- port truth-telling because it serves to cast blame and collective guilt on other groups. Evidence suggests (see Akhavan 2001:22), for example, that Croatians support the ICTY because it is believed to demonstrate that the Serbs committed more crimes against the Croatians than the Croatians did against the Serbs. Thus, it plays directly into the hands of ethnic divisions and hatred.

The assumption that truth-telling closes the book on a painful past also rests on the validity of one other critical assumption: that truth-telling actually settles the past and produces a consensus view of history (Assumption 15). Advocates of truth- telling through criminal prosecutions claim that trials produce an authoritative record of the past even though many (Minow 1998:23-51) have raised obvious doubts about the completeness and impartiality of the trial record. Advocates of truth-telling by investigative commissions claim that final reports offer a much more complete and accurate record. But this too is debatable. As Minow (1998:52- 90) has noted, truth commissions in particular, probably more than trials, are likely to yield historically inaccurate results because rules of evidence are nonexistent and testimony is provided without cross-examination. Furthermore, clinical studies have shown that testimony from traumatized victims may not be entirely accurate (Minow 1998:60, 128-129). The TRC has been criticized for leaving out many relevant crimes that did not rise to the level of crimes against humanity, including other forms of economic and social injustice, and for failing to produce a definitive historical document of the nature of apartheid (see Kiss 2000:89; Villa-Vicencio and Verwoerd 2000:279-294, especially 288-289; comments by Mahmood Mamdani quoted in Rigby 2001:141; Tepperman 2002:141). In short, both trial transcripts and truth commission reports have strengths and weaknesses, but nei- ther offers a complete, and fully accurate, historical record. That requires many years of interpretation, synthesis, and debate by professional historians.

Even if truth-telling does not produce a complete, objective historical record of the past, it may still benefit democratic development in other ways. Truth-telling claims include the assumption, for example, that truth-seeking helps develop de- mocracy by establishing respect for human rights and the rule of law (Assumption 16). The supporting logic and evidence, however, is ambiguous. There seems to be little clear relationship between truth-seeking and the human rights records of postconflict states (Putnam 2002). In the most commonly cited states that have carried out truth-telling in some form, human rights remain tenuous. South Africa, Guatemala, El Salvador, Nicaragua, and Rwanda are all plagued by continuing human rights abuses of varying degrees." In cases in which human rights records have improved, such as the former Yugoslavia, other factors, such as a robust

"See recent Amnesty International Annual Reports (www.amnesty.org) and US State Department Country Reports on Human Rights Practices (http://www.state.gov/g/drl/rls/hrrpt). Interestingly, one of the main advocates of

truth-telling (Sarkin 1998) has written a detailed study of the development of a "human rights culture" in South Africa without any mention of the TRC as a factor in that development. Of course, this oversight may be because the author found that a human rights culture had barely begun to develop.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 22: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 375

international monitoring by civil police forces, might more readily account for this result. In the absence of systematic study of the relationship between human rights and truth-telling, this assumption remains open to question.

Of course, even a weak human rights record does not necessarily mean that civil war is likely to resume in postconflict societies. Nonetheless, much of the truth- telling literature assumes that respect for human rights helps promote peace (As- sumption 17). To the extent that human rights violations are a manifestation of systemic discrimination and repression of minority groups in multiethnic societies, this assumption has some validity. Discriminatory or repressive state policies may be a source of grievance that can, under certain conditions, spark violent group re- bellion. Therefore, if truth-telling can preempt or deter the violation of human rights abuses in postwar societies-a hypothesis yet to be fully explicated-then it may actually help generate peace. Still, the link between human rights and peace is hardly self-evident. Respect for human rights and the rule of law may be as much a consequence of peace as a cause of it.

Is There Value In Truth-Telling? Defenders of truth-telling might argue that this gloomy assessment is both unfair and premature. Formal truth-telling has been carried out for only a relatively short time and in many cases truth-telling mechanisms have been imperfect. Truth com- missions have been plagued by problems (Hayner 1994, 2001); truth-telling through trials has really begun to gain legitimacy only in the past decade and more recently with the creation of the ICC. In short, they might argue that it is too soon to judge the effectiveness of truth-seeking. However, truth-telling advocates rarely accept these limitations themselves when pronouncing its utility. If it is too soon to pass judgment on truth-telling, why is it almost universally endorsed as an effective and important peacebuilding tool? Further, although it is problematic to pass judgment on truth-seeking given that the mechanisms remain imperfect, what is the guarantee that truth-telling mechanisms will be more perfect in the future? Perhaps the spotty record of truth-seeking is not a passing phase at all; imperfect truth-telling mechanisms may be the best that we can get. In an imperfect world with imperfect institutions, we will often have imperfect solutions.

Nonetheless, even perfectly functioning truth-telling mechanisms still rest on a number of factual and theoretical assumptions that are either dubious or highly contested. Thus, although we cannot systematically test the impact of truth-telling now, we can certainly test the validity of the assumptions on which its claims are based. This essay has raised more questions than answers in that regard. It has not offered systematic tests of the assumptions but, in the interest of clarifying the debate, has highlighted the core claims and the assumptions behind them: a nec- essary first step toward more systematic study of the phenomenon. Truth-telling in postconflict societies may have some peace-promoting effects, but more systematic research needs to be done before determining its utility. At a minimum, we must remain skeptical of truth-telling until its claims are on much firmer ground. We have a large number of hypotheses, but not many systematic tests.

Given the questions raised here, is there any value in promoting truth-seeking in postconflict societies? To answer that query we must distinguish when truth-telling is needed and when it is likely to work. Based on our knowledge of the causes of war and peace, truth-telling may help shape perceptions of group security over the long term in certain types of war-torn societies, namely those that are deeply di- vided along cultural lines. In deeply divided war-torn societies in which groups are forced to live together, truth-telling may help dampen security fears that could spark conflict in the event of state weakness. It is in conditions of state weakness that political entrepreneurs are most likely to appeal to group security or status concerns through ethnic scapegoating and hate-mongering. A sustained policy of

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 23: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

376 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

truth-seeking could make it harder for such political entrepreneurs to use historical lies and distortions as a basis for these political appeals.

But the utility of truth-telling in these circumstances may still be limited. At least seven such limitations seem evident. First, it is likely to be most relevant to conflicts that are characterized by security dilemmas or elite manipulation. In conflicts marked by predatory motivations or hegemonic ambition, truth-telling is likely to have little impact. Second, formal truth-telling alone is unlikely to be sufficient. It is probably more likely to be effective if sustained and institutionalized, such as through public education (a point acknowledged by the International IDEA, see Freeman and Hayner 2003). Even though public spectacles may have some role to play, little evidence supports the conclusion that truth-telling in the form of trials or truth commissions is likely to create the kind of changes in ideas and beliefs that could prevent future conflict. Third, truth-telling is likely to take a very long time to affect change. There is no guarantee that it will have much effect before historical ideas and beliefs are transformed, which is likely to take generations. Fourth, truth- seeking will probably be most effective when states are relatively stable. In other words, when peace is already present, truth-telling is most likely to change attitudes and beliefs. Fifth, truth-seeking is also likely to be most effective if states have a minimum level of democracy to sustain public debate. "Democracy," argues Ignatieff (1996:119), "is a pre-condition for that free access to historical data and free debate about its meaning on which the creation of public truth depends." If institutions are too undemocratic, they cannot allow "countervailing truth to cir- culate." Jack Snyder (2000) and Jack Snyder and Karen Ballentine (1996) have suggested just such a danger. Sixth, truth-telling is likely to be most effective when groups want to discuss the past. It cannot be forced. And, seventh, truth-telling probably needs to be accompanied by an apology or some form of restitution (Barkan 2000; Freeman and Hayner 2003; Lind 2003), though even that is no guarantee of effectiveness (Hamber and Wilson 2002).

In short, truth-telling may have value, but it is likely limited. Ultimately, though, the answer to the questions raised here will have to wait until more research is done. The first place to start is with designing studies that can systematically test the truth-telling claims and their assumptions outlined here. Future research needs to focus more directly on the core peacebuilding dilemma-how to prevent the re- sumption of war in postconflict societies. What is needed is greater clarity in think- ing about how truth-telling prevents the recurrence of civil war, how important it is relative to other factors and peacebuilding strategies, and the conditions under which it is likely to prove helpful, harmful, or irrelevant. Thus far, none of these questions has been satisfactorily answered.

References

ADAM, HERBERT, AND KANYA ADAM. (2001) The Politics of Memory in Divided Societies. In After the TRC: Reflections on Truth and Reconciliation in South Africa, edited by Wilmot James and Linda Van de Vijver. Athens: Ohio University Press.

AKHAVAN, PAYAM. (1998) Justice in The Hague, Peace in the Former Yugoslavia? A Commentary on the United Nations War Crimes Tribunal. Human Rights Quarterly 20:737-816.

AKHAVAN, PAYAM. (2001) Beyond Impunity: Can International Criminal Justice Prevent Atrocities? American Journal of International Law 95(1):7-3 1.

ALLAN, ALFRED, AND MARIETJIE M. ALLAN. (2000) The South African Truth and Reconciliation Com- mission as a Therapeutic Tool. Behavioral Sciences and the Law 18:459-477.

AMNESTY INTERNATIONAL. (1994) Rwanda: Reports of Killings and Abductions by the Rwandese Patriotic Army, April-August 1994. Available at http://web.amnesty.org/library/index/engafr470161994.

AMNESTY INTERNATIONAL. (1996a) Rwanda: Alarming Resurgence of Killings. Available at http://web. amnesty.org/library/index/engafr470131996.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 24: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 377

AMNESTY INTERNATIONAL. (1996b) Rwanda: Two Years After the Genocide-Human Rights in the Balance: An Open Letter to President Pasteur Bizimungu. Available at http://web.amnesty.org/library/index/ engafr470021996.

BARKAN, ELAZAR. (2000) The Guilt of Nations: Restitution and Negotiating Historical Injustices. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

BASSIOUNI, M. CHERIF. (1996) Searching for Peace and Achieving Justice: The Need for Account-

ability. Law and Contemporary Problems 59(4):9-28. BLOOMFIELD, DAVID. (2003a) Reconciliation: An Introduction. In Reconciliation After Violent Conflict:

A Handbook, edited by David Bloomfield, Teresa Barnes, and Luc Huyse. Stockholm: Interna- tional Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (IDEA).

BLOOMFIELD, DAVID. (2003b) The Context of Reconciliation. In Reconciliation After Violent Conflict: A Handbook, edited by David Bloomfield, Teresa Barnes, and Luc Huyse. Stockholm: Interna- tional Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (IDEA).

BORER, TRISTAN ANNE. (2001) Reconciliation in South Africa: Defining Success. Kroc Institute Occasional

Paper 20:OP:1. BRECKE, PETER, AND WILLIAM J. LONG. (1999) War and Reconciliation. International Interactions

25(2):95-117. BROWN, MICHAEL E. (1996) Introduction and Causes and Regional Dimensions of Internal Conflict.

In The International Dimensions of Internal Conflict, edited by Michael E. Brown. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

BROWN, MICHAEL E. (2001) Ethnic and Internal Conflicts: Causes and Implications. In Turbulent Peace: The Challenges of Managing International Conflict, edited by Chester A. Crocker and Fen Osler Hampson with Pamela R. Aall. Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press.

BURMEO, NANCY. (2002) The Import of Institutions. Journal of Democracy 13(2):96-110. BURUMA, IAN. (1994) The Wages of Guilt: Memories of War in Germany and Japan. New York: Farrar

Straus Giroux. BYMAN, DANIEL L. (1997) Divided They Stand: Lessons about Partition from Iraq and Lebanon.

Security Studies 7(1): 1-29. BYMAN, DANIEL L. (2000) Forever Enemies? The Manipulation of Ethnic Identities to End Civil Wars.

Security Studies 9(3):149-190. BYMAN, DANIEL L. (2002) Keeping the Peace: Lasting Solutions to Ethnic Conflicts. Baltimore: Johns

Hopkins University Press. BYMAN, DANIEL L., AND STEPHEN VAN EVERA. (1998) Why They Fight: Hypotheses on the Origins of

Contemporary Deadly Conflicts. Security Studies 7(3):1-50. CHANDLER, DAVID. (1999) Bosnia: Faking Democracy After Dayton. London: Pluto Press. COBBAN, HELENA. (2002) The Legacies of Collective Violence: The Rwandan Genocide and the Limits

of Law. Boston Review 27(2). COMMISSION NATIONALE CONSULTATIVE DES DROITS DE L'HOMME AND THE INTERNATIONAL COMMIS-

SION OF JURISTS. (1993)Justice Not Impunity: International Meeting on Impunity of Perpetrators of Gross Human Rights Violations. Geneva: International Commission of Jurists.

COUSENS, ELIZABETH M. (2001) Introduction. In Peacebuilding as Politics: Cultivating Peace in Fragile Societies, edited by Elizabeth M. Cousens and Chetan Kumar with Karin Wermester. Boulder:

Lynne Rienner Publishers. CROCKER, DAVID. (2000) Truth Commissions, Transitional Justice, and Civil Society. In Truth v. Justice:

The Morality of Truth Commissions, edited by Robert I. Rotberg and Dennis Thompson. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

DAALDER, IVO H., AND MICHAEL E. O'HANLON. (2000) Winning Ugly: NATO's War to Save Kosovo.

Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press. DOWNES, ALEXANDER B. (2001) The Holy Land Divided: Defending Partition as a Solution to Ethnic

Wars. Security Studies 10(4):58-116. EIZENSTAT, STUART E. (2003) Reconciliation. Not Just Reconstruction. New York Times, July 4,

2003:A21. ERLANGER, STEVEN. (2003) Did Serbia's Leader Do the West's Bidding Too Well? New York Times,

March 16, 2003:sec. 4, p. 4. FLOURNOY, MICHELE, AND MICHAEL PAN. (2002) Dealing with Demons: Justice and Reconciliation.

The Washington Quarterly 25(4):111-123. FREEMAN, MARK, AND PRESCILLA B. HAYNER. (2003) Truth-Telling. In Reconciliation After Violent Con-

flict: A Handbook, edited by David Bloomfield, Teresa Barnes, and Luc Huyse. Stockholm: Inter- national Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (IDEA).

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 25: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

378 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

GALTUNG, JOHAN. (1969) Violence, Peace, and Peace Research.Journal of Peace Research 6(3): 167-191. GIBSON, JAMES L. (2003) Overcoming Apartheid: Can Truth Reconcile a Divided Nation? Unpublished book

manuscript. GLEDISCH, NILS PETTER. (1999) Democracy and Peace. In Encyclopedia of Violence, Peace, and Conflict,

edited by Lester Kurtz. San Diego: Academic Press. GOLDSTONE, RICHARD J. (1996) Justice as a Tool for Peacemaking: Truth Commissions and Inter-

national Criminal Tribunals. New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 28: 485-503.

GUTMAN, AMY, AND DENNIS THOMPSON. (2000) The Moral Foundations of Truth Commissions. In Truth v. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions, edited by Robert I. Rotberg and Dennis

Thompson. Princeton: Princeton University Press. HAMBER, BRANDON. (2001) Does the Truth Heal? A Psychological Perspective on Political Strategies

for Dealing with the Legacy of Political Violence. In Burying the Past: Making Peace and Doing Justice after Civil Conflict, edited by Nigel Biggar. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.

HAMBER, BRANDON, AND RICHARD A. WILSON. (2002) Symbolic Closure Through Memory, Reparation, and Revenge in Post Conflict Societies. Journal of Human Rights 1:35-530.

HAMPSON, FEN OSLER. (1997) Can Peacebuilding Work? Cornell International Law Journal 30: 701-716.

HAMRE, JOHN J., AND GORDON R. SULLIVAN. (2002) Toward Postconflict Reconstruction. The Wash-

ington Quarterly 25(4):85-96. HARVARD LAW SCHOOL HUMAN RIGHTS PROGRAM, ED. (1997) Truth Commissions: A Comparative Assess-

ment, Interdisciplinary Discussion Held at Harvard Law School in May 1996. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Law School Human Rights Program. Available at http://www.law.harvard.edu/programs/HRP/ Publications/truth 1 .html.

HAYNER, PRESCILLA B. (1994) Fifteen Truth Commissions, 1974 to 1994: A Comparative Perspective. Human Rights Quarterly 16:597-655.

HAYNER, PRESCILLA B. (2001) Unspeakable Truths: Confronting State Terror and Atrocity. New York:

Routledge. HEGRE, HAVARD, TANJA ELLINGSEN, SCOTT GATES, AND NILS PETTER GLEDITSCH. (2001) Toward

a Democratic Civil Peace? Democracy, Political Change, and Civil War, 1816-1992. American Political Science Review 95:33-48.

HENDERSEN, ERROL A., AND J. DAVID SINGER. (2000) Civil War in the Post-Colonial World, 1946-92.

Journal of Peace Research 37:275-299. HERMAN, JUDITH LEWIS. (1994) Trauma and Recovery. New York: Basic Books. HOROWITZ, DONALD L. (1990) Making Moderation Pay: The Comparative Politics of Ethnic Conflict

Management. In Conflict and Peacemaking in Multiethnic Societies, edited by Joseph V. Monteville.

Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. HUMAN RIGHTS WATCH. (1995) World Report 1995. Available at http://www.hrw.org/reports/1995/

WR95. HUMAN RIGHTS WATCH. (1999a) Federal Republic of Yugoslavia: Abuses against Serbs and Roma in the New

Kosovo. Available at http://www.hrw.org/reports/1999/kosov2. HUMAN RIGHTS WATCH. (1999b) Leave None to Tell the Story: Genocide in Rwanda. Available at http://

www.hrw.org/reports/1 999/rwanda. HUYSE, LUC. (2003) The Process of Reconciliation. In Reconciliation after Violent Conflict: A Handbook,

edited by David Bloomfield, Teresa Barnes, and Luc Huyse. Stockholm: International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (IDEA).

IGNATIEFF, MICHAEL. (1996) Articles of Faith. Index on Censorship 5:110-122. INTERNATIONAL CENTER FOR TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE. (2003) Transitional Justice in Iraq: An ICTJ

Policy Paper. May. Available at http://www.ictj.org/downloads/Iraq%20Transitional%20Justice %20Policy%20Paper.pdf.

INTERNATIONAL CRISIS GROUP. (1999) Violence in Kosovo: Who's Killing Whom? ICG Balkans Report 78:Amended version. 2 November.

INTERNATIONAL INSTITUTE FOR DEMOCRACY AND ELECTORAL ASSISTANCE (IDEA). (2003) Reconciliation

after Violent Conflict: A Handbook, edited by David Bloomfield, Teresa Barnes, and Luc Huyse. Stockholm: International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance.

KAUFMAN, STUART J. (2001) Modern Hatreds: The Symbolic Politics of Ethnic Wars. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

KAUFMANN, CHAIM. (1996) Possible and Impossible Solutions of Civil War. International Security 20(4):136-175.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 26: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

DAVID MENDELOFF 379

KAUFMANN, CHAIM. (1999) When All Else Fails: Evaluating Population Transfers and Partition as Solutions to Ethnic Conflict. In Civil Wars, Insecurity, and Intervention, edited by Barbara E Walter and Jack Snyder. New York: Columbia University Press.

KAYE, MIKE. (1997) The Role of Truth Commissions in the Search for Justice, Reconciliation, and Democratization: The Salvadorean and Honduran Cases. Journal of Latin American Studies 29:693-716.

KEMALI, MARYAM. (2001) Accountability for Human Rights Violations: A Comparison of Transitional Justice in East Germany and South Africa. Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 40(1):89-141.

KIss, ELIZABETH. (2000) Moral Ambition within and beyond Political Constraints. In Truth v. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions, edited by Robert I. Rotberg and Dennis Thomspon. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

KRITZ, NEIL J. (1999) War Crimes Trials: Who Should Conduct Them, and How. In War Crimes: The Legacy of Nuremberg, edited by Belinda Cooper. New York: TV Books.

KUMAR, RADHA. (1997) The Troubled History of Partition. Foreign Affairs 76(1):22-34. LAPIDOTH, RUTH. (1996) Autonomy: Flexible Solutions to Ethnic Conflicts. Washington, DC: United States

Institute of Peace Press. LEDERACH, JOHN PAUL. (1997) Building Peace: Sustainable Reconciliation in Divided Societies. Washington,

DC: United States Institute of Peace Press. LICKLIDER, ROY. (2001) Obstacles to Peace Settlements. In Turbulent Peace: The Challenges of Managing

International Conflict, edited by Chester A. Crocker and Fen Osler Hampson with Pamela R. Aall. Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press.

LIJPHART, AREND. (1990) The Power-Sharing Approach. In Conflict and Peacemaking in Multiethnic Societies, edited by Joseph V. Monteville. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.

LIND, JENNIFER M. (2003) Sorry States: Apologies in International Politics. Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

LONG, WILLIAM J., AND PETER BRECKE. (2003) War and Reconciliation: Reason and Emotion in Conflict Resolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

LU, CATHERINE. (2002) Justice and Moral Regeneration: The Lessons from the Treaty of Versailles. International Studies Review 4(3):3-26.

LUND, MICHAEL. (2002) What Kind of Peace Is Being Built? Taking Stock of Peacebuilding and Charting Next Steps. Paper presented at the International Development Research Centre (IDRC) workshop, "What Kind of Peace." Ottawa, Canada, September 30-October 1.

LYONS, TERRENCE. (2002) The Role of Postsettlement Elections. In Ending Civil Wars: The Implemen- tation of Peace Agreements, edited by Stephen John Stedman, Donald Rothchild, and Elizabeth M. Cousens. Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers.

MAIER, CHARLES. (1993) A Surfeit of Memory? Reflections on History, Melancholy, and Denial. History and Memory 5:136-151.

MCCRAE, KENNETH D. (1990) Theories of Power-Sharing and Conflict Management. In Conflict and Peacemaking in Multiethnic Societies, edited by Joseph V. Monteville. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.

MENDELOFF, DAVID A. (2001) Truth-Telling and Mythmaking in Post-Soviet Russia: Pernicious Historical Ideas, Mass Education, and Interstate Conflict. Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

MERTUS, JULIE A. (1999) Kosovo: How Myths and Truths Started a War. Berkeley: University of California Press.

MINOW, MARTHA. (1998) Between Vengeance and Forgiveness: Facing History after Genocide and Mass Violence. Boston: Beacon Press.

PANKHURST, DONNA. (1999) Issues of Justice and Reconciliation in Complex Political Emergencies: Conceptualizing Reconciliation, Justice, and Peace. Third World Quarterly 20:239-255.

PARIS, ROLAND. (1997) Peacebuilding and the Limits of Liberal Internationalism. International Security 22(2):54-89.

PARIS, ROLAND. (2001) Wilson's Ghost: The Faulty Assumptions of Postconflict Peacebuilding. In Turbulent Peace: The Challenges of Managing International Conflict, edited by Chester A. Crocker and Fen Osler Hampson with Pamela R. Aall. Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press.

PETERSEN, ROGER D. (2002) Understanding Ethnic Violence: Fear, Hatred, and Resentment in Twentieth Century Eastern Europe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

POPKIN, MARGARET, AND NAOMI ROHT-ARRIAZA. (1995) Truth as Justice: Investigatory Commissions in Latin America. Law and Social Inquiry 20(1):79-116.

POSEN, BARRY R. (1993) The Security Dilemma and Ethnic Conflict. Survival 35(1):27-47.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 27: Mendeloff 2004 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, And Postconflict Peacebuilding: Curb the Enthusiasm?

380 Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peacebuilding

PUTNAM, TONYA L. (2002) Human Rights and Sustainable Peace. In Ending Civil Wars: The Imple- mentation of Peace Agreements, edited by Stephen John Stedman, Donald Rothchild, and Elizabeth M. Cousens. Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers.

RIGBY, ANDREW. (2001)Justice and Reconciliation: After the Violence. Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers. ROSENBERG, TINA. (1995) The Haunted Land: Facing Europe's Ghosts after Communism. New York:

Random House. SAMBANIS, NICOLAS. (2000) Partition as a Solution to Ethnic War: An Empirical Critique of the

Theoretical Literature. World Politics 52:437-483. SARKIN, JEREMY. (1998) The Development of a Human Rights Culture in South Africa. Human Rights

Quarterly 20:628-665. SARKIN, JEREMY. (1999) The Necessity and Challenges of Establishing a Truth and Reconciliation

Commission in Rwanda. Human Rights Quarterly 21:767-823. SCHARF, MICHAEL P. (1997) The Case for a Permanent International Truth Commission. Duke Journal

of Comparative and International Law 7:375-403. SISK, TIMOTHY D. (1996) Power Sharing and International Mediation in Ethnic Conflicts. Washington, DC:

United States Institute of Peace Press. SNYDER, JACK. (2000) From Voting to Violence: Democratization and Nationalist Conflict. New York: W.W.

Norton. SNYDER, JACK, AND KAREN BALLENTINE. (1996) Nationalism and the Marketplace of Ideas. International

Security 21(2):5-40. SNYDER, JACK, AND LESLIE VINJAMURI. (2003/04) Trials and Errors: Principles and Pragmatism in

Strategies of International Justice. International Security 28(3):5-44. STEDMAN, STEPHEN JOHN. (2002) Introduction. In Ending Civil Wars: The Implementation of Peace

Agreements, edited by Stephen John Stedman, Donald Rothchild, and Elizabeth M. Cousens. Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers.

TEPPERMAN, JONATHAN D. (2002) Truth and Consequences. Foreign Affairs 81(2):128-145. VAN EVERA, STEPHEN. (1994) Hypotheses on Nationalism and War. International Security 18(4):5-39. VAN ZYL, PAUL. (1999) Dilemmas of Transitional Justice: The Case of South Africa's Truth and

Reconciliation Commission. Columbia Journal of International Affairs 52:647-667. VILLA-VICENCIO, CHARLES, AND WILHELM VERWOERD. (2000) Constructing a Report: Writing up the

Truth. In Truth v. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions, edited by Robert I. Rotberg and Dennis

Thomspon. Princeton: Princeton University Press. WAGNER, ROBERT HARRISON. (1993) The Causes of Peace. In Stopping the Killing: How Civil Wars End,

edited by Roy Licklider. New York: New York University Press. WALTER, BARBARA E (1997) The Critical Barrier to Civil War Settlement. International Organization

51:335-364. WILSON, RICHARD A. (2001) The Politics of Truth and Reconciliation in South Africa: Legitimizing the Post-

Apartheid State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 10 Nov 2014 21:52:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions