12
The South Atlantic Quarterly 112:4, Fall 2013 doi 10.1215/00382876-2345252 © 2013 Duke University Press Lewis R. Gordon Race, Theodicy, and the Normative Emancipatory Challenges of Blackness “Race,” as Sylvia Wynter argues, is also a “biod- icy” (Wynter 2006: 142). By this, she means that the theodicean grammar of the world in which race was constituted is also, we should understand, one about the negotiation of life and death. Among its many consequences, race is about in one sense who lives and who dies. In another sense, its nor- mative significance leads to a rephrasing of who is supposed to live and who to die. 1 Theodicy literally means “god’s justice.” From theo (god) and dike ¯ (justice), the word emerges from a problem forged by expectations of a good or benevolent, omniscient, and omnipotent deity. Such a being is presumed to be committed to what is right—in some reasoning even more, where the being itself is what is right and good— which makes the emergence of evil and injustice a major problem. If the deity has the capacity to eradicate evil, indeed, the ability to have prevented its emergence in the first place, why are there manifestations of evil and injustice? The problem raises a variety of vexing prob- lems for all except perhaps the most extraordi- nary of the faithful or the most naive among them. If the deity’s benevolence is a necessary condi- tion of its existence, then the presence of iniquity South Atlantic Quarterly Published by Duke University Press

L Gordon South Atlantic Quarterly Libre

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

;

Citation preview

  • The South Atlantic Quarterly 112:4, Fall 2013

    doi 10.1215/00382876-2345252 2013 Duke University Press

    Lewis R. Gordon

    Race, Theodicy, and the Normative

    Emancipatory Challenges of Blackness

    Race, as Sylvia Wynter argues, is also a biod-icy (Wynter 2006: 142). By this, she means that the theodicean grammar of the world in which race was constituted is also, we should understand, one about the negotiation of life and death. Among its many consequences, race is about in one sense who lives and who dies. In another sense, its nor-mative significance leads to a rephrasing of who is supposed to live and who to die.1

    Theodicy literally means gods justice. From theo (god) and dike (justice), the word emerges from a problem forged by expectations of a good or benevolent, omniscient, and omnipotent deity. Such a being is presumed to be committed to what is rightin some reasoning even more, where the being itself is what is right and goodwhich makes the emergence of evil and injustice a major problem. If the deity has the capacity to eradicate evil, indeed, the ability to have prevented its emergence in the first place, why are there manifestations of evil and injustice?

    The problem raises a variety of vexing prob-lems for all except perhaps the most extraordi-nary of the faithful or the most naive among them. If the deitys benevolence is a necessary condi-tion of its existence, then the presence of iniquity

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • 726 The South Atlantic Quarterly Fall 2013

    suggests either the deitys impotence or malicious foreknowledge. If evil and injustice are the deitys will, the universe is under the yoke of a very bad deity. Another conclusion is simply that the deity doesnt exist.

    A third solution is to demonstrate the compatibility of evil and injus-tice alongside the existence of such a god. Many theologians have taken this course. From St. Augustine (1950) in the early middle ages to Gottfried Leib-niz (1952) in early modern through to Kwame Gyekye (1987), John Hicks (1978), William R. Jones (1997), Sherman A. Jackson (2009), and Anthony B. Pinn (1999) in recent times, the conundrum persists with answers not often satisfactory for the faithful (see also Gordon 2008). Not much has gone beyond St. Augustines reflection on two exonerating conditions for his deity, although argued in many instances with increasing brilliance, which was for his fellow Christians and him the deity: the problem is a consequence of human limitations.

    Human beings are not omniscient and therefore cannot possibly understand the full significance of what appears to be evil and unjust. That familiar response boils down to the old adage, G-d knows.2 The alterna-tive response reminds us of the significance of love. The deity endowed humanity with free will. As an act of love, it demands restraint as human will, imperfect as it is, makes its way through the ages through actions good and bad, right and wrong. In both formulations, human beings are the problem. Gyekye (1987), Jones (1997), Jackson (2009), and Pinn (1999), while endorsing its humanistic ethical implications, are not satisfied with this response. Its metaphysical implications are not in the favor of G-ds existence.

    Others, such as F. W. J. von Schelling, G. W. F. Hegel, and Friedrich Nietzsche, had thought through the implications of theodicy at the level of nature and history.3 The existential problematic raises the question of what is permitted to be in the world versus what is not. If the unfolding of time and history is at the end of the day right, then what is to be made of that which it eliminates and those who are pushed to the wayside in this drama? They, along with others such as W. E. B. Du Bois (1903) through to Frantz Fanon (1991) and more, have noticed the continued presence of this kind of argumentation even where there is the absence of an avowed deity.4 Even secular societies may have a theodicean mode of rationalization, where the society itself or some system of treasured knowledge or values occupies the deific role. In theology, this is called idolatry.

    For our purposes, idolatry offers a theodicean grammar or form. Its rationalization depends on rendering its contradictions external, which

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • Gordon Race, Theodicy, and Emancipatory Challenges 727

    means, from a systemic point of view, systematically dead. This dimen-sion of theodicy, then, shifts as normative investment moves from knowl-edge and society to life, from biology (bio-logos) to a biodicy (life-justice). We could call this the presupposition of inherently lived justification.

    Such is not only the story of race but also the specificity of its modern, Manichaean manifestation. That protorace had its origin in theological natu-ralism brings these considerations to the fore. The world of theological natu-ralism was, after all, one in which the theological and the natural were insep-arable. There was no supernatural in that world because the natural was what the deity produced. Thus, instead of the natural and the supernatural, pri-mary distinctions in Western modernity, there was the natural and the unnat-ural. The latter simply meant that which deviated from the former. In medi-eval Christian theology, the unnatural was that which deviated from Christ, which made it also evil or demonic. Among such deviations were two refus-ing groups: Jews and Muslims.

    The etymology of race points to this theological naturalism but with odd considerations. The prototerm was raza, which referred to breeds of dogs and horses, and then Jews and Moors.5 The complicated issue with dogs and horses, as we know, is that their emergence from their ancestral species was through human involvement. Thus, their natural form was heavily mediated or, under another interpretation, deviated. It would be odd to consider dogs and horses unnatural, however. That they are domesticated animals signals a relationship between them and the human beings they serve. Jews and Moors represented a deviation from the natu-ral in a similar way: each supposedly part of G-ds creation, they are, never-theless, deviations through supposedly human hubris. Comparing them with domesticated animals, then, signaled also the social role they were expected ultimately to play. Thus, in the reconquest, referring more to an order of power than to historical fact, since there was not a prior Christian conquest of Islam because the latter emerged after Christianity and was in fact the conqueror, the search for signs, markings, of unnatural origins was among its governing activities well attested to by the Inquisition.

    The question of origins was, however, among the considerations of raza. The term was not German, Latin, or Greek, languages that dominated the northern Mediterranean northward, but Arabic, Hebrew, and Egyptian. As a variation of such words as ra (Arabic), rosh (Hebrew), and ra (Egyptian), words referring to head and beginning, its significance for origins was clear. The Afro-Muslim conquest of Iberia, which created Andalusia, no doubt offered distinctions premised on originsa consideration not only

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • 728 The South Atlantic Quarterly Fall 2013

    among the conquered Christians but also among the Muslims who were transformed the more their faith reached beyond western Asia.6

    The Christian triumph in Grenada in 1492 meant, among many things, the expansion of a legitimation crisis, where origins became a constant con-sideration even as ships reached shores in which those who greeted them were not Christian, Jew, or Muslim. The epistemic upheavals that followed, where justification shifted from the deity to the question of deities them-selves, where accounting for the natural required nontheological sources, led to new examinations of origins and correlative anthropologies: raza was adopted, adapted, and transformed into classification systems through which, over time, we have race. But along with this transformation were also contin-ued forms of rationalization. Thus, as deviance was marked by a shift from normative centers, old theologically symbolic markers of the light and the dark, Manichaean throughout, continued. There was no hope of a good deal for the night in this tale.7

    The historical situation of the dark, which eventually became the black, was marked before the debates between Bartolom de Las Casas and Juan Gins de Seplveda about the humanity of Native American popula-tions and their salvation both spiritually and biologically, through appeal to heathenish and darker sources from Africa (see Hanke 1974). The recon-quest had already set the stage for the relationship with the black, but this blackness was one in which refuge could not be sought in the soul because of its already betrayed presence in the color of skin. To make matters worse, the populations thus marked by blackness had no reason to have expected such, which meant their inauguration into this schema, an epidermal one as Fanon (1967) characterized it, were without knowledge of the logic that erased their inner or lived reality. A form of amnesia was necessary to trans-form people from a world in which they once saw themselves as the futureas, in other words, their version of modernto the Fanonian problematic near the end of Les damns de la terre: In reality, what am I? (Fanon 1991: penultimate ch.).

    This problematic of blackness is symbiotically linked to the world in which Christendom was transformed into Europe, where Germanic and Mediterranean Christians were transformed into whites. As there was no reason to have considered themselves black or African prior to the imposi-tions of these identities on them from kidnapping to Middle Passage to enslavement, black existence became marked by the peculiarity of paradox and melancholic displacement. The former was a consequence of having to have always been what one becomes. The melancholia is to be endemic to a

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • Gordon Race, Theodicy, and Emancipatory Challenges 729

    world in which one is rejectedto be homeless in the epoch to which one is indigenous. Paradoxes are brought about through displacement at levels of identity, for to be black is not to be; it is to be, as Fanon observed, in the zone of nonbeing. Thus, blackness is fundamental to the formation of Euro-pean modernity as it is one that imagines itself legitimate and pure through the expurgation of blackness. It is, in other words, the theodicy of European modernity.

    Du Bois saw this problem in many ways. In one sense, he formulated it as the problem of being a problem. This realization led to a schism in which a consciousness of society and of not belonging to it through paradox-ically being endemic to it is one of Du Boiss great insights. He outlined well the theodicean problematic of blackness as the absent term, even in its pres-ence. This logic required apartheid behavior even at epistemic levels, as Railand Rybalka (2010) correctly observed, and that consideration moved more radically to the conditions for the possibility of thought itself (see also L. R. Gordon 2006). In effect, it demanded purification of theory, which meant theory that behaves, theory that abides by the rules, theory, in other words, with limited vision. The reference to vision is no accident here, as theory etymologically emerges from the Greek infinitive theorein (to see), through which we get theoria. As with theodicy, the theological groundings of this concept should be evident, which reminds us of a basic insight of the-oretical work as an attempt to see what deities would see. To see as a godindeed, as G-dwould be an extraordinary achievement for humanity, which is no doubt why much of early modern reflection on decoding the uni-verse took the form of deciphering the language of G-d. Where G-d is seen as light, however, there is no darkness, which makes all truth, all thought, ultimately without contradiction. Truth and thought obey G-d in this theo-logical metaphysics precisely because the deity could command their obedi-ence. In that conception, necessity and sufficiency meet because thought and deed, from that which is omniscient and omnipotent, are one.

    Epistemic theodicy takes the form, however, of demanding the supervenience of consistency models of rationality. In effect, it requires rationalizing reasons obedience. A problem emerges, however, when the scope of this effort includes its own evaluation. It begs the question for ratio-nality to assess its own consistency, since it is consistency itself that is up for evaluation. To evaluate consistency or rationality requires something more, and that is reason. What, in other words, if reason doesnt behave? And what if its delinquency is precisely because, as an evaluator, it must be above, para-doxically even, itself? These kinds of questions reveal the contradictions of

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • 730 The South Atlantic Quarterly Fall 2013

    metasystems, of any theoretical model that must evaluate itself. But brought down to earth in the context of these reflections, it means addressing the sides of theory that rationality hoped to suppress, and what are they other than their darker sides? Theory, in other words, could articulate the light only because its reach is also into its negations, namely, the zones of non-being (for more, see Gordon 2010b).

    This understanding leads to rethinking some key features of the emer-gence of colonized epistemic practices. To identify them as colonized means to admit their suppressed terms, their hidden or feared undersides. The previ-ous meditations on theory bring to the fore considerations of practices of sci-ence as well. Here we are in a terrain similar to Du Boiss (1903) reflections on potentiated double consciousness, where the contradictions of false particu-larities unveil and enlarge the grammatical practices of knowledgein more prosaic language, the universalizing, as opposed to universal, activities of expanding thought (for discussion, see Henry 2005; and J. A. Gordon 2007). And made plainer: This means blackness, broader in scope, unmasks the false security of whiteness. Reality, in other words, is always bigger than that.

    Among the many instances of this unfolding is the constellation of epistemic practices known as the human sciences. One fallacy is the ten-dency to treat these sciences as pure, wherein their completeness is dem-onstrated and then they are methodically applied to human beings.8 What is missing is the understanding that human being was already racially inflected through the presupposition of epistemic practices premised on normative whiteness. The human sciences emerged, after all, out of the question, What is man?9 But as we have seen, that question emerged through encounters with the extraordinary and the different. When a presumed human we meets them, interrogation emerges on the question of whether we are they. This rupture leads to meditations on the question of standards by which we are determined as who or what we are and they are the same for what they are. This identity question, however, leads to fur-ther meditations on those standards, and in them is the additional problem-atic of what is a human being (for more, see Gordon 2011c). This philosophi-cal anthropological question, if we will, is rendered more difficult by the epistemic upheavals that emerged from a collapsed theological naturalism. Where necessity no longer reigns as a god, where idea does not mean exis-tence, where the human being must take hold of the responsibility for what is seen (secular theory), the possibility of what to become is the metaphysical and epistemic investment in no less than the modern problematic of freedom in an epoch conditioned through and through by the presupposition of racial

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • Gordon Race, Theodicy, and Emancipatory Challenges 731

    difference. In blackness, in other words, emerged three conditions of mod-ern thought itselfnamely, philosophical anthropology, freedom, and the justificatory practices of both (see Gordon 2010b, 2008).

    The emergence of the first is already outlined and understood through the historical reality of systems denying the humanity of whole groups of human beings in the first place. Such denial, contradictory in terms (because it relies on the supposed nonhumanity of some human groups, of putting outside of human relations that which depends on human relationships), inevitably leads to the effort to force behavior on human subjects through epistemic and political acts of closure. The problem, however, is that a closed human being, a human being without possibility, is not properly a human being.10 Freedom, then, became an intimate condition of human exemplifi-cation. As symbiotic, the two faced legitimating questions, and thus the jus-tificatory practiceis blackness justifiable?emerged (see, e.g., Gordon 2000: ch. 1). I have elsewhere called this the metacritique of reason precisely because of the black side of thought premised on contradictions of reason (see Gordon 2010b). A Fanonian allegory is perhaps useful here. In Black Skin, White Masks, Fanon (1967: ch. 5) observed the flight of reason when the black enters the room. The black could force reasons obedience, but this will no doubt be unreasonable. But reasons flight as he reached out to it is also unreasonable. The black faces, in other words, the nightmare of unrea-sonable reason. Barred from the use of force, the only alternative is to reason with such (unreasonable) reason (see Gordon 2011d). This reasoning, if we will, is the continued burden of blackness.

    Although these reflections pertain fundamentally to the epistemic challenges of blackness, I do not think they are radical enough. One presup-position of decolonizing the epistemic conditions is that it will lead to a form of normative catharsis. The presumption is that a form of false knowledge is sequestering the kinds of responsible activities needed to think and act better, and by the latter I mean at least ethically and justly. These normative terms are often presumed as prisoners behind European-nurtured epistemic walls. What if there is another layer of imprisonment? What if the presumed nor-mative resources to be unleashed from the putting aside of epistemic infelici-ties persist at a more radical levelthat is, at those of the norms themselves?

    In his critique of European colonialism, Aim Csaire (2000: 41) raised a similar concern when he argued that what transpired in World War II was not anomalous but instead was a manifestation of the actual values Europeans lived in the colonies, namely, Hitlerism (see also Maldonado-Torres 2008b: ch. 1). It was not only that European colonialism actively

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • 732 The South Atlantic Quarterly Fall 2013

    fought against the humanity of colonized subjects but also that the modes or technologies of colonization were expressions of Europe itself. That being the case, Csaires analysis of what emerged on the European continent was sim-ply its value system turned inward. His argument was not that there werent good things about Europe. As a human community, it also had bad elements, and as those were pushed outward to the colonies (in theodicean language, outside of the god), they eventually spilled over into a vengeful return.

    Csaire identified a problem later echoed by Fanon in his encomium for people of what is today called the global South to look beyond Europe for inspiration, develop new concepts, and set afoot a new humanity. The con-ceptual question alerts us to the epistemic challenge, but Fanons praxis demand (set afoot a new humanity) speaks to a task at the level of lived reality. Even more, Fanon earlier in the same passage encouraged going beyond the Greco-Latin pedestal of European values (see Fanon 1991: ch. 1 and conclusion; for discussion, see Gordon 2010a). While proponents of those values might attempt to defend them as human values or universal val-ues, this normative critique questions such an assertion on a par with that of double consciousness and potentiated double consciousness. Is it not another case of European particularity asserting itself as human universality? And even more, as we saw in the philosophical anthropological question, isnt part of a radical critique the question of privileging one group of human beings as the human in the first place?

    We are on familiar terrain. For as with the theological and epistemic questions, the normative one faces the problem of theodicean grammar as well. Are the norms for which many of us are fighting in the name of, say, racial justice or liberation from antiblack racism free of normative coloni-zation even where they may be so at an epistemic level? Isnt it presumptu-ous to think that the decolonization of knowledge has the same norms as its consequence?

    We do already have a clue on this potentially vexing problem. Black-ness, after all, as the underside of theory, is a relational concept (see Gordon 2010b). To think of blackness means always to imagine it in relation to some-thing else, since to do so is to establish at least a phenomenological relation-ship of thought to its object or subject (Gordon 2010b; see also Gordon 2011b). This basic relationship offers the critique of the theodicean one, where the role of a god in effect eliminates the rest of the world by becoming an exclusive domain. It requires being without an outside and thus being outside of relations with anything else. The distinction of being-in-relations ver-sus nonrelationality raises a normative difference since blackness, and its

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • Gordon Race, Theodicy, and Emancipatory Challenges 733

    relationship not only to the included but also the excluded, promises an ever-widening normative range.

    An example of this difference is what we could call justice talk. This activity is often done as if it is all-encompassing but insufficiently addressed. Thus, there is always the search for justice as though every normative arrangement of social institutions has simply fallen short of its virtue, as John Rawls (1971: introduction) espoused through his claim of justice as the primary virtue of institutions. This presumption works, of course, if justice were simply a term already present in every human community and simply standing within the northern European tradition of thought as a term trans-latable into its correlate in other languages. But translatability often begs many important questions of human difference. It could not only be the case that justice was not translated but in fact imposed but also that its scope, even where translatable, is part of a smaller normative field within the frame-work of the non-European group to which it is posed. If this is correct, then the proponent of justice has the task not only of understanding what is com-mon about justice across human communities but also what could be learned beyond justice across them as well. Where justice is asserted in a theodicean way, this is a terrifying thought, as it requires looking at the underside of justice only as injustice instead of what may be right or good beyond justice.11

    Race, theodicy, and normativity, then, pose special questions for our age, especially in terms of challenges raised by blackness. The last, for instance, has a bad habit of demonstrating societal, scientific, and normative contradictions. Blackness, constantly posed as illicit appearance, means that hopes for justice in a system premised on licit appearance leads not only to contradictions but also to the maintenance of exclusion in the name of justice. In the realm of science, there was the presumption that science is correctly implemented through the exclusion of race, particularly blackness. The cri-tique is the same as on the societal level: it is a theodicy that elides the sym-biotic foundation of its own system. The human sciences, for instance, emerged out of worries and encounters with human difference. Instead of bad science producing race, it was, in other words, race that produced human science, since it required a meditation not only on the human but also the really human. I have outlined some of the normative problematics in terms of justice, but there is more to consider, for the normative dimensions of what it means to be human also affect the conditions of appearance and other norms such as those of violation and violence. If one is not supposed to appear, then one has violated a norm by doing so (see, e.g., Gordon 2012).

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • 734 The South Atlantic Quarterly Fall 2013

    Blackness, then, is a challenge at the heart of what is to be done as humanity reflects on how it is bound to its subsequent generations, how, that is, it is bound to itself. This binding, the hallmark of religiosity, raises the question as well, in a secular age, of the extent to which religiosity itself as a disavowed condition is also a blackened one. These reflections at levels of knowledge and value, the separation of which I hope has been shown to be neither neat nor even viable, I also hope will be of some use as we con-tinue to reflect on the continued significance and future of things black.

    Notes

    To Sylvia Wynter, with continued admiration and appreciation.

    1 This is familiar to anyone who reflects on racism and genocide. For critical discus-

    sion in these terms, see Feder 2008; Sheth 2009; and Gordon 2011a.

    2 For readers wondering about this expression, G-d. The answer: Im in the Jewish

    camp and subscribe to the logic of what is involved, including the hubris, of referring

    to the ineffable or, at least, that which shouldnt be fully written or uttered.

    3 For discussion, see, for example, Gabriel 2011; and iek and Gabriel 2009.

    4 For discussion, see Gordon 2008; and compare also Gordon 2004.

    5 See, e.g., Sebastian de Covarrubias Orozsco (1611), who in his Tesoro de la lengua,

    explained the term as pertaining to the caste of purebred horses, which are marked

    by a brand so that they can be recognized. . . . Raza in lineages is meant negatively, as

    in having some raza of Moor or Jew (quoted and translated in Nirenberg 2007: 79).

    6 Literature on this subject is vast. In addition to Greer, Mignolo, and Quilligan 2007, see

    Mignolo 2003; Davis 2003; and Van Sertima 1992. Compare also Gordon 2008: ch. 1.

    7 In addition to Gordon 2008, see also Gordon 1995b; Baltazar 1973; Mignolo 2003,

    2012; and Maldonado-Torres 2008a.

    8 For discussion of this fallacy, see Gordon 2000: ch. 4; J. A. Gordon 2006; and

    Rybalka 2010.

    9 See Foucault 1971 for a magisterial study of this question and the formation of the

    human sciences, and compare Wynter 2006 and Bogues 2006.

    10 For more, see the discussion of epistemic closure Gordon 1995a: ch. 3.

    11 For more on this problem and formulation, see Gordon 2013.

    References

    Baltazar, Eulalio. 1973. The Dark Center: A Process Theology of Blackness. New York: Paulist

    Press.

    Bogues, B. Anthony, ed. 2006. After Man, towards the Human: Critical Essays on the Thought

    of Sylvia Wynter. Kingston, Jam.: Ian Randle.

    Csaire, Aim. 2000. Discourse on Colonialism. Translated by Joan Pinkham, with an intro-

    duction by Robin D. G. Kelley. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Covarrubias Orozsco, Sebastian de. 1611. Tesoro de la lengua. Madrid: Lus Snchez.

    Davis, Robert. 2003. Christian Slaves, Muslim Masters: White Slavery in the Mediterranean,

    the Barbary Coast and Italy, 15001800. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Du Bois, W. E. B. 1903. The Souls of Black Folk: Essays and Sketches. Chicago: A. C. McClurg.

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • Gordon Race, Theodicy, and Emancipatory Challenges 735

    Fanon, Frantz. 1967. Black Skin, White Masks. Translated by Charles Lam Markman. New

    York: Grove.

    Fanon, Frantz. (1961) 1991. Les damns de la terre. Introduction by Jean-Paul Sartre. Paris:

    ditions Gallimard.

    Feder, Ellen K. 2008. Disciplining the Family. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Foucault, Michel. 1971. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. Trans-

    lated by A. M. Sheridan Smith. New York: Pantheon.

    Gabriel, Markus. 2011. Transcendental Ontology: Essays on German Idealism. New York:

    Continuum.

    Gordon, Jane Anna. 2006. Some Reflections on Challenges Posed to the Social Scientific Study

    of Race. In A Companion to African-American Studies, edited by Lewis R. Gordon and Jane

    Anna Gordon, 279304. Malden, MA: Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9780470996645.ch19.

    Gordon, Jane Anna. 2007. The Gift of Double Consciousness: Some Obstacles to Grasping

    the Contributions of the Colonized. In Postcolonialism and Political Theory, edited by

    Nalini Persram, 14361. Lanham, MD: Lexington.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 1995a. Fanon and the Crisis of European Man: An Essay on Philosophy and

    the Human Sciences New York: Routledge.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 1995b. Bad Faith and Antiblack Racism. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2000. Existentia Africana: Introducing Africana Existential Thought. New

    York: Routledge.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2004. Philosophical Anthropology, Race, and the Political Economy of

    Disenfranchisement. Columbia Human Rights Law Review 36, no. 1: 14572.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2006. Disciplinary Decadence: Living Thought in Trying Times. Boulder,

    CO: Paradigm.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2008. An Introduction to Africana Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge

    University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511800726.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2010a. Fanon on Decolonizing Knowledge. In Fanon and the Decoloniza-

    tion of Philosophy, edited by Elizabeth A. Hope and Tracey Nicholls with a foreword by

    Mireille Fanon-Mends-France, 318. Lanham, MD: Lexington.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2010b. Theory in Black: Teleological Suspensions in Philosophy of Cul-

    ture. Qui Parle: Critical Humanities and Social Sciences 18, no. 2: 193214.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2011a. Falguni A. Sheth: Toward a Political Philosophy of Race. Continen-

    tal Philosophy Review 44, no. 1: 11930. doi:10.1007/s11007-011-9171-z.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2011b. Lexistence noire dans la philosophie de la culture. Translated by

    Christine Klein-Lataud. Diogne, nos. 235236: 13347.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2011c. Race in the Dialectics of Culture. In Reconsidering Social Identifi-

    cation: Race, Gender, Class and Caste, edited by Abdul JanMohamed, 5579. New

    Delhi: Routledge India.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2011d. When Reason Is in a Bad Mood: A Fanonian Philosophical Por-

    trait. In Philosophys Moods: The Affective Grounds of Thinking, edited by Hagi Kenaan

    and Ilit Ferber, 18598. Dordrecht: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-1503-5_13.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2012. Below Even the Other: Colonialisms Violent Legacy and Challenge,

    with Respects to Fanon. TransEuropeennes: International Journal of Critical Thought.

    www.transeuropeennes.eu/en/articles/358.

    Gordon, Lewis R. 2013. Justice Otherwise: Thoughts on uBuntu. In Ubuntu: Curating the

    Archive, edited by Leonhard Praeg. Scottsville, South Africa: University of KwaZulu

    Natal Press.

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press

  • 736 The South Atlantic Quarterly Fall 2013

    Greer, Margaret R., Walter D. Mignolo, and Maureen Quilligan, eds. 2007. Rereading the

    Black Legend: The Discourses of Religious and Racial Difference in the Renaissance

    Empires. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Gyekye, Kwame. 1987. An Essay on African Philosophical Thought: The Akan Conceptual Scheme.

    Rev. ed. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Hanke, Lewis. 1974. All Mankind Is One: A Study of the Disputation between Bartolom de Las

    Casas and Juan Gines de Sepulveda in 1550 on the Intellectual and Religious Capacity.

    Chicago: Northern Illinois University Press.

    Henry, Paget. 2005. Africana Phenomenology: Its Philosophical Implications. C. L. R.

    James Journal 11, no. 1: 79112.

    Hicks, John. 1978. Evil and the God of Love. Rev. ed. New York: Harper and Row.

    Jackson, Sherman A. 2009. Islam and Black Suffering. New York: Oxford University Press.

    doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195382068.001.0001.

    Jones, William R. 1997. Is God a White Racist? A Preamble to Black Theology. 2nd ed. Boston:

    Beacon Press.

    Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1952. Theodicy. Edited by Austin Farrer. Translated by E. M.

    Huggard. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Maldonado-Torres, Nelson. 2008a. Against War: Views from the Underside of Modernity. Dur-

    ham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Maldonado-Torres, Nelson. 2008b. From Liberalism to Hitlerism: Tracing the Origins of

    Violence and War. In Against War: Views from the Underside of Modernity, 2351. Dur-

    ham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Mignolo, Walter. 2003. The Darker Side of the Renaissance: Literacy, Territoriality, and Coloni-

    zation. 2nd ed. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Mignolo, Walter. 2012. The Darker Side of Western Modernity: Global Futures, Decolonial

    Options. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Nirenberg, David. 2007. Race and the Middle Ages: The Case of Spain and Its Jews. In

    Rereading the Black Legend: The Discourses of Religious and Racial Difference in the

    Renaissance Empires, edited by Margaret R. Greer, Walter D. Mignolo, and Maureen

    Quilligan, 7187. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Pinn, Anthony B. 1999. Why, Lord? Suffering and Evil in Black Theology. New York: Continuum.

    Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Rybalka, Railand. 2010. Against Epistemic Apartheid: W. E. B. Du Bois and the Disciplinary

    Decadence of Sociology. Lanham, MD: Lexington.

    Sheth, Falguni. 2009. Toward a Political Philosophy of Race. Albany, NY: State University of

    New York Press.

    St. Augustine. 1950. The City of God. Translated by Marcus Doas, with an introduction by

    Thomas Merton. New York: Modern Library.

    Van Sertima, Ivan, ed. 1992. Golden Age of the Moor. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

    Wynter, Sylvia. 2006. On How We Mistook the Map for the Territory, and Re-Imprisoned

    Ourselves in Our Unbearable Wrongness of Being, of Dstre: Black Studies toward

    the Human Project. In Not Only the Masters Tools: African American Studies in The-

    ory and Practice, edited by Lewis R. Gordon and Jane Anna Gordon, 85106. Boulder,

    CO: Paradigm.

    iek, Slavoj, and Markus Gabriel. 2009. Mythology, Madness, and Laughter: Subjectivity in

    German Idealism. New York: Continuum.

    South Atlantic Quarterly

    Published by Duke University Press