Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Pétursdóttir 31 53

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    1/24

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/Journal of Social Archaeology

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31The online version of this article can be found at:

    DOI: 10.1177/1469605312456342

    2013 13: 31Journal of Social Archaeologyra Ptursdttir

    Concrete matters: Ruins of modernity and the things called heritage

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    can be found at:Journal of Social ArchaeologyAdditional services and information for

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31.refs.htmlCitations:

    What is This?

    - Feb 4, 2013Version of Record>>

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31http://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31http://www.sagepublications.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://jsa.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://jsa.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31.refs.htmlhttp://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31.refs.htmlhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31.full.pdfhttp://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31.full.pdfhttp://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31.full.pdfhttp://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31.refs.htmlhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://jsa.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://jsa.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://www.sagepublications.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/content/13/1/31http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    2/24

    Journal of Social Archaeology

    13(1) 3153

    ! The Author(s) 2012

    Reprints and permissions:

    sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav

    DOI: 10.1177/1469605312456342

    jsa.sagepub.com

    Article

    Concrete matters: Ruinsof modernity and thethings called heritage

    ora PetursdottirDepartment of Archaeology and Social Anthropology,University of Troms, Norway

    Abstract

    Intangibility has become a trendy term within heritage studies and is now evenconsidered to refer to heritage in general. This article discusses this development,along with its integrity and consequences for the fate of things in the heritage discourse.

    With reference to the concrete ruins of Icelands recent past it addresses the traditionaland contemporary processes of discrimination and othering within heritage definitions,and the often fragile dialectic between heritage and waste. With a foothold in these veryconcrete and tangible remains the article questions the emerging claim that all heritageis intangible and suggests that a broader heritage conception, and a true concern forthe very tangible qualities of things, may bring us closer to a comprehension of the(heritage) value of these modern ruins.

    Keywords

    Gelassenheit, heritage, heritage value, intangible heritage, modern ruins, ruination,thingness

    Ruin memory

    They have destroyed the factory! It is not the same it has lost its charm now. These

    were the words of a frustrated photographer I met in Strandir, in Icelands Westfjords,

    while working on my project on herring factories in the area last summer. I instantly

    knew what he was referring to. One of the two decaying and roughly half a century old

    Corresponding author:

    ora Petursdottir, University of Troms, Department of Archaeology and Social Anthropology, Breiviklia,

    9037 Troms, Norway.

    Email: [email protected]

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    3/24

    herring rendering factories I was working on had been painted white earlier in

    the summer. Abandoned in the 1950s the factory had been left to ruination until

    bought, along with most of its adjacent buildings, by its present day owners in the

    1980s. Soon after they had restored and opened a small hotel in one of the old

    buildings where they have since served a constantly growing number of tourists

    making their way to this beautiful but remote region every summer. The restoration

    of the factory itself, however, a colossal degrading concrete structure, was for long,

    and still is really, beyond their capacity. Nevertheless, step by step, replacing broken

    windows, roof tiles and gutters, stopping leakage and infilling frost cracks the build-

    ings constant aging and decay has, to some extent, been tamed. This has made it

    possible for the hotel managers to exploit the lure the old factory has on visitors,

    inviting guests on guided tours along the processing line, creating a small herring

    history exhibition in the engine hall, and throwing art exhibitions and concerts in

    the many wonderfully lit and acoustic spaces it provides (Figure 1). The latest amend-

    ment in this process was the painting of the factory, turning its outer appearance from

    concrete grey to glistering white. It is not for this that I have travelled all this way!,

    the photographer announced, and although I sympathized with the owners intentions

    and effort, genuinely caring for this abandoned building, I understood his frustration.

    I too knew the factory before its face-lift and realized the enormous transformation

    caused by this white makeup.

    Introduction

    The latest theoretical twirl in the humanities and social sciences has been articu-

    lated as a new concern with matter, materiality or a turn towards things.1 As

    stated by historian Frank Trentmann, Things are back. After the turn to discourse

    and signs in the late 20th century, there is a new fascination with the material stuff

    of life (2009: 283). Interestingly, the contemporary development within heritage

    studies, to some extent at least, has been characterized by an opposite turn. Here

    intangibility seems to have become an equally attractive catchword. While firstentering the heritage toolkit in order to accommodate other, often non-western,

    aspects of heritage than monuments and objects, the concept of intangible heritage

    is now even seen as representing . . . a radical paradigm shift from the objective

    nature of material culture to the subjective experience of the human being

    (Ruggles and Silverman, 2009: 11). Thus, intangibility is, by some scholars,

    argued to describe the essence of heritage in general. [A]ll heritage is intangible,

    it is stated (Smith, 2006: 3; see also Waterton and Smith, 2009b: 16), and, further-

    more, there is, really, no such thingas heritage (Smith, 2006: 11, my emphasis; see

    also e.g. Waterton and Smith, 2009b: 10). Though it may truly be debated to whatextent the current turn towards things in the humanities and social sciences

    involves a sincere concern with the things themselves (see Ingold, 2007; Olsen,

    2010), the call for a reverse or opposite turn within heritage studies is worthy of

    a closer look.

    32 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    4/24

    The critique uttered by advocates of intangible heritage is that monuments,

    physical objects or material culture have dominated heritage definitions and in

    effect excluded other possible perspectives or ways to understand heritage. That

    in itself may be a legitimate and understandable critique. But where does it lead us

    to claim that all heritage is intangible, that there are no such things as heritage?And, can it really be claimed to account for a paradigm shift in heritage studies or

    management? Moreover, where does it leave things, in heritage, to deny them their

    tangibility or thingness? And where does it leave heritage to ignore things role, or

    to assign them innocence, in the discourse and construction of heritage concep-

    tions? In this article I discuss these questions as well as possible consequences of

    this development.

    My discussion will seek concreteness in a case study: on-going research focusing

    on ruins of modernity in Icelands northwest, specifically the concrete ruins of

    herring factories that were constructed and abandoned during the first half ofthe twentieth century. The factories emerged due to the advent of industrialized

    herring fishing, known as the herring adventure (sldarvintyri) in Icelandic

    public and historical discourses. It is an adventure, furthermore, generally referred

    to as one of the most significant elements in the nations modernization process,

    independence and economic viability during the first half of the twentieth century.

    Despite their historical significance, however, the herring factories themselves have

    been more or less ignored as heritage. Because of their young age, or immaturity,

    and their corroding and rotting state, they find themselves caught up somewhere

    between disposal and history. They linger on as more or less worthless matter outof place in the Icelandic ideological heritage landscape of myth and Sagas and

    thus create an ideal context for reflection on the fate of things in the heritage

    discourse. As I argue, the durability and weight of their concrete carcasses exceeds

    a mere intangible reflection. Through their very presence, and the presence-effects

    Figure 1. From waste to heritage? Herring history exhibition in the engine hall of Dju pavk

    herring factory (Photo: ora Petursdottir).

    Petursdottir 33

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    5/24

    (Gumbrecht, 2004) they provoke, they can be said to utter their own critique of

    conventional heritage conceptions and urge us to critically consider the significance

    of the concrete and tangible in relation to heritage value, and of ruination as not

    only a negative but also a generative process (cf. DeSilvey, 2006; Shanks, 1998).

    Intangible heritage heritage contra things?

    The historical scope of heritage and heritage practices is frequently traced back to

    the official acts of monument and heritage protection in the nineteenth century, or

    slightly earlier, and the associated programs of nationalism, romanticism and

    historicism thought to have triggered these early initiatives. Others see no need

    to go further back than to the global approaches to heritage appearing in the latter

    half of the twentieth century. As argued by David C. Harvey, however, these recentdates of origin may be seen as representing particular strands in the history of

    heritage, or heritageisation, which should be understood . . . as a process or a

    human condition rather than a single movement or a personal project (2001:

    320) with a datable genesis.

    Definitions of the heritage concept have been many and varied, while the con-

    ceptions of inheritance and bequest have been central to many of them. UNESCOs

    definition of heritage claims that heritage is our legacy from the past, what we live

    with today, and what we pass on to future generations (UNESCO, n.d.). This

    emphasis on inheritance and possession (Rowlands, 2002a, 2002b), and the conse-quential conception of heritage as a physical thing or property crystallized also in

    the concept of cultural resourcemanagement has been increasingly criticized by

    heritage scholars, of which Harveys (2001) suggestion of heritageisation and

    heritage as a process is an example. This criticism is maybe most explicitly

    voiced in the work of Laurajane Smith, especially in her research on the heritage

    canon and the dominant or authorized heritage discourse (AHD) manifested in it

    (2006; see also Smith and Waterton, 2009a, 2009b; Waterton and Smith, 2009b).

    According to Smith, this dominant discourse has acted to normalize or naturalize

    our conception of heritage, how it is defined, and who is authorized to do so.Heritage is here reduced to an authentic physical artefact or site, aesthetically

    pleasing and monumental, confined to a distant past rather than present processes,

    and reflecting and promoting certain western-elite cultural conceptions and values.

    Moreover, Smith argues, heritage sites or objects have, through this dominant and

    materially focused discourse, been attributed an inherent valueor significance. The

    material object or site has . . . come to stand in for the social and cultural values it

    symbolizes and hence the authorized conception is that . . . heritage is the monu-

    ment, archaeological site or other material thing or place, rather than cultural

    values or meanings (Waterton and Smith, 2009b: 14, original emphasis). As aconsequence, heritage has commonly been understood from the perspective of

    shortage or loss: a scarce and non-renewable resource (for criticism of this see

    e.g. Brattli, 2006, 2009), the authenticity and sustainability of which has to be

    secured through management, legal protection and conservation.

    34 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    6/24

    Arguing against this tradition, Smith . . . starts from the premise that all heri-

    tage is intangible (2006: 3). She underlines that this is not to dismiss the tangible

    aspect of heritage but rather to refute its natural presumption; while tangible

    objects or sites may be identified as heritage, they . . .

    are not inherently valuable,

    nor do they carry a freight of innate meaning. Stonehenge, for instance, is basically

    a collection of rocks in a field (Smith, 2006: 3, original emphasis; see Solli, 2011,

    for criticism). Heritage should rather be understood as a mentality, an experience,

    or an act of remembering that engages with the present, and where . . . the sites

    themselves arecultural tools that can facilitate, but are not necessarily vitalfor, this

    process (Smith, 2006: 44, my emphasis). In other words, heritage is a process where

    things or sites may be engaged in the representation or manifestation of amorphous

    social values, but are themselves by no means imperative to that process.

    Therefore, as Smith (2006) proclaims, all heritage can be claimed to be intangible.UNESCOs adoption of the Convention for the Safeguarding of Intangible

    Cultural Heritage in 2003 was a response to criticism of this nature.2 UNESCOs

    universal definition of heritage and heritage value was accused of privileging west-

    ern, and predominantly material, conceptions of heritage while excluding other,

    non-western and often intangible, conceptions. In the 2003 convention, intangible

    cultural heritage is thus defined as . . . the practices, representations, expressions,

    knowledge, skills as well as the instruments, objects, artefacts and cultural spaces

    associated therewith that communities, groups and, in some cases, individuals

    recognize as part of their cultural heritage (UNESCO, 2003). This intangible heri-tage is, furthermore, described as manifested in, for example, language or other

    oral tradition, craftsmanship, rituals and other social practices that provide groups

    of people with a sense of identity and belonging (UNESCO, 2003).

    The convention does not, therefore, counterpose intangible to tangible heritage,

    but underlines the interdependence of the two (see e.g. Bouchenaki, 2003) that

    valuing or safeguarding one will come with and urge the appreciation of the other.

    Nevertheless, as described above, the intangible heritage discourse tends to imply a

    hierarchy in the sense that meaning is inevitably seen as subjective and humanly

    derived. It thus involves an underlying conception of anthropocentrism, whichreflects limited, if any, concern for the qualities, significance or affordances of

    things themselves in their construction as heritage.

    The introduction of intangible heritage has also been legitimized or rationalized

    as a means to negotiate and level supposed asymmetrical power relations on the

    heritage arena, reducing the authority of top-down policies and increasing the

    influence of various interest groups and local populations. Moreover, it is, accord-

    ing to Smith and Waterton (2009a), not least the privileged position of archaeology

    within the AHD and heritage policy development that roots the material bias in

    dominant heritage conceptions. Because of their own interests, archaeologists tendto promote and protect what they see as their own database, which in effect has

    sustained a material understanding of heritage. In their edited volume with the

    telling titleTaking Archaeology out of Heritage, Waterton and Smith (2009a) there-

    fore suggest that archaeology is (experimentally) removed from heritage

    Petursdottir 35

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    7/24

    conceptions, in order to de-emphasize materiality and give room to other possible

    understandings (Smith and Waterton, 2009a: 2).

    Archaeology is of course the discipline of things. It is therefore not surprising

    that archaeology became the scapegoat for advocates of a fundamentally intangible

    heritage definition. This critique, however, appears less reasonable when seen in the

    light of the development within archaeology and archaeological theory through the

    1980s and 1990s, when focus was on subjective and intangible values, ideological

    and symbolic meanings, and where the things themselves were often reduced to

    tools in social interaction. Moreover, archaeological data, fragmented, incomplete

    and sparse as it often is, is not by definition welcomed as heritage. Heritage has its

    own regime of cultural valuing and othering and leaves a large portion of the

    archaeological record by the wayside (cf. Watson, 2009: 45). It should therefore

    not be entirely baffling, nor without reason, that archaeologists endeavor to pro-mote their largely undesired heritage, if not for other purposes than to challenge

    normative heritage conceptions of the grand or aesthetically pleasing. Moreover, as

    a discipline located in between the opposed divides of the modern regime a

    discipline that embraces human-thing and material-culture relations archaeology

    is in a unique position to address the relation/opposition between tangible and

    intangible heritage, not only in discourse but also by exposing the common

    grounds underneath this very rupture/relation (cf. Webmoor and Witmore, 2008).

    The material bias and the source of heritage value

    Leafing through heritage conventions, policies and legislations, there is truly an

    emphasis on the physical or tangible aspect of heritage. UNESCOs Convention

    Concerning the Protection of the World Cultural and Natural Heritage (1972) defines

    cultural heritage asmonuments,groups of buildings and sites. The current Icelandic

    law on national heritage is more or less concurrent with this, stressing the protec-

    tion of sites, structures and artefacts of culture-historical significance (Lo g um

    menningarminjar, 2013[2012]). However, if we look at the rationale for the man-

    agement and protection of this tangible heritage, globally or nationally, it is clearthat concern does not generally lie with materiality or the things themselves.

    Despite claims of the opposite, the source of value in this traditional heritage

    discourse, just like in the intangible heritage discourse, is rarely found within

    things or sites but is based on human perception, experience and attachment,

    and percolated through conceptions of history, identity and sense of belonging.

    The same intangible focus is in fact apparent in the general archaeological codes of

    ethics, such as those implemented by the Society for American Archaeology, the

    World Archaeological Congress and the European Association of Archaeologists,

    where emphasis is consistently on cultural heritage as a concern for people, for theirrights to a history and identity (Hamilakis, 2007; Scarre and Scarre, 2006), and

    more generally as a scientific, socio-political or economic resource. None of the

    codes, and hardly any of the academic texts concerning ethics in archaeology,

    articulate this responsibility as an ethical concern in relation to the things

    36 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    8/24

    themselves they are simply the means or cultural tools (cf. Smith, 2006: 44)

    employed to reach a moral end.

    Hence, while sympathizing with the critique that initially led to the introduction

    of intangible heritage, I question the novelty, and the gain, of the assertion that all

    heritage is intangible. It hardly accounts for a paradigm shift in conceptions of

    heritage value, but rather makes explicit, and reinforces, what has always been the

    underlying, yet rarely specifically uttered, rationale of heritage discourses: that,

    although there may at times be room for a relational value where value may

    spring from the encounter of mind and matter sole things, qua things, have never

    really been considered the sources of this value. It might rather be claimed that

    heritage definitions generally suffer from being under-materialized, reducing things

    to epiphenomena of supposedly intangible cultural and social processes.

    To recall UNESCOs definition of heritage, it is . . .

    our legacy from the past,what we live with today, and what we pass onto future generations (my emphasis).

    While a rather acceptable definition, the rarely considered reality is that things or

    heritage is passed on to the future whether welike it or not, whether we manage it

    or not. Moreover, despite that things life expectancy and maturity with age varies

    greatly, their aging is nevertheless characterized by a certain egalitarianism; that is,

    due to their material persistency there is survival also of the unwanted, outmoded

    or discarded (Olsen, 2010: 166167). The undesired debris of the past, thus, is

    continuously accumulating around us (Lowenthal, 1998: xvi), and the majority

    of it will, furthermore, remain just that spoils of history.The category of heritage cannot, it may be argued, proliferate infinitely.

    However, such commonsense rationale may conceal the effective regimes of valuing

    involved and the fact that some things simply do not fulfil the requirements needed

    for such a promotion. Despite claims of the opposite, it has really never been

    enough for things or sites to simply be in order to become regarded as heritage,

    and this is especially true for ruins of the modern. Things have to be in a very

    specific way; in fact, badheritage comes close to a conceptual contradiction. The

    heritage ruin is preferably pleasing and attractive, carefully selected to suit our

    needs and expectations. Properly old, ready-ruined, sanitary and trouble-free, itprovides visitors with a disciplined and purified space without extraneous mater-

    ials, plants, fauna, debris and modern intrusions (Edensor, 2005a, 2005b).

    Seemingly frozen in time, further decay is staved off through restoration and pres-

    ervation, since the urge to arrest decay, of course, has always been the imperative of

    modern museums and heritage management.

    If we look at the rationale behind this specific heritage management of things it is

    again questionable whether it really is the things or sites themselves, and their mater-

    ial integrity or thingness, that is being cared for. Or is it rather so that they are kept

    in a manner presentable to us, for us, and our own well being? Here I agree withSmith that, as it is generally understood, . . . heritage is heritage because it is sub-

    jected to the management and preservation/conservation process, not because it

    simply is (2006: 3). In other words, promotion to heritage is a constitutive process

    where things are made into heritage (Smith, 2006; see also Carman, 2010) rather than

    Petursdottir 37

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    9/24

    preserved as such. Unlike Smith and others, however, I cannot see this conservation

    ethics as a sign of a general material fervour or a physically founded value concep-

    tion. Rather, I see it as a sign of a very specific material intolerance, one quite obvi-

    ously based on specific aesthetical values for example, as expressed in the urge to

    separate heritage from waste, and proper ruins from mere spoils of history.

    Histories of significance and spoils of history a case from

    the Icelandic herring saga

    The two herring factories in the Strandir region, on the east coast of the Westfjord

    peninsula, are only two examples of a common phenomenon in Icelandic land-

    scapes modern3 ruins, including derelict industrial ventures, deserted farms and

    half abandoned rural settlements. The twentieth century as the age of extremes(Hobsbawm, 1994) may serve as a trope when describing the Icelandic context,

    where social and economic conditions were radically and rapidly transformed

    during the course of the century. This transformation is evident in the patterns

    of settlement and the increasingly sharp contrast between the urbanized capital

    area and the rural rest. Today 90 per cent of the countrys population of 320,000

    live in towns or villages, and 60 per cent live in the Reykjavk (capital) area alone.

    In 1910, however, 85 per cent of the population lived in rural districts, on farms

    mainly, while only 15 per cent resided in Reykjavk (Snvarr, 1993: 118121;

    Statistics Iceland, n.d.). Most people, moreover, lived in traditional turf andstone houses, constituting 52 per cent of all buildings in the country at the time,

    and still amounting to 27 per cent in 1930 (Kjartansson, 2002: 202).

    Obviously, many factors made possible this swift development, but an important

    trigger was the herring adventure and the rapid development of industrialized

    fishing in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries (Jo nsson, 1980, 2004;

    Sigursson et al., 2007). Growing exploitation of the abundant maritime resources

    now triggered an increase in urbanization and the establishment of several landing

    and processing stations along the coast (see Ragnarsson, 2007). Some of these were

    satellite settlements located in remote and previously sparsely or unsettled areaswhere proximity to the resource was a first priority. Hence, places previously mar-

    ginal and out of reach suddenly became centres in complex economic networks of

    production. With time some of these communities grew strong, while others awaited

    a more gloomy fate. Due to technological advancement in terms of transport, pro-

    cessing and preservation, their strategic, marginal location was no longer essential

    and even proved economically unfeasible. Furthermore, although debated, years of

    excessive exploitation did most likely also decimate the herring stock (Karlsdo ttir,

    2005), causing seasons of catch failure. As the herring dissapeared, so the economic

    basis of many small and newly established communities was impaired.Two such settlements, which came and went with the herring, are the two sites in

    Strandir region referred to in the recollection at the beginning of this article:

    Djupavk in Reykjafjo rur and Eyri in Ingo lfsfjo rur (Figure 2). The factory in

    Djupavk, completed in 1935, was at the time the largest concrete building in the

    38 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    10/24

    country, equipped with the most advanced and up-to-date machinery of the day and,

    according to some, the most advanced in all of Europe (Matthasson, 1973). In the

    years that followed, Djupavk became a place filled with life and a focal point in a

    prosperous industrial network. Along with the growing industry, the small commu-

    nity also expanded houses were built, along with other dwellings, a shop, a bakery,

    piers and so on (Jo hannesson, 2001; Matthasson, 1973). A similar development

    took place at Eyri, with the construction of a competing large scale and highly

    mechanized herring factory in 1944 (Figure 3). As in Djupavk, this industrial enter-

    prise initiated the formation of a small, and partly seasonal, community at the site,

    with dwellings, offices, garages, a shop, a bakery and so on (Jo hannesson, 2001;

    Matthasson, 1973). During the 1940s and early 1950s the herring stock diminished

    considerably along the Westfjord peninsula and the reason for the two industrial

    powers in Strandir was gradually eradicated. After a short working life, the enginesat Eyri and Djupavk were, thus, finally silenced in 1952 and 1954 respectively

    (Jo hannesson, 2001; Matthasson, 1973). When abandoned, the factories, engines,

    dwellings, shops, bakeries, beds, chairs, food supplies and spare parts were left

    behind, in hope of return (Figure 4) a wish, however, never fulfilled. Once again,

    these sites were rendered peripheral and out of reach.

    Today, 60 years after their official abandonment, the deserted herring stations

    seem completely at odds with both official and general understandings of cultural

    heritage. Unlike the traditional romanticized ruin that so effortlessly acquires our

    Figure 2. Location of the two herring factories in Djupavk and Eyri, Strandir region on the

    Westfjord peninsula (Map: Oscar Aldred).

    Petursdottir 39

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    11/24

    appreciation, these modern concrete installations stand in sharp contrast to the

    peripheral landscapes in which they obtrude in as well as to our preferred percep-

    tion of those landscapes as pristine, natural landscapes beyond anything but

    authentic, traditional human impact (Figure 3). And, despite literally materializ-

    ing what is believed to have brought modernism to the shores of this island, the

    uncanny remains of the deserted herring stations now contradict our general

    Figure 3. Industrial ruins in pristine landscapes: Eyri herring factory, seen from the west with

    the towering mountains behind it (Photo: ora Petursdottir).

    Figure 4. Abandoned figurines: oil centrifuging machines in the engine hall, Eyri (Photo:

    Bjrnar Olsen).

    40 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    12/24

    conception of modernity (Latour, 1993) they have become matter out of place

    and order. Left mostly, or partly in the case of Djupavk, to non-human inter-

    actions and preferences, the sites have developed disturbing mixtures and combin-

    ations (Figure 5). Walls and concrete have decomposed; nature has intruded,

    mingled and reclaimed. The previous clear distinction between the man-made

    and the natural surroundings has evaporated as material debris disperses into

    the surrounding landscape while nature trespasses the concrete boundaries of the

    sites, creating . . . manifestations of threatening otherness in a [yet] familiar

    space . . . (Edensor, 2005b: 313).

    Icelandic heritage law defines (and automatically protects) archaeological heri-

    tage as well as houses and standing structures over 100 years old (Lo g um men-

    ningarminjar, 2013[2012])4 while later remains may be specially protected.

    Although this is rather unusual and liberal in European terms, the concern withrelatively recent heritage has been motivated primarily in order to protect and

    conserve surviving expressions of traditional culture. As mentioned earlier, the

    majority of vernacular architecture in Iceland remained turf and/or stone structures

    until as late as 1920 (Kjartansson, 2002: 202) and emphasis has been on protecting

    this category of late traditional style housing. Thus, the reason for this somewhat

    peculiar age criterion can be seen as a means to discriminate between traditional/

    authentic and modern remains, between heritage and waste.

    In other words, the many modern ruins littering Icelandic landscapes generally

    lack special protection and thus an official declaration of cultural or heritage value.

    Figure 5. Things entangled: floor deposit in the female workers dormitory, Eyri (Photo: ora

    Petursdottir).

    Petursdottir 41

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    13/24

    Curiously, though, through the rapid growth of tourism during recent decades,

    modern ruins, like the herring factories in Djupavk and Eyri, seem to have become

    somewhat popular destinations among travelers seeking to move beyond the con-

    ventional tourist routes and onto the dusty sideways adding a hint of irony to

    their neglected state. In the case of Djupavk, this lure of the ruin has also been

    taken advantage of, as described at the beginning of this article. However, since this

    has involved interference, although on a very small scale, with the factorys ruinous

    state, it has stirred skeptical and sometimes hostile reactions among some of its

    admirers reactions that provoke thoughts on the value of these concrete ruins.

    Of course, people may have different ideas about their value; they may see the

    factories as sites of remembrance, as monuments to workers life and struggles, as

    testimonies to a century of capitalist-driven politics, or just as symbols of a time

    gone by all of which could correspond to a conventional conception of heritagevalue. However, before suggesting that modern ruins, like Icelands crumbling

    herring factories, are incorporated into a category of heritage and thus enrolled

    in conventional heritage management processes, it is maybe worth asking whether

    something of their character, something of their lure and value, might be lost in

    that process. In other words, maybe we should also consider the possibility that the

    ruins themselves, in their dynamic state of being, may be the source of their own

    value and significance.

    Letting things be: Heritage beyond anthropocentrism

    They have destroyed the factory!, the photographer announced in my recollection

    at the beginning of this article. Truly an interesting opinion considering the general

    state of the factory, both before and after this very limited amendment to its

    genuinely disintegrating appearance. And no less, when considering the intent of

    the hotel managers and owners; in their mind, this was of course one step towards

    preventing its destruction. Out of concern for the factory itself and its conservation

    but mostly because of its historical significance for present and future visitors

    mending and maintaining this concrete carcass, and painting it white, was to themthe way to honour its legacy and preserve its value. These are quite clearly two very

    different perceptions of the site and its value. On the one hand it is believed to

    reside in the past, in the sites history and former glory, and is thus best secured by

    preventing decay and maintaining a clear link to its former use value. On the other

    hand the site is valued in its present state, in decay, which importantly, however,

    does not contest an acknowledgement of its historical value. Whereas the former

    stance resembles the conventional conception of what heritage is all about, saving

    things from loss, the latter seems to reflect the opposite, an attitude where value

    also resides in the ruin itself, in its concrete presence and the fact that it is notarrested but dynamic, confusing and constantly becoming. An attitude where ruin-

    ation, or a things natural aging (Van de Wetering, 1996), is not seen as the

    incarnation of loss but as a generative process that is part of its messy biography

    (Ouzman, 2006).

    42 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    14/24

    But valuing ruination and decay how is that heritage management? And how

    can that possibly tone with the current ethics of heritage and conservation? Well,

    the answer is simple: it does not. While heritage scholars have repeatedly encour-

    aged an understanding of heritage as process, that conception has never included

    the tangible aspect of heritage. The traditional idea is that as things or sites become

    heritage they should, by means of management and conservation, be rescued from

    any material processes natural to them and turned into frozen facts, into stable

    points of departure around which processes of intangible value prescription may

    evolve. In other words, things are made manageable restrained, controlled and

    kept from revealing themselves to us in their true being.

    But maybe there is room for a different kind of heritage conception, one that is

    open to the life of things, materiality as dynamic, and thus also to the tangible

    forces involved in any intangible process of heritageisation (Harvey, 2001). Aheritage conception that might, at times, see an ethical stance involved in letting

    things be, as Lucas Introna (2009) puts it with reference to Heideggers (1966)

    concept of Gelassenheit or releasement. Not a conventional ethical stance, but

    one extended to things themselves,5 where we might consider the possibility of

    granting things certain rights, as suggested by Ouzman (2006: 275). Not only

    rights to be managed, conserved or curated (2006: 275), which in essence may

    have more to do with our well-being than that of things, but a right also to be

    released from the drudgery of such human utilitarian relations without that

    rendering them value- or meaningless. And, is it not possible that valuing ruinsas ruins, or occasionally presenting museum objects in their decay, might add to

    our understanding of things, their temporality and being (Ouzman, 2006: 270)?

    In relation to his discussion of the concept of Gelassenheit, or releasement,

    Heidegger distinguishes between calculative and meditative thinking (1966: 46),

    where the former is a way of wilful thinking that already expects an outcome,

    whereas the latter is released from the chains of prospects, or willing, and instead

    awaits that which may come towards it (1966: 47). In other words, it is an aware-

    ness, an attitude, that is open to the mystery of its surrounding, and thus open to

    the possibility of releasement. Rather than a distinct phenomenon, Gelassenheitshould therefore be understood as a process, an experience or a movement towards

    the unexpected, the thing itself in its native mysterious being a releasement

    towards things (1966: 54). Importantly, this Gelassenheit, to let be, is not a sug-

    gestion of a passive or indifferent attitude but rather an active but non-intrusive

    acceptance of things in their remote otherness. It is a different way of valuing the

    world, thus, that does not precondition its management or domestication.

    The ethics of heritage, the ethics of conservation, have never really been an

    ethics of things or materiality. Of course, modern ethical discourse is traditionally

    founded on a clear ontological distinction between nature and culture, betweennatural laws and social contracts (Poole, 1991), between people and things. And the

    drive of modern ethics is to secure the integrity of the subject, to defend it by all

    means possible from the fate of objectification; ethics, thus, is traditionally about

    people and not things, and the ethics of heritage are no different. To extend ethics

    Petursdottir 43

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    15/24

    to things may therefore in a conventional understanding imply the humanist

    impossibility of equating people with things. This, however, is not the case. It is

    not a claim to do away with the differencebetween people and things, but rather a

    plea for a middle ground where it is possible to appreciate both in their difference;

    where the valuation of things does not have to take place through their domesti-

    cation or the abolition of their thingness by transforming them into humanized

    things but is possible also through an appreciation of things in their otherness, for

    example in ruination.

    As already noted, bad heritage comes close to a conceptual contradiction and

    discussing the rights of things not only raises questions of how to value things in

    ruins but also the question of bad things, and whether or not we should extend

    such ethical concerns to technologies of terror, polluted industrial wastelands or

    memorials of drained natural resources indeed, to ruins of modernity. Ethics,however, are not necessarily about good, bad or evil, because the ethical measure is

    not . . . an abstract principle or value, but reality itself, its concreteness, the gravity

    of things (Benso, 1996: 134). The moral move is rather to take things seriously. An

    ethics extended to things is moreover significant on two levels: firstly, in terms of

    acknowledging things own affordances and their right to be, which also includes

    the right to be released from us, our management and conceptualization, without

    that rendering them devoid of meaning or value. Things may of course embody or

    symbolize, but in the end it is the thing itself that presents; it . . . stands in the

    relationship of immediacy, not of mediation (Armstrong, 1971: 26, my emphasis)and its ultimate frame of reference is its concrete presence the thing itself. This

    presence-effect (Gumbrecht, 2004) is thus not restricted to our conception or

    interpretation, but is inherent to the thing itself and its (alter)native and dynamic

    being its thingness. It is a meaningful presence that is prior to logic and concep-

    tualization and is therefore not necessarily salvaged through our interference or

    management, but may in fact be drained or lost in that very process.

    Secondly, an ethics extended to things is significant in terms of acknowledging

    the moral obligations that come with things rights. As relational entities, in a

    society of monsters (Law, 1991), things are never innocent beings, they arenever just there as simple means towards our ends. In our society of hybrids we

    constantly enrol things and charge them with our values and meanings to give them

    substance, weight and durability. These inscriptions are successful because things

    outlive us, and . . . those that encounter and use these inscribed things may become,

    wittingly or unwittingly, enrolled into particular programmes, or scripts for action

    (Introna, 2009: 400401). Things should, therefore, rather be thought of as polit-

    ical locations (Introna, 2009), charged with values, that may be negotiated or even

    ignored, but are also, because of their thingly qualities, their weight and durability,

    somewhat involuntarily re-membered into ever new presents and ever new contexts.We need to be aware of this power of things. That is, we should not rule out the

    possibility that sometimes . . . we find what was meant to be found . . . (Gonza lez-

    Ruibal, 2011: 63), that Stonehenge isnt simply any collection of rocks, that some

    things actuallyare heritage or at least through their physiognomic difference and

    44 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    16/24

  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    17/24

  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    18/24

    Interpretation in archaeology has almost without exception been driven by the

    inclination to dig deeper, as the immediate, what meets the eye, is not enough; it is a

    mere material expression of the more important and genuine social and symbolic

    meanings that reside behind it. This also relates, and not without a certain irony, to

    Laurajane Smiths claim that all heritage is intangible, that Stonhenge is meaning-

    less and devoid of value unless contextualized through contemporary social pro-

    cesses. Conversely though, it is not her statement that Stonehenge . . . is basically a

    collection of rocks in a field (2006: 3) that is problematic; that is in fact exactly

    what Stonehenge is. The problem, however, is to see that as meaningless. What

    characterizes the intangible heritage discourse (or even heritage discourses in gen-

    eral), as well as much of interpretive archaeology, is not only that meaning, value

    and significance are seen as inevitably subjective, but also that meaning is confused

    with or restricted, rather, to symbolical or other modes of derivative meanings(Olsen, 2012: 223) that meaning beyond intellectualization is always meaningless.

    But is it so that Stonehenge itself, in its simple stoniness (Solli, 2011), brings

    nothing of value to the encounters with the subjective experiences that for centuries

    have circulated around it?

    Of course things may be contextualized and made meaningful in all kinds of

    ways. Importantly, however, the ruins themselves should not be seen as simple

    cultural tools or symbols in that process but also as sources of value and signifi-

    cance. They are actively part of the process through their affecting presence, in the

    form of an immediacy that cannot be reduced to mediation or transmission(Armstrong, 1971: 26). Therefore we should also be aware of the possibility that

    a heritage domestication or normalization may quite literally drain things of their

    meaning subjecting them to sameness, to frozen and manicured heritage, easily

    brings their own critical antiphonal voices to silence. Caring for and respecting the

    integrity of things may occasionally, as in the case of the whitewashed factory, also

    be to let things be in difference, in their otherness, without that being regarded as

    an attitude of indifference. It is possible that our recent persistent efforts to make

    our silent objects speak in order to make them meaningful have made us forget

    the simple fact that they actually dont. And without at all denying the significanceof materially conveyed meanings, an ethics extended to things may in its simplest

    form be described as an effort to occasionally respect and acknowledge their silence

    (Figure 6). That is, to bestow things with one simple right, the most basic of all: the

    right to remain silent.

    The modern regime has the tendency to tidily organize our messy being

    into sealed and binary ontological compartments, and heritage definitions are of

    course examples of such purifying means, enabling us safely to separate the wanted

    (heritage) from the unwanted (waste) (see e.g. Burstro m, 2009). In this neatly

    organized scheme of dualities the prime divide is between the world of intentionaland thinking subjects on one side and a naturally given object-world of mute things

    and non-humans on the other (Latour, 1993). The latter world has no meaningful

    existence in itself, but awaits passively its symbolic or metaphoric incarnation

    (Ingold, 2000). In this anthropocentric regime of subjective interpretation the

    Petursdottir 47

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    19/24

    silence of things, their pre-discursive materiality, is at the same time meaningless

    and disturbing; it is an empty otherness that must be infused with meaning and

    value through contextualization and embodiment (cf. Benjamin, 1999). A similar

    imperative characterizes dominant modes of historical narration, molding the past

    as linear, progressive and continuous an order our fragmented material reality,

    past or present, has never amounted to. The ruins of the past, the archaeological

    record our material heritage is incomplete, fragmented, discontinuous and

    silent. But rather than seeing that merely as a problem to be solved by filling in

    the gaps and healing the material pastas history, we might occasionally also try out

    the option to let things be fragmented and incomplete, to allow them to remain

    partly mysterious, and instead allow this otherness to affect the stories we tell (see

    Pe tursdo ttir, 2012). After all, . . . silence is perhaps one of the most important

    constituents of any story the length, frequency, and quality of pauses can buildsuspense, deliver a de nouement, or show a necessary fallibility in the teller, the

    inevitable fragmentation of a narrative thread over time (Ouzman, 2006: 291).

    There may therefore even be a historical significance, an evolving historical

    lesson, involved in valuing things by letting them be in their material otherness.

    It is about time, as suggested by heritage critiques, that we democratize heritage.

    It is a fallacy, however, to think that this is best achieved by excluding things or

    materiality from such ambitions, which, effectively, is the outcome of a general

    intangible heritage conception. Such a conception undermines the role things play

    in heritage processes, and thus supports and strengthens further their traditionallyambiguous state within heritage definitions and management. The ruins of

    Djupavk and Eyri are good examples of this ambiguity, while at the same time

    they can be said to utter their own critique of conventional heritage conceptions.

    Through their very presence, and the presence-effects (Gumbrecht, 2004) they

    provoke, they urge us to critically consider the significance of the concrete and

    Figure 6. Utter silence: the concrete pillars inside the herring oil tank in Dju pavk reflecting

    in the still water that covers the floor (Photo: ora Petursdottir).

    48 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    20/24

    tangible in relation to heritage value, to reflect on the discrimination involved in

    our management of things and on the possibility of a different kind of heritage a

    heritage where ruination, decay and the material being of things are not always

    regarded as negative but may be thought of as a generative process of becoming. A

    process, even, ofbecoming heritage.

    Heritage is a process: dynamic and negotiated, tangible and intangible. It is

    about time, in that process, we also acknowledge and value the things called heri-

    tage as the things that they are.

    Acknowledgements

    Many have commented on this article, or parts of it, at earlier stages. I especially thank my

    supervisor, Bjrnar Olsen, for his most helpful comments and fruitful discussions. I also

    thank my co-supervisor, Gavin Lucas, and other members of the Ruin Memories group, for

    valuable input. A version of this article was presented at Stanford University in March 2012.

    I would like to express my gratitude to Lynn Meskell for allowing me that opportunity, and

    I thank her, Michael Shanks and others at the Stanford Archaeology Centre for welcoming

    me to their facilities during the 2012 spring semester, where this paper grew into its final

    form.

    Notes

    1. See e.g. Appadurai, 1986; Bennett, 2010; Brown, 2001, 2003; Gell, 1998; Graves-Brown,

    2000; Hodder, 2011; Hoskins, 1998; Ingold, 2000; Latour, 1993, 2005; Meskell, 2004,2005; Miller, 1987, 2005; Olsen, 2003, 2010; Preda, 1999; Tilley, 1994, 2004.

    2. For the development from tangible to intangible heritage see e.g. Bortolotto, 2007;

    Kirshenblatt-Gimblett, 2004; Munjeri, 2004; Ruggles and Silverman, 2009; Smith,

    2006; Smith and Akagawa, 2009; and for its limitations see Ahmad, 2006.

    3. Modern in this context refers to the twentieth century. Although an ambiguous concept,

    and in the Icelandic context no less so, I here relate it to the industrialized Iceland, which

    is a reality no earlier than the late nineteenth and early twentieth century (Jo nsson, 2004).

    4. This new law replaced the older law from 2001 (Lo g um husafriun, 2001; jo minjalo g,

    2001) on 1 January 2013.

    5. See Benso, 1996, 2000; Introna, 2009; Olsen, 2012.

    References

    Ahmad Y (2006) The scope and definitions of heritage: From tangible to intangible.

    International Journal of Heritage Studies 12(3): 292300.

    Andreassen E, Bjerck H and Olsen B (2010) Persistent Memories. Trondheim: Tapir

    Akademisk Forlag.

    Appadurai A (1986) The Social Life of Things: Commodities in Cultural Perspective.

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Armstrong RP (1971) The Affecting Presence: An Essay in Humanistic Anthropology.

    Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Benjamin W (1999) The Arcades Project. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Bennett J (2010) Vibrant Matter: A Political Economy of Things. Durham, NC: Duke

    University Press.

    Petursdottir 49

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    21/24

    Benso S (1996) Of things face-to-face. With Levinas face-to-face with Heidegger:

    Prolegomena to a metaphysical ethics of things. Philosophy Today 40(1): 132141.

    Benso S (2000) The Face of Things: A Different Side of Ethics . Albany: State University of

    New York Press.Bouchenaki M (2003) The interdependency of the tangible and intangible cultural heritage.

    Keynote address, 14th ICOMOS General Assembly and International Symposium: Place,

    Memory, Meaning: Preserving Intangible Values in Monuments and Sites, 2731 October,

    Victoria Falls, Zimbabwe. Available at: http://openarchive.icomos.org/468/1/2_-

    _Allocution_Bouchenaki.pdf (accessed November 2011).

    Bortolotto C (2007) From objects to processes: UNESCOs intangible cultural heritage.

    Journal of Museum Ethnography 19: 2133.

    Brattli T (2006) Fortid og forvaltning. En analyse av norsk kulturminneforvaltning i peri-

    oden 19902005, med hovedvekt pa arkeologiske forhold [Past and management. An

    analysis of Norwegian cultural resource management in the period 1990-2005, with par-ticular focus on archaeological aspects]. Doktorgradsavhandlinger ved NTNU 32.

    Trondheim.

    Brattli T (2009) Managing the archaeological world cultural heritage: Consensus or rhetoric?

    Norwegian Archaeological Review 42(1): 2439.

    Brown B (2001) Thing theory. Critical Inquiry 28(1): 122.

    Brown B (2003) A Sense of Things: The Object Matter of American Literature. Chicago, IL:

    University of Chicago Press.

    Burstro m M (2009) Garbage or heritage: The existential dimension of a car cemetery.

    In: Holtorf C and Piccini A (eds) Contemporary Archaeologies: Excavating Now.

    Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, pp. 131143.Carman J (2010) Promotion to heritage: How museum objects are made. In: Pettersson S,

    Hagedorn-Saupe M, Jyrkkio T and Weij A (eds) Encouraging Collections Mobility A

    Way Forward for Museums in Europe. Helsinki: Finnish National Gallery, pp. 7485.

    DeSilvey C (2006) Observed decay: Telling stories with mutable things. Journal of Material

    Culture11(3): 318338.

    Edensor T (2005a) Industrial Ruins. Space, Aesthetics and Materiality. Oxford: Berg.

    Edensor T (2005b) Waste matter the debris of industrial ruins and the disordering of the

    material world. Journal of Material Culture 10: 311332.

    Fririksson A (1994)Sagas and Popular Antiquarianism in Icelandic Archaeology. Aldershot:

    Avebury.Gell A (1998)Art and Agency: An Anthropological Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Gonza lez-Ruibal A (2011) Naturalizing the Anthropocene? Ideology, heritage and modern-

    ity [Comments on Brit Solli: Some Reflections on Heritage and Archaeology in the

    Anthropocene]. Norwegian Archaeological Review 44(1): 6264.

    Graves-Brown PM (2000) Matter, Materiality and Modern Culture. London: Routledge.

    Gumbrecht HU (2004) Production of Presence: What Meaning Cannot Convey. Stanford,

    CA: Stanford University Press.

    Hamilakis Y (2007) From ethics to politics. In: Hamilakis Y and Duke P (eds) Archaeology

    and Capitalism: From Ethics to Politics. Walnut Creek, CA: Left Coast Press, pp. 1540.

    Harvey DC (2001) Heritage pasts and heritage presents: Temporality, meaning and thescope of heritage studies. International Journal of Heritage Studies 7(4): 319338.

    Heidegger M (1966) Discourse on Thinking. New York: Harper & Row.

    Heidegger M (1977) Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings. Farell Krell D (ed. and trans.). San

    Francisco, CA: Harper Collins.

    50 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    22/24

    Hobsbawm E (1994) The Age of Extremes: A History of the World, 19141991. New York:

    Vintage Books.

    Hodder I (2011) Human-thing entanglement: Towards an integrated archaeological perspec-

    tive. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 17: 154177.Hoskins J (1998) Biographical Objects: How Things Tell the Stories of Peoples Lives. New

    York: Routledge.

    Ingold T (2000) The Perception of the Environment: Essays in Livelihood, Dwelling and Skill.

    London: Routledge.

    Ingold T (2007) Materials against materiality. Archaeological Dialogues 14: 116.

    Introna LD (2009) Ethics and the speaking of things. Theory, Culture & Society 26(4):

    398419.

    Jo hannesson H (2001) Stundir a Strondum: Fra Kolbeinsv k norur a Geirholm [Time in

    Strandir: From Kolbeinsvk to Geirho lmur]. Reykjavk: Ferafe lag I slands.

    Jo nsson S (1980) The Development of the Icelandic Fishing Industry, 19001940, and itsRegional Implications. Unpublished PhD thesis, University of Newcastle upon Tyne, UK.

    Jo nsson G (2004) The transformation of the Icelandic economy: Industrialisation and eco-

    nomic growth 18701950. In: Heikkinen S and Van Zanden JL (eds) Exploring Economic

    Growth: Essays in Measurement and Analysis. Amsterdam: Academic, pp. 131166.

    Karlsdo ttir H (2005) Fishing on Common Grounds: The Consequences of Unregulated

    Fisheries of North Sea Herring in the Postwar Period. Doctoral dissertation,

    Department of Economic History, Go teborg University. Publications of the

    Department of Economic History, School of Economic and Commercial Law,

    Go teborg University, no. 94.

    Kirshenblatt-Gimblett B (2004) Intangible heritage as metacultural production. MuseumInternational56: 5265.

    Kjartansson HS (2002) Island a20. old[Iceland in the 20th century]. Reykjavk: So gufe lag.

    Latour B (1993) We Have Never Been Modern. London: Harvard University Press.

    Latour B (2005)Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxford:

    Oxford University Press.

    Law J (1991) The Sociology of Monsters: Essays on Power, Technology and Domination.

    London: Routledge.

    Lowenthal D (1998)The Heritage Crusade and the Spoils of History. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Lucas G (2004) Modern disturbances: On the ambiguities of archaeology. Modernism/mod-ernity11(1): 109120.

    Lucas G and Snsdo ttir M (2006) Archaeologies of modernity in the land of the Sagas.

    Meta 3: 518.

    Lo g um husafriun [Law concerning the protection of houses] (2001) Nr. 104/2001,

    Lagasafn. I slensk lo g 1. okto ber 2009. U tga fa 137. Available at: http://www.althingi.is/

    lagas/137/2001104.html (accessed March 2012).

    Lo g um menningarminjar [Law concerning cultural remains] (2013[2012]) ingskjal 1610.

    Available at: http://www.althingi.is/altext/140/s/1610.html (accessed June 2012).

    Matthasson (1973) Hrundar borgir: Djupav k, Ingolfsfjorur og Gjogur [Fallen cities:

    Djupavk, Ingo lfsfjo rur and Gjo gur]. Reykjavk: Bo kamistoin.Meskell L (2004) Object Worlds in Ancient Egypt: Material Biographies Past and Present.

    Oxford: Berg.

    Meskell L (ed.) (2005) Archaeologies of Materiality. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Petursdottir 51

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    23/24

    Miller D (1987) Material Culture and Mass Consumption. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Miller D (ed.) (2005) Materiality. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Munjeri D (2004) Tangible and intangible heritage: From difference to convergence.

    Museum International56: 1220.Olivier L (2011) The Dark Abyss of Time: Archaeology and Memory. Trans. Greenspan A.

    Lanham, MD: Alta Mira Press.

    Olsen B (2003) Material culture after text: Re-membering things. Norwegian Archaeological

    Review 36(2): 87104.

    Olsen B (2010) In Defense of Things: Archaeology and the Ontology of Objects . Lanham,

    MD: AltaMira Press.

    Olsen B (2012) Symmetrical archaeology. In: Hodder I (ed.) Archaeological Theory Today.

    Cambridge: Polity Press, pp. 208228.

    Ouzman S (2006) The beauty of letting go: Fragmentary museums and archaeologies of

    archive. In: Gosden C, Edwards W and Phillips R (eds) Sensible Objects: Museums,Colonialism and the Senses. Oxford: Berg, pp. 269301.

    Pe tursdo ttir (2012) Small things forgotten now included, or what else do things deserve?

    International Journal of Historical Archaeology 16(3): in press.

    Poole R (1991) Morality and Modernity. London: Routledge.

    Preda A (1999) The turn to things: Arguments for a sociological theory of things.

    Sociological Quarterly 40(2): 347366.

    Ragnarsson H (2007) So ltunarstair a 20. o ld [Salting stations in the 20th century].

    In: Sigursson B, Sigursson B, Jo hannesson GTh, et al. (eds) Silfur hafsins gull

    Islands: S ldarsaga Islendinga II [Silver of the sea gold of Iceland: Icelanders herring

    history II]. Reykjavk: Nesutga fan, pp. 281361.Rowlands M (2002a) Heritage and cultural property. In: Buchli V (ed.) The Material Culture

    Reader. Oxford: Berg, pp. 105114.

    Rowlands M (2002b) The power of origins: Questions of cultural rights. In: Buchli V (ed.)

    The Material Culture Reader. Oxford: Berg, pp. 115133.

    Ruggles DF and Silverman H (2009) From tangible to intangible heritage. In: Ruggles DF

    and Silverman H (eds) Intangible Heritage Embodied. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 114.

    Scarre C and Scarre G (eds) (2006) The Ethics of Archaeology: Philosophical Perspectives on

    Archaeological Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Shanks M (1998) The life of an artifact in an interpretive archaeology. Fennoscandia

    Archaeologica15: 1542.Sigursson B, Sigursson B, Jo hannesson GTh, et al. (2007) Silfur hafsins gull Islands:

    S ldarsaga Islendinga[Silver of the sea gold of Iceland: Icelanders herring history II].

    Reykjavk: Nesutgafan.

    Smith L (2006) Uses of Heritage. London: Routledge.

    Smith L and Akagawa N (2009) Introduction. In: Smith L and Akagawa N (eds) Intangible

    Heritage. Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 19.

    Smith L and Waterton E (2009a) Introduction: Heritage and archaeology. In: Waterton E

    and Smith L (eds)Taking Archaeology out of Heritage. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge

    Scholars Publishing, pp. 17.

    Smith L and Waterton E (2009b) The envy of the world: Intangible heritage in England.In: Smith L and Akagawa N (eds) Intangible Heritage. Abingdon: Routledge,

    pp. 289302.

    52 Journal of Social Archaeology 13(1)

    by guest on September 16, 2014jsa.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/http://jsa.sagepub.com/
  • 8/11/2019 Journal of Social Archaeology 2013 Ptursdttir 31 53

    24/24

    Snvarr S (1993) Haglysing I slands [Icelands economic description]. Reykjavk:

    Heimskringla, Ha sko laforlag Ma ls og menningar.

    Solli B (2011) Some reflections on heritage and archaeology in the Anthropocene.Norwegian

    Archaeological Review 44(1): 4088.Statistics Iceland (n.d.) Hagstofa I slands. Available at: http://www.statice.is/Statistics/

    Population (accessed December 2009).

    Tilley C (1994)A Phenomenology of Landscape: Places, Paths and Monuments. Oxford: Berg.

    Tilley C (2004)The Materiality of Stone: Explorations in Landscape Phenomenology. Oxford:

    Berg.

    Trentmann F (2009) Materiality in the future of history: Things, practices, and politics.

    Journal of British Studies 48(2): 283307.

    UNESCO (n.d.) World heritage. Available at: http://whc.unesco.org/en/about/ (accessed

    March 2012).

    UNESCO (1972) Convention Concerning the Protection of the World Cultural and NaturalHeritage. Adopted by the General Conference at its seventeenth session, Paris, 16

    November.

    UNESCO (2003) Convention for the Safeguarding of Intangible Cultural Heritage. Paris, 17

    October.

    Van de Wetering E (1996) The surface of objects and museum style. In: Stanely Price N,

    Kirby Talley Jr. M and Melucco Vaccaro A (eds) Historical and Phiosophical Issues on the

    Conservation of Cultural Heritage. Los Angeles, CA: Getty Conservation Institute,

    pp. 415421.

    Waterton E and Smith L (eds) (2009a) Taking Archaeology out of Heritage. Newcastle upon

    Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Waterton E and Smith L (2009b) There is no such thing as heritage. In: Waterton E and

    Smith L (eds) Taking Archaeology out of Heritage. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge

    Scholars Publishing, pp. 1027.

    Watson S (2009) Archaeology, visuality and the negotiation of heritage. In: Waterton E and

    Smith L (eds) Taking Archaeology out of Heritage. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge

    Scholars Publishing, pp. 2847.

    Webmoor T and Witmore CL (2008) Things are us! A commentary on human/things rela-

    tions under the banner of a social archaeology. Norwegian Archaeological Review 41(1):

    5370.

    jo minjalo g [Law on national cultural resource management] (2001) Nr. 107/2001,Lagasafn. I slensk lo g 1. okto ber 2005. U tga fa 131b. Available at: http://www.althin-

    gi.is/lagas/131b/2001107.html (accessed December 2011).

    Author Biography

    o ra Pe tursdo ttir completed an MA in Archaeology from the University of

    Troms, Department of Archaeology and Social Anthropology, in 2007, and is

    currently a PhD student at the same university. Her current research is focused on

    archaeologies of the recent past and present, predominantly in Iceland. Her PhDproject is part of the research project Ruin Memories: Materiality, Aesthetics and

    the Archaeology of the Recent Past (http://www.ruinmemories.org).

    Petursdottir 53