Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    1/21

    [PT  12.4 (2011) 511-530]  Political Theology  (print) ISSN 1462-317Xdoi:10.1558/poth.vl2i4.511  Political Theology  (online) ISSN 1473-1719

    JAN ASSMANN AND THE THEOLOGIZATION OF THE POLITICAL

    Daniel Steinmetz-Jenkins1

    Graduate Department of History

    Fayerweather Hall 413

    1180 Amsterdam Ave.

    Mail Code 2527

    Columbia University

    New York, NY 10027-7039

    USA

    [email protected]

    ABSTRACT

    This paper focuses in part on Jan Assmann's interpretat ion and refutation

    of Carl Schmitt's very well-known secularization theory that all significantmodern concepts of the state are secularized theological notions. It will be

    demonstrated that Assmann attempts to counter Schmitt's conception of

    modern secularization by suggesting that Mosaic monotheism inaugurated a

    revolution by theologizing the political. By briefly exploring Assmann's inter

    pretation of Egyptian religion, it will be argued that a conception of the polit i

    cal as distinct from the theological characterized the political form of ancient

    Egypt. This leads to a discussion of Assmann's argument that Schmitt's con

    ception of the friend/enemy distinction should be understood as an aberration

    of the political form of ancient Egypt and therefore viewed as a category of

    political illegitimacy. In order to illustrate this, attention will first be drawn to

    Assmann's distinction between primary and secondary religion. This is fol

    lowed by a discussion of Assmann's notion of the structural transform of the

    political by theology, which then moves specifically into his argument for the

    intellectual origins of Schmitt's concept of the political. It will be attempted

    throughout this paper to bring conceptual clarification to Assmann's notion

    of theologization by relating it to the question of political theology currently

    taking place in France and the English-speaking world. Towards the end I

    offer a number of criticisms of Assmann's notion of theologization.

    Keywords:  Jan Assmann; monotheism; Mosaic distinction; Carl Schmitt;

    secularization; theologization

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    2/21

    512  Political Theology

    Jan Assmann is certainly one of the most wide-ranging and ambitious

    theorists of religion writing today. Assmann's groundbreaking work on

    the history of Egyptian religion, his understanding of biblical monotheism

    as the defining psycho-historical event of the West, and his call for a new

    perspective on Moses have all contributed to pushing him into the center

    of much scholarly debate and inquiry.2 Assmann has played a significant

    role in reviving interest in Freud's Moses and Monotheism and he is perhaps

    best known in the States for his writings on cultural memory. Though his

    work has made him famous in Europe, his American reception has lagged

    behind as his works continue to be translated in English.3

    This paper focuses in part on Assmann's interpretation and refutation

    of  Carl Schmitt's very well-known secularization theory that all significant

    modern concepts of the state are secularized theological notions. Assmann

    attempts to counter Schmitt's conception of modern secularization by

    suggesting that Mosaic monotheism inaugurated a revolution by theolo

    gizing the political.

    By briefly exploring Assmann's interpretation of Egyptian religion,

    it will be argued that a conception of the political as distinct from the

    theological characterized the political form of ancient Egypt. This leads

    to a discussion of Assmann's argument that Schmitt's conception of thefriend/enemy distinction should be understood as an aberration of the

    political form of ancient Egypt and therefore viewed as a category of politi

    cal illegitimacy. In order to illustrate this, attention will first be drawn to

    Assmann's distinction between primary and secondary religion. This is

    followed by a discussion of Assmann's notion of  the  structural transform

    of the political by theology, which then moves specifically into his argu

    ment for the intellectual origins of Schmitt's concept of the political. It

    will be attempted throughout this paper to bring conceptual clarificationto Assmann's notion of theologization by relating it to contemporary

    2.  This debate has primarily taken place in Germany where his book Moses the Egyp

     tian was met with fierce criticism, especially by German theologians. For reactions to the

    book see Politsche Theologie, ed. Jürgen Manemann, Band 4 (Berlin: Lit Verlag, 2002); Klaus

    Muller, "Gewalt und Wahrheit: Zu Jan Assmanns Monotheismuskritik," in   Das Gewalt

     Potential des Monotheismus und der dreieine  Gott,  ed. Peter Walter (Freiberg: Herder, 2005),

    74-83; Peter Schäfer, "Das jüdische Monopol. Jan Assmann und der Monotheismus," Süd-

     deutsche Zeitung, August 8,2004; Jan Assmann, Die Mosaische  Unterscheidung.  Oder der Preis des Monotheismus (München: Carl Hanser Verlag, 2003), 145-273.

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    3/21

    Steinmetz-Jenkins  Jan Assmann & the Theologization of  the Political  51

    discussions in political theology and philosophy currently taking place in

    France and the English-speaking world. This paper concludes by putting

    forward a number of criticisms of theologization.

    Assmann's book on political theology in Ancient Egypt, Israel and Europe,

    entitled Herrschaft und  Heil, was published in the year 2000.4 That it remains

    without English translation is indeed unfortunate since it contains some

    of the most original and creative work written on the subject of political

    theology in the last decade. Its introduction provides a brief and useful his

    torical overview of political theology from Marcus Varrò to Claude Lefort.

    This is followed by Assmann's objective to accomplish nothing less than

    the undoing of Carl Schmitt's famous dictum that all significant concepts of

    modern state theory are secularized theological concepts. What did Schmittspecifically mean by this assertion? Schmitt understood the political to be

    structured according to a monotheistic and omnipotent conception of God.

    As the Schmitt scholar György Geréby explains:

    The political is structured analogically to theology, especially to monothe

    ism. The decision about the law is analogous to the  creatio  ex nihilo.  The

    lawgiver is analogous to the omnipotent deity. The state of emergency, the

    exceptional case, corresponds to the concept of the miracle.5

    Assmann believes that this view of God, which forms the basis of Schmitt's

    secularization thesis, is the product of the biblical conception of mosaic

    monotheism, or what he describes as the Mosaic distinction. In order to

    understand the revolutionary political significance of the Mosaic distinc

    tion it is first necessary to grasp that Ancient Egypt established a political

    order entirely this-worldly, immanent, and legitimated through visible

    religious representations. The Mosaic distinction initiated a political

    revolution by associating such representations with idolatry. The biblical

    figure of Moses inaugurates a new conception of  the political by rooting

    the legitimacy of political order onto a non-worldly, transcendent, and

    non-representable reality. Assmann describes the shift from political order

    being secured by worldly representations in Egypt to political legitimacy

    being derived from a monotheistic God that refuses all representations as

    theologization. Assmann states this thesis as follows:

    It will be shown, that the process of secularization also has an opposite

    direction. I call this process theologization and would like to demonstrate it by

    means of the theological becoming central political concepts, just like Carl

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    4/21

    514 Political Theology

    Schmitt wanted to demonstrate the process of secularization by means of

    the political becoming central theological concepts. One could also rewrite

    the Schmittian project of political theology: The birth of the political or

    better state theory—out of the spirit of theology. I will turn the tables anddeal with the birth of religion out of the spirit of the political.6

    In something of a polemic manner, Assmann, arguing in the vein of

    Schmitt but with cross-purposes, is suggesting that theologization means

    in principle that there are no legitimate theological-political concepts.

    Alois Halbmayr, one of Assmann's German critics, remarks that this actu

    ally entails that theological concepts "before they became theological con

    cepts were political concepts and even as theological concepts they are still

    political."7 It is in this manner that Assmann attempts to counter Schmittnot by appealing to the legitimacy of modernity,8 but the illegitimacy of

    political theology by using Schmitt against himself.9

    6. "Es soll gezeigt werden, daß der Prozeß der Säkularisierung auch eine Gegen-

    Richtung hat. Diesen Prozeß nenne ich »Theologisierung« und möchte ihn anhand des

    Theologischwerdens zentraler politischer Begriffe nachweisen, genauso wie Carl Schmitt

    den Prozeß der Säkularisierung anhand des Politischwerdens zentraler theologischer Beg

    riffe. Das Schmittsche Projekt der PolitsichenTheologie könnte man auch überschreiben:»Die Geburt desPolitischen—oder besser: des Staatsrechts—aus dem Geist der Theologie«.

    Ich werde den Spieß umdrehen und von der »Geburt der Religion aus dem Geist des Poli

    tischen« handeln." Assmann, Herrschaft und  Heil, 29. All translations are mine unless other

    wise noted.

    7. "Bevor sie also theologische Begriffe wurden, waren sie politische Begriffe, und

    selbst als theologische Begriffe sind sie immer noch politisch." Alois Halbmayr, "Mono

    theismus als theologisch-politisches Problem: Kommentare," Politsche Theologie, ed. Jürgen

    Manemann Band 4 (Berlin: Lit Verlag, 2002), 135.

    8. This of course is a reference to Hans Blumenberg, who nevertheless argues thatSchmitt's political theology was itself a product of  a secularized eschatology carried out as

    the ancient Church became more institutionalized. See Hans Blumenberg,  The Legitimacy

     of Modernity (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983), 37-51.

    9. Clearly Assmann's acceptance of Schmitt's conception of modernity is inseparable

    from his critique of biblical monotheism. The connection of Schmitt to the Mosaic dis

    tinction is confirmed by Assmann's acknowledged acceptance of Heinrich Meier's thesis

    of Schmitt being a political theologian, especially with the revelation of Schmitt's  Glos

     sarium. In his book on Carl Schmitt and the "Jewish Question," Raphael Gross singles out

    Assmann's acceptance of Schmitt's appraisal of political modernity as entirely problem

    atic. Gross condemns Assmann's transfer "of an entire spectrum of Schmittian positions

    intertwined with the jurist's Nazi and anti-Semitic engagement." See Raphael Gross, Carl

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    5/21

    Steinmetz-Jenkins  Jan Assmann & the Theologization of the Political 515

    As Geréby explains, Schmitt's conception of secularization leaves itself

    vulnerable to this specific type of  argument:

    Schmi tt has elaborated a "theology" of the secular wor ld, conceiving of politics as an immanentist theology in its own right. His argument, however,

    can cut two ways: from the idea that politics is a consequence of the imma-

    nentist theology of the secular, immanent political order, it follows that it

    might not be theology that changes into politics but politics that forms the

    ology and makes it conform to its own shape. Modern politics may be an

    heir to theology, but this might be only an instance of theology bluntly dis

    playing its derivation from politics.10

    Nevertheless, on Assmann's own  terms, what does it mean to say that

    theological  concepts are really political concepts? The answer to thisquestion  is inseparable from Assmann's theory of  religion and politics in

    ancient Egypt.

    Understanding Assmann's rigorous conception of religion and politics

    in ancient Egypt is essential to accessing his notion of  theologization. To

    reiterate, Assmann believes that the  "theologization of the political had jus t

    as fundamentally revolutionized the world of its time, as the secularization

    of  the theological had in the modern age."11 This suggests that Assmann

    understands the concept of the political in ancient Egypt to be a categorythat in some way is separable from the question of  religion. Assmann uses

    a  number of terms to describe this contrast, but conceptually it is most

    easily grasped through the notions of primary and secondary religion:

    We must distinguish between religion, which belongs to the basic condi

    tions of human existence, and theology, which came into being as a reflex

    ive and emerging critical form of true worship in Israel and elsewhere over

    other religions. Theology in this sense is the hallmark of secondary religion.

    The concept, "emergence of theology" does not refer to the emergence ofreligion in general, but instead to the emergence  oí  secondary  [emphasis his]

    reflexive and exclusive religion.12

    nations' and, as such, echoes anti-Semitic conceptions of a German   Volk."  See Christian J.

    Emden, "How to Fall into Carl Schmitt's Trap,"  ΗNet Reviews, July 2009. http://www.h

    net.org/reviews/showrev.php?id=24782. 

    10.  Geréby, "Political Theology versus Theological Politics," 12.

    11.  "»Theologisierung« des Politischen hat die damalige welt, ebenso fundamental rev-

    olutionert wie in der Neuzeit die Säkularisierung des Theologischen." Assmann, Herrschaft

    und Heil,  30. Assmann's thought on the theologization of the political are reminiscent of

    http://www.hnet.org/reviews/showrev.php?id=24782http://www.hnet.org/reviews/showrev.php?id=24782http://www.hnet.org/reviews/showrev.php?id=24782http://www.hnet.org/reviews/showrev.php?id=24782

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    6/21

    516  Political Theology

    A Heideggarian tone is quite apparent in Assmann's distinction between

    primary and secondary religion. For Assmann, primary religion is a non-

    reflexive and first-order category that defines the basic presuppositions of

    everyday existence. It speaks of the day-to-day conditions by which life

    is lived and the normalities and regularities of existence that are simply

    assumed as reliable. Secondary religion emerges in the place where the

    distinction established between true and false is introduced in the context

    of religion. It questions the rules and norms that primary religion takes

    for granted.

    Based on the distinction between primary and secondary religion, how

    did the Mosaic distinction carry out a political revolution that defines the

    current political form of the West? What is clear is that Assmann's exegetical

    analysis of Egyptian texts has led him to the conclusion that Ancient Egypt

    possessed, to a qualified degree, a secular conception of political order.

    Assmann's argument for this is based on a subtle distinction he makes

    between a broad and narrow conception of religion in Egypt. According to

    Assmann, the broad conception of religion in Egypt encompassed society

    at large. Assmann, reworking terminology developed by the German soci

    ologist of religion Thomas Luckmann, describes the broad conception of

    religion as invisible religion. "Invisible religion is responsible for a viewof the world as a whole and is not capable of being institutionalized...

    invisible religion determines the relationship of the individual to society

    and the world."13  This is contrasted with visible religion, which speaks

    of the institutionalization of religious life and practices. Invisible religion

    "articulates a space-time schema overrarching and exceeding the empirical

    space-time coordinates in which concrete activities and events occur."14

    Visible religions speak of empirically analyzable religious activities and

    practices such as festivals and ceremonies.For the sake of conceptual clarification it will be useful to observe that

    Assmann's distinction between visible and invisible religion structurally

    Religion." Jan Assmann, "Monotheismus," Politische Theologie 4 (2002): 123-24. It is inter

    esting that in Herrschaft und Heil   Assmann does not use the term theology to distinguish

    secondary from primarily religion but simply to contrast one form of religion with another.

    Assmann, Herrschaft und  Heil, 30-31. Assmann acknowledges the German theologian Theo

    Sundermeier for this distinction. In Was ist Religion, however, Sundermeier seems to reserve

    primary religions only for small traditional societies: Theo Sundermeier,  Was ist Religion

    (München: Chr. Kaiser/Gütersloher, 1999).

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    7/21

    Steinmetz-Jenkins Jan Assmann & the Theologization of  the Political 517

    parallels what the contemporary French political theorist Claude Lefort

    describes as the difference between the political (le politique)  versus poli

    tics  (la politique).15 The political for Lefort is analogous to what Assmanndescribes as invisible religion. It speaks of the overarching symbolic

    framework that characterizes the form and shape of a given society. As

    Charles Taylor notes, "Within this outlook, what constitutes a society as

    such is the metaphysical order it embodies. People act within a framework

    which is there prior to and independent of their action."16 Taylor speaks

    of this as the social imaginary that forms the background conditions for

    how a society perceives of its day-to-day existence. According to Lefort,

    the political is concerned with how the appearances behind the classifica

    tions of politics come to appear. Assmann's conception of visible religion

    parallels Lefort's conception of politics. Lefort associates "politics" with

    the social sciences, namely such disciplines as political science or politi

    cal sociology. In this sense politics, like Assmann's conception of visible

    religion, is understood as secondary discourse in contrast to the political

    which is seen as society's grounding dimension.

    Following Merleau-Ponty, the distinction between the political and

    politics speaks of the relationship between figure and ground. Politics

    arise from a differentiation within the political form of society. As

    Marcel Gauchet, a former student of Lefort's, explains, "the political

    constitutes the most encompassing level of the organization [of  society],

    not a subterranean level, but veiled in the visible."17  What is veiled in

    the visible is the very condition that gives rise to its possibility, namely

    the invisible or political form that generates it. Put differently, politics

    should be understood as an objective expression or quasi-representation

    of the primal dimensionality of the social imaginary, to use Taylor's

    language. As Lefort remarks, "Political science emerges from a desireto objectify, and forgets that no elements, no elementary structures,

    no entities (classes or segments of classes), no economic or technical

    determinations, and no dimensions of social space exist until they have

    been given a form."18  This means that politics and the political are not

    15.  For an analysis of this distinction in the wor k of Lefort and as it relates to the ques

    tion of political theology, see my "Claude Lefort and the Illegitimacy of Modernity, "Journal

     for Cultural and Religious Theory 10, no. 1 (Winter 2009): 102-17.

    16.  Charles Taylor, A  Secular  Age  (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2007),

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    8/21

    518 Political Theology

    two separate realms but rather they are chiasmatically intertwined. What

    appears as politics is an extraction and therefore quasi-representation of

    the social imaginary. Politics should be understood as a simulacra of the

    political form that engenders it.

    This brief foray into Lefort's conception of the political and politics

    clarifies Assmann's understanding of invisible and visible religion. In

    particular Assmann associates invisible religion with what the Egyptians

    described as maat.

     Maat  signifies the principle of  a  universal harmony that manifests itself in

    cosmos as order and in the world of human beings as justice. Such concepts

    exist also in other cultures to describe the totality of meaningful order on

    the highest plane of abstraction. Examples are the Greek concept kosmos, the

    Indian dharma, and the Chinese  tao} 9

     Maat   (abstract principle of universal harmony) on earth is facilitated andmanifested into two opposing culture realms of law and religion. Paradoxi

    cally, "these are the spheres in which  maat —which is otherwise a higher,invisible form and as such is not capable of being institutionalized—is

    made visible."20 Maat  veiled in the visible (the domestic) divides itself intothe spheres of religion and law that facilitate order. Visible religion in Egypt

    involves engagement in worship, sacrifices, offering and the observance of

    festivals. This is religion narrowly defined and must be contrasted with

    the domestic sphere of social and legal order which is also instantiated

    by maat  yet is distinct from religious practices. The social and legal orderinvolves adhering to the law, administering justice and providing welfare

    for the poor. In other words, maat  accounts for and legitimates both legaland religious activities, but these spheres do not institutionally overlap

    and reside in two distinct jurisdictions. This leads to Assmann's interest

    ing conclusion that a form of secularism was present in Egyptian religion

    and politics:

    The "moral and political cosmos" is contrasted with the "religious cosmos"

    as something else, something that is not religion in the narrower sense. This

    sphere too has a religious foundation, but it has nothing to do with placating

    the gods, with cults, theology, and the priesthood. Instead it forms its own

    "sub-universe of meaning"... This, incidentally teaches us that in Egypt the

    law was not a sacred institution, as it was in Israel, nor was it a medium to

    "satisfy the gods." On the contrary, the law was kept outside the sphere of religion proper [italics mine], which was exclusively concerned with communicating

    with the divine 21

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    9/21

    Steinmetz-Jenkins  Jan Assmann & the Theologization of  the Political  519

    With the conceptual framework in mind, an attempt can be made to

    give a proper account of Assmann's understanding of theologization. It

    specifically takes place when the distinction between the spheres of law

    and religions are merged into one. When this occurs a secondary religionarises that pushes back the visible basis for political order into the invisible

    in which justice is now assimilated into a relationship with the divine.

    Theologization takes place "when concepts that had previously belonged

    in the sphere of justice are now inscribed theologically in this process

    of de-differentiation."22  Out of the inscription of the political within the

    theological emerges the birth of a lawgiving deity.23

    What is important here to grasp is that the semantic universe of sec

    ondary religion comes into existence by a stark break with the primaryreligion.

    24 In this sense secondary religion is understood by Assmann as a

    counter-religion that defines itself in opposition against the primary reli

    gion it rejects. The tenor of Egyptian religion is inclusivity, integration,

    compatibility, reciprocity and plurality. These notions are the product of a

    cosmotheistic25 worldview by which the divine does not stand in opposi

    tion between the world, human beings or society, but instead constitutes a

    principle that permeates and arranges them. This is a world of continually

    developing synergistic processes. The sources of legitimacy that facilitatethese processes are the pantheon of deities that represent and maintain

    political and religious order in the world. As Assmann states:

    In the political-religious dimension, a polytheistic world structured the

    political arrangement of society. It determined the membership of each to a

    city, festival and religious community. It decided the relationship of settle

    ments to states, states to districts and districts to residency and defined in

    this manner the political identity of the land and all of its subdivisions down

    to the individual citizen.

    26

    22.  Assmann, Religion and Cultural Memory, 36.

    23.  "[Monotheism] had made justice for the first time into a direct concern of God' s.

    Th e world until this point had not known a lawgiving God." "er hat sie erstmals zur unmit

    telbaren Sache Gottes gemacht. Einen gesetzgebenden Gott hatte die Welt bis dahin nicht

    gekannt." Assmann, Mosaische Unterscheidung, 75.

    24.  Assmann's multiple dualistic pairings can lead to confusion. It appears that all pr i

    mary and secondary religions are visible but not all visible religions are secondary religions.

    A secondary religion is defined as a counter-religion.

    25.  For a philosophical engagement with Assmann's notion of cosmotheism see

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    10/21

    520 Political Theology

    In Moses the Egyptian Assmann argues that cosmotheism not only ordered

    society down to the lowest sum of its parts, but also allowed for the

    "ecumen" of interconnected nations. This affirms that not the names

    or shapes of deities, but their similar functions allowed for their trans

    lation between disparate cultures. "Thus they functioned as a means of

    intercultural translatability. The gods were international because they

    were cosmic. The different people worshiped different gods, but nobody

    contested the reality of foreign gods and the legitimacy of foreign forms of

    worship."27 Translation is made possible by a commensurability of func

    tion that allows for an overlapping consensus amongst the gods. The basic

    premises of this commensurability are guaranteed by cosmotheism. This

    would suggest that ancient Egyptian religion interestingly possessed muchin common with John Rawls's political liberalism. Rawls's notion of an

    overlapping consensus is made possible by "certain fundamental intui

    tive ideas implicit in the political culture of  a democratic society."28 This

    is to affirm that contained within the various comprehensive doctrines

    of democratic societies are functional equivalents than can be translated

    into a public conception of reason allowing for an overlapping consen

    sus. An overlapping consensus is derived from divergent comprehensive

    doctrines operating within the restraints of  a democratic culture. Vis-à-visAssmann, if translation in primary religion is guaranteed by the premises

    of cosmotheism then translation in the Rawlsian sense is guaranteed by the

    premises of  a democratic culture allowing for an overlapping consensus.

    Functional equivalents, translation and even the idea of a romantic poly

    theism are all notions that contemporary political theorists have espoused

    that share a deep affinity with the tenor of Assmann's project.29

    The Mosaic distinction derives its semantics from the rejection of Egypt.

    By juxtaposing Egypt with true religion it "cut the umbilical cord whichconnected [Moses'] people and his religious ideas to their cultural and

    natural context."30 Assmann describes this as semantic relocation by which

    the concepts and rhetoric of loyalty were transferred from the political to

    zu den Gauen und der Gaue zur Residenz und definiert auf diese Weise die politische Iden

    tität des Landes und aller seiner Untergliedergungen bis hinab zum einzelnen Bürger."

    Assmann, "Monotheismus," 124.

    27.  Jan Assmann, Moses the Egyptian: The Memory of Egypt in Western Monotheism  (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997), 3.

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    11/21

    Steinmetz-Jenkins  Jan Assmann & the Theologization of  the Political  52

    the divine sphere, where they acted as models between the relationship of

    god and man:

    Relocation means that something is withdrawn from one sphere and transferred to another. Thus, protection was no longer sought on the "mundane"

    plane, from kings and patrons, but on the divine plane, from a deity... It

    means the transfer of the political institutions of alliance, treaty and vas-

    seldom from the mundane sphere of politics to the transcendental sphere

    of  religion. In Israel we are dealing with the "semiological divinization" or

    theologization of Egyptian, Hittite, Babylonian, and especially Assyrian for

    eign politics.31

    This passage suggests that at the heart of semantic relocation is the emer

    gence of political theology. The carrying out of this relocation is mostclearly seen in the prohibition of images. Representations establish con

    duits for the divine by which political and religious authority is legitimated.

    In this sense idols are sacraments which secure the gods real presence on

    earth. As such, "the state's most important task is to ensure divine pres

    ence under the condition of divine absence, and thereby to maintain a

    symbiotic relationship between man, society and cosmos."32  Therefore,

    the prohibition against idols must be construed as a counter-politic that

    sets itself directly against the very core of Egyptian political authority. Assuch, Egypt offers not a false religion but a false politics.

    The parallels between Israel as possessing a true politics versus Egypt as

    possessing a false politics demonstrates strong affinities with the explicit

    language of a certain strand of American post-liberal political theology.

    Exemplary of  this  is the theologian Stanley Hauerwas who portrays lib

    eralism as offering a seductive "false politics" of the world that the true

    politics of the church must set itself against.33 Furthermore, Assmann's

    reading of the Exodus brings him very close to liberation theologians whenhe argues that freedom for Israel could only mean freedom from political

    oppression through divine deliverance: "Monotheism appears as a political

    movement of liberation from pharaonic oppression and as the foundation

    of  an alternative way of life, where humans are not ruled by a state, but

    freely consent to enter an alliance with God and adopt the stipulations of

    divine law."34 From this angle, political authority is no longer represented,

    but rather is grounded by entering into a covenant with an unrepresentable

    31.  Jan Assmann, "Axial Breakthroughs and Semantic Relocations in Ancient Egypt

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    12/21

    522  Political Theology

    and transcendent God. The result is a world made strange by an inversion

    in which the discourse of incommensurability now becomes essential-

    ized in the concept of the political on account of  theology. On this basis

    Assmann is able to argue that as a result of the prohibition against idols

    the discourse between true and false religion first emerges since loyalty to

    the one true God affirms not denying the existence of other deities, but

    denying loyalty and allegiance to a false politic.35

    In an article entitled, "Monotheismus," Assmann asks the question

    what this distinction has meant for the history of political theology. This

    question is raised in light of Assmann's assertion that semantic reloca

    tion is sufficient but does not necessitate the potential for violence. The

    propensity towards violence arises not from the idea of the One God

    nor with distinction between truth and untruth. It instead is linked with

    the persecution of untruth when the distinction between true and false

    is conflated between "us" and "them" and thus construed in terms of

    friends and enemies. It is at this juncture that he suggests Carl Schmitt's

    conception of friends and enemies can be accounted for within the

    semantic field of the Mosaic distinction, and specifically the ban on

    images:

    Is there a correlation between the distinction of true and false and that

    between friends and enemies? This relationship is obvious and connected

    with the prohibition of images. The prohibition of images directed the theo

    logical distinction between truth and untruth, god and gods, into the politi

    cal and interpreted it in the sense of friends and enemies. It defines who

    God's enemies are and where they stand. With the banning of images it is

    a matter of defining an enemy in light of the distinction between true and

    false.36

    35.  "The political meaning of monotheism in its early stage does not deny the exis

    tence of other gods. On the contrary, without the existence of other gods the request to stay

    faithful to the lord would be pointless." Assmann, "Axial Breakthroughs," 50. They are false

    not because they are non-existent but rather because they signify an oppressive political

    alternative. Of course this conception of the political is inseparable from a sharp distinction

    between God and the world. In Mosaische  Unterscheidung,  Assmann makes the interesting

    argument that Karl Barth's dialectic theology and its radical transcendence vis-à-vis the lib

    eral Protestant culture of its day is analogous to the Mosaic distinction and Egyptian culture

    and religion. Mosaische Unterscheidung, 53.

    36.  "Gibt es einen Zusammenhang zwischen der Unterscheidung von wahr und

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    13/21

    Steinmetz-Jenkins  Jan Assmann & the Theologization of  the Political  52

    What might present itself at this moment is one particular charge against

    Assmann suggesting that his argument is potentially anti-Semitic.37

     From

    this angle the levelling of anti-Semitism at Assmann involves the claim

    that Judaism is ultimately responsible for establishing a turn not for thebetter, but for the worst by abolishing the golden age of primary religion.

    It seems Assmann has responded to this charge in a variety of  ways. The

    following interaction focuses on two of his responses to this criticism.

    Foremost, Assmann argues that of the three Abrahamitic religions,

    "Judaism is the only one that has never turned the implications of  vio

    lence and intolerance into historical reality precisely because it has rele

    gated the final universalizing of truth to eschatology and not to history."38

    In light of this statement, it should be asked how Assmann views themodern state of Israel. It is interesting that in Herrschaft  und Heil Assmann suggests that the very identity of ancient Israel was predicated as

    being against the Egyptian state in a manner analogous to Pierre Clastres'

    notions of  Société contre  l'État?9 This could suggest that Assmann makesa direct link between the monotheistic revolution and a rejection of the

    state. Assmann further remarks that, though Judaism constitutes a cul

    ture established fundamentally on difference historically, this distinction

    has not been predicated on a division between friends and enemies. Judaism draws and maintains this boundary in the form of self-exclusion.

    Self-exclusion necessitates no violence and is to be contrasted with Islam

    and Christianity that historically have not recognized a boundary of this

    nature. This leads to Assmann's conclusion regarding the specific link

    between counter-religion and Schmitt's political theology:

    God is truth; the gods of others are lies. That is the theological basis of

    the distinction between friend and enemy. Only on this ground and in this

    semantic context has political theology actually become dangerous. The

    political theology of Carl Schmitt also stands in this tradition of revelational

    theology's propensity towards violence. Here lies, in my opinion, the actual

    "political problem" of monotheism.40

    37.  For Assmann's reaction to this charge, see Mosaische Unterscheidung, 25-26.

    38.  Assmann, God and gods, 111.

    39.  See Herrschaft  und Heil, 49.

    40.  "Gott ist die Wahrheit, die Göt ter der anderen sind Lüge. Das ist die theolo

    gische Basis der Unterscheidung von Freund und Feind. Erst auf diesem Boden und in

    diesem semantischen Rahmen ist die politische Theologie der Gewalt wirklich gefahrlich

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    14/21

    524  Political Theology

    Furthermore, Assmann suggests that one primary purpose of  Moses  the Egyptian was its ecumenical intent.

    41 By interpreting Moses as an Egyptian,

    Assmann hoped to accomplish something like what the second temple

    Judaism scholar E. P. Sanders achieved by emphasizing the Jewishness of

    Saint Paul, namely the mitigation of traditional theological distinctions.42

    the importance which a present ascribes to the past... The task of mnemohistory consists

    in analyzing the mythical elements in tradition and discovering their hidden agenda." Ass

    mann, Moses the Egyptian, 11.

    41.  This is perhaps what separates the tone of Assmann's project from that of Regina

    Schwartz and Jonathen Kirsch's works on the connection between monotheism and vio

    lence; see Regina Schwartz, The Curse of Cain: The  Violent  Case of Monotheism (Chicago:

    University of Chicago Press, 1996); Jonathen Kirsch, God  against the Gods: The History of War

     between Monotheism and Polytheism  (London: Penguin Press, 2005). The recent work of Peter

    Sloterdijk on monotheism can also be read in this context: God's Zeal: The Battle of  the Three

     Monotheisms (New York: Polity Press, 2009). For the so-called "new debate" on religion and

    monotheism that has arisen in Germany see the edited volume: Fragen nach dem einen Gott,

    ed.  Gesine Palmer (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2007). Assmann's  Moses the Egyptian pro

    vides a historiography of this debate starting from the seventeenth century up until his own

    work, with major consideration of Freud's Moses and Monotheism.  See Moses the Egyptian,

    55-167.

    42.  The similarities between Assmann and E. R Sanders' motivational concerns and

    comparative textual analysis are striking. Published in 1977, E. R Sanders' Paul and  Palestin

    ian Judaism remains the pivotal event in post-World War II Pauline studies. Sander's book in

    part initiated what the New Testament theologian James D. G. Dunn later described as the

    New Perspective on Paul. Undeniably, the New Perspective, as represented by Sanders, was

    motivated by the attempt to mitigate traditional binary interpretations of Paul, which made

    significant salvific distinctions between faith and works, law and grace, etc. that historically

    gave rise to anti-Semitism. At a level of scholarship that perhaps remains almost unrivaled

    in the English-speaking world today, Sanders' comparison of Palestinian literature from200 BCE to 200  CE with Pauline literature concluded that election and salvation in Judaism

    is based on God's mercy and is not a human achievement. Sanders' argument is more com

    plex than space allows, but the ultimate implication is that Paul understood in the context of

    the Judaism of his time actually embodies what is common to both Judaism and Christian

    ity. The New Perspective on Paul is now directed at a variety of agendas, but what must be

    stressed here is its original concern with traditional Pauline scholarship's semantic potential

    for anti-Semitism and thus the need to reconsider it on exegetical grounds. It is in this light

    that Jan Assmann's call for a new perspective on Moses must be seen. In particular Assmann

    suggests that understanding Moses as an Egyptian parallels the New Perspective's emphasis

    on Paul as a Jew: "Paul the Jew embodies what is common to Judaism and Christianity. In

    the same way, Moses the Egyptian embodies what is imagined to be common to Ancient

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    15/21

    Steinmetz-Jenkins  Jan Assmann & the Theologization of  the Political  525

    Assmann states that "monotheism derives its crucial semantic elements

    from a construction of the rejected other.. .it depends on the preservation

    of what it opposes for its own definition."43 It appears that the resources

    of primary religion are made available but veiled in secondary religion.Assmann's new perspective on Moses is an attempt to recall a cultural

    memory and thus an alternative tradition that remains present but in a

    theologized form. This "simultaneity makes it possible to identify with the

    forms of expression of  a past going back thousands of  years."44 This would

    suggest that Assmann appears to be advancing not simply a remembrance

    but rather a possible recovery of political legitimacy. By invoking an alter

    native memory of the past, Assmann is attempting to revive an alternative

    political tradition.There are a number of difficulties with Assmann's conception of the

    theologization of the political. Foremost, Assmann's wholesale accep

    tance of Schmitt's conception of political theology is problematic. In

    particular, by embracing Schmitt's conception of secularization he sets

    himself up for the very same charges that the German philosopher

    Hans Blumenberg levelled at Carl Schmitt's conception of history. In

    the Legitimacy of  Modernity Blumenberg argued that "there were no real

    transformations of religious into worldly concepts in the areas whereadvocates of the secularization thesis saw them."45 His main argument

    suggested that the transposition of theological categories into secular

    ones was philosophically untenable. This is a consequence of secular

    ization thesis's inability to produce in any satisfactory manner a dem

    onstration of transformation in a substantialistic sense. Both Schmitt

    and Assmann's understanding of historical change posits an underlying

    substance that provides continuity in the underlying content of chang

    ing ideas. This is most clearly represented in Assmann when he suggests that monotheism depends on the preservation of what it opposes

    for its own definition. This means that secondary religion is indissolu-

    memory that nevertheless does not remain beyond the threshold of remembrance. What

    separates Assmann from the New Perspective on Paul is the ambitiousness of his project

    that sees the fate of the West as something like the tragic consequence of the biblical repre

    sentation of Moses the Hebrew. What unites them is their attempt to uncover forgotten or

    overlooked traditions that call into question the narrowness of received tradition that have

    engendered anti-Semitism. It should be noted that Assmann does not describe his project

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    16/21

    526  Political Theology

    bly bound up with primary religion.46  As such, Blumenberg's remarks

    concerning Schmitt's secularization theory apply to theologization as

    well: "the genuine substance that was secularized is wrapped up in what

    thus became worldly, and remains wrapped up in it."47

    Unlike with Schmitt, however, this criticism of Assmann is the conse

    quence of his imbibing the philosophical holism of the phenomenologi-

    cal tradition that does not allow him to make an ontological distinction

    between visible and invisible religion. Using the language of Merleau-

    Ponty, visible and invisible religion are not two separate realms but rather

    they are chiasmatically intertwined. As such, Assmann's understanding

    of theologization lends itself to conceiving of history as a totality of sub

    stances and is entirely absent of a conception of alterity In this regards

    Blumenberg's critique of Schmitt is again valid for Blumenberg:

    The world is not a constant whose reliability guarantees that in the historical

    process an original constitutive substance must come back to light, undis

    guised, as soon as the superimposed elements of theological derivation and

    specificity are cleared away.48

    A Blumenbergian position would also reject the notion that the original

    political substance of Egyptian society can come back to light as soon as thesuperimposed elements of political derivation are cleared away. Neverthe

    less,  it is clear that Assmann's conception of political legitimacy, and his

    call to remember an alternative political memory that still remains with

    us, espouses just this very notion. As he remarks in Moses the Egyptian:

    A counter-religion can be compared to a palimpsest, a reused papyrus or

    parchment. The old text is erased, and the new text is written on the cleaned

    surface. The more care has been taken to clean the surface, the less of the

    old text is available. But some faint trace of the told text usually remains.

    It is viewed with hatred and abomination. This is the old paradigm. The

    new paradigm focuses on the old text, which is still visible under the new49

    inscription.

    These observations led to the conclusion that Assmann's understanding

    of theologization can be reduced to a Left Hegelian projection theory of

    religion. This is most clearly apparent in Assmann's notion of semantic

    relocation by which the concepts and rhetoric of loyalty are projected

    from the "mundane" sphere of kings and patrons to the transcendental

    sphere of an Almighty God. In this context, the constructive aspect of

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    17/21

    Steinmetz-Jenkins  Jan Assmann & the Theologization of  the Political  527

    Assmann's work presents itself as nothing more than the modern attempt

    to de-theologize the political.

    Viewed in this light, Assmann seems entirely unaware of contempo

    rary critiques of the concept of religion, which demonstrate that universal

    definitions of religion, such as Assmann's, are problematic. Talal Asad

    specifically argues that "religion" must be seen within

    the context of Christian attempts to achieve a coherence in doctrines and

    practices... [and that as a result] there cannot be a universal definition of

    religion, not only because of its constituent elements and relationships are

    historically specific, but because that definition is itself the historical prod

    uct of discursive processes.50

    Asad would argue that the difficulty with Assmann's conception of reli

    gion is that once it is posited in universal terms it establishes a measuring

    stick that places all religions outside its narrative and in the position of

    never being able to advance to that standard. Asad maintains that

    ethnographers and others ought to limit themselves to description, reserv

    ing critique to those who participate firsthand in the language and culture

    under discussion: that is, people who offer their criticism on the basis of

    shared values and are prepared to engage in a sustained conversation of  give-

    and-take.51

    This would mean that the very bifurcations Assmann hopes to overcome

    appear inherently necessary to the alternative political form he seeks to

    remind us.

    It could also be said that Assmann's negative rendering of theism

    appears reminiscent of  a particular formulation of secularism that mar

    ginalizes or attempts to privatize comprehensive religious doctrines in

    the name of securing political and social equality. As such, Assmann'sconception of the political seems out of touch with the recent turn

    in political theory to a post-secular conception of the theological and

    the political.52 From this angle, the theological and the political are no

    longer viewed as incommensurable spheres of discourse, but instead as

    potentially overlapping discursive frameworks that possess the semantic

    50.  Talal Asad, Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and  Reasons of Power in Christianity and

     Islam (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Universi ty Press, 1993), 29.51.  Quoted from Bruce Lincoln, Review of  Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    18/21

    528  Political Theology

    possibility for the securing of  a democratic society. From a post-secular

    perspective, the fact that Assmann can so easily reverse the Schmittian

    narrative implies a common jointure that enables a solidarity to exist

    between them. The opposition between the political and the theological

    "can be asserted only as long as both parts are compelled to be in one and

    the same place.. .the greatest antithesis is possible only where the greatest

    identity is present."53 This parallels the recent claim of Giorgio Agamben,

    who argues that this site of convergence "constitutes the secret point

    of contact where theology and politics communicate unceasingly and

    exchange roles."54  In the end Assmann remains prisoner to a narrative

    that prevents him from seeing that the very place where the theological

    and political appear locked into a relation of antagonism also consti

    tutes a mutual site of engagement between them. In this sense both the

    political and the theological should be understood as rival categories of

    legitimacy in their mutual and often overlapping attempt to articulate a

    vision of society.

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Agamben, Giorgo. Le Règne et la Gloire. Homo sacer, II, 2. French translation by Joël Gayraudand Charles Alunni. Paris: Le Seuil, 2008.

    Asad, Talal. Genealogies  of Religion: Discipline and  Reasons  of  Power in Christianity and Islam.

    Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993.

    Assmann, Jan. Moses the Egyptian: The Memory of Egypt in Western  Monotheism.  Cambridge,

    MA: Harvard University Press, 1997.

     Herrschaft und  Heil: Politische Theologie in Altägypten, Israel und  Europe. München: Fischer

    Verlag, 2000.

    "Monotheismus." Politische Theologie  4 (2002): 122-32.

     Die Mosaische  Unterscheidung.  Oder der Preis des Monotheismus.  München: Carl HanserVerlag, 2003.

    "Axial Breakthroughs and Semantic Relocations in Ancient Egypt and Israel." In

     Religion and  Politics: Cultural  Perspectives, ed. Bernhard Giesen. London: Brill Academic,

    2005.

     Religion and  Cultural  Memory, trans. Rodney Livingstone. Stanford, CA: Stanford Uni

    versity Press, 2006.

    Of God  and  gods: Egypt, Israel,  and the Rise of Monotheism.  Madison, CT: University of

    Wisconsin Press, 2008.

    The Price of Monotheism, trans. Robert Savage. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press,

    2009.

    Blumenberg, Hans. The Legitimacy of Modernity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983.

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    19/21

    SteinmetzJenkins  Jan Assmann & the Theologization of  the Political  529

    Breckman, Warren. "Democracy  between  Disenchantment  and Political Theology: French

    PostMarxism  and the  Return  of  Religion," New  German Critique 94  (Winter   2005):

    72105.

    Caputo, John.  On  Religion.  London:  Routledge, 2001.Connolly, William E. Why I  am not  a Secularist.  Minneapolis: University  of  Minnesota Press,

    2000.

    Dallmayr,  Fred.  "Postmetaphysics  and  Democracy."  Political   Theory 21.1  (February   1993):

    10127. http://dx.doi.Org/10.l 177/0090591793021001006

    Emden,  Christian  J. "How to  Fall into Carl  Schmitt's  Trap."  ΗNet   Reviews, July 2009.

    http://www.hnet.org/reviews/showrev.phpPid=24782.  

    Geréby, György. "Political Theology versus Theological Politics: Erik Peterson and Carl

    Schmitt." New German Critique 35, no. 10 (Fall 2008): 12.

    Gross,  Raphael.  Carl Schmitt and thefews: The 'Jewish Question," the Holocaust, and German

     Legal Theory, trans. Joel Golb. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 2007.

    Habermas, Jürgen. Between Naturalism and Religion: Philosophical Essays. N ew York:  Polity,

    2008.

    Halbmayr, Alois. "Monotheismus als theologisch-politisches Problem: Kommentare." In

    Politsche Theologie, ed. Jürgen Manemann, Band 4. Berlin: Lit Verlag, 2002.

    Hauerwas, Stanley.  In Good Company: The Church as Polis. South Bend, IN: Not re Dame

    University Press, 1997.

    Kirsch, Jonathen .  God against the Gods: The History of War between Monotheism and Polytheism.

    London: Penguin Press, 2005.

    Lefort, Claude.  Democracy and Political Theory. Minnesota, M N : University of MinnesotaPress, 1989.

    Lincoln, Bruce. "Review of   Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in Chris

    tianity and Islam." History of Religions 35, no. 1 (August 1995): 83- 86. http://dx.doi. 

    or^lO. 1086/463408

    Luckmann, Thomas.  The Invisible Religion: The Problem of Religion in Modern Society. Ne w

    York: Macmillan, 1967.

    Manemann, Jürgen, ed. Politsche Theologie, Band 4. Berlin: Lit Verlag, 2002.

    Müller, Jan-Werner.  A Dangerous  Mind:  Carl Schmitt in Post-War European Thought.  New

    Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2003.

    Müller, Klaus. "Gewalt und Wahrheit: Zu Jan Assmanns Monotheismuskritik." In  Das

    Gewalt Potential des Monotheismus und der dreieine Gott, ed. Peter Walter, 74-83. Freiberg:

    Herder, 2005.

    Palmer, Gesine, ed. Fragen nach dem einen Gott. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2007.

    Rawls, Joh n. "The Dom ain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus ." New  York  Univer

    sity Law Review 64, no. 2 (May 1989): 233-55.

    Rorty, Richard. "Pragmatism as Romantic Polytheism." In  The Rival of Pragmatism,  ed.

    Morris Dickstein. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1998.

    Sanders, E. P. Paul and Palestinian Judaism.  Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1977.

    Schäfer, Peter. "Das jüdische Monopol. Jan Assmann und der Monothe ismus."  Süddeutsche

     Zeitung, August 8, 2004.

    http://dx.doi.org/10.lhttp://dx.doi.org/10.lhttp://www.h-net.org/reviews/showrev.phpPid=24782http://dx.doi/http://dx.doi/http://www.h-net.org/reviews/showrev.phpPid=24782http://dx.doi.org/10.l

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    20/21

    530  Political Theology

    Stout, Jeffrey. Democracy and Tradition.  Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005.

    Sundermeier, Theo. Was ist Religion. München: Chr. Kaiser/Gütersloher, 1999.

    Taylor, Charles. Λ   Secular  Age. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University  Press, 2007.

    Tillich, Paul. Mysticism and  GuiltConsciousness   in Schelling's Philosophical Development,  trans. Victor  Nuovo.  Lewisburg, PA: Bucknell University  Press,  1974.

     Werbik, Jürgen. "Absolutistsicher Eingottglaube? Befreiende Vielfalt des Polytheismus." In

     ht  der Glaube Feind der Freiheit?:  Die  neue Debatte um den Monotheismus,  ed.  Thomas

    Söding, 142-75. Breisgau: Herder, 2003.

  • 8/9/2019 Jan Assmann and the Theologization of the Political

    21/21

     Λ Π ^ ,

    Copyright and Use:

     As  an ATLAS user, you may print, download, or send articles for individual use

    according to fair use as defined by  U.S. and international copyright law and as

    otherwise authorized under your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement.

    No content may be copied or emailed to multiple  sites or publicly posted without the

    copyright holder(s)' express written permission. Any use, decompiling,

    reproduction, or distribution of  this journal in excess of fair use provisions may be a

     violation of copyright law.

    This journal is made available to you through the ATLAS collection with permissionfrom the copyright holder(s). The copyright holder  for  an entire issue of  a journaltypically   is the journal owner, who also may own the copyright in each article. However,for certain articles, the author of  the article may  maintain the copyright in the article.

    Please  contact the copyright holder(s) to request permission to use an article or   specific work   for  any  use  not covered by  the fair use provisions of  the copyright laws or  covered by your respective ATLAS subscriber agreement. For information regarding the

    copyright holder(s), please refer to the copyright information in the journal, if   available,or  contact ATLA to request contact information for  the copyright holder(s).

     About ATLAS:

    The ATLA Serials (ATLAS®) collection contains electronic versions of previously

    published religion and theology journals reproduced with permission. The ATLAS

    collection is owned and managed by  the American Theological Library Association(ATLA) and received initial funding from Lilly  Endowment Inc.

    The design and final form of  this electronic document is the property  of  the AmericanTheological Library Association.