2
Reprinted Crom Journa} oC Chamica} Education, Vol. 68, Page 131, February 1991. Copyright @ 1991 by the Division oCChamica} Education oCthe American Chemical godety, and reprinted by permission oC the copyright owner. There Are No Soch Things as Orbitals-Act Two! Jack Simons University ot Utah, Salt laka City, UT 84112 In a recent artiele in the Journal of Chemical Educationl Ogilvie states "There Are No Such Things as OrbitaIs!" and goes on to criticize the teaching of orbital concepts (e.g., hybridization, electronegativity, sigma and pi bonds, hyper- conjugation, HOMO-LUMO, inductive and resonance ef- fects) in OUtcurricula. In that artiele, Ogilvie distinguishes between what he calls quantum laws (e.g., quantities Buch as energy and various angular momenta exist in discrete quantized states under certain conditions) that ara subject to experimental verifica- tiaR and quantum theories or models (e.g., orbitaIs, configu- rations, term symbols, wave functions) that scientists have invented as devices for solving equations (e.g., the Schro- dinger equation) that purport to describe the behavior of atoms and molecules. He directs his attack not at the laws but only at the models or theories. For example, by noting that the solutions ofthe molecular orbital (MO) approach to electronic structure and the valence hond (VB) approach ara identical (when carried to completion), he coneludes that the concepts and constructs of the MO and VB theories have no ultimata meaning (Le., ara not real). Relative to chemical education, he coneludes " 'Quantum chemistry' or the quali- tative ('hand waving') explanations of molecular structure and reactions based on orbitaIs and Buch ilk ara not science (Le., ara nonsense) and should consequent1y be completely discarded." I wish to offer a somewhat different perspective on these subjects. I prefer to do so by stressing the fundamental differences between the point of view put forth by Ogilvie and that to which I subscribe, rather than by pointing out where I differ with Ogilvie in each of his numerous examples of problems that arise in using orbital concepts. I agree with soma of what Ogilvie says, and I concur, in particular, with his view that orbitals ara not real. However, as the following remarks indicate, I am of the opinion that models, ineluding the orbital concept and its derivatives, will continua to play important tales in chemistry and chemical education because they provide useful frameworks in terms of which to organize patterns that ara observed in experi- mental data. If accepted as Buch, and not as "real" entities, models and their constructs ran be useful and not confusing or threatening. My point ofview on models and on the theory of electronic structure in particular ran be summarized in the following three remarks and accompanying observations: 1. Experimental data and the molecules,atoms, and substances we subject to scrutiny constitute the "real" things2 in chemistry. Alt quantities derived from onr data through the application ofmodels, theories, and their associated equations Brenot "real". Applied to MO and VB theories, this means that orbitais, hybrid- ization, screening, electronic configurations (e.g., Is22s22p3),and term symbols Bre not real. Applied to molecular vibrational/rota- tional spectroscopy,it means that forceconstants, equilibrium hond lengths (Re) and angles, vibrational frequencies ("'e),anharmonici- ties ("'eXe), Coriolos coupling constants, as wen as the potential energy surfaces on which these motions Bre thought to occur Bre algo not real. Applied to chemical kinetics, it means that the phenomeno- logical rate constant (k) and the activation energy (t.E+) Bre not real. 2. Models, equations, and theories Breconstructs of onr imagina- tions designed to Bid us in organizing in a systematic manner the trends that appear in onr data. The quantities we extract from the application of a model to onr data Bre, in same sense, no more than "fitting parameters". 3. The value of aRYparticular model or theory is judged byhow accurately, reliably, and compactly it can be used to organize known data, and whether the parameters obtained by applying the model to one or more sets of data can be used to make reasonably accurate predictions of data for materials that have not yet been subjected to onr experiment. In my opiriion, it is with respect to the accuracy of its predictions that Ogilvie could reasonably have criticized quantum theory as applied to electronic structures of atoms, molecules, and materials. For example, in comparison with the theoretical framework used to analyze data from vibra- tional/rotational spectroscopy, modern electronic structure models lack accuracy. The expressions used to rit the lina positions, spacings, and intensities of microwave and infra- red spectral features as functions ofthe quantum numbers v and J provide a very accurate, reliable, and compact frame- wark in terms of which to rit the experimental data. More- over, experience indicates that the parameters so obtained ran be used to predict accurately spectra for molecules that have not bean subjected to experiment.3 However, the pa- rameters (e.g., Re, "'e, "'eXe, etc.) obtained by Buch models ara, in principIe, no mora or less "real" than those obtained from electronic theories applied to electronic experimental data. The fart is that soma models ara mora useful than others because they provide a mora accurate and predictive representation of the experimental data. On this basis, the foundations of vibrational/rotational spectroscopy may be viewed as superior to quantum theory of electronic states. Even the most sophisticated and modern theories of elec- tronic structure do not provide as accurate and reliable a description of the experimental observations as the mora matura and long-studied theories of vibrational/rotational spectroscopy. On this basis, it is proper to question whether the constructs that arise in orbital theories (e.g., orbitaIs, screening, HOMO-LUMO interactions, bark bonding, etc.) ara as meaningful as the analogous constructs (e.g., Re, "'e, "'eXe, etc.) ofvibrational/rotational spectroscopy. However, I 1 Ogilvie,J. F. J. Cham. Educ. 1990, 67, 280. 2 One caR, ot course, pursue things turther and ask whether even these quantities ara real. I do not intend to enter into Buch a philosoph- ical discussion hera; I choose to detine as real things that most (perhaps BIl) chemists would agree caR be directly measured in the laboratory (e.g., a photon energy or wavelength, the attenuation ot a light beam, an angle ot scattering ot a light beam, the enthalpy given oft by a reaction in a calorimeter). 3 In applying Buch spectroscopic energy-Ievel tormulas, one usual- Iy must make assumptions about the equilibrium structure ot the molecule under study. For soma tamilies ot molecules (e.g., highly tluxional molecules and "tloppy" Van der Waals complexes), the observed rotational/vibrational energy ravel patterns ara not well- represented by the conventional equations. For this reagan, Buch molecular tamilies pasa new challenges to the spectroscopist; a new "starting point" model is needed to mora accurately and compactly represent their energy level patterns. In this seRsa, the analysis ot "tloppy" molecule vibrational/rotational energies is in the same situ- ation as atomie and molecular electronic structure theory. Volume 68 Number 2 February 1991 131

Jack Simons - University of Utahsimons.hec.utah.edu/papers/paperso/146.pdf ·  · 2008-08-11continua to play important tales inchemistry and chemical ... Even the most sophisticated

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Reprinted Crom Journa} oCChamica} Education, Vol. 68, Page 131, February 1991.Copyright @ 1991 by the Division oCChamica} Education oCthe American Chemical godety, and reprinted by permission oC

the copyright owner.

ThereAre No Soch Thingsas Orbitals-Act Two!

Jack SimonsUniversity ot Utah, Salt laka City, UT 84112

In a recent artiele in the Journal of Chemical EducationlOgilvie states "There Are No Such Things as OrbitaIs!" andgoes on to criticize the teaching of orbital concepts (e.g.,hybridization, electronegativity, sigma and pi bonds, hyper-conjugation, HOMO-LUMO, inductive and resonance ef-fects) in OUtcurricula.

In that artiele, Ogilvie distinguishes between what he callsquantum laws (e.g., quantities Buch as energy and variousangular momenta exist in discrete quantized states undercertain conditions) that ara subject to experimental verifica-tiaR and quantum theories or models (e.g., orbitaIs, configu-rations, term symbols, wave functions) that scientists haveinvented as devices for solving equations (e.g., the Schro-dinger equation) that purport to describe the behavior ofatoms and molecules. He directs his attack not at the lawsbut only at the models or theories. For example, by notingthat the solutions ofthe molecular orbital (MO) approach toelectronic structure and the valence hond (VB) approach araidentical (when carried to completion), he coneludes that theconcepts and constructs of the MO and VB theories have noultimata meaning (Le., ara not real). Relative to chemicaleducation, he coneludes " 'Quantum chemistry' or the quali-tative ('hand waving') explanations of molecular structureand reactions based on orbitaIs and Buch ilk ara not science(Le., ara nonsense) and should consequent1y be completelydiscarded."

I wish to offer a somewhat different perspective on thesesubjects. I prefer to do so by stressing the fundamentaldifferences between the point of view put forth by Ogilvieand that to which I subscribe, rather than by pointing outwhere I differ with Ogilvie in each of his numerous examplesof problems that arise in using orbital concepts.

I agree with soma of what Ogilvie says, and I concur, inparticular, with his view that orbitals ara not real. However,as the following remarks indicate, I am of the opinion thatmodels, ineluding the orbital concept and its derivatives, willcontinua to play important tales in chemistry and chemicaleducation because they provide useful frameworks in termsof which to organize patterns that ara observed in experi-mental data. If accepted as Buch, and not as "real" entities,models and their constructs ran be useful and not confusingor threatening.

My point ofview on models and on the theory of electronicstructure in particular ran be summarized in the followingthree remarks and accompanying observations:

1. Experimental data and the molecules,atoms, and substanceswesubject to scrutiny constitute the "real" things2in chemistry. Altquantities derived from onr data through the application ofmodels,theories, and their associated equations Brenot "real".

Applied to MO and VBtheories, this means that orbitais, hybrid-ization, screening, electronic configurations (e.g., Is22s22p3),andterm symbols Brenot real. Applied to molecular vibrational/rota-tional spectroscopy,it means that forceconstants, equilibrium hondlengths (Re)and angles, vibrational frequencies ("'e),anharmonici-ties ("'eXe),Coriolos coupling constants, as wen as the potentialenergy surfaces on which these motions Bre thought to occur Brealgonot real. Applied to chemical kinetics, it means that the phenomeno-logical rate constant (k) and the activation energy (t.E+) Bre notreal.

2. Models,equations, and theories Breconstructs of onr imagina-tions designed to Bidus in organizing in a systematic manner the

trends that appear in onr data. The quantities we extract from theapplication of a model to onr data Bre, in same sense, no more than"fitting parameters".

3. The value of aRYparticular model or theory is judged byhowaccurately, reliably, and compactly it can be used to organize knowndata, and whether the parameters obtained by applying the modelto one or more sets of data can be used to make reasonably accuratepredictions of data for materials that have not yet been subjected toonr experiment.

In my opiriion, it is with respect to the accuracy of itspredictions that Ogilvie could reasonably have criticizedquantum theory as applied to electronic structures of atoms,molecules, and materials. For example, in comparison withthe theoretical framework used to analyze data from vibra-tional/rotational spectroscopy, modern electronic structuremodels lack accuracy. The expressions used to rit the linapositions, spacings, and intensities of microwave and infra-red spectral features as functions ofthe quantum numbers vand J provide a very accurate, reliable, and compact frame-wark in terms of which to rit the experimental data. More-over, experience indicates that the parameters so obtainedran be used to predict accurately spectra for molecules thathave not bean subjected to experiment.3 However, the pa-rameters (e.g., Re, "'e, "'eXe,etc.) obtained by Buch models ara,in principIe, no mora or less "real" than those obtained fromelectronic theories applied to electronic experimental data.

The fart is that soma models ara mora useful than othersbecause they provide a mora accurate and predictiverepresentation of the experimental data. On this basis, thefoundations of vibrational/rotational spectroscopy may beviewed as superior to quantum theory of electronic states.Even the most sophisticated and modern theories of elec-tronic structure do not provide as accurate and reliable adescription of the experimental observations as the moramatura and long-studied theories of vibrational/rotationalspectroscopy. On this basis, it is proper to question whetherthe constructs that arise in orbital theories (e.g., orbitaIs,screening, HOMO-LUMO interactions, bark bonding, etc.)ara as meaningful as the analogous constructs (e.g., Re, "'e,"'eXe,etc.) ofvibrational/rotational spectroscopy. However, I

1 Ogilvie,J. F. J. Cham. Educ. 1990, 67, 280.2 One caR,ot course, pursue things turther and ask whether even

these quantities ara real. I do not intend to enter into Buch a philosoph-ical discussion hera; I choose to detine as real things that most(perhaps BIl) chemists would agree caR be directly measured in thelaboratory (e.g., a photon energy or wavelength, the attenuation ot alight beam, an angle ot scattering ot a light beam, the enthalpy givenoft by a reaction in a calorimeter).

3 In applying Buch spectroscopic energy-Ievel tormulas, one usual-Iy must make assumptions about the equilibrium structure ot themolecule under study. For soma tamilies ot molecules (e.g., highlytluxional molecules and "tloppy" Van der Waals complexes), theobserved rotational/vibrational energy ravel patterns ara not well-represented by the conventional equations. For this reagan, Buchmolecular tamilies pasa new challenges to the spectroscopist; a new"starting point" model is needed to mora accurately and compactlyrepresent their energy level patterns. In this seRsa, the analysis ot"tloppy" molecule vibrational/rotational energies is in the same situ-ation as atomie and molecular electronic structure theory.

Volume 68 Number 2 February 1991 131

feel it is hypocritical to dismiss entirely the constructs of onetheory or model (i.e., orbitaIs) while clinging to the reality,relevance, and value of the constructs of other theories (e.g.,Re, "'eXe,force constants, rate constants).

In summary, if Ogilvie's objections to orbitaIs and theirderivatives bad been based on considerations of accuracyand reliability in making predictions, I would have beenmore in agreement with bim. However, my reading of hispaper leads me to believe he thinks there is something fun-damentally wrong with orbitaIs while there is not somethingequally fundamentally wrong with the constructs of themodels andtheories that relate to other chemical phenome-na (e.g., vibrational/rotational spectra, chemical kinetics, X-ray diffraction, NMR spectra).

It is my belief that orbitaIs are here to stay until they arereplaced by a construct that more efficiently (i.e., accuratelyand compactly) "fits" the experimental data on electronicspectroscopy and molecular shapes. Certainly, we shouldwork to improve the accuracy of the mean-field mode14 onwhich the orbital picture is based, and we should be open tosny replacement ofthe orbitalconcept that more accurately,reliably, and compactly represents our (real) data. However,until we either improve or replace the orbital model, we

'.

should continue to te ach chemistrystudents about the peri-odic table, chemical bonding, electronic spectroscopy, andreactivity using ls, 2s, 2p, 3s, 3p, 4s, 3d, etc., orbitals. Ofcourse, we must algo stress to our students that orbital con-cepts (and rosny other that they will encounter throughouttheir study of chemistry and other sciences) are merely as-pects of the best presently available model; they are not"real" in the same sense that experimental observations are.

4 Mean-tield models ara used in many areas ot chemistry andphysics. In each case, one attempts to represent a many-body prob-lem, in which interparticle interactions make solution ot the appropri-ata equations (e.g., Schrodinger quantum or Newtonian classical orhydrodynamic) impossible, in terms ot a simpler (model) problem. Inso doing, one introduces the average (or mean) interaction ot arepresentattve particie with sIl ot the other particles by "averaging"over a prObability distribution that approximately describes the spatialdistribution ot these other particles. The solution ot this mean-tieldmodel is then used as a starting point in terms ot which to moraaccurately (e.g., by perturbation theoryor variationally) representsolutions to the tuli many-body problem. Such approaches ara usedsuccesstully in many areas ot science and engineering includingclassical astronomy, mechanical engineering, quantum theory, andfluid mechanics.