How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    1/33

    JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL RESEARCH

    VOLUME 36, 2011

    I

    HOW TO BE A KANTIAN ANDA NATURALIST ABOUT

    HUMAN KNOWLEDGE: SELLARSS MIDDLE WAY

    JAMES R. OSHEA

    UNIVERSITY COLLEGE DUBLIN

    ABSTRACT:The contention in this paper is that central to

    Sellarss famous attempt to fuse the manifest image and the

    scientific image of the human being in the world was an at-

    tempt to marry a particularly strong form of scientific naturalism

    with various modified Kantian a priori principles about the unity

    of the self and the structure of human knowledge. The modified

    Kantian aspects of Sellarss view have been emphasized by

    current left wing Sellarsians, while the scientific naturalist

    aspects have been championed by right wing Sellarsians, the

    latter including William Rottschaefers constructive criticisms

    of my own reconciling interpretation of Sellars. In this paper I

    focus first on how (1) Sellarss Kantian conception of the neces-

    sary a priori unity of the thinking self does not conflict with his

    ideal scientific naturalist conception of persons as bundles

    or pluralities of scientifically postulated processes. This then

    prepares the way for a more comprehensive discussion of how

    (2) Sellarss modified Kantian account of the substantive a priori

    principles that make possible any conceptualized knowledge of

    a world does not conflict with his simultaneous demand for an

    ideal scientific explanation and evolutionary account of those

    same conceptual capacities. Sellarss own attempted via media

    synthesiswhat I call his Kantian scientific naturalism

    merits another look from both the left and the right.

    I. INTRODUCTION

    t is no surprise that Kantians have often been hostile to comprehensive

    forms of philosophical naturalism, whether in theoretical or practical philosophy.

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    2/33

    328 JAMES R. OSHEA

    For it is characteristic of the Kantian to argue that there are substantive conceptual

    truths about human cognition and action that can be uncovered by the philosopher

    independently of the results of particular empirical observations and of ongoing

    natural scientific inquiry. Suppose we take naturalism, as I shall take it here, to be

    the particularly controversial thesis that all truths about the human being and the

    world are in principle exhaustivelyexplainableby the methods of ongoing scientific

    inquiry. Admittedly this familiar thesis requires much clarification, each step of

    which would likely be as controversial as the thesis itself; and furthermore, this

    is only one among many ways of understanding naturalism. With naturalism so

    understood, however, it is certainly not hard to understand the traditional hostility

    between the Kantians, with their supposedly substantive a priori conceptual claims

    about the self and any possible knowable world, and the philosophical naturalists

    with their patient and ever knowledge-increasing scientific fallibilism.

    In a recent book, Wilfrid Sellars: Naturalism with a Normative Turn(2007), I

    have argued that Wilfrid Sellars was both a Kantian anda thoroughgoing scientific

    naturalist in something like the traditionally mutually hostile senses described

    above. We might put it in crude terms, in relation to recent philosophical history, as

    follows. In my view, Sellars held that, on the one hand, the sort of updated Kantian

    and later Wittgensteinian views defended by Peter Strawson, for instanceor in

    another tradition, the transcendental phenomenology of Husserlwere right in

    spirit and in fact true in central respects. But they were conceived in a way that

    rendered them incompatible with the ideally all-comprehensive scientific natural-

    ism that Sellars also sought to defend. On the other hand, the broadly scientific

    naturalist outlooks of positivists such as Rudolf Carnap, Herbert Feigl, and Carl

    Hempel, and including the sophisticated successor naturalism of W. V. O. Quine,

    were also right in spirit and correct in central respects. But on Sellarss view both

    positivism and Quinean naturalism ultimately failed to recognize (among other

    things) that genuinely Kantian and Wittgensteinian views about human knowledge,

    intentionality, and agency are in fact essential to achievingin a subtle roundabout

    wayan ideally complete scientific explanation of the nature of the human being

    in the world. In his Autobiographical Reflections Sellars interestingly remarks

    upon his roundabout way of defending a naturalistic materialism as follows:

    Feigl and I shared a common purpose: to formulate a scientifically oriented,

    naturalistic realism which would save the appearances. . . . We hit it off

    immediately, although the seriousness with which I took such ideas as causal

    necessity, synthetic a prioriknowledge, intentionality, ethical intuitionism,

    the problem of universals, etc., etc., must have jarred his empiricist sensi-

    bilities. Even when I made it clear that my aim was to map these structures

    into a naturalistic, even a materialistic, metaphysics, he felt, as many have,

    that I was going around Robin Hoods barn [i.e., taking an unnecessarily

    long route to the same endJOS]. (AR, 289290)

    I hope to show that understanding what Sellars retained from his lonely walk

    around Robin Hoods barnaccompanied by few if any other scientific naturalists,

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    3/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 329

    past or presentis crucial to understanding the unique nature of his naturalistic

    metaphysics.

    In my view, then, Sellarss famous synoptic vision and stereoscopic fusion

    of what he called the manifest image of man-in-the-world and the scientific

    image of man-in-the-world (PSIM) was an attempt to happily marry, by means

    of some deft and persistent matchmaking, the two ostensibly antagonistic figures

    of the Kantian and the scientific naturalist.

    In a judicious and probing examination, Why Wilfrid Sellars is Right (and

    Right-Wing): Thinking with OShea on Sellars, Norms, and Nature, William Rott-

    schaefer (2011) makes a strong case for rejecting central aspects of my interpreta-

    tion of Sellarss synoptic vision, in particular my understanding of the latter as an

    attempt to marry enduring Kantian and later-Wittgensteinian conceptual analyses

    (in a sense of conceptual and analytic that is not restricted to narrowlyanalytic

    truths) with an all-comprehensive scientific-explanatory naturalism. Rottschaefer,

    by contrast, ably defends the so-called right-wing interpretation of what Sellars

    certainly did embrace, namely, the primacy of the scientific image (PSIM, 32).

    The right-wing interpretation typically understands Sellarss synoptic vision in such

    a way that it involves the ultimate scientific replacement rather than the preservation

    of the Kantian and later Wittgensteinian aspects that I emphasize in my reading of

    Sellars. Rottschaefer argues in impressive detail that not only is this a more accu-

    rate reading of Sellars, it also harmonizes with various currently widely embraced

    naturalistic philosophical views that reject Kantian style a priorism in philosophy

    in general. Thus, Rottschaefer argues, there is reason to resist OSheas attempt

    to turn Sellars transcendentally to the left (33);1and on Sellarss account of the

    structure of knowledge, in particular, he contends that OSheas reading runs into

    massive problems, since . . . Sellars rejects Kant, arguing that we can know things

    in themselves because of the successes of the project of scientific knowing that has

    as its ideal the completed scientific image (36).

    The Right-Wing of Rottschaefers title refers, of course, to the distinction

    frequently informally made by Sellarsians between left wing Sellars-influenced

    philosophers, such as (in different ways) Robert Brandom and John McDowell,

    and right wing Sellars-influenced philosophers such as (in different ways) Ruth

    Millikan and Paul Churchland. The left/right distinction, whatever its merits or

    demerits, can roughly be understood in terms of the two sides of Sellarss philoso-

    phy that I have highlighted above. The left wing emphasizes the Kantian and later

    Wittgensteinian (in fact, also Hegelian) aspects of Sellarss views while rejecting

    Sellarss alleged scientism and reductionism. The left has no problem with

    garden varieties of scientific realism about theoretical entities such as electrons,

    etc. (as opposed, for example, to instrumentalism). But the left firmly rejects

    the all-comprehensive scientific naturalist thesis as I articulated it above and as

    expressed in Sellarss notorious scientia mensura claim in Empiricism and the

    Philosophy of Mind (1956) that in the dimension of describing and explaining

    the world, science is the measure of all things, of what is that it is, and of what is

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    4/33

    330 JAMES R. OSHEA

    not that it is not (EPM 42; see also Sellars SSIS, 396397, for Sellarss descrip-

    tion of himself as an Extreme scientific realist even with respect to explaining

    the ultimate nature ofpersons).

    The right, by contrast, fully embraces Sellarss all-comprehensive scientific

    naturalism, but as exemplified by the case of Ruth Millikan, likewise tends to ar-

    gue that there is ultimately a crack in Sellarss system due to his treatment of

    the nature of linguistic rules and the relation of these to conceptual roles and thus

    to intentionality (Millikan 2005, 78). (Note, however, that Rottschaefer himself

    does not argue that there is any crack or tension in Sellarss overall system.) In

    particular the right wing tends to be suspicious of the Kantian a priori and Witt-

    gensteinian conventionalist elements in Sellarss view, ifthese are simply taken

    and left at face value, and are not ultimately fully scientifically naturalized, as

    the right wing argues is frequently the case with Sellarss left-wing admirers. As

    Rottschaefer correctly suggests, right-wing Sellarsians such as Millikan and many

    other contemporary naturalistic philosophers are engaged in developing philosophi-

    cal insights based on evolutionary biology and other domains of scientific inquiry

    in the attempt, inter alia, to naturalistically explain the normative dimensions of

    human language, thought, perception, and action, in the context of wider theories

    of human and other animal cognition and behavior. Rottschaefer argues that while

    Sellars initially articulates those normative dimensions in terms of insights from

    Kant and the later Wittgenstein within the manifest image, Sellars himself envi-

    sioned and would thus embrace the sorts of right-wing naturalistic theories that

    seek ultimately to better explain those normative dimensions in scientific terms.

    All of these left vs. right tangles in the wake of Sellarss philosophy seem to

    suggest that it is difficult if not impossible to bring together the two sides of his

    philosophy into one coherent picturewhich after all was Sellarss own central

    goal (see PSIM passim). On Rottschaefers sophisticated right-wing view, Sellarss

    scientific naturalism is in the endall that we need to make sense of Sellarss ideal

    synoptic vision of the nature of the human-being-in-the-worldand this is a good

    thing, Rottschaefer further contends, given the promise of philosophical naturalism

    in light of recent developments.

    In what follows I take Rottschaefers welcome and insightful criticisms as an

    opportunity to continue the defense of my reconciling middle way (some might

    say, Polyanna) interpretation, according to which Sellarss actual position is such

    that, if successful, it enables us to sustain the centralpositiveclaims of boththe left

    and right wings. This will require further clarifying the nature of Sellarss novel

    attempt to bring about the unlikely marriage described above, as well as responding

    to some more specific objections that are helpfully raised by Rottschaefer.

    II. SELLARSS SYNOPTIC VISION AND HIS

    NORMATIVE FUNCTIONALISM ABOUT THOUGHTS

    I begin with one important issue that has wide ramifications. Here, as in several

    other places in his article, I think that Rottschaefer appropriately raises some pivotal

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    5/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 331

    questions concerning the interpretation of Sellarss philosophy. In his section II on

    Sellarss Functionalism, Rottschaefer comments as follows on the momentous

    character of Sellarss claim concerning the theoretical character of our knowledge

    of both our own and other persons inner thought episodes, which in Empiricism

    and the Philosophy of Mind Sellars had famously defended in terms of the myth

    of genius Jones:

    From the point of view of introspection and philosophical reflection, the

    manifest image of thought, broadly construed, with its propositional attitudes

    of belief and desire what has come to be called folk psychologymay

    appear to be a given. But if Sellars functional role account of intentionality

    is correct that entire framework is a theoretical one replaceable by a more

    adequate scientifically based framework. On the Right-wing account, not

    only is Eddingtons ordinary table replaceable by a scientific table, but so also

    is the manifest image thinker seated at that table. As we shall see, OSheas

    take on the matter is different. (295296)

    I think I am right to have a different take on this matter, for I think that there is a

    subtle, and quite common, yet crucial mistake embodied in the central comparison

    made in the passage from Rottschaefer above. Roughly put, the faulty comparison

    is this: just as (i) the entire manifest image ontology of ordinary, colored physi-

    cal objects is ultimately to be replacedby a more adequate scientifically based

    framework in which, to take a notable example, colors in some sense end up inthe perceiver and notin whatever scientifically conceived processes replace the

    manifest table in the ultimate scientific ontology; in the same way, (ii) with respect

    to the manifest image of thought. . . with its propositional attitudes of belief and

    desire, and including the manifest imagethinker, that entire framework is a

    theoretical one replaceable by a more adequate scientifically based framework

    (italics added).

    The problem with Rottschaefers comparison here, I contend, is that on Sellarss

    view (i) is true, but (ii)in the most important sense to be explained belowis

    false. And I hold that this is essential to understanding Sellarss attempted synopticvision of the nature of persons and their thoughts within an ideal scientific image

    of man-in-the-world. There are crucial respects in which the fate of the manifest

    image conception of persons and their thoughts and intentionsand therefore also

    the communally shared normative standards and ought-to-be rules that make any

    logicalspace of reasons possible, to use Sellarss famous phrase (EPM VIII,

    36)differs from the fate of the manifest image conception of colored physical

    objects. The fate of so-called folk psychology is radically different, on Sellarss

    view of the matter, from the fate of folk physics.

    In particular, there is a primary sense in which, with crucial insights fromperennial philosophers from Kant and Hegel to Wittgenstein and Strawson, and

    culminating in Sellarss own normative functionalist or conceptual role account

    of meaning and intentionality, we have already achievedan adequate conception

    of what it is to be a thought and what it is to be a thinker in general, and we have

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    6/33

    332 JAMES R. OSHEA

    done so without any reliance on the Myth of the Given. We have it now, in the

    philosophically refined manifest image, in a way that is notthe case with respect to

    our (strictly speakingfalse) manifest image conception of what it is to be a colored

    physical object out there in space. And again, this difference is not due to any

    alleged immediate awareness of the ultimate nature of the self and its thoughts as

    inner mythical Givens.

    For interests sake and to avoid repetition, I will begin by exploring this claim

    in relation to some less well-known remarks of Sellarss on the topic. Eventually

    this will bring us to Sellarss conception of what it is to be a thinker, and thereby

    back to general questions concerning the Kantian dimensions of Sellarss scien-

    tific naturalism.

    Compare the passage quoted above from Rottschaefer with the following

    comments from Sellars, which are taken from a Question and Answer session fol-

    lowing the delivery at the University of Notre Dame in 1969 of what became his

    important essay on The Structure of Knowledge (SK). Fortunately the original

    audio recordings have recently been transcribed and made available as Wilfrid

    Sellars: Notre Dame Lectures 19691986the Bootleg Version (WSNDL). I

    do not claim that there is any surprise or smoking gun in these remarks, or that

    they contain any claim that is not also clearly made by Sellars in his published

    writings. But the remarks do help to illustrate the point I want to emphasize.

    (I have added the original audience question, taken from the audio version, to

    Amarals transcript.)

    Audience question put to Sellars: [Y]ou liken the classical philosophical

    postulation of thought episodes, as explanatory of our propensities to speak,

    to what some day, perhaps, will be the last word that neurophysiology has

    to say on why in fact we really do have these propensities to speak. No mat-

    ter how nicely you polish it, it seems as if you make the manifest image a

    nice tryyou know, you have to begin with some error, so well use this

    oneand that ultimately thats going to be just phased out, you know, its

    going to be long gone.

    Sellars reply: I assure you that thats false. I think that human beings are

    always going to think and know that they think. . . . I understand thinking

    to be fundamentally a functional notion, governed by correctnesses and

    rules and validity; the most that the scientific image can do here is to give

    us some notion, in Aristotles sense, for the material cause of thinking

    but theformal cause of thinking is surely afunctionand this is a function

    which exists now and which we think of well now, we understand it well. I

    think that what science can add here is trivial. For me, to say that thought is

    neurophysiological is like saying English contains noises like and, or,

    but, and so on. The actual function of thinking is to be found in the rulesthat govern inferences and the rules that govern the conceptual structures of

    language. . . . We have an adequate notion of what thinking is in its formal

    cause, the most the science can do, if I can use this terminology, is to give

    us the material cause and as I said that is really quite unexciting as far as Im

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    7/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 333

    concerned and that is why I think that as far as human living and the person

    is concerned, the manifest image contains the formal truth and that science

    is going to give an account of the material substructure. (WSNDL, 221222)

    The views expressed in offhand fashion in these remarks are central to Sellarss

    ultimate solution to the problem of integrating theoretical science with the

    framework of sophisticated common sense into one comprehensive synoptic vi-

    sion (PSIM, 19); and they are especially important for understanding his insis-

    tence that, as I see it, the manifest image is not overwhelmed in the synthesis

    (PSIM, 9). To explore this further we first need to see how the case of physical

    objects (i.e., (ii) in the comparison above) differs from the case of thoughts and

    persons gestured at in these remarks; and then in the next section we shall need

    to explain in a bit more detail Sellarss Kantian conception of persons and their

    thoughts, which is the formal truth about human beings that Sellars clearly

    takes to survive all the way into the ideal, final, Peircean scientific image of

    man-in-the-world.

    In the same Question and Answer session Sellars takes it to be crucial to clearly

    distinguish cases (i) vs. (ii), as discussed above. Specifically with regard to the

    idea that the scientific image will replace the manifest image, Sellars comments

    that the most I have ever said is that in its descriptive aspects the scientific image

    could in principle replace the contentualaspects of the manifest image (and he

    here again repeats that we are not going to replace the notion of thinking, all weare going to do is have a better understanding as to what specifically it is that is

    doing those functions) (WSNDL, 223). It is at this point that he remarks that it

    is very important not to suppose that sensation and thought are going to be handled

    in the same way (ibid.). The reason for this is that sensation is quite a different

    sort of thing and it is, in a way, a contentnot a function, like thoughtthat is

    going to remain in the world picture regardless; and it will turn out that the locus

    of color and sound . . . is not in the physical world, but in ourselves (ibid.). In the

    case of color and the other sensible qualities:

    It is not just [that the scientific image is] going to throw a light on it becauseI think it literally would involve a replaceability in the material aspects. I

    think that putting it in Kantian language . . . the world of commonsense solid

    colored objects is a phenomenal world in Kants sense of the term; it is an

    appearance of scientific reality. . . . Let me emphasize that I have had rela-

    tively little to say about values, and standards and norms and obligations . . .

    because, putting it very crudely, I am talking here about the is of the world

    and my whole theory of ethics hasnt been touched on at all. . . . When I talk

    about the in principle replaceability of the manifest image by the scientific

    image, I do so with respect to the contentof the world, its material and not

    with respect to those forms which concern the normative, the obligatory,

    the correct, the incorrect, the valuable. . . . I think Kant is essentially right,

    not only in many of the things he said in a theory of knowledge but also in

    ethics. (WSNDL, 223224)

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    8/33

    334 JAMES R. OSHEA

    Following this passage, on which I shall comment below, Sellars proceeds to discuss

    animal cognition as opposed to human conceptual cognition (a topic which I shall

    also briefly mention), before finally summing up as follows:

    The formal components of the manifest imagethat remains. The formal

    features of the manifest imagewhich are the important features, the features

    that concern the normative, the evaluative, the matter of personal intention

    and so onthese are going to remain in the scientific image. What is going

    to change is the contentualaspect. (WSNDL, 226, slightly re-punctuated)

    Having laid out Sellarss remarks, let us now compare the manifest image claim

    (i) that Smith sees the pink ice cube over there, with the manifest image claim (ii)

    that Smith is thinking that it is raining.

    In the terminology he used above, Sellars holds that there is a particularly prob-lematic material content or contentual aspect involved in (i), an ineliminable

    sensory content that Sellars typically describes as thecube of pink, i.e., a certain

    volume of perceived color. What happens to the iceis a different story, though an

    equally interesting one, because being ice is a causal property rather than aproper

    sensible (pink) or common sensible (cube) quality, in the Aristotelian terms Sellars

    uses. It is the proper and common sensibles that notoriously raise what Sellars called

    the sensorium-body problem, a problem that is closely related to what others call

    the problem of qualia. On familiar, if highly complex and controversial grounds

    (e.g., concerning hallucinations, etc.), Sellars and his mythical genius Jones arguethat the experienced cube of pink, needs to be relocated, as it were (i.e., its true

    location is recognized), by being ontologically reconceived to be a sensory state

    of the manifest image person who is Smith, rather than being an intrinsic content-

    character of the physical ice cube over there. Sellars then leaves Jones and the mani-

    fest image behind and argues that in the ideal scientific image there will need to be

    afurtherreconception of Smiths state of sensing a-cube-of-pink-ly. In this case

    the same sensible content (the volume of pink) is now ontologically reconceived as

    a bottom-level and in some sense non-physical (i.e., physical1-but-not-physical

    2,

    in Sellarss technical terminology) absolute process (a sensing) that is takingplace in whatever Smiths visual cortex turns out to be, causally interacting with

    whatever (physical2) quarkings, electronings, and other absolute processes will

    ultimately be revealed to make up Smiths living body.2

    In relation to claim (i), then, Sellars holds that the core contentthat is involved

    in seeing (or merely vividly seeming to see) a pink ice cubenamely, the sensed

    cube of pinkneeds to be preserved throughout a long journey of reconception as

    to what ontological kind or category of item (quality of object? state of perceiver?

    absolute pure process?) that same contentual cube of pink will ultimately turn

    out to be. Hence the special importance of the rejection of the Myth of the Givenin this domain, since the Myth would allege, inter alia, that what kind of thing a

    sensory appearance isits ontological nature and location, as it wereis Given

    immediately with the conscious sensing of it.3Claim (i), then, when viewed in

    light of the regulative ideal of the conjectured final scientific image, turns out to be

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    9/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 335

    strictly speaking false (because there really is nopink ice cube of the kind conceived

    in the manifest image). In another sense, of course, the manifest image claim (i)

    is intelligibly and in some sense approximately true, in that the appearances

    embodied in the manifest image conception will turn out to be explainedin terms

    of the ultimately correct recategorization in the final scientific successor theory. (A

    similar process occurs in scientific theory-replacementin general.)

    What about claim (ii), the manifest image claim that Smith is thinking that it

    is raining? Roughly put, this claim will be true, on genius Joness initial model, if

    Smith is either candidly saying out loud, or has a short term propensity to say out

    loud, It is raining, i.e., in a way that accords with the normatively rule-governed

    conceptual role (functional role, inferential role) that gives that sentence its meaning

    in English. And then on the theory of genius Jones, which starts from that rule-

    governed verbal model, claim (ii) will be true if there was somethinggoing on in

    Smiths soul or brain or heart (or whatever, as far as genius Jones, still within the

    manifest image, is concerned) that is playing a functional role relevantly similar to

    that played by the utterance-type, It is raining (more strictly, an it is raining),

    but this time occurring silently in Mentalese, as Sellars calls it, i.e., in something

    likea language of thought.

    What does the ongoing scientific image then add to Joness initial theoretical

    enrichment, an enrichment that takes place within the manifest image (i.e., Joness

    postulation is of new inner statesof the same old manifest imagepersons)? Scientific

    inquiry adds a series of more detailed, perhaps in some cases revolutionary theories

    concerning how the conceptual roles or semantical rule-governed functions that,

    on Sellarss view, are definitive of both inner and outer conceptual thinking, are

    in fact realized in whatever will turn out to have been the real material vehicles

    of our thoughts all along. We soon forget about hearts and souls, for example, and

    concentrate on brains. Then we have ongoing scientific and philosophical inquiries

    into the nature of the representational medium in the brainquestions that were

    wisely left wide open by Sellars (as correctly noted by Dennett on Sellars in his

    1987 book, The Intentional Stance). Perhaps, for example, the brain does not carry

    information in the sort of symbol-processingway that Sellars might have projected

    for his Mentalese, but rather in something more like the parallel distributed pro-

    cessing way anticipated by connectionists, including eliminativists such as Paul

    Churchland (who was Sellarss Ph.D. student). There are certainly complex issues

    involved here, but the remarks above (along with his other writings, I believe) sug-

    gest that Sellars would not accept the eliminativist conclusions that Churchland

    attempts to draw from the projected neurophysiological facts.

    Let us suppose, finally, that the Peircean ideal scientific image of man-in-the-

    world is completed. What might we anticipate to be the conception of conceptual

    thinking and intentional action in that final vision, on Sellarss view? Whereas with

    respect to claim (i) and the manifest image conception of the pink ice cube or the

    red apple, to recall the passage from Rottschaefer quoted earlier, it is true that

    that entire framework is . . . replaceable by a more adequate scientifically based

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    10/33

    336 JAMES R. OSHEA

    framework, there is an important sense in which the same is not true with respect

    to claim (ii). Whatever very different things people might be thinking aboutin that

    future timei.e., however radically differently conceived the inner and outer objects

    of their thoughts might be4and whatever they might have discovered to be the

    neurophysiological or behavioral-cum-environmental vehiclesof their thoughts,

    the manifest image account of what it is to be a thinking that p, on Sellarss view,

    remains true and is not replaced. Conceptually contentful thoughts are inner and

    outer inferential role-players, where the relevant roles (in the case of logic-using

    animals) are determined by the socially maintained, rule-governed linguistic norms

    that constitute a given logical space of reasons (EPM, 36).

    The semantical rules, in Sellarss sense, and hence the contents of thinkable

    thoughts, will of course change as new conceptual frameworks replace old ones.

    But the ontology of thoughts, in the sense of accounting for what it is to be a

    thought and what it is to be a thinker, remains the same account across changing

    conceptual frameworks, and will remain the same in the ideal scientific image of

    thinkers-in-the-world. Changes in the conceptual roles that constitute the contents

    of thinkable thoughts, however radical such changes might be in the course of

    scientific theory-succession, do not involve the replacement of the conception

    of thoughts as normatively rule-governed inferential role-players. The process

    of conceptual change in that sense must be clearly distinguished from the sort of

    recategorization of the nature of objects that Sellars thinks is involved in scien-

    tific theory-succession, whether the latter concerns the problem of the nature and

    location of color in particular, or the ultimate categorial structure of physical

    reality in general.

    So in relation to the sensible qualities and claim (i), as Sellars remarked above,

    we in some sense have a contentthat is going to remain in the world picture regard-

    less (WSNDL, 211), but the ontological categorization of this preserved content

    does indeed undergo radical replacement from the manifest image conception to the

    ideal scientific image. In the case of thoughts and claim (ii), however, the opposite

    is the case: the realizing contentual aspect or material vehicles of thought are

    what undergo radical reconceptualization and replacement. But the correct ontologi-

    cal categorization of what it is to be a thought, and of what it is to be a thinker, is

    already at hand in the manifest image, and in particular in that image as it continues

    to be refined by what Sellars calls the perennial philosophy (PSIM passim). The

    crucial insights in this domain, as interpreted by Sellars, were: (1) Kants formal,

    broadly logical conception of concepts as rules, together with his corresponding

    formal accounts of what it is to be a thinking selfin aknowable world; (2) Ryle

    and the later Wittgensteins so-called meaning as use conceptions of meaning and

    thinking, with the focus on norm-governed linguistic behavior (communal aspects

    of which were anticipated by Hegel and Peirce); and building on those insights,

    (3) Sellarss normative-functionalist philosophy of mind as described above, as

    well as his modified Kantian conceptions of self and knowledge to be explored in

    the sections to follow.

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    11/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 337

    It follows from the above that Rottschaefers thesis that, according to Sellarss

    way of integrating the two global images, the claims of the manifest image are

    false (7), is problematic with respect to certain definitive formal features of

    persons, their thoughts, and their intentions. I shall say more about this difficult

    issue in the next section. Rottschaefer also has many important things to say about

    goal-directed normativity in nature during the course of his discussion of Sellarss

    functionalism, and I shall briefly return to some of those issues later.

    III. SELLARSS MODIFIED KANTIAN VIEW OF

    PERSONS AS LOGICALLY UNITARY THINKERS

    In the substantial middle sections III and IV of his article, Rottschaefer rightly

    raises some pressing questions concerning the Kantian aspects of my interpreta-tion of Sellarss views on the structure of empirical knowledge. Here I will begin

    by taking up a difficult question left hanging from the previous section: namely,

    what is it to be a humanpersonon Sellarss overall stereoscopic integration of the

    manifest and scientific images of man-in-the-world?

    In one sense Sellarss various writings make clear that he wants to defend the

    view that the scientific image will ultimately reveal the real truth about persons to

    be as follows (see in particular Sellarss SSIS, i.e., his lengthy Reply to Cornman).

    While in the philosophically refined manifest image we conceive a person to be the

    single logical subject of its various thoughts and feelings, the ideal scientific imagewill reveal that a person is reallya complex system (a plurality, a series, a group)

    of whatever logical subjects turn out to be explanatorily basic in that scientific

    image. On Sellarss way of anticipating the latter, a person would be a bundle

    of absolute processes (FMPP III.125). It might seem, then, that the conception

    of persons in the manifest image is, after all, strictly speakingfalse, in the way

    that the manifest image conception of the colored table is revealed to be strictly

    speaking false, though ultimately scientifically explainable. Obviously this issue

    bears directly on my interpretation of the comparison between claims (i) and (ii)

    discussed in the previous section.Ifthe conception of the self within the philosophically refined manifest image

    did consist in the positive ontological assertion that a person isa certain (conten-

    tual) kindof thing, in particular, that the self isa single (substantial, persisting,

    identical) objecti.e., a logical subject in the sense of being a basic subject of

    propertiesthen the truth of the ideal scientific image of the person as a basic plu-

    rality of items wouldentail the falsity of the manifest image conception of persons.

    But Sellarss modified Kantian conception of persons within the manifest image

    precisely does not have that consequence. The purpose of Sellarss endorsement

    of central aspects of Kants arguments in the Paralogismssection of the Critiqueof Pure Reasonis precisely to hammer home the point that the idea of a unitary

    logical subject occurs in two different senses when one is considering the idea of

    a thinkeras a unified subject of its thoughts, as opposed to when one is considering

    the nature of the thinker as a kind of object.

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    12/33

    338 JAMES R. OSHEA

    In the manifest image, Sellars holds, our concept of a person is that of a

    system of capacities pertaining to the various modes of thinking (MP, 239), and

    such a system necessarilyrepresents itself as a unitary thinking self: the I think

    as the single logical subject of its various successive thoughts. (The crucial role

    of those particular thoughts that are intentions, in Sellarss account of persons and

    normativity, will be mentioned below.) Without attempting to reconstruct Sellarss

    detailed analysis of Kants Paralogisms in his striking essay, . . . this I or he or

    it (the thing) which thinks . . . (I; cf. MP), it is clear that Sellars endorses Kants

    central arguments in the Paralogisms, while rejecting certain wider aspects of

    Kants view in which those arguments are embedded. In the end this turns out to

    have implications not only for Sellarss synoptic vision of the nature of persons,

    but also for his account of the structure of human knowledge.

    What Sellars primarily rejects are certain mistaken aspects of, and resulting

    limitations imposed by, Kants conception of the material(for Kant, phenomenal)

    world in Newtonian Space and Time. In particular, Sellars argues that we must

    add to Kants analysis Sellarss own scientific-theoretical, analogical conception

    of space and time as pertaining to ultimately real things in themselves (see SM

    chapters one and two). In this way, Sellars also rejects what he characterizes as

    Kants agnosticism about the ultimate noumenal reality of persons or thinking

    selves. The incorrect aspects of Kants view force him into an empirical dualism

    about the empirical self, as opposed to what Sellars takes to be the broadly correct

    Strawsonian conception of persons (within the manifest image) as materially em-

    bodied subjects possessing intellectual capacities. But what he thinks the correct

    aspects of Kants analysis of persons as thinking selves deliberately and coherently

    leaves open is the possibility that, while a thinker necessarily represents itself as

    a single logical subject of its plurality of thoughts, such a thinker could turn out,

    as a thing in itself, to be an ultimateplurality of basic logical subjects (Sellars

    cites A363, for example). For Sellars, but not for Kant (given the incorrect aspects

    of his view), this plurality can coherently turn out to be a materialplurality of

    scientifically basic items. The following passage illustrates what Sellars wants to

    endorse from Kant and then put to his own non-Kantian use:

    [Kant] is suggesting that the logical identity of the I through Time, which

    is an analytic implication of the knowledge of oneself as thinking different

    thoughts at different times, is compatible with the idea that these thoughts

    are successive states of different ultimate subjects. Compare the materialist

    who argues that the thoughts which make up the history of an I are states of

    systems of material particles which are constantly losing old and gaining

    new constituents.

    Thus although I do not represent my successive thoughts as successive

    states of a series of different subjects of attributes, and do not need to doso in order to know my logical identity through the period in which these

    thoughts occur, a being with suitable cognitive powers [JOS: God for Kant,

    the ideal scientific image for Sellars] might know me to be such a series.

    This insight, however, would not require him to say that my knowledge of

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    13/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 339

    myself as logically identical through the period of time in question is an

    illusion, but only that the logical identity of the I as I represent itis not an

    adequate conceptualization of the nature of our thinking being. (I, 2728)

    To begin with the final sentence, Sellars is notsaying that an ideally adequate

    knowledge of what the self is in itself would reveal that the manifest thinking self,

    like the colored manifest table, is a strictly speaking false but approximately true

    appearance in the same sense as such manifest physical objectsas the colored

    table or the pink ice cube discussed earlier. Kants analytic conception of the

    knowledge of oneself as thinking different thoughts is what discloses asparalo-

    gistic (i.e., a fallacious equivocation) any attempt to regard the logically necessary

    unity of any thinking self as requiring or enabling the knowledge of the self as any

    kind of objectat all. The correct aspects of Kants analysis of the necessary unity

    of any thinking self, that is, does not involve the framework conception of a kind of

    objectthat could even be coherently thought of as undergoing scientific correction

    by being categorially reconceived in the ideal scientific image in the way that the

    cube of pink does get categorially relocated (so to speak), thereby revealing

    the manifest image conception of pink physical ice cubes to be, strictly speaking,

    false.5What makes the scientific image conception of persons more adequateis

    that it doesreveal the ultimate nature of our thinking being (namely, as an ulti-

    mate plurality of items), while the necessary analytic unity of any diachronically

    thinking self, which Sellars embraces from Kants analysis, does not even involve

    taking a shot at such an object of knowledge.

    So, in the ideal scientific image, will there be (1) any logically unitary thinking

    selveswho are engaged in the business of fully adequately conceptually represent-

    ing the world, and (2) doing so solely in terms of the representation of scientifically

    conceived objects and processes? Yes, there necessarily will be, given: (1) the

    necessary conditions that Sellars argues (following Kant and Wittgenstein) must

    be satisfied for there to be such a thing as thelogically structured conceptual rep-

    resentationof a world at all; and (2) Sellarss conceptionabout which, I think,

    sophisticated right-wingers such as Rottschaefer are correctof what the ideallycomprehensive scientific image of man-in-the-world ultimately will represent

    to be the fundamental contents or basic objects (or pure processes) in the world

    (cf. note 4 above).

    The crucial point is that the ideal scientific-naturalistic representation of all

    objects and processes in the world involved in (2) does not conflict with (1), i.e.,

    with the perennial Kantian conception of the self in relation to any conceptually

    knowable world, a conception that I think Sellars clearly adopted and adapted while

    subtracting what he takes to be Kants detachable errors. The fact that Kant was

    ultimately wrong about the nature and status of the represented objects in the world,on Sellarss view, does not invalidate central aspects of Kants conception of what

    anyconceptual representation of a worldeven in ideal scientific termsrequires.

    It is ultimately a non-trivial analytictruth, on Sellarss reading of Kant (and in this

    respect, according to Sellarss own view), that any such conceptual representation of

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    14/33

    340 JAMES R. OSHEA

    a world is possible onlyfor a being that represents itself as having the sort of logi-

    cal identity that is embodied in the representation, I think. And that conceptual

    representation, which takes place within the manifest image, is the key aspect of

    the manifest image that is preserved(not overwhelmed) within the ideal scientific

    image. That is, it is preserved ifwe can assume that there are any conceptual thinkers

    representing a world in that ideal scientific imagewhich of course, we can, given

    that an image, on Sellarss view, is precisely a conceptual frameworkthat represents

    the world as being a certain way. Furthermore that conceptual representation, i.e.,

    the logically unitary representation I think in relation to a manifold of thoughts,

    is on Sellarss view not falsebut rather true, although it is also not an adequate rep-

    resentation of the nature of the self since it remains agnostic about the underlying

    noumenal plurality of scientifically conceived processes that, on Sellarss view,

    such thinking selves ultimately really are. These are deep and controversial Kantian

    waters, yes. But those are the waters in which Sellars swam, from start to finish.

    At any rate, I hope that the above helps to clarify my understanding of the

    passage from Sellars with which I ended my book (and for this opportunity I am

    thankful for Rottschaefers criticisms):

    The heart of the matter is the fact that the irreducibility of the I within the

    framework of first person discourse . . . is compatible with the thesis that

    persons can (in principle) be exhaustively described in terms which involve

    no reference to such an irreducible subject. For the description will mention

    rather than usethe framework to which these logical subjects belong. Kant

    saw that the transcendental unity of apperception is a form of experience

    rather than a disclosure of ultimate reality. If persons are really multiplici-

    ties of logical subjects, then unless these multiplicities used the conceptual

    framework of persons there would be no persons. But the idea that persons

    really are such multiplicities does not require that concepts pertaining to

    persons be analysable intoconcepts pertaining to sets of logical subjects.

    Persons may really be bundles, but the concept of a person is not the con-

    cept of a bundle. (PH, 101)

    IV. SELLARSS MODIFIED KANTIAN VIEW OF

    THE NECESSARY STRUCTURE OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE

    The preceding discussion of Sellarss modified Kantian conception of the thinking

    self is connected with his theory of knowledge in ways that Sellars explored in a

    variety of writings throughout his career. Here I will begin by continuing with Sel-

    larss article, . . . this I or he or it (the thing) which thinks . . . The correct aspects

    of Kants view of the thinking self and the transcendental unity of apperception,

    as Sellars explains, begins with an

    unrestrictedprinciple in the philosophy of mind, which transcends the dis-

    tinction between the noumenal and the phenomenal self, to the effect that

    an I thinks of a manifold

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    15/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 341

    is not to be confused with

    an I has a manifold of thoughts.

    . . . The ways in which many thinkings constitute one thinking are the formsof thought, e.g., the categories. The recognition of the radical difference

    between categorial forms and matter-of-factual relationships is the pons

    asinorumof the Critical Philosophy. (I, 78)

    Before continuing the analysis of the correct aspects of Kants view here, let me

    briefly digress on an important point. For the final sentence in this passage reflects

    another way in which Sellars criticizes Kants agnosticism about things in

    themselves, one that Rottschaefer correctly describes in his section IV, but that he

    incorrectly takes to be incompatible with my reading of Sellars and Kant.

    Ultimately, in order show how language hooks up with the world, Sellars, onmy readingwhich in this respect is congenial to the right-wingers but notto the

    left-wingersthinks that we must provide a naturalistic theory of representation

    (or picturing) that explains how all of the Kantian and Wittgensteinian rule-

    governed epistemic activity I am describing really succeeds in mappingmatter-

    of-factual occurrences among things in themselves. John McDowell from the

    left, for example, rejects this sort of sideways on attempt to naturalistically

    explain (in the sense of naturalism I am using here) how our representations

    ultimately succeed in corresponding to and correctly representing objects in the

    world. On the importance both philosophically and to Sellars (but notto Kant)of this sort of comprehensive attempt to naturalistically explainhow our mental

    representations hook up to the world, I am with Rottschaefer, Millikan, and the

    other right-wingers, contrary to what Rottschaefer suggests. (Furthermore, I am

    with the right wing in holding that, according to Sellars, even the content and

    efficacy of those community-based conceptualized intentions that constitute ratio-

    nal normativity itself (i.e., within a logicalspace of reasons) must be susceptible

    to an ultimate scientific explanationin naturalistic terms. But here, too, Sellarss

    account of those we-intentions that generate rational normative principles is

    given a Kantianformaltwist, as we go around Robin Hoods barn, that is noteliminatedin the final synoptic vision of man-in-the-world. I shall comment

    upon this point in the final section.)

    What apparently distinguishes my reading of Sellarss middle way from both

    the left-wingers and the right-wingers is that I think the whole point of the subtle

    Kantian aspects of Sellarss unifying stereoscopic vision is to argue that Sellarss

    bold (and non-Kantian) attempt to comprehensively naturalistically explain the

    ultimate nature of our intentional and epistemic activities within the ideal scientific

    image is consistentwiththe enduring formal truth, as we saw him call it earlier,

    of the Kantian and equally Sellarsian conception of thinkers and thoughts (andrational normativity itself) that I have been trying to articulate here and in the book.6

    To return to the passage from Sellars quoted above, for our present purposes

    I will continue to take its central Kantian claim concerning the necessary unity

    of the I think in all conceptual thinking both to be true (it is of course not

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    16/33

    342 JAMES R. OSHEA

    uncontroversial) and to be endorsed by Sellars. Sellars immediately continues that

    passage as follows:

    In epistemology, which, as concerned with good thinking in its variousmodes, is a fortioriconcerned with thinking as such, this general principle

    becomes the epistemic principle that any true content of thought, e.g., that

    Socrates is wise, must, in principle, be an element in a certain kind of larger

    context, e.g.,

    an I thinks the true thought of a world in which Socrates is wise [italics

    added].

    Roughly, the form of empirical knowledge is: an I thinking (however sche-

    matically) the thought of a temporal system of states of affairs to which any

    actual state of affairs belongs.Thus, in the Transcendental Analytic, the above unrestricted principle

    about thinking provides the clue to the form of the phenomenal world. This

    world is a presented world, and Space, Time, and the Categories are its

    forms. (I, 910)

    On my interpretation, Sellars agrees with the Kantian epistemic principle that

    any true content of thought must be an element in a certain kind of larger con-

    text, which is roughly, an I thinking (however schematically) the thought of a

    temporal system of states of affairs to which any actual state of affairs belongs. I

    think Sellars, in this respect similar to Strawson, regards this as a truth about thepossibility of any discursive representation of an objective state of affairs. Where

    he particularly disagrees with Kant is with respect to complex issues concerning

    realism and idealism, in particular with respect to the possibilities for the sort of

    world-in-itself that we might come justifiably to represent.

    The issue is especially complex because Sellars agreeswith Kant that the world

    as conceived in the manifest image is phenomenal or transcendentally ideal,

    but not because of the Kantian epistemic principle described above. Sellars makes

    clear in the second chapter of his Science and Metaphysicsthat he rejects most of

    Kants ownreasons for being a transcendental idealist, and accepts only a versionof Sellarss own argument from the categorial relocation of colored physical ob-

    jects when we move from the manifest image to the scientific image, as described

    earlier (SM, II 5879). This fits nicely the reading I gave above in section II of

    Sellarss views on the crucial differences between (i) the ultimate falsity (and for

    Sellars, transcendental ideality) of the manifest image claims concerning manifest

    pink ice cubes and other colored physical objects, as opposed to (ii) the perennial

    formal truth of manifest image claims concerning thinkers and their thoughts.

    Sellars thinks Kant was right to treat the manifest image of common sense objects

    as phenomenal, but only for Sellarss reasons concerning the ultimate falsity ofthe framework-conception of the objectsin the manifest image.

    Sellars also thinks Kant was right with respect to the necessary holistic and

    systematic conceptual requirements on having any true thought about a temporal

    state of affairs. But Kant also failed to see how the rule-governed holistic framework

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    17/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 343

    of self-conscious human knowledge can (and must) itselfbe given a sideways on

    scientific explanation in naturalistic terms, in terms of things in themselves. The

    latter, boldly naturalistic explanatory task, which targets the nature of human cogni-

    tion and action themselves as objectsa task which the left-wing Sellarsians regard

    as misguided, but about the importance of which to Sellars I think Rottschaefer

    and I agreewill itself be an instanceof the sort of conceptual representation of a

    world, by self-conscious human thinkers (i.e., logically unitary subjects of thought),

    that Sellars thinks Kant correctly analyzed.

    Within Sellarss own view, what modified form do the holistic Kantian epis-

    temic principles take concerning the necessary conditions for the possibility of the

    conceptual representation of a world, which I claim Sellars endorsed for conceptual

    representings in anyimage, whether manifest or scientific, while rejecting certain

    of Kants limitations upon them? In his Autobiographical Reflections Sellars

    remarks as follows on his early encounters with Kant at Oxford:

    Kant wasnt attempting to prove that in addition toknowing facts about im-

    mediate experience, one alsoknew facts about physical objects, but rather

    that a skeptic who grants knowledge of even the simplest fact about an event

    occurring in Time is, in effect, granting knowledge of the existence of nature

    as a whole. I was sure he was right. But his own question haunted me. How

    is itpossiblethat knowledge has this structure? (AR, 285)

    Sellars then comments that it wasnt until much later that I came to see that thesolution of the puzzle lay in correctly locating the conceptual order in the causal

    order and correctly interpreting the causality involved (AR, 285286). What the

    latter is designed to naturalistically support is the former, Kantian epistemological

    formal insight (based on a perennial philosophical analysis) that knowledge neces-

    sarilyhas a certain systematic holistic structure: namely, that granting knowledge

    of even the simplest fact . . . is, in effect, granting knowledge of the existence of

    nature as a whole.

    Rottschaefer carefully considers the attempt in my book to bring to the surface

    a variety of Sellarss own modified versions of the Kantian epistemic principlesdiscussed above in several of his works, in particular with respect to my use of Sel-

    larss Some Remarks on Kants Theory of Experience (KTE), More on Givenness

    and Explanatory Coherence (MGEC), and the Structure of Knowledge (SK).

    Here is a characteristic snippet from SK (see Rottschaefer, 305): We have to be in

    this framework[of epistemic meta-principles] to be thinking and perceiving beings

    at all; and furthermore,

    the exploration of these principles is but part and parcel of the task of

    explicating the conceptof a rational animal or, in VB [verbal behaviorist]

    terms, of a language-using organism whose language is aboutthe world inwhich it is used. It is only in the light of this larger task that the problem

    of the status of epistemic principles reveals its true meaning. (SK, 4546,

    first italics added)

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    18/33

    344 JAMES R. OSHEA

    Or as Sellars puts it in the more explicitly Kantian context of KTE, with Kants

    views modified by Sellarss linguistic turn:

    Transcendental linguistics . . . is not limited to the epistemic functioning ofhistorical languages in the actual world. It attempts to delineate the general

    features that would be common to the epistemic functioning of any language

    in any possible world. As I once put it, epistemology, in the new way of

    words, is the theory of what it is to be a language that is about a world in

    which it is used. Far from being an accidental excrescence, Kants tran-

    scendental psychology is the heart of his system. He, too, seeks the general

    features any conceptual system must have in order to generate knowledge

    of a world to which it belongs. (KTE, 41)

    What Kants formal philosophical analysis correctlyrevealed, according to Sellars,

    is that any conceptual system must, if there are to be any such things as concep-

    tualized thoughts of a sensible world of temporally locatable events at all, have a

    structure according to which there are warrantedmeta-principles pertaining to the

    correctness of language entry perceptions and material inference principles in

    general (see, e.g., KTE, 37; and SM: chapter four, 61, and chapter five, 30).7

    Where we must go beyond Kants agnosticism about things in themselves, ac-

    cording to Sellars, is in relation to the ongoing scientific naturalist project conceived

    as extending to both of the following tasks: (a) Explaining how rule-governed

    linguistic behaviour and the (rational and non-rational) animal cognition of objectsin an environment actually works, as for example including a naturalistic theory

    of mental and linguistic representation. And ultimately, (b) providing a natural-

    istic answer to the question How did we get in to the framework? constituted

    by conceptual thinking and hence by epistemic meta-principles in the first place,

    which Sellars says [p]resumably . . . has a causal answer consisting in a special

    application of evolutionary theory to the emergence of beings capable of conceptu-

    ally representing the world of which they have come to be a part (MGEC, 79).

    Upon closer examination I still find, despite Rottschaefers critical comments

    on my reading of the Kantian-formal dimension of Sellarss theory of knowledge,that each of the articles KTE, SK, and MGEC strongly confirms the reading of Sel-

    larss complex relationship to Kant that I have given in this paper and in the book.

    I will try to be brief here, although Rottschaefers analysis is admirably detailed.

    Many of Rottschaefers criticisms here and throughout his article have to do

    with my alleged view that, on Sellarss view, nature as pictured in the scientific

    image is bereft of goal-directed normativity. In fact, however, I hold that Sellars

    stressed the importance to present and future science of ideal evolutionary explana-

    tory accounts of both kinds of goal-directed animal representational systems, as

    Sellars called them in his important late article, Mental Events (MEV, passim):namely, the rational or Aristotelian logic-using kind of animal representational

    system, involving conceptual representationproper(and hence, a logical space

    of reasons); and the Humean, non-logic-using yet quasi-propositional kind of

    animal cognition of objects. Sellars thought that in the ideal scientific image there

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    19/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 345

    would be complex evolutionary and behavioural-learning explanations(rather than

    conceptual analyses) of bothkinds of goal-directed processes in nature. On this I

    am at one with Rottschaefer, and I have tried to explain above how I think Sellarss

    modified Kantian conceptual analyses are consistent with the idea of such an ideally

    complete naturalistic explanation. It should be pointed out, however, that for Sellars

    the goal-directedness of non-logic-using Humean animal representational systems

    is cashed out in terms of the wider context of natural selection in a way that does

    not require the additional considerations that pertain to persons and logic-using

    Aristotelian animal representational systems. Accounting for the overall coher-

    ence and justificatory structure of the latter systems requires not only a complex

    causal account of how language and thought evolved by natural selection out of the

    former representational systems, but also the independent philosophical account

    of the necessary structure of conceptual knowledge that Sellars is providing on the

    backs of his colleagues from the perennial philosophical tradition.

    So while such evolutionary explanations in the ideal scientific image would

    explain how it is possible that human beings came to possess the sort of conceptual-

    linguistic abilities that we do possess, I do not claim that Sellars regarded the

    justification of his modified Kantian epistemic principles, which pertain to logi-

    calrepresentational systems, as being provided by those projected ideal scientific

    explanations (see Rottschaefer on the split personality of my Sellars, 302).

    Sellarss account of the ultimate justification of those fundamental Kantian epistemic

    principlesin Sellarss view, principles that concern (as Rottschaefer recounts)

    the necessary elements in a conceptual framework which defines what it is to

    be a finite knower in a world one never made (MGEC, IV, 73; and similarly in

    KTE and SK, III)comes from theperennial conceptual analysisside rather than

    the complementary ongoing scientific explanatoryside of his subtle stereoscopic

    view. Such justification is ultimately due to updated versions of what Sellars took

    to be right about Kants philosophical analysis of the conceptually necessary

    conditions for any conceptual representation of an empirically mind-independent

    world. Sellars explicitly endorses such an account when he refers, for example, to

    the pure pragmatics or transcendental logic of empirical knowledge as such,

    where the former, of course, refers to one way in which he framed his own overall

    philosophical framework (TTC, 51). But he carefully disagrees with Kant in all

    those key places where he argues that Kant shut off the possibility of Sellarss own

    scientific naturalism about things as they ultimately are in themselves.

    Where my view is relatively silent, and where Rottschaefer has helpful further

    proposals to recommend in relation to recent philosophical and scientific theorizing,

    is where I think Sellarss view remained prudently quiet, too: namely, in relation to

    any details concerning the projected ideal scientific explanation of how linguistic-

    conceptual capacities evolvedin the human species in the first place (see OShea

    2007, 85 and n13; and Rottschaefer 2011, 296ff.). I did say quite a lot in the book

    about closely related matters concerning which Sellars himself said quite a lot, in

    particular about the possibility of an ideal behavioral-functionalist account of what

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    20/33

    346 JAMES R. OSHEA

    it is to acquire the ability to haveconceptualized thoughts and norm-instituting

    intentions within and across inherited conceptual frameworks in general. This is an

    account according to which both naturalistic and normative elements track one

    another in complex relations of interdependence that I briefly encapsulated in what

    I called Sellarss norm-nature meta-principle. But Rottschaefer and I agree on the

    right-wing view that Sellars envisioned both kinds of overall explanation, referred

    to above, within the ideal scientific image. Rottschaefer rejects my attempt to argue

    that the formal epistemological truths about thinkers and their knowledge that Sel-

    lars embraced and modified from the perennial philosophy are consistent within

    fact synoptically fused withthat projected ideal scientific explanation. What I

    dont see is why my attempt to interpret Sellarss synoptic vision as preserving both

    the substantive neo-Kantian conceptual analyses and the projected ideal scientific

    explanationsboth of them concerning the same rule-governed linguistic-conceptual

    phenomena, one from the side of broadly empirically warranted scientific explana-

    tion and the other from the side of perennial philosophical analysisis guilty of

    producing a Sellars with a split personality in any sense that involves inconsistency,

    as Rottschaefer seems to suggest. I think Sellarss stereoscopic vision is precisely a

    delicate simultaneous combination of those two dimensions, the ongoing scientific-

    explanatory and the philosophical-analytic, in one coherent view.

    What is the ultimate justification for the Kantian epistemic principles that I

    have suggested Sellars adapts from Kant in modified form? In an important sense,

    Sellars rejected Kants notion of the synthetic a priori, as Rottschaefer correctly

    notes (although Rottschaefer does not register the sense in which Sellars alsoclearly

    sought to preserve a pragmatic and framework-relativized version of something

    akin to the synthetic a priori, but this is not my main concern in this paper); and

    Sellars also rejected, as Rottschaefer notes, what he calls the this or nothing

    justification of epistemic principles that he finds in Chisholm and says is familiar

    to the Kantian tradition (SK, III, 43).

    Sellarss view is that Kant justified his synthetic a priori meta-principles by

    embeddingthem within what is ultimately an analysisof the conceptually neces-

    sary conditions on any conceptual representation of temporal states-of-affairs in a

    world, as explained earlier. Like the good non-traditional, Kantian empiricist that

    he is, Sellars does not think that anything other than (broadly) logico-conceptual

    and (broadly) empirical warrants are ultimately required for this Kantian analysis, at

    bottom. But Kants analysis has a complex and illuminating structure, according to

    Sellars, and hence is in its own way explanatory. It is in fact one of the two dimen-

    sions of explanatory coherencethat is embodied in the complex that is theory T,

    to be discussed in the next section in relation to Sellarss MGEC. And contrary to

    what Rottschaefer suggests, Sellars thinks that such an analysis does carry weight

    against scepticism, despite not engaging in the futile task of attempting to provide

    apresuppositionlessproof that there exists such a thing as empirical knowledge

    (see TTC, VIII, e.g., 53). Here is how Sellars puts these subtle methodological

    and interpretive points concerning Kant in KTE (see also TTC, part VIII):

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    21/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 347

    (10) It is obvious to the beginning student that the truths of transcenden-

    tal logic cannot themselves be synthetic a priori. If they were, then any

    transcendental demonstration that objects of empirical knowledge conform

    to synthetic universal principles in the modality of necessity [JOS: whichSellars himselfholds, too] would be question-begging. It must in a tough

    sense be an analytictruth that objects of empirical knowledge conform to

    logically synthetic universal principles. It must however, also be an illumi-

    nating analytic truth, far removed from the trivialities established by the

    unpacking of body in to extended substance and brother into male

    sibling. [In a footnote here Sellars says that the concluding chapters of the

    Critique show that Kant himself understood that transcendental logic

    as knowledge about knowledge could consist of analytic knowledge about

    synthetic knowledge.](11) It is also obvious, on reflection, that Kant is not seeking toprovethat

    there is empirical knowledge, but only to show that the concept is a coher-

    ent one and that it is such as to rule out the possibility that there could be

    empirical knowledge not implicitly of the form such and such a state of

    affairs belongs to a coherent system of states of affairs of which my percep-

    tual experiences are a part. By showing this, he undercuts both the skeptic

    and the problematic idealist who, after taking as paradigms of empirical

    knowledge items that seem to involve no intrinsic commitment to such a

    larger context, raise the illegitimate question of how one can justifiably movefrom these items to the larger context to which we believethem to belong.

    What Sellars rejects are unexplicated, primitive, dogmatic appeals to the synthetic

    a priori, to self-evidence, or to the this or nothing move.

    In the next section I argue that, contrary to Rottschaefers criticism, the mod-

    ified-Kantian aspects of my reading of Sellarss article, More on Givenness and

    Explanatory Coherence (MGEC), are strongly confirmed by a closer look at the

    argument of that article.

    V. MORE ON SELLARS ON

    GIVENNESS AND EXPLANATORY COHERENCE

    More on Givenness and Explanatory Coherence is one of Sellarss most im-

    portant and complex articles in epistemology. Rottschaefer argues in some detail

    that my emphasis on the Kantian aspects of Sellarss theory of knowledge is not

    supported by this text. In particular, Rottschaefer argues that what Sellars in

    MGEC calls theory T is exclusively a scientificexplanatory theory, and not in

    any respect a Kantian transcendental justification that is warranted in some way

    independent of the sorts of warrant that derive from ongoing scientific theoriz-ing. I argue, however, that a further examination of MGEC strongly reconfirms

    my original interpretation and also explains why as sensitive a reader of Sellars

    as Rottschaefer might have been led to misconstrue certain key moves in Sel-

    larss argument.

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    22/33

    348 JAMES R. OSHEA

    In sections III and IV of his article Rottschaefer helpfully highlights the central

    features of my account of Sellarss views on the status epistemic principles, rightly

    focusing upon what I called Sellarssperceptual reliabilityprinciple:

    [PR] Ss perceptual judgment [P] thatx, over there, is redconstitutes a case

    of perceptual knowledge if and only if there is a generally reliable

    connection between cases of Ss judging that [P] and its being in fact

    true that there is a red physical object over there. (Cf. Rottschaefer

    2011, 299; and OShea 2007, 126)

    [PR] is a meta-judgment, an epistemic principle, concerning the reliability, ce-

    teris paribus, of first-order perceptual judgments such as [P]. In the terminology

    of Sellarss MGEC, [P] is an example of a first-order IPM judgment, i.e., an

    ostensible introspection, perception, or memory, and [PR] would be an instanceof Sellarss meta-judgment MJ

    5, i.e., IPM judgments are likely to be true

    (MGEC, 83). Sellars uses Roderick Firths Coherence, Certainty, and Epis-

    temic Priority as a starting point for raising questions about the inferentialor

    non-inferential warrantfor judgments such as [PR] and [P] (using my terminol-

    ogy). In paragraphs 3339, Sellars uses Firth to make essentially the following

    points, one of which is particularly important for my diagnosis of Rottschaefers

    mistaken reading of MGEC.

    Sellars explains Firths distinction between two modes of inferentialwarrant-

    increasing properties (33) that a judgment may possess. Kind-1 inferentialwarrant is the sort of straightforward case in which [P] is validly inferable from

    certain other statements of a specified kind (ibid.). Kind-2inferential warrant is

    more indirect: in this case [P] is inferentially warranted if a certain meta-judgment

    about [P]for example, [P] is believed by the relevant expertsis itselfinfer-

    entially warranted in the straightforward kind-1 way, for instance by instantial

    induction from the past successes of the experts. By contrast, a judgment has a

    non-inferentialwarrant-increasing property if, put negatively, it is not warranted

    in either of the two kinds of inferential way; and just what non-inferential warrant

    might positively amount to, withoutappealing (as Firth does) to the Given, is oneof the central questions of Sellarss essay.

    The point that is important not to miss, however, is that in sections 34 and

    39 (and implicitly invoked again in 6061 and 76) Sellars appeals to Firths

    use of coheres with in connection with inferable from to broadenthe scope of

    inductive inference to include other [i.e., non-instantial] modes of non-deductive

    explanatory reasoning (34): as a matter of fact, even if one counts the acquisi-

    tion of a theoryby a substantial degree of confirmation as a variety of acquiring

    inductive support, the distinctions remain reasonably straightforward (39). Sellars

    is here broadening the scope of inductive inferential warrant (relevant to bothkind-1 and kind-2 inferential warrant) to include more complex accounts of the

    inductive confirmation of scientific theoriesimplicitly including his own account

    of induction in terms of the rationality of theory-replacement in ongoing scientific

    inquiry relative to certain broader ends of explanation. (See Sellarss Induction

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    23/33

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    24/33

    350 JAMES R. OSHEA

    Sellarss response to this circularity threat involves a further subtle distinction

    betweentwo kinds of explanatory coherence, both of which are aspects of what in

    MGEC he calls a more encompassing version of what I have been calling theory

    T (74, italics added), and which embodies epistemic principles such as [PR]. Sel-

    larss first anticipation of what (in 61) he calls Theory T occurs in 40, directly

    after having included the broadernotions of inductive confirmation by theories

    within Firths kind-1 and kind-2 inferential warrants:

    But suppose that P'[i.e., the inferential warranting principle (38)] is the

    property of belonging to a theory of persons as representers of themselves-

    in-the-world, which, although it has good explanatory power and is capable

    of refinement by inductive procedures, was not(and, indeed, could not have

    been) arrived atby inferences guided by inductive canons however broadly

    construed. Would P'be an inferentialWP [warrant-increasing property] or

    an explanatory but not inferentialWP? (MGEC, 40)

    It turns out (5965) that if such a theory of persons as representers of

    themselves-in-the-worldwhich Sellars in 61 calls theory T, and which is sup-

    posed to provide the warrantfor such epistemic meta-judgments as the reliability

    principle [PR]is itself inferentially warranted only by the standard means of

    empirical confirmation, including the broadest sense involved in ongoing scientific

    theorizing, then we are still stuck inside the vicious circle. Sellars indicates that

    the circle threatens not only narrowly inductively supported claims, but empiri-cally confirmed claims in the broadened sense (which as we have seen, includes

    scientific-theoretical hypotheses). Thus, of epistemic meta-judgments such as [PR]

    (or in Sellarss terminology, meta-judgments MJ1,3,4

    about the reliability of our

    IPM judgments), his answer to the following question is negative if it is construed

    empirically (in however broad a sense):

    (58) . . . Might not these [principles] be both principles which provide

    criteria for adjudicating certain empirical knowledge claims andempirical

    knowledge claims in their own right? (59) Now if an affirmative response

    took the form of a claim that MJ1, MJ3, and MJ4are empirically confirmedknowledge claimsthus putting them in a box with MJ

    2[i.e., the instantial

    induction, Statements which are accepted by the AGS [experts] are likely

    to be true], a sensitive nerve would be struck. Would not such a claim

    involve a vicious circularity? (60) Since it is obvious that they cannot be

    empirical generalizations which owe their epistemic authority to confirma-

    tion by instances, one might look for a less direct mode of confirmation by

    experience [cf. 3439]. (61) Even if indirectly, however, an appeal must

    ultimately be made [that is, if such meta-judgments are to be construed as

    empiricalclaims even in the broadersense] to the fruits of introspection,

    perception, and memory. (MGEC, 5861)

    Sooner or later, Sellars continues, we would be confronted by such pairs of

    statements as (here I will paraphrase by substituting my own abbreviations):

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    25/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 351

    It is reasonable to accept epistemic principle or meta-judgment [PR] because

    it is an element in a theory Twhich coheres with our perceptions [P]. And

    [P] is likely to be true because it falls under [PR]. (Cf. MGEC, 61)

    In 66 (cf. 58) Sellars consequently makes the crucial claim that in order to

    break out of the circle what we need is a way in which it could be independently

    reasonable to accept principles such as [PR] in spite of the fact that aground

    for accepting such meta-judgments is the fact that they belong to T, which we

    suppose to be an empirically well-confirmed theory. That is, to escape from the

    circle we need a warranting ground for the theory T (of persons as represent-

    ers of themselves-in-the-world) that is independent of and additional to the sort

    of empirically based inferential warrant that theory Tmay also(now, coherently)

    possess, i.e., of the broadly empirical sort paradigmatically exemplified by ongoing

    scientific theoretical explanation.

    In the final sections of the article (6689), Sellars accordingly sketches an

    account according to which there is a more encompassing version of what I have

    been calling theory T (74). Sellars indicates that this more encompassing theory

    Tis something like theory T (88, 8081, 74) in that, as he concludes in the

    final sentences of the article:

    (88) . . . as it exists at any one time, theory Tis a complex [i.e., this is the

    more encompassing version] which includes MJ5[e.g., [PR]] andattempts

    to explain why IPM judgments [e.g., [P]] are likely to be true. The latterenterprise is still unfinished business [i.e., of ongoing empirical scientific

    theorizing].

    (89) It is in the former respect that it constitutesthe conceptual framework

    which spells out the explanatory coherence which is the ultimate criterion

    of truth. (MGEC, interpolations and final emphasis added)

    That is, the complex that is the more encompassing theory Tincludes two dif-

    ferent sources of warrant, only one of which is a matter of the ongoing process of

    scientific explanation:

    (84) Now for the linchpin. We must carefully distinguish between having

    good reason to accept MJ5[PR] and having good reason to accept a proposed

    explanationof whyIPM judgments [P] are likely to be true.

    (85) To explain why IPM judgments [P] are likely to be true doesinvolve in-

    ductive support [i.e., including the broadersense] for hypotheses concerning

    the mechanisms involved and how they evolved in response to evolutionary

    pressures. And thisobviously presupposes the reasonableness of accepting

    IPM judgments [P]. (MGEC, interpolations added)

    So ongoing scientific explanatory proposals will concern, for example, par-ticular empirically based theories as to how natural selection generated perceptual

    mechanisms that are reliably truth-conducive. This aspect of the more encompass-

    ing theory T, i.e., the ongoing scientific explanatory attempt to provide a causal

    answer to the question How did we get into the framework? that is constituted

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    26/33

    352 JAMES R. OSHEA

    by epistemic meta-principles such as [PR] (78),presupposes the validity of [P]-

    judgments in general in the effort to provide observational support for proposed

    scientific-evolutionary theories as to why [P]-judgments are likely to be true.

    But since Sellars has just argued that this ordinary scientific interplay between

    hypotheses and observations does notbreak us out of the vicious circle, [PR]

    [P], unlessthere is also a source of warrant for epistemic principles such as [PR]

    that is independentof the ongoing process of empirical confirmatory warrant, the

    burden of the entire article rests on the latter, non-empirically generateddimension

    of explanatory coherence that Sellars argues is possessed by the more encompass-

    ing version of theory Tand hence by epistemic reliability principles such as [PR].

    So the final question is: what is Sellarss account of the latter dimension of non-

    empiricallybased epistemic warrant for such epistemic meta-principles as [PR]?

    Here the modified Kantian dimension of Sellarss theory of knowledge that I have

    outlined in the previous sections and in the book breaks us out of the threatening

    vicious circle. It does so by providing a substantive philosophical-conceptual analy-

    sis of the conceptual framework which defines, i.e., independently of ongoing

    scientific theorizing, what it is to be a finite knower in a world one never made

    (73, emphasis added). Here philosophy makes a contribution that ongoing scientific

    theorizing does not makeand should we really be surprised that Sellars thinks

    that philosophy can play such a role?by analysing the general structure of the

    systematically coherent framework of epistemic principles that must be exhibited

    by anyparticular conceptual framework within which ongoing scientific or any

    other epistemic activity is possible in the first place. Once this is established we can

    now coherently hold that to be in this framework is to appreciate the interplay of

    the reasonablenesses of inductive hypotheses [in the broadest sense] and of IPM

    judgments [P] (MGEC, 75, interpolations added). That is, once we have in this

    manner revealed the way in which it could be independentlyreasonable to accept

    epistemic meta-principles such as [PR], then we have philosophically resolved the

    appearance of vicious circularity that seemed to threaten the ordinary scientific

    interplay (75) between warranted principles and warranted observations that

    is characteristic of all ongoing theoreticalexplanation (76).

    In MGEC Sellars entitles this account of the permanent dimension of explana-

    tory coherence that is required for all possible human knowledge, and is explicated

    by philosophical analysis rather than by ongoing scientific explanation, Epistemic

    Evaluation as Vindication (68). As we have already seen, in KTE he had char-

    acterized essentially the same project as transcendental linguistics and in TTC

    as pure pragmatics or transcendental logic. In The Structure of Knowledge

    (SK) he characterized it this way:

    (45) . . . We have to be in this framework [of epistemic principles] to bethinking and perceiving beings at all. I suspect that it is this plain truth which

    is the real underpinning of the [Chisholmian, this or nothing] idea that

    the authority of epistemic principles rests on the fact that unless they were

    true we could not see that a cat is on the roof.

  • 8/12/2019 How to Be a Kantian and a Naturalist About Human Knowledge

    27/33

    BEING KANTIAN ANDNATURALIST ABOUT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE 353

    As we have seen, t