Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    1/15

    A P Q

    Volume 48, Number 2, April 2011

    2011 by the Board of Trustees of the University of Illinois

    A PLAGUE ONBOTH YOUR ISMS

    P. M. S. Hacker

    . N

    Isms can be the bane of critical thought,for they provide an array of ready-mades

    that are often used as substitutes for careful

    description and analysis. Todays isms also

    have a tendency, as Robert Hughes observed,

    to become tomorrows was-ms. Our charac-

    teristic isms come in pairs that purport to be

    exclusive and exhaustive answers to a given

    question, and we unthinkingly assume that a

    philosopher must be one corresponding ist

    or the other corresponding istlittle think-

    ing that he may reject the question to which

    the pair of isms are severally answers.

    When a philosopher fails to fit a favored

    ism, we are typically tempted to squeeze

    him in even at the cost of gross deformation.

    Without a philosophical identity card, one

    is a persona non grata. So it has been withWittgenstein. His later philosophical views

    (in the Philosophical Investigationsand the

    Remarks on Philosophy of Mathematics) have

    been described as those of a linguistic ideal-

    ist, a phenomenalist, a verificationist (in the

    private language arguments), an anti-realist,

    a strict finitist, and a behaviorist. In fact, he

    was demonstrably none of those things. It

    is indeed much easier to enumerate what,

    philosophically speaking, he was not thanto find ready-mades to characterize what he

    was. For he was constitutionally incapable of

    walking in other mens furrows. He rejectedtypical dichotomies in terms of which phi-

    losophers tend to think (e.g., realism versus

    nominalism, mentalism versus behaviorism,

    Platonism versus formalism), holding that

    the questions the opposed isms purport to

    answer rested on confused presuppositions.

    It is these presuppositions that need to be

    challenged. If the challenge is successful,

    then both isms will collapse like houses

    of cards. Wittgenstein ploughed the fields

    of philosophy in his own inimitable manner,

    and in the course of doing so, cut through

    received modes of thought in the philosophy

    of logic, philosophy of language, epistemol-

    ogy, metaphysics, philosophy of mind, and

    philosophy of mathematics. Isms and ists

    are absurdly crude nets in which to try to

    catch this most subtle of philosophers.

    The term naturalism has been an honorif-ic expression in philosophy for some decades

    now, especially in the United States. Indeed,

    it has been characterized as thedistinctive de-

    velopment over the last thirty years, marrying

    the American pragmatist tradition with rigor-

    ous scientific method in philosophy. For, it

    is claimed, there has been a naturalistic turn

    away from the a priori methods of traditional

    philosophy towards a methodological unifica-

    tion of science and philosophy. But it is nonetoo clear what naturalism means. As Barry

    Stroud nicely remarked, naturalism seems

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    2/15

    98/ AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    rather like World Peace. Almost everyone

    swears allegiance to it and is willing to march

    under its banner. But disputes can still break

    out about what it is appropriate or acceptable

    to do in the name of that slogan.1

    The most perspicuous use of the term

    naturalism in philosophy is when it is

    contrasted with super-naturalism. In this

    sense, Descartes or Berkeley elaborated non-

    naturalist philosophies, since in both cases

    an appeal to the activity of God was held to

    be needed in order to warrant our knowledge

    claims concerning a rerum natura. Similarly,

    Kants transcendental idealism was not a

    naturalist account of our knowledge of the

    empirical world, since an appeal to noumena

    is demanded by his metaphysical system.

    In this sense of naturalism, Hume was a

    naturalist philosopher par excellence. He

    explained the nature and limits of human

    understanding without recourse to any super-

    natural agencies. He also noted sapiently that

    the word naturalis commonly taken in so

    many senses and is of so loose a significationthat it seems vain to dispute whether [some-

    thing] be natural or not.2This, too, should

    be a warning to us to proceed carefully.

    The contrast between naturalism and super-

    naturalism in philosophy is not the sense in

    which philosophical journalists proclaim

    enthusiastically that there was a naturalis-

    tic turn in American philosophy in the last

    quarter of the twentieth century. Those who

    marched under the banner of naturalism werenot concerned with combating philosophi-

    cal super-naturalismthey took its demise

    for granted. The gonfalonier of American

    naturalism was Quine, and it is to him that

    we can turn to find out what this weasel word

    signifies.

    One can distinguish in Quines work onto-

    logical naturalism, epistemological natural-

    ism, and philosophical naturalism3:

    (i) Ontological naturalism is the doctrine

    that it is within science itself and not in some

    prior philosophy, that reality is to be identified

    and described.4On this account, it is up to

    science to tell us what there is, and it offers

    the best theory of what exists and of how we

    come to know what exists. The only differ-

    ence between the ontological philosopherand the scientist, Quine wrote (with tongue

    in cheek), lies in the breadth of concern: the

    philosopher being concerned with the exis-

    tence of material objects or classes, and the

    scientist with wombats and unicorns.

    (ii) Epistemological naturalism is the pro-

    posed displacement of traditional foundation-

    alist epistemology by an enterprise within

    natural science,5a psychological enterprise

    of investigating how the input of radiation,

    etc., impinging on the nerve endings of hu-

    man beings, can ultimately result in the output

    of our theoretical descriptions of the external

    world. This heir to epistemology, according

    to Quine, is to study how the stimulation of

    sensory receptors, which is all the evidence

    anyone has to go on, ultimately, in arriving

    at his picture of the world,6relates to theory,

    and in what ways ones theory of nature tran-scends any available evidence.

    (iii) Philosophical naturalism is the view

    that philosophy is not . . . an a priori pro-

    paedeutic or groundwork for science, but

    [is] . . . continuous with science.7This view

    was a reversion to the Russellian conception

    of philosophy as advanced before the First

    World War and a repudiation of the tradition

    of analytic philosophy as it had evolved in the

    Vienna Circle, at Cambridge in the interwaryears, and at Oxford in the postwar years.8

    This reversion to a widely repudiated concep-

    tion was one aspect of what Quine called his

    apostasy in relation to the doctrines of the

    Vienna Circle.9

    One might add yet further kinds of natu-

    ralism to this triplet. The most obvious is

    ethical naturalism, an epithet commonly

    used to characterize Humes project in book

    three of the Treatise of Human Natureand

    in the second of the Enquiries Concerning

    Human Understanding and Concerning the

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    3/15

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    4/15

    100/ AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    and scientific explanation and increasingly

    oblivious to the understanding of much of

    what makes us distinctively human. It is a

    turn away from hermeneutical understanding

    of human behavior and institutions and of thegoals and values that inform them, of history

    and society, and of our cultural creations.

    The subject of this essay is Wittgenstein and

    naturalism. So I shall reflect a little on how

    Wittgenstein stands in relation to the three

    forms of Quinean naturalism in his philoso-

    phy of logic, mathematics, language, psychol-

    ogy, and epistemology. I shall not discuss

    post-Quinean developments of naturalism

    in the United States, although some of what

    I have to say about Quine applies to those

    variants too. Wittgenstein made no appeal to

    anything that might be deemed supernatural,

    so that is an issue that can be passed by.

    . W

    P N

    I wrote some years ago that Quine and

    Wittgenstein are related in a very peculiarway. There is, at first glance, extensive and

    impressive agreement between them. But on

    closer scrutiny, their proximity is deceptive

    for it is akin to the proximity of the far Left

    and far Right in the horseshoe-shaped French

    National Assembly. They sit close to each

    other, but to get from one to the other one has

    to go through the whole spectrum of political

    ideology.13This peculiarity is patent when we

    juxtapose their views on the three doctrinesof naturalism just elaborated.

    Philosophical naturalism patently stands in

    diametrical contrast to everything Wittgen-

    stein believed about the nature, scope, and

    limits of philosophy, both in the Tractatus

    Logico-Philosophicus(hereafter Tractatusor

    TLP) and in all his later writings. Wittgenstein

    would have agreed with Quine that philoso-

    phy is not . . . an a priori propaedeutic orgroundwork for science in the Cartesian,

    Kantian, or indeed Aristotelian sense. It is

    not the task of philosophy to lay the founda-

    tions of science in metaphysical principles,

    or to determine the synthetic a priori prin-

    ciples of natural science, or to investigate the

    fundamental presuppositions of each of the

    sciences. But with that negative agreement,consensus ceases. Where Quine held that

    philosophy is continuous with the natural

    sciences, Wittgenstein asserted as early as

    the Tractatusthat

    philosophy is not one of the natural sciences.

    (The word philosophy must mean something

    whose place is above or below the natural sci-

    ences, but not beside them.) Philosophy aims

    at the logical clarification of thoughts. Philoso-

    phy is not a body of doctrine but an activity.

    A philosophical work consists essentially of

    elucidations. (TLP4.1114.112)

    And he continued to think for the rest of his

    life that the task of philosophy is conceptual

    clarification and dissolution of philosophical

    problems by analysisalthough, to be sure,

    what counts as analysis changed radically.

    Above all, whereas Quine thought that

    philosophy is a part of the scientific questfor knowledge, Wittgensteinboth in the

    Tractatusand in all his later work (albeit for

    different reasons)denied that there are any

    philosophical truths analogous to the truths

    of the empirical sciences or that there is

    philosophical knowledge of any such truths,

    and he denied that philosophy is a quest for

    knowledge. Contrary to Russell, who held

    that logic was the study of the most gen-

    eral features of the universe and that logicalpropositions are the most general truths we

    can achieve in our knowledge of the world,

    Wittgenstein, both early and late, denied that

    logically true propositions are essentially

    generalizations; denied that they yield us

    knowledge of the universe; and held that far

    from being descriptions of the universe, they

    are altogether without sense.

    Metaphysicists have argued that philoso-

    phy, unlike science, aims to attain knowledge

    of special philosophical propositionsin par-

    ticular, necessary truths concerning the world

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    5/15

    or truths concerning all possible worlds.

    Russell and Quine held that philosophy was

    part of the scientific quest for truth about the

    worldthe knowledge it yields is not special

    knowledge about a special domain, but gen-eral knowledge about the ordinary domain

    of nature. Wittgenstein rejected both these

    antithetical conceptions, for he denied that

    philosophy is a quest for the enlargement of

    human knowledge at all. It is a contribution

    to human understanding.

    It is not the task of philosophy to ex-

    plain empirical phenomena, but rather to

    describeor perhaps better, to stateand

    marshal familiar grammatical rules or norms

    of representation for philosophical purposes.

    The philosophical purposes are to resolve

    or dissolve philosophical problems and per-

    plexities, to eradicate conceptual confusions

    in philosophy, science, and daily discourse.

    The methods of philosophy include gram-

    matical description, i.e., the delineation of

    conceptual connections, compatibilities and

    incompatibilities, presuppositions, and formsof context dependencyin short, concep-

    tual analysis, or, as Strawson has helpfully

    denominated it, connective analysisfor,

    as Wittgenstein remarked, a proposition

    is completely logically analysed when its

    grammar is laid out completely clearly.14The

    pertinent conceptual truths need to be selected

    and arranged in such a manner as to shed light

    on the philosophical, i.e., conceptual, prob-

    lem at hand. Philosophy does not producenovel empirical truths, it merely draws our

    attention to the structure of familiar segments

    of our form of representation (or conceptual

    scheme) for elucidatory purposes. This may

    involve drawing our attention to similarities

    that we had not noticed and to differences

    that had escaped our attentionin that sense

    it may well involve realization of features

    of our conceptual scheme, and in that sense

    knowledge. But thisis knowledge concerning

    evident features of our forms of representa-

    tion, not knowledge concerning the world

    about us that we represent by these forms. If

    these features of our conceptual scheme are

    evident, how is it then that we are not already

    apprised of them? To master the use of the

    expressions of a language, it is not necessarythat one hold in view all the analogies and

    disanalogies between one expression or kind

    of expression and another expression or kind

    of expressionbut it is precisely that which

    commonly needs to be brought to our atten-

    tion to dispel bafflement, misconceptions, and

    illusions.

    2.1 The Naturalist Riposte

    Quines followers have made much ofQuines criticism of Carnaps early distinc-

    tion between analytic and synthetic proposi-

    tions and argued that with the rejection of that

    distinction, the possibility of anything that

    might be called conceptual analysis collapses,

    and the possibility of resolving philosophi-

    cal questions by means of a priori argument

    and elucidation is foreclosed. This is held to

    demonstrate the futility of any Wittgenstein-

    ian enterprise. So I shall digress for a moment

    to examine this mistaken idea.

    Wittgenstein was no less critical of the

    Vienna Circles idea of truths in virtue of

    meanings than Quine. He characterized

    this confused idea as the meaning-body

    conception, which he duly demolished. He

    thought that nothing could follow from the

    meaning of a word, but only from a proposi-

    tion. He also thought that propositions whichsome members of the Circle held to be true

    in virtue of the meanings of their constituent

    terms were not true in virtueof meanings at

    all, but were rather constitutiveof the mean-

    ings of the terms in question. It is not as if

    one could first fully grasp the meaning of a

    given term (say, vixen or red) and then

    go on to discover what follows from its mean-

    ing (e.g., that vixens are female, or that red

    is darker than pink). Far from espousing theanalytic/synthetic distinction that members of

    the Vienna Circle advanced, Wittgenstein as-

    BOTH YOUR ISMS/ 101

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    6/15

    102/ AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    siduously avoided invoking it and its ancestral

    congeners. The term analytic occurs in only

    one remark in the more than eighteen thou-

    sand pages of Nachlasswritten after 1929,

    and then only in order to suggest an affinitybetween his reflections on arithmetic and

    Kants denial that arithmetical propositions

    such as 7 + 5 = 12 are analytic.

    Quines naturalist defenders commonly

    castigate Wittgenstein for cleaving to the

    obsolete idea of a priori knowledge. They

    will perhaps be surprised to learn that Witt-

    genstein wrote:

    It was characteristic of theorists of the pastcultural period to want to find the a priori where

    it isnt. Or should I say a characteristic of the

    past cultural era was to form//to create// the

    concept or non-concept of the a priori. For it

    would never have created the concept if, from

    the start, it had seen things// the situation// as we

    do. (Then the world would have lost a greatI

    mean significanterror.)15

    So far, then, there are two points of agreement

    which demonstrate the folly of the assertionthat Wittgenstein cleaved to Carnaps early

    analytic/synthetic distinction or that he ac-

    cepted the traditional conception of the a

    priori.

    Nevertheless, the agreement between

    Quine and Wittgenstein is superficial and

    provides no support for any form of philo-

    sophical naturalism. Indeed, their initial

    agreements mask far-reaching disagree-

    ments. Wittgenstein differentiated betweenlogical propositions; mathematical propo-

    sitions; general grammatical propositions;

    empirical propositions of a multitude of

    different kinds; the special categories of

    empirical propositions of the world picture;

    as well as ethical, aesthetic, and religious

    propositions. He held the concept of a propo-

    sition to be a family-resemblance concept,

    and showed that the logical articulations

    of one kind of proposition in use differ

    profoundly from those of others. One may

    grant Quine that truth is truth, i.e., that

    the truth-predicate and the truth-operator

    are univocal. Like Quine, Wittgenstein

    espoused a deflationary conception of truth

    (wavering between a disquotational form

    and a de-nominalization form of such aconception). But that truth is truth is

    perfectly consistent with the view that what

    it is for one kind of proposition to be true

    may be altogether differentfrom what it is

    for a different kind to be true. Knowledge is

    knowledge, no doubt, but what it is to know

    that the sun is shining, that water is H2O, that

    red is darker than pink, that 25 x 25 = 625,

    that envy is a vice, that meaning something

    is not a mental act, and so on, all call out

    for very different explanations involving

    very different conceptual, or grammatical,

    articulations.

    Logical propositions have no truth-con-

    ditions, since they are true (or false) come

    what may. What it is for such a proposition

    to be true is for it to be unipolar and also to

    say nothing at all. Logical truths have no

    sense, but are correlative to a rule of infer-ence. Mathematical propositions are likewise

    bivalent and unipolar. True mathematical

    propositions are norms of representation,

    constituting standards for the re-description

    of quantifiable phenomena and for the

    transformation of empirical propositions

    concerning magnitudes and quantities. Gen-

    eral grammatical propositions, like logical

    and mathematical ones, are unipolar; like

    true mathematical propositions, they arenormative. But while the negation of a logi-

    cal truth is a contradiction, and the negation

    of a true mathematical proposition is a false

    mathematical proposition, the negation

    of a grammatical proposition is arguably

    best conceived as a form of nonsense. For

    a grammatical proposition, e.g., that red is

    darker than pink, or that nothing can be red

    and green all over simultaneously, is a rule

    in the guise of a description of an objective

    necessity. Its negation is nota rule for the use

    of its constituent termsif A is red and B is

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    7/15

    pink, one may notinfer that A is lighter than

    B. The rules for the use of the constituent

    terms exclude precisely this inference among

    empirical propositions. On the other hand,

    the negation of a true grammatical proposi-tion is not a bipolar empirical proposition

    either. Contrary to views held by members

    of the Vienna Circle, a grammatical proposi-

    tion does notfollowfrom the meanings of its

    constituent terms, but is constitutiveof their

    meanings. Expressing a grammatical propo-

    sition is a feature of the use of a sentence on a

    given occasion. Different tokens of the same

    type-sentence may be used on one occasion

    to express an empirical proposition and on

    another to express a grammatical one, e.g.,

    This is red (which may be a description

    or an ostensive definition), Water consists

    of H2O (which may report an empirical

    discovery or stipulate a rule for the use of

    the word water in chemistry), or Force is

    the product of mass and acceleration (which

    can be used to express a law of nature or a

    definition of force). Unlike an empiricalproposition, a grammatical propositions

    being true does not amount to its correspond-

    ing to the facts; nor does it consist in things

    being as it describes them as being. Rather,

    its being true consists in its correctly stating

    the content of a rule of representation. This

    is comparable to the fact that the truth of

    the proposition that the chess king moves

    a square at a time consists in its correctly

    stating a rule of chess. (It is not the rule thatis truethere is no such thing as a true or

    false rulebut, rather, the proposition truly

    specifies the content of a rule.)

    There is no inconsistency at all in simulta-

    neously avoiding the term analytic while

    invoking the category of conceptual truths.

    For what Wittgenstein called grammatical

    propositions are conceptual truths. Their

    role is not descriptive but normative. The

    suggestion that mathematical and grammati-

    cal propositions such as Red is darker than

    pink, or 25 25 = 625, or One cannot

    trisect an angle with a compass and rule are

    analytic in the sense of being true in virtue

    of the meanings of their constituent terms, or

    in the different sense of being derivable from

    the truths of logic and explicit definitions, orin the sense of the subject terms containing

    the predicate is at best misleading, at worst

    wrong.16 But animadversions to analyticity

    in these different senses are irrelevant to

    Wittgensteins notion of conceptual truths.

    Conceptual truths articulate normative con-

    nections between concepts expressed by

    words we use. They determine concepts,

    specifying rules for the use of concept-words.

    They are grammatical propositions, i.e., ex-

    pressions of norms of representationof a

    kind that are of no interest to grammarians

    or lexicographers, but of maximal interest for

    philosophers seeking to resolve or dissolve

    philosophical problems.

    2.2 Concluding Overview of

    Wittgensteins Relation to

    Philosophical Naturalism

    Wittgenstein repudiated the traditional

    conception of a priori truths as lying at the

    foundations of all empirical knowledge, a

    conception exemplified by Descartess sup-

    position that eternal truths and common no-

    tions fulfil this role. He would have rejected

    the Kantian conception of synthetic a priori

    truths that the mind imposes upon intuition to

    yield experience. But he had no qualms about

    characterizing his investigations as a prioriin method or as characterizing mathematical

    propositions and what he idiosyncratically

    called grammatical propositions as a priori.

    They are neither the foundations of knowl-

    edge nor the first principles of knowledge.

    They are not foundation stones but, as it were,

    spectacles. For they are constitutive of our

    means of representation, and are not descrip-

    tions of what we represent by these means.

    Wittgensteins philosophical methods do notdepend on observation and experiment. They

    are investigations of what does and does not

    BOTH YOUR ISMS/ 103

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    8/15

    104/ AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    make sense, not of what is or is not empiri-

    cally true. And his arguments about what does

    not make sense are not subject to empirical

    confirmation or refutation. They presuppose

    the shared usage of competent speakers. Theyturn on familiar features of the uses of words,

    ordinary words like pain or technical words

    like transfinite cardinal that we are prone

    to overlooki.e., they turn on reflection on

    our means of representation, not on what we

    represent by those means, i.e., observations

    of nature.

    It might seem to a confused philosophical

    naturalist that Wittgenstein is a paradigm of a

    philosophical non-naturalist. For does he not

    advance an array of propositions that he infu-

    riatingly and misleadingly calls grammatical?

    And are not these the results of philosophical

    investigation? Are they not true propositions?

    So is it not disingenuous for Wittgenstein to

    suggest that philosophy does not result in a

    body of philosophical knowledge?

    Certain grammatical propositions are of

    great philosophical interest. But it would bewholly mistaken to suppose that the result

    of philosophical investigation is an array of

    hitherto unknown grammatical propositions

    or conceptual truths. Mathematics is concept-

    formationby means of proof, but philosophy

    is concept-elucidation. One of its methods

    (but by no means the only one) is to marshal

    appropriate grammatical propositions in a

    surveyable manner in order to dissolve philo-

    sophical or conceptual unclarity and illusion.If someone is inclined to identify the mean-

    ing of an expression with its bearer, one may

    remind them that one can, in certain cases,

    sit on the bearer of a namebut it makes no

    sense to sit on the meaning of a name. But

    that the meaning of a name is not its bearer

    is no more a philosophical proposition than

    that a bachelor is not a married man is a

    philosophical proposition, or that red is not

    lighter than pink is. It is a rule for the use of

    words (viz., that meaning cannot be re-

    placed by bearer in the phrase the meaning

    of a name)in the guise of a description.

    Other familiar grammatical propositions

    are themselves the source of philosophical

    difficulties, e.g., the vexing proposition that

    nothing can be red and green all over. Thequestion of the status of such propositions ex-

    ercised analytic philosophers endlessly in the

    interwar yearsto little purpose save in the

    case of Wittgenstein. Yet other grammatical

    propositions may indeed be the result of long

    and elaborate philosophical discussion and

    argument, e.g., that one cannot have a logi-

    cally private language. Here we have a gram-

    matical proposition that is far from obvious at

    first blush. It is a grammatical proposition, a

    rule, that excludes the form of words a logi-

    cally private language from currencyjust

    as the proposition that one cannot checkmate

    in draughts excludes a form of words, viz.,

    checkmate in draughts, from currency, and

    as the proposition, which took two thousand

    years to prove, namely, that one cannot trisect

    an angle with compass and rule, excludes a

    form of words from currency. To be sure, onecannot have a logically private language is

    not the upshot of a deductive proofit is the

    upshot of a detailed array of arguments that

    involve careful reflection on a multitude of

    other grammatical propositions and the man-

    ner in which they are interwoven. Here one

    needs an overview of a large and convoluted

    segment of our conceptual scheme.

    So if philosophical naturalism is the view

    that philosophy is continuous with science andthat, like the natural sciences, it adds to the sum

    of human knowledge about nature, then it is

    evident that Wittgenstein rejected naturalism.

    But it is also evident that he rejected the view

    that philosophy aimed to achieve some other

    form of knowledge, such as knowledge of the

    foundations of science in principles of first

    philosophyto which Quine was so opposed.

    A plague on both your houses, Wittgenstein

    might have saidfor there is no such thing

    as philosophical knowledge as opposed to

    knowledge of the great works of philosophy.

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    9/15

    . W

    O N

    Ontological naturalism, you will remember,

    is the doctrine that it is within science itselfand not in some prior philosophy, that real-

    ity is to be identified and described. This,

    as it stands, is a curious claim. It is far from

    obvious what science is supposed to be.

    We are familiar with a multitude of sciences,

    ranging from physics and cosmology through

    chemistry and biochemistry to biology and

    medicine, not to mention neuroscience and

    psychology, economics and sociologyeach

    of which divides into a multitude of branches.Whichscience identifies and describes real-

    ity? Indeed, what is it to identify, let alone to

    describe, reality?

    If identifying and describing reality

    amounts to making true existential claims and

    advancing true empirical descriptions, then it

    is, of course correct that the various natural

    sciences do make such claims and do advance

    such descriptions. But it would be absurd to

    suppose that onlythe various sciences do so,or indeed that only they are entitled to do

    so, let alone that they have the last word on

    what really exists or on what kinds of things

    really exist. No science is likely to gainsay

    Everyman when he asserts that his childhood

    diaries still exist, sincerely avows a toothache

    or describes it as throbbing, or when he re-

    marks there is no justice in this world. And

    unless history is a science, no science is goingto be in the position to gainsay the standard

    explanation of Elizabeth Is etceteration of

    her letters to Phillip of Spain or that class con-

    flict really existed in the nineteenth century.

    And unless the study of law is a science, no

    science is going to be in a position to gainsay

    the claim that in the course of the last twenty

    years, a more robust form of international law

    has gradually come into being. And so on.

    Physics studies, among other things, whatfundamental particles exist in nature, and on

    that it has the last wordbut it does not have

    the last word, or even the first word, on what

    things or kinds of things in general exist or

    on what fundamental kinds of things exist

    (fundamental for what, one must first ask).

    If the claim is merely that no prior phi-losophy is in a position to dictate to science

    what kinds of things do or do not exist, or to

    advance true empirical descriptionsthen

    that is a quite different issue. One might

    be sympathetic with one aspect of Quines

    claim. With the exception of rational theol-

    ogy, which is a special case that investigates

    necessary existence, it is surely not a remit

    of philosophy to determine or discover what

    things do or do not exist. Philosophy is cer-

    tainly not in competition with the natural

    sciences in discovering what fundamental

    particles exist.

    On the other hand, it is surely bizarre to

    suppose that philosophical concern with the

    existence of material objects, or classes, or

    universals (the ontological commitments of

    our best scientific theories of the world) is

    on a par with a concern with whether this,that, or another species (wombats or unicorns)

    exist. It is surely notthe task of philosophy

    to discoverthat there are material things or

    universals (when, one wonders, did it make

    these remarkable discoveries?). It is not as if

    science discovers the existence of such fun-

    damental kinds of things as positrons, while

    philosophy discovers the existence of such

    fundamental kinds of things as universals.

    When did philosophy last discover the exis-tence of a new kind of thing? Or has it now

    completed its inventory of the universe?

    Where would Wittgenstein have stood on

    the matter? It seems clear enough that he

    would have agreed with the claim that the

    natural sciences do not depend upon the

    results of prior philosophy. He repudiated

    rational theology as an illusion. He would

    surely have dismissed the idea that one of the

    goals of philosophy is to discover what kinds

    of fundamental things there are. It could never

    be a discoveryof philosophy that universals

    BOTH YOUR ISMS/ 105

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    10/15

    106/ AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    exist, and the claim that there are universals

    is wholly unlike the claim that positrons exist.

    Ontology, he would surely have asserted, is

    no more a serious subject for philosophers to

    engage in than is metaphysics. The seriousphilosophical questions in this domain are

    not Are there universals? Do substances

    exist? Are there transfinite cardinals?

    Rather, the questions concern meaning, not

    truth. They do not take the misleading form

    of Do universals (or substances) exist? but

    rather What is a universal (or a substance)?

    and What does it mean to say that there are

    universals (or substances)? The question is

    not whether transfinite cardinals exist, but

    rather whether transfinite cardinals are num-

    bers at all in the sense in which cardinals are?

    Such questions are answered by grammatical

    investigations, not by discoveries.

    The heir to the pseudo-subject of ontology

    is the patient grammatical investigation of

    what it means, from one domain to another, to

    say that such and such a kind of thing exists.

    Given the confusions engendered by Galileo,Descartes, Boyle, and Locke about the sub-

    jectivity of colors, it is a task for philosophy to

    clarify what is meant by color predicates and

    what, if anything, is meant by asserting that

    colors exist. Given the seventeenth-century

    claim that colors do not exist in nature, what

    we need is not an attempt to discover whether

    they really doafter all, the Galilean claim

    was never really an empirical one, and no

    experiment could possibly show that there areno colored objects in nature. What we need

    is grammatical clarification of the concept of

    color and of color attributions.

    Difficulties with existential statements of

    one kind or another range far and wide. We

    say that there are laws of nature, that laws of

    the state are created by legislation and that le-

    gal systems exist, that there are various kinds

    of numbers, that rules exist, that moral values

    exist and that there are principles of moral-

    ity by which we should live. From case to

    case, we typically tie ourselves into knots in

    trying to clarify what these assertions mean.

    And from case to case, Wittgenstein would,

    I think, have suggested that what is needed is

    grammatical clarification and careful investi-

    gation of the sources of our confusions. Wittgenstein was patently not an ontologi-

    cal naturalist, if that means that the physical

    sciences have the best and last word on what

    things and kinds of things exist. But neither

    was he an ontological anti-naturalist, hold-

    ing that it is the task of first philosophy to

    determine, antecedently to science, what

    fundamental kinds of things there are.

    . W:E N

    Quines idea of naturalizing epistemology

    is, in one sense and up to a point, unobjec-

    tionable, and in another sense, and beyond

    a certain point, absurd. There can surely be

    no philosophical (or any other) objection to

    the idea that cognitive neuroscience should

    investigate the neural processes involved in

    the acquisition of information by the use ofthe sense organs. What is absurd is first, the

    suggestion that this enterprise should displace

    epistemology, and second, the idea that this

    neuro-psychological heir to epistemology is

    to study how evidence relates to theory.

    Cognitive neuroscience does indeed inves-

    tigate how the impingement of radiation upon

    our retinae yields perceptual knowledge of

    our environment. It is a very long way from

    having anything remotely like a comprehen-sive theory of such perceptual processes, but

    its achievements so far are impressive and

    the project continues. What it does not do,

    and I fancy never will, is investigate how the

    irritations of our surfaces, as Quine put it,

    yield our theories of the world. In the first

    place, none of us hasa theory of the world.

    Nor does any science. And even the conjunc-

    tion of all the scientific knowledge and theorythat is available does not yield a theory of the

    world. There is no such thing as a theory of

    the world. Second, it is simply mistaken to

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    11/15

    suggest that the stimulation of our sensory

    receptors is ultimately all the evidence

    anyone has to go on in arriving at knowledge

    of our environment, or that this sensory input,

    as Quine wrote, supports physical theory.Indeed, one thing that is neverevidence for

    our theories is the irradiation of our sense

    organs and irritation of our surfaces. Light

    waves impinging on our retinae and sound

    waves agitating our eardrums are not our

    evidencefor what we see and hear. Third, no

    neuro-psychological investigation could pos-

    sibly explain how sensory input of radiation

    yields scientific theorysince it patently

    does not. One may argue that if we are good

    scientists, our observations (rather than our

    irradiations) and experiments in conjunction

    with the transmitted fund of knowledge that

    is provided by a scientific education may

    result in our advancing a successful scientific

    theory. But the fund of knowledge that we

    must master is not a battery of irradiations,

    even though it can only be acquired through

    reading and listening and watching or mak-ing observations and experiments. And the

    cannons of evidence and rules of inference

    are not neural processes. They are normative

    standards of correct reasoning and can be

    studied by studying logic and science.

    Quine blithely asserts, without argument,

    that naturalized epistemology, although

    a far cry from old epistemology, is an

    enlightened persistence in the original

    problem.17That original problem, accordingto Quine, was to combat scepticism and to

    explain how our knowledge of the world is

    firmly rooted in our knowledge of our sub-

    jective perceptual states. This foundational-

    ism was exemplified for Quine in Russells

    Our Knowledge of the External Worldand

    more systematically in Carnaps Logischer

    Aufbau. His critical response to it was why

    all this creative reconstruction, all this make-

    believeand instead of foundationalism

    he advocated the study of psychology and

    cognitive neuroscience that would give an

    empirical account of knowledge acquisition

    and theory construction. But the alternative

    to foundationalism is not the scientism of the

    imaginary subject of naturalized epistemol-

    ogy. It is the explanation of why it is mis-conceived to think that our knowledge of the

    world either has, or could have, foundations

    in the traditional sense. Nor could natural-

    ized epistemology possibly answer the kinds

    of questions that are the proper domain of

    epistemology. No amount of neuroscience is

    going to be able to explain the reticulations of

    the subtle and complex network of epistemic

    terms. Even if, in the fullness of time, we

    know everything we wish to know about

    the workings of the human brain, that will

    not provide a description of that conceptual

    network. Nor can neuroscience be envisaged

    as answering such questions as, If A knows

    that p, does it follow that he also believes

    that p? Can A know that p even though

    his grounds for holding thatpare false? Is

    mathematical knowledge more certain than

    empirical knowledge? and Why can we bein a state of ignorance but not in a state of

    knowing?

    How might we imagine Wittgenstein

    responding to the Quinean suggestion that

    epistemology naturalized can fruitfully

    replace old-fashioned foundationalist epis-

    temology. Again, it seems evident that he

    would have shared Quines animadversions

    to classical foundationalist epistemology

    although for reasons quite different fromQuines. But he would have been amazed

    to hear that the alternative to foundation-

    alism is Quinean naturalism. One cannot

    refute scepticism by appealing to scientific

    knowledge any more than one can unravel

    Zenos paradox of Achilles and the tortoise

    by measuring their relative velocities. A

    plague on both your isms, Wittgenstein

    might have exclaimed before pursuing his

    own investigations into the nature of human

    knowledge that he began in On Certainty

    and, alas, never finished.

    BOTH YOUR ISMS/ 107

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    12/15

    108/ AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    . W . . . A F

    E [] I

    F M J

    B E N

    Wittgenstein objected no less than Quine

    to foundationalist epistemology, to founda-

    tionalist philosophical ontology, and to the

    conception of philosophy as a propaedeutic

    to science. His reasons, however, were very

    different. Moreover, he would have objected

    to Quines scientistic alternatives even more

    vehemently. Nevertheless, in one sense of this

    polysemic term there is a powerful natural

    strand in Wittgensteins later philosophy.It might also be termed anthropological.

    Given what I by now hope are well-taken

    warnings, this approach should perhaps not

    be crowned with an ism at all, but merely

    described. What I have in mind is:

    (i) Wittgensteins methodological principle

    of investigating ways in which prob-

    lematic expressions are or might be

    taught in order to shed light on theirmeaning.

    (ii) His exploration of the natural and ac-

    culturated roots of our psychological

    vocabulary and the nature of the first/

    third person asymmetries of many

    psychological verbs.

    (iii) His emphasis on the function of

    expressions in the context of the

    language-games in which they are at

    home, and hence on their place in thestream of life.

    (iv) His examination of thepointof a given

    language-game or conceptual activity

    within a form of life.

    (v) His elaborate account of the varieties

    of necessary truth.

    I shall make only a few observations here to

    indicate what I have in mind.

    (i) In his writings on philosophy of lan-guage, Wittgenstein commonly reflects on

    how expressions might be taught and on

    what natural capacities and dispositions are

    presupposed for learning them. This is not

    armchair learning theory. It is a reminder of

    the natural primitive powers of humanity and

    of the uncultivated forms of human reaction

    and response. By this means he endeavorsto show how our concepts and language-

    games are rooted in our natural abilities and

    propensitiesand hence to show the extent

    to which our concepts are molded by our

    nature (as well as by features of the natural

    world around us). It also enables us to call

    to mind the natural contextsin which teach-

    ing the use of the problematic expression is

    called for, as is evident, for example, when

    one reflects on how one might teach a child

    how to use the expression I dreamt (that in

    itself sheds light on philosophical puzzlement

    with respect to dreaming).

    (ii) In his writings on the philosophy of

    psychology Wittgenstein steered between

    the Scylla of mentalism enshrined in the

    Cartesian and Lockean tradition and the

    Charybdis of the behaviorism popular in the

    Vienna Circle. He denied the reducibilityof mental states, events, and processes to

    behavior, but he also denied that first-person

    present-tense utterances are reports resting

    on introspection. Rather, he accounted for the

    peculiar status of a range of such utterances

    as extensions of primitive natural behavior

    suggesting that the utterance It hurts or

    the groan I have a pain are acculturated

    linguistic extensions of natural pain-behavior.

    It is on these primitive utterances that laterreportive and descriptive uses of our pain

    vocabulary are constructed. Other kinds of

    utterances are to be seen as rooted in primitive

    moves of a language-game, as when a child

    learns the use of Im going to . . . to herald

    an incipient action. The child does not learn

    to identify an intention within its breast and

    then to announce it to others. Rather, it learns

    that when one says, Im going to . . . in such

    contexts, one then has to go on to. . . . Yet

    other utterances are to be seen as accultur-

    ated linguistic extensions of more primitive

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    13/15

    linguistic activitiesas when we learn to

    use epistemic operators to qualify a simple

    utterance. We do not learn the primitive use

    of I think by noting the occurrence within

    us of a process called thinking, but rather asa qualification on an utterance for which we

    have less than adequate grounds. And so on.

    In all these diverse cases (and there are many

    more), philosophical confusions pertaining

    to privileged access, private ownership of

    experience, epistemic privacy, certainty, and

    doubt are eliminated by scrutiny of natural

    processes in which the primitive form of a

    certain typical expression could beacquired

    and mastered in the course of natural matu-

    ration. He gives, one might say, a perfectly

    natural account of the illusions of privileged

    access, introspection, absence of doubt, and

    infallible knowledge.

    (iii) Wittgenstein constantly emphasizes

    that words are deeds. To learn the meaning

    of a word is to learn how it is to be used, and

    to learn the use of a word is to learn how to

    do something with it in the stream of life. Wehave for too long labored under the illusion

    that words are au fondnames and sentences

    are (or contain) descriptions. We fail even to

    notice the diversity of what is called describ-

    ing: for example, describing the room one is

    in, describing the room one was in, describ-

    ing the room as it will be when the house is

    built, describing a room in ones dream, an

    architects blueprint of a room, an architects

    drawing of a room, an archaeologists recon-structive drawing of a room, a description

    of a room in a novel. Hence, too, we fail to

    advert to what counts, from case to case, as

    improving ones description, and we remain

    oblivious to the different functions of kinds

    of description in the various language-games

    that are part of human life. A fortiori, we tend

    to obscure the extent to which even declara-

    tive sentences have nondescriptive functions,

    e.g., as avowals of experience, expressions of

    attitudes and emotions, forms of appraisal,

    statements of norms of representation. We

    are obsessed with the idea that words are

    names, that words are (at least for the most

    part) referring expressions (which may refer

    to particulars, to kinds, to properties or rela-

    tions, to numbers, to truth-functions, and soforth). Gross oversimplification ensues and

    the multitudinous different roles that words

    play in language-games are occluded by the

    limited roles of symbols in formal calculi

    that we invoke to make our reflections more

    precise.

    (iv) Wittgenstein recurrently reminds us of

    what we take for granted in our philosophi-

    cal reflections, namely thepointof different

    language-games. For the purposes of philo-

    sophical elucidation, it is often not enough

    to call to mind the rules for the use of words

    within familiar language-games and to mar-

    shal them in a surveyable representation. One

    needs to bear in mind thepointof the whole

    game in the form of life of which it is a part.

    The very same arithmetical rules for the use

    and manipulation of numerals in our calcula-

    tions might be used solely for the purpose ofdecorating wallpaper with theoremsbut that

    would not be arithmetic, since its point would

    be far removed from the point of calculating.

    Here, too, one might say, the exploration of

    the natural anthropological context of our

    linguistic and conceptual activities plays a

    crucial role in Wittgensteins methods.

    (v) Wittgenstein did not give a uniform ac-

    count of all kinds of necessary truth. But he

    accounted for the true propositions of logic,arithmetic, geometry, and so-called meta-

    physics without recourse to a third realm of

    Platonist entities accessible to our logical

    faculty and powers of reasoning, such as Frege

    invoked, and equally without recourse to nec-

    essary facts or language-independent natures

    discoverable by Wesensschau, an intuitive

    insight into the essences of things, as Husserl

    supposed. His complex accounts of these dif-

    ferent kinds of necessary truth render them

    and their necessity perspicuous by reference

    to human practices of using words, of concept-

    BOTH YOUR ISMS/ 109

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    14/15

    110/ AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    formation, and of reasoning. They belong to,

    or are systematically related to, our forms of

    representation, and our forms of representa-

    tion are our creation. Their necessity does

    not derive from what they describe, since theydescribe nothing. It derives from their roles as

    norms of representation or as internally related

    to our norms of representation. They are not

    forced upon us, but rather we force them on

    ourselves. Their truth is not answerable to any

    reality, but determines the forms in which we

    describe reality and draw inferences from what

    we know about reality.

    This could be further elaborated. But I

    hope it suffices to show that Wittgenstein

    would have found current philosophical

    naturalism utterly repugnantfor very good

    reasons. Nevertheless, his own investigationsdemonstrate that one may advance powerful

    descriptions of aspects of our conceptual

    scheme that advert to what is natural to hu-

    mankind, without falling into the confusions

    of philosophical (scientistic) naturalism.

    St. Johns College, Oxford

    NOTES

    1. Barry Stroud, The Charm of Naturalism,Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophi-

    cal Association, vol. 70 (1996), p. 43.

    2. David Hume,An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, app. III,

    258 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1902), p. 307. He was speaking here of the principles of justice. He also

    observed in a footnote that natural may be contrasted with what is unusual, or what is miraculous,

    or what is artificial.

    3. For discussion of the history of the term and of the various forms of naturalism, see H.-J. Glock,

    What Is Analytic Philosophy?(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), pp. 137146.

    4. W. V. O. Quine, Things and Their Place in Theories, repr. in Theories and Things(Cambridge,

    Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981) p. 21.

    5. W. V. O. Quine, The Nature of Natural Knowledge, inMind and Language, ed. S. Guttenplan

    (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 68.

    6. W. V.O. Quine, Empirical Content, in Theories and Things, p. 75.

    7. W. V. O. Quine, Natural Kinds, in his Ontological Relativity and Other Essays(New York: Co-

    lumbia University Press, 1969), p. 126.

    8. For more detailed discussion, see P. M. S. Hacker, Passing by the Naturalistic Turn: On QuinesCul-de-sac, Philosophy, vol. 81 (2006), pp. 231254.

    9. I have remarked elsewhere on Quines apostasy (P. M. S. Hacker, Wittgensteins Place in

    Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy[Oxford: Blackwell 1996], p. 197), and critics have assumed

    that this is my description of Quine (the latest is Avishai Margalit in Wittgensteins Knight Move,

    in Wittgenstein and Analytic Philosophy, ed. H.-J. Glock and J. Hyman [Oxford: Oxford University

    Press, 2009], p. 5). That is mistaken. It rather is Quines description of himself and the evolution of

    his ideas on analyticity (see Autobiography of W. V. Quine, in The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, ed.

    L. E. Hahn and P. A. Schilpp [La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986], p. 16.)

    10.Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, App. III.

    11.Enquiry, App. III.

  • 8/13/2019 Hacker - A Plague on both your 'isms'

    15/15

    12. Anthony Kenny pointed out that it is a mistake to suppose evolutionary theory eliminated teleol-

    ogy from biology. It eliminated design, notpurpose(A. J. P. Kenny, Cosmological Explanation and

    Understanding, in Perspectives on Human Conduct, ed. L. Hertzberg and J. Pietarinen [Leiden, The

    Netherlands: Brill, 1988], pp. 7287). For further elaboration, see P. M. S. Hacker, Human Nature:

    The Categorial Framework(Oxford: Blackwell, 2007), chap. 6. Darwin was the first to acknowledgeprecisely this, as is evident in his correspondence with Asa Grey. Grey, in his review in Natureon June

    4, 1874, wrote: Let us recognise Darwins great service to Natural Science in bringing back to it Teleol-

    ogy: so that instead of Morphology versus Teleology, we shall have Morphology wedded to Teleology.

    Darwin was delighted, and the next day he wrote to Grey: I . . . cannot be easy without again telling

    you how profoundly I have been gratified. Every one, I suppose, occasionally thinks that he has worked

    in vain, and when one of these fits overtakes me, I will think of your article, and if that does not dispel

    the evil spirit, I shall know that I am at the time a little bit insane, as we all are occasionally. What you

    say about Teleology pleases me especially, and I do not think any one else has ever noticed the point.

    I have always said you were the man to hit the nail on the head.

    13. See P. M. S. Hacker, Wittgensteins Place in Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy (Oxford:Blackwell, 1996), p. 227.

    14. L. Wittgenstein, The Big Typescript(Oxford: Blackwell, 2005), p. 417.

    15. Wittgenstein, MS 183, 81.

    16. Of course, this is not to say that somepropositions held to be analytic in one sense or another of the

    term are not also grammatical, e.g., A vixen is a female fox or A bachelor is an unmarried man.

    17. W. V. O. Quine,Roots of Reference(La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1974), p. 3.

    BOTH YOUR ISMS/ 111