35

Glock WS2012

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • What are Concepts?

    Hans-Johann Glock

    Summary: The article argues that a reasonably unied

    account of the established use of `concept' and its cogna-

    tes can be provided by a cognitivist approach. Such an

    approach starts out from the role the ascription of con-

    cepts plays in characterizing certain cognitive operations

    and abilities, yet without treating concepts as symbolic

    representations or particulars in the minds of individu-

    als. In particular, it explores the idea that concepts are

    rules or principles of classication and inference. At the

    end I argue that a cognitivist account can deal not just

    with the role of concepts in cognition, but also with the

    idea that they are components of propositions.

    This article aims to elucidate the established use or uses of the

    term `concept', and those of its equivalents and cognates. This

    established use includes everyday uses: like some related terms

    with a philosophical provenance notably `idea' but unlike

    others notably `universal' `concept' is widely employed in

    everyday parlance.

    1

    But it also comprises the established uses

    of these terms in special disciplines like the history of ideas,

    psychology, logic and philosophy.

    Within these disciplines, one encounters numerous theoretical

    judgements or prejudices about concepts, for instance that they

    contrast with intuitions (Kant), are tied to language (rationalist

    tradition), are unsaturated entities (Frege), are compositional

    1

    Quotidian contexts are particularly signicant for the German Be-

    gri, since the humdrum verb begreifen covers all types of compre-

    hension. In a lecture, the late Michael Dummett once illustrated the

    pervasiveness of Begri by relating how struck he was on his rst

    visit to Germany when reading a sign at a railway station mentio-

    ning `Gepckstcke, die unter den Begri Koer fallen' that is,

    pieces of luggage which fall under the concept suitcase.

  • 8 Hans-Johann Glock

    (Fodor), must be amenable to naturalization (most philosophers

    and cognitive scientists in the USA), are socially constituted

    (most other North-American academics in the humanities), etc.

    However, my account seeks to respect not such specic theories

    about concepts, but rather fruitful uses of `concept' and its

    cognates. It is salutatory to remember that even in specialised

    disciplines the use of `concept' is rarely entirely stipulative or

    unconnected to the everyday use, since these disciplines purport

    to explain cognitive and semantic phenomena describable in

    terms of concepts in ordinary discourse.

    Philosophers and logicians talk of comparative (x is heavier

    than y), quantitative (x weighs 20kg), individual (the author

    of Atemschaukel), logical (negation, implication), spatial and

    temporal concepts, including the concepts of space and of time.

    My initial focus here will be on those concepts that have tended

    to occupy centre stage, namely predicative concepts. These are

    concepts that correspond to general terms of a particular kind,

    namely to the verbs, adjectives or count-nouns that feature in

    one-place predicates like `x runs', `x is radioactive' and `x is a

    tool'. But I shall also consider the question whether suggested

    denitions of concepts capture other types of concepts.

    It is relatively uncontroversial that predicative concepts are

    involved when rational creatures entertain thoughts like

    (1) Dogs bark.

    The nature of this involvement remains controversial, ho-

    wever. In the history of philosophy, one can distinguish three

    fundamental approaches to concepts. According to subjectivist

    conceptions, concepts are mental phenomena, particular entities

    or goings-on in the mind or in the head of individuals. According

    to objectivist conceptions, concepts exist independently of human

    minds, as self-subsistent abstract entities. Finally, there is an

    intermediate position, which may be termed cognitivist. It agrees

    with objectivism in denying that concepts are mental particulars,

    while at the same time maintaining, with subjectivism, that

  • What are Concepts? 9

    they have an ineliminable mental or cognitive dimension. One

    version of cognitivism is intersubjectivism. It holds that concepts

    exist independently of individual rational subjects, but insists

    that they are constituted by intersubjective linguistic practices.

    Another version brackets the question of existence, yet holds

    that what concepts are their essence, if you wish can be

    explained only by reference to the operations and capacities of

    rational subjects.

    This article investigates whether the concept of a concept can

    be given a fairly uniform explanation through a `cognitivist'

    account of this second, less committal kind, one that accepts

    that concepts may exist independently of individual subjects

    or even linguistic communities, yet nonetheless invokes mental

    achievements and capacities. I shall argue that (many) of

    the established ways of using `concept' can be explained by

    looking at the relationship between the concept of a concept

    and cognitive notions like ability, way of thinking and rule. In

    particular, I shall present a case for holding that a cognitivist

    explanation can account not just for the connection between

    concepts and human thinking and speaking but also for the idea

    that they are components of thoughts (propositions). If we are

    to situate concepts within the subjective/objective spectrum, it

    is useful to distinguish at least ve philosophical questions that

    can be raised about them:

    Denition question: What are concepts?

    Individuation question: How are concepts individuated?

    Possession question: What is it to have a concept?

    Function question: What is the role of concepts in cognition?

    Once we keep apart these four questions, one further question

    arises: Priority Question: Which of these questions denition,

    individuation, possession or function is the most fundamental?

    I have criticized prominent objectivist denitions of concepts el-

    sewhere (2010b: 312-5), and shall take their failure for granted

    here. Instead, I shall start by arguing against subjectivist ans-

  • 10 Hans-Johann Glock

    wers to the denition question. These arguments point in the

    direction of a cognitivist approach. Yet the most straightforward

    cognitivist denition, which identies concepts and abilities, will

    also be found wanting. On the other hand it will transpire that

    the cognitivist tradition gives the right response to the possession

    question, and that this response does not entail untenable ans-

    wers to the individuation question. This result will also suggest

    that cognitivism is right in according priority to the possession

    question.

    1 Concepts and general terms

    In many everyday contexts, `concept' means roughly: general

    term with a meaning.

    2

    This denition also ts the role of `con-

    cept' in logic in so far as concepts have an extension and are

    components of sentences (see below). Yet it does not capture

    crucial uses in philosophy, logic and psychology. In psychology, in

    particular, concepts are invoked to account for cognitive processes

    that are not verbalised. And this chimes with common sense. We

    do not express all of our thoughts in words- and thank goodness

    for that. Equally, we sometimes say that p when we think that q.

    A lingualist might reply that in such cases we talk to ourselves

    in foro interno, and that thinking is a kind of internal monologue

    (as Plato had suggested in Thaetetus: 189e). But Wittgenstein

    and Ryle ought to have taught us that speaking to oneself in the

    2

    This is more felicitous than predicates with a meaning, since the

    latter are supposed to involve the copula or its equivalents. The

    concept of a dog corresponds to the general term `dog' rather than

    the predicate `x is a dog'. A moot question which I shall not take up

    here is whether the latter is more closely aligned to the concept or

    property of being a dog. The addition `with a meaning' is superuous

    if a term is understood as a symbol, part of an established language;

    but it is required if a general term is understood as mere sign which

    has been accorded a syntactic role but no specic meaning (some-

    thing represented by a predicate-letter in an uninterpreted formal

    language).

  • What are Concepts? 11

    imagination is no more sucient or necessary for thinking than

    having mental images (see Glock 1997).

    Now, one might grant this point, yet insist that genuinely concep-

    tual thought must issue in `judgements', something in which the

    subject consciously and explicitly applies a general term, whether

    it be in overt or inner speech. This gambit would imply, however,

    that human cognition involves much less conceptual thought than

    commonly assumed; and it is not forced on us by the meaning of

    concept in psychology or ordinary parlance (see Prior 1953: ch.

    XI). Furthermore, the retreat to silent predication rules out ab

    initio the possibility of concept-possession by non-linguistic crea-

    tures, which is at least contentious (see Glock 2010a).

    Even if these qualms could be waived, moreover, silent predica-

    tion would not solve another problem. Talking to oneself in the

    imagination is a process involving specic languages. By contrast,

    in philosophy, logic and psychology concepts are standardly sup-

    posed to cut across dierent languages, whether they be natural

    languages or interpreted formal calculi. According to psycholo-

    gists, it is the concept of a dog rather than general terms like

    `dog' or `chien' that is involved in thinking (1). And a logical

    concept like that of negation is expressed equally by logical par-

    ticles from dierent languages: `not', `nicht', `ne pas', `~', etc. In

    such contexts, `concept' is more closely aligned with `idea' than

    with `word' or `term', which signify lexical items from specic

    languages.

    Now, there is a venerable tradition which would allow us to ex-

    tend the denition of concepts as general terms to non-verbalised

    cognitive processes and cognitive processes of non-linguistic crea-

    tures, and which also lifts the restriction to particular languages.

    This tradition postulates a mental language that is shared by

    all creatures capable of conceptual thought, a universal mental

    symbolism that underlies all specic languages. Concepts, the

    story goes, are nothing other than the words of this language of

    thought, a language that is thought by individuals rather than

    spoken by linguistic communities. This is a version of subjecti-

    vism. It goes back at least to Occam, and it ts Kant's claim

  • 12 Hans-Johann Glock

    that a concept is a `predicate of a possible judgement' (Critique

    of Pure Reason: A 69/B 94). Its most explicit and prominent ver-

    sion, however, is Fodor's `representational theory of mind'. This

    position will now be criticized.

    2 Are concepts mental particulars or mental

    representations?

    According to Fodor, so-called propositional attitudes like belief

    and desire are mental states, and they `are constituted by rela-

    tions to mental representations', namely `thoughts' (Fodor 2003:

    141, 10). Concepts are `the constituents of thoughts' (Fodor 1998:

    25). They constitute a kind of `mental representation' and hence

    a `kind of mental particular'. As mental particulars, they are `ob-

    jects in the mind' or `in the head' of individuals; they are `concre-

    te' rather than abstract; and they have causes and eects in the

    physical world (Fodor 1998: 3, 7-8, 22; Fodor 2003: 13 and note).

    As mental representations, they have `representational content'.

    They contribute to the content of our propositional attitudes, to

    what we believe, desire, etc. They do so by determining the con-

    ditions under which our beliefs are true and our desires satised.

    Any form of subjectivism faces a Fregean objection: concepts can-

    not be phenomena in the minds or heads of individuals, since they

    can be shared between dierent subjects. Now, `sharing' and its

    cognates are used in a variety of ways. One paradigm is that of

    dividing an object into parts, which themselves are not shared,

    as in sharing a banana. But there is another, equally basic, para-

    digm which does not imply division and extends well beyond ma-

    terial objects. Dierent people can share bicycles, predilections,

    insurance companies, heads of states, the credit for an invention,

    beliefs, etc. It is in this sense that concepts are shareable. Two

    individuals A and B can both have the same concept F, which

    means that it is possible that both A and B have mastered and

    employ F.

    Shareability is a feature of the concept of a concept in both every-

    day life and in disciplines like psychology and the history of ideas.

  • What are Concepts? 13

    One central use we make of `concept' and terms that are equiva-

    lent in the relevant contexts (like `conception', `idea' or `notion')

    is in claims about dierent individuals or even groups of indivi-

    duals either sharing a concept, or failing to do so. For instance,

    dierent political and religious traditions may or may not share

    the same concept of freedom or of guilt. Such claims are equally

    central to intellectual history, e.g. when it comes to comparing

    the Greek concept of eudaimonia with our concept of happiness.

    Fodor accepts shareability as a `non-negotiable condition', that

    concepts are `the sorts of things that lots of people can, and do,

    share' (Fodor 1998: 28). The obvious diculty is that mental

    particulars contrast with concepts in that they are modes of in-

    dividual minds or heads, and hence private to their owners. Fodor

    thinks, however, that he can easily overcome this diculty by in-

    troducing a distinction between type and token. Fodor's `language

    of thought hypothesis' treats mental representations as symbols

    of a `language of thought' or `Mentalese'. Thoughts, the larger

    wholes formed by concepts, are the sentences of Mentalese, phy-

    sical tokens of computational types. When we engage in concep-

    tual thought, Mother Nature inscribes the words of a computer

    programme into our brains. And concepts are nothing other than

    the token-words of Mentalese, i.e. computationally identied pat-

    terns of neural rings.

    Consider the scenario in which Anne and Sarah both believe that

    dogs bark and (improbably) utter `Dogs bark' in close succes-

    sion. In that case we have two tokens of a single type-sentence

    `Dogs bark', and two tokens of a single type-word `bark'. Similar-

    ly, according to Fodor, in Anne's brain there occurs one neural

    token-sentence, and in Sarah's brain there occurs another neural

    token-sentence. Yet Anne and Sarah both believe the same thing,

    namely that dogs bark, since both tokens instantiate the same

    Mentalese type-sentence DOGS BARK. Finally, they share the

    concept DOG, because both have tokens of one and the same

    Mentalese type-word.

    This position can account for shareability. It does so at a pri-

    ce, however. The type/token distinction implies abandoning the

  • 14 Hans-Johann Glock

    claim that concepts themselves are particulars. After all, Anne

    and Sarah do not have a Mentalese token-word in common, what

    they have in common is that their distinct token-words are of

    the same type. What can be shared between dierent individuals

    are representation-types; and these types, as Fodor duly acknow-

    ledges, are `abstracta' rather than mental particulars (see 1998:

    20-1, 28). To be more precise, types are repeatable universals and

    hence abstract. Conversely, what can qualify as mental particu-

    lars are representation-tokens; and these tokens are conned to

    each individual rather than shareable. This leaves Fodor's positi-

    on in tatters. On the one hand, the non-negotiable constraint on

    concepts, namely that they be shareable, is satised only by the

    abstract types which are neither particulars (mental, physical or

    otherwise) nor concrete. On the other hand, his central claim, na-

    mely that concepts are concrete particulars, applies only to the

    tokens which are not shareable. If one persistently keeps apart

    types and tokens, one is forced to abandon the subjectivist credo

    that concepts are mental particulars that can enter into causal

    relations. Concepts themselves the things that can be shared

    by dierent individuals are not particulars.

    As far as shareability is concerned, concepts might yet be mental

    representations, namely of the type- rather than token-variety.

    This is in line with Fodor's contention that `concepts are [Menta-

    lese] symbols' (Fodor 1998: 28). But at the same time he is driven

    to the claim that concepts are something that `mental representa-

    tions . . . express', namely `word meanings' (Fodor 1998: 2; Fodor

    2003: 13). Accordingly, he is committed to the inconsistent claim

    that concepts are both mental words and the meanings of those

    very same words. This inconsistency is no coincidence. Instead,

    it is connected to a fundamental aw in the language of thought

    hypothesis and a general problem with the idea that concepts or

    thoughts are representations.

    Following Peirce's theory of signs (1933), one can distinguish bet-

    ween dierent types of representation:

    Icons resemble what they represent

    Symbols are related to what they represent by convention

  • What are Concepts? 15

    Indices are connected to what they `represent' by causal de-

    pendencies or by other natural relations such as spatial or

    temporal proximity.

    Thus realist paintings are icons of what they represent. Linguistic

    expressions, with the possible exception of onomatopoetic ones,

    are symbols of what they represent. The word `dog', for example,

    is connected to the animals not through any kind of resemblance,

    but through an arbitrary convention. Smoke, nally, is an index

    of re, because it is a causal result of re.

    Given this distinction, one might deliver the following brief ver-

    dict on the idea of a neurophysiological language of thought:

    a) Patterns of neural rings are indices of external phenomena,

    but only for suitably informed with neurophysiological mea-

    suring equipment, not for ordinary subjects of thought;

    b) they might be icons (but in fact not);

    c) they cannot be symbols.

    That neural rings are causal results of external events and cau-

    sal preconditions of perception is agreed on all sides. The extent

    to which there is, for example, a spatial resemblance between the

    objects of perception and the neural activities that underlie per-

    ception, is a matter for empirical investigation. For the most part,

    no such iconic relation has been observed. Although experiments

    like those of Hubel and Wiesel show that particular neurons are

    involved in seeing lines of a particular orientation, there is no ico-

    nic similarity between the lines and the pattern of ring neurons.

    Finally, neural rings cannot be symbols because there is no one

    who uses them to represent somehing in a conventional way (a

    point to which I shall return). Accordingly, there can be no men-

    tal symbols and hence no language of thought.

    What about the more general idea that concepts are representati-

    ons? According to an orthodoxy shared by Fodor, concepts must

    be shareable because they are components of what people belie-

    ve, of shareable thoughts or `propositional contents'. But as their

    components, concepts can no more be representations or signs

    than propositions themselves they are what is represented, the

  • 16 Hans-Johann Glock

    content of thinking, not what represents, i.e. what expresses these

    contents (Glock 2009 elaborates these objectioins to Fodor).

    This lesson is in line with the common sense view that concepts

    are expressed by signs such as predicates or logical operators. It

    also follows from a more basic feature of the notion of represen-

    tation.

    Bona de representations, at least of an iconic or symbolic kind,

    require a medium. That is to say, they have representational pro-

    perties by virtue of having non-representational properties. For

    instance, Rembrandt's self-portrait in the National Gallery of

    Scotland represents a particular individual on account of more

    basic properties, roughly the way in which it arranges colours

    and shapes (see Hyman 2006). Similarly, the sign-token `Rem-

    brandt Harmenszoon van Rijn' signies that same individual on

    account of its typographic properties, which are subject to the

    kind of conventions characteristic of symbols.

    The idea that thoughts and concepts are (mental, computatio-

    nal or neural) representations is incompatible with this dening

    feature of representations. With apologies to Marshall McLuhan,

    thoughts and by implication concepts are all message and no

    medium! Or, with rather fewer apologies to Ludwig Wittgenstein,

    thought is not a linguistic symbol requiring interpretation; it is

    itself `the last interpretation' (1958: 34).

    But couldn't one respond that concepts and propositions qua

    sign-types of Mentalese do occur in a medium, namely a medium

    of neural rings? The latter represent propositional or conceptu-

    al contents on account of their non-representational physiological

    or physical properties. According to Fodor, for instance, these

    representations have certain syntactic properties properties de-

    termining the way they are processed on account of their phy-

    siological qualities, and they have certain semantic properties,

    properties determining what they represent, on account of their

    causal relations to the environment.

    At this juncture, the epistemic or cognitive dimension of repre-

    sentations comes into play. The non-representational properties

    of representations must be accessible to the subject of representa-

  • What are Concepts? 17

    tion. After all, a representation R is not just a sign of something

    an object O, but a sign for someone a subject of representati-

    on S someone to whom X is represented through R (again, the

    point was epitomized by Peirce, in his famous semiotic triangle).

    Yet neural tokens of computational types are entirely and in prin-

    ciple inaccessible to the subject; they are `deeply unconscious', to

    use Searle's (1997) critical label. By the same token, they cannot

    be used by S intentionally or, a fortiori, with the specic intent

    to represent something. Nor can the subject employ them accor-

    ding to rules, as required for symbolic representation.

    A possible response: neural signs are used by sub-personal sub-

    jects, e.g. by the brain, its parts, or functionally dened modu-

    les.

    3

    But this invites the charge of a `homunculus' or `mereological

    fallacy' (Kenny 1984: ch. 9; Bennett/Hacker 2003). This is the

    fallacy of explaining mental attributes of an animal or subject

    in our case the capacity for conceptual thought by postulating

    sub-personal subjects homunculi with the same or similar

    mental capacities in this case the capacity for the intentional

    employment of signs. The explanation is fallacious because these

    capacities can only be attributed to the animal or subject S as

    a whole, and not save metaphorically to its parts, whether

    they be organs like S 's brain or capacities like S 's mind. Further-

    more, even if it made sense to credit sub-personal instances with

    symbolic understanding, this would only push back the problem.

    One then needs to explain the representational capacities of these

    postulated homunculi, which engenders a regress.

    Yet surely, to anyone except die-hard behaviourists the very exis-

    tence of cognitive phenomena shows that there are mental repre-

    sentations! Doesn't thought require some kind of representation?

    The answer is yes, but only if `representation' is divested from

    the standard connection with a medium and understood in a mi-

    3

    Fodor himself does not fall back on this response. He grants that

    `nobody ever interprets mental representations' (2008: 16). Yet this

    concession removes any license for holding that these representations

    are symbolic, and hence for speaking about a language of thought.

  • 18 Hans-Johann Glock

    nimalist sense. On that understanding, our thoughts are repre-

    sentations, simply because they have what are nowadays called

    semantic properties:

    a proposition that p is true or false

    a singular representation a refers or fails to refer to an object x

    a concept F applies or doesn't apply to an object x

    However, representations in this minimalist sense cannot explain

    thought. For to represent (that p or x or F s or things being F )

    in this sense simply is to think (to think that p, about x, about

    F s, or about things being F ).

    4

    Representationalism is reduced to

    uninformative claims like:

    to think that a is F is to represent a as being F,

    and to think of F s qua F s is to represent F s, etc.

    A non-representationalist (`cognitivist') approach at least holds

    the promise of a genuine explanation of what thought amounts

    to: what it is to think that p or about F s as F s is spelled out in

    terms of the possession of certain cognitive abilities.

    4

    Austere representationalists such as Husserl (1900), have disassocia-

    ted the idea of representation from any specic connotations, nota-

    bly from the link with a particular medium whether it be mental

    images or words crossing one's mind, neural rings or computational

    symbols. But such positions once more face the task of explaining

    what having a representation amounts to. In Husserl's case, for ex-

    ample, we seem to be left with the idea that it is `just like' mental

    picturing, only without mental images. But that simply boils down

    to saying that having a representation of (an) F is to think about

    (an) F, which means that the explanation of thought has moved

    in a circle. A logical relation, thinking about (an) F, has rst been

    construed as a pictorial one, and has then been robbed of the picto-

    rial aspects which alone can give it any substance (Tugendhat 1976:

    62-3, 276-7).

  • What are Concepts? 19

    3 Concepts and abilities

    The most popular and straightforward cognitivist answer to the

    denition question identies concepts with abilities. Thus, in re-

    sponse to the question `Are concepts entities or are they dispo-

    sitions?' Price states in no uncertain terms: `a concept is not an

    entity [. . . ] but a disposition or capacity' (1953: 320, 348). In the

    same vein Geach pronounces that concepts `are capacities exer-

    cised in acts of judgement' (1957: 7, see also 13; Saporiti 2010).

    The idea that concepts are abilities is also espoused by Millikan

    from a very dierent, naturalistic perspective (2000: ch. 4). This

    proposal respects several features of established use.

    First, properties are objective, something possessed by things of

    all kinds. By contrast, concepts are something possessed by ra-

    tional subjects capable of classifying things according to their

    properties. This is simply a crucial aspect of the cognitive dimen-

    sion of concepts stressed by cognitivism.

    Secondly, the identication of concepts and capacities does not

    fall foul of the constraint that concepts must be shareable. As Ge-

    ach points out, it does not entail that `it is improper to speak of

    two people as having the same concept ', since dierent indivi-

    duals can possess the same mental capacities (1957: 14). Thirdly,

    concepts and abilities alike can be acquired, applied and lost, and

    some of them may be innate.

    Finally, to possess a concept is to possess a certain kind of mental

    ability, capacity or disposition. In what follows, I refrain from de-

    ciding which of these types of potentiality is the most appropriate

    general category (see Glock 2010b: section 5). Barring that issue,

    identifying concept-possession with an ability, capacity or dispo-

    sition of some kind is inevitable. That concept-possession is an

    ability of some kind is accepted, willy-nilly, even by Fodor, who

    purports to contradict cognitivism (a.k.a. `pragmatism') on this

    issue (2003: 19). The real bone of contention between representa-

    tionalists like Fodor and those cognitivists that can properly be

    called `concept pragmatists' in a wide sense e.g. Wittgenstein,

    Ryle, Travis and concerns the question of whether concept-

    possession is simply the ability to represent the property of being

  • 20 Hans-Johann Glock

    F or F s as F s, or whether it should be explained as the ability to

    classify things into those which are F s and those which aren't, or

    to draw inferences from thoughts about F s. Concepts are involved

    not just in occurrent thoughts or beliefs, but also in long-standing

    or dispositional beliefs. Consequently, the possession of concepts

    must be at least as stable as the possession of dispositional beliefs.

    Put in Aristotelian terms, concept-possession must be a poten-

    tiality of some kind, since it combines two features. On the one

    hand, it is enduring rather than episodic. On the other hand, it

    is something which manifests itself in certain episodes, notably of

    overt or silent classication and inference.

    In addition to respecting features of the established concept of

    a concept, dening concepts as abilities has advantages when it

    comes to explaining both the phylo- and the ontogenesis of con-

    ceptual thought and of language. Of course, the denition itself

    does not provide such a genetic explanation. But it claries how

    we might be able to give a genetic account that avoids vicious

    regress and circularity and thereby the paradoxical denial that

    an explanation is impossible in principle. In particular, the abili-

    ty approach is congenial to the following claims that facilitate a

    genetic explanation of conceptual thought:

    i. there are preconceptual forms of cognition, conation and in-

    tentional action;

    ii. these dier from the conceptual forms through the absence

    of certain advanced cognitive abilities.

    iii. abilities can be possessed in varying degrees, and they can be

    acquired through a gradual process.

    4 The individuation of concepts and abilities

    Its attractions notwithstanding, the identication of concepts

    with abilities faces the objection that it implies an untenable ans-

    wer to the individuation question. Thus Fodor has alleged that

    concepts are more nely individuated than abilities. For instance,

    `creature with a kidney' and `creature with a heart' apply to all

    and only the same things, but they express dierent concepts.

  • What are Concepts? 21

    Furthermore, `equilateral triangle' and `equiangular triangle' ap-

    ply necessarily to the same things, yet they still express dierent

    concepts. In current jargon, concepts are not just `intensional'

    but `hyperintensional'.

    Now, an ability is individuated by reference to its exercise. But,

    Fodor maintains, the same sorting and inferential performances

    can manifest the possession of dierent concepts. Conning our-

    selves to the ability to sort or discriminate, sorting equilateral tri-

    angles from all other gures is also sorting equiangular triangles

    from all other gures (Glock 2003: 256, 1436). It seems to fol-

    low that concepts cannot be individuated by the exercise of an

    ability, and hence that they cannot be individuated by reference

    to abilities. In eect, Fodor's objection runs as follows:

    P1 Abilities are individuated by their exercise (ability to =ability to i ing = ing).P2 In all possible situations, one and the same sorting activity

    can manifest dierent concepts.

    C: Concepts cannot be individuated through the abilities which

    constitute their possession.

    The argument is valid. Yet P2 is false: sorting triangles according

    to lengths is not the same activity as sorting triangles according

    to angles, even though the results are the same. The dierence in

    the two activities can be displayed by linguistic creatures, who can

    justify their sorting along dierent lines. It can even be manifes-

    ted in non-linguistic behaviour. A creature that sorts on account

    of comparing or measuring lengths applies equilateral triangle, a

    creature that sorts on account of measuring angles applies equian-

    gular triangle. These are dierent activities, manifesting dierent

    abilities and thereby the possession of dierent concepts. And it

    is obvious that one can have one of these abilities or concepts

    without having the other. Indeed, most children actually learn

    how to measure lengths before learning how to measure angles.

    But individuation also poses another challenge to identifying con-

    cepts with abilities. Many cognitivists grant that there is no pre-

    cise way of individuating abilities. Thus Travis (2000) grants that

  • 22 Hans-Johann Glock

    linking concepts to abilities may not be much help in individua-

    ting concepts, since it is not clear how abilities are to be counted.

    That concession needs to be put in perspective, however. Like

    Travis, Geach (1957: 15) accepts that it is absurd to ask how

    many abilities are exercised in a judgement. Yet he also insists,

    rightly, that we can still distinguish between such abilities. More

    generally, one must distinguish between the possibility of enume-

    rating and the possibility individuating entities of a particular

    kind (see Strawson 1997: ch. 1; Glock 2003: 4752). And this ge-

    neral lesson applies equally to abilities.

    Still a problem remains. It is prima facie plausible to hold that

    we are able not only to distinguish the concept of a dog from that

    of barking, but also to specify that precisely two concepts are in-

    volved in judging that dogs bark. So concepts and abilities seem

    to come apart on the issue of enumerability. This verdict can be

    contested, however, on the grounds that it does not compare like

    with like. The claim that the number of concepts involved in (1)

    is determinate is only even remotely plausible if we conne oursel-

    ves to predicative concepts (otherwise we have to add at least one

    quantitative concept that corresponds to the plural in English; al-

    ternatively, if we analyse (1) with the help of Fregean logic, we

    need to add the logical concepts of universal quantication and

    of material implication). But the very same consideration applies

    to abilities. It is just as plausible to insist that precisely two pre-

    dicative abilities are involved in judging that (1) namely that of

    thinking about dogs and that of thinking about things that bark

    as it is to maintain that precisely two predicative concepts are

    involved in (1).

    5 Dierences between concepts and abilities

    The stumbling block for identifying concepts with abilities is not

    individuation. It is rather that there are other respects in which

    the established use of `concept' diers from that of `ability', not

    least as regards the role or function of concepts.

    First, one thing we do with concepts is to dene or explain them.

  • What are Concepts? 23

    But to dene or explain a concept is not to dene or explain a

    capacity. Normally, to explain an ability is to explain its causal

    preconditions (causal explanation), whereas to explain a concept

    is to explain its content (semantic explanation). Furthermore,

    even when we dene an ability (i.e. explain its content), we

    specify what it is an ability to do; as just mentioned, abilities

    are individuated through their exercise. By contrast, to explain

    a predicative concept is to specify the conditions that an object

    must satisfy to fall under it.

    Secondly, and relatedly, concepts can be instantiated or satised

    by things; conversely, things instantiate, satisfy or fall under

    concepts. These things cannot be said of abilities, or at least not

    in the same sense.

    Thirdly, and once more relatedly, concepts have an extension

    (the set of objects which fall under them) and an intension

    (the features which qualify objects for falling under them); yet

    this cannot be said of abilities. Insofar as the ability linked to

    possessing the concept F has an extension, it is not the range of

    things that are F, but either the range of subjects that possess

    F, or the range of situations in which these possessors can apply

    or withhold F.

    Fourthly, a concept can occur in a proposition or statement, but

    an ability cannot. Of course, abilities can occur in propositions

    in the sense of being mentioned in them, as in

    (2) The ability to lie convincingly is a great asset in ban-

    king.

    But it seems that concepts occur in propositions in yet

    another and more pervasive way, not just as topics or referents,

    something the proposition is about, but as components. The

    concept of being sweet occurs in the proposition that

    (3) Sugar is sweet

    even though no ability occurs in it.

  • 24 Hans-Johann Glock

    6 Tools

    At this point it behoves us to return to the issue of concept

    possession, since it provides the strongest argument in favour of

    the identication. It starts out from

    (I) to possess a concept is to possess a certain mental ability.

    Next, it glosses (I) as

    (I') to possess a concept = to possess a certain mental ability

    It then invokes the additional premise

    (II) to possess x = to possess y x = y

    in order to reach the conclusion that

    (III) a concept = a certain mental ability.

    But this reasoning is problematic. First, it is unclear whe-

    ther (I) is indeed an identity statement, as the paraphrase (I')

    assumes. Often statements of the form `to is to ' merelyexpress a generality statement of the form `For all x, if x F s then

    x Gs)'. The latter need not even be reversible (as in `to be a

    Cretan is to be a liar'). Next, to be reversible, (I) and (I') would

    have to specify a particular mental ability which is equivalent

    to concept possession. This is far from trivial, as we shall see.

    And even if this feat has been achieved, it will be insucient

    to establish an identity. It will only mean that everyone who

    possesses a concept also possesses this specic mental ability,

    and vice versa.

    Furthermore, it remains an open question whether (I) should

    not instead be glossed as:

    I* S has the concept F S has the ability of operating with F.

  • What are Concepts? 25

    To be sure, someone who identies concepts with abilities will

    resist that paraphrase and insist that the ability with which pos-

    sessing the concept F is to be identied must be explained with-

    out mentioning the concept F, an entity with which the subject

    operates. But it is an alternative that her arguments do not rule

    out. That alternative is based on the following line of thought. If

    having a concept is an ability, it is an ability to operate with con-

    cepts. In that case, however, the concept itself cannot be identical

    with the ability. Rather, it is something employed in the exercise

    of that ability.

    A cognitivist conception which picks up this cue is the popular

    idea that concepts are a kind of cognitive or linguistic tool. Con-

    cepts are things employed in the exercise of conceptual abilities,

    just as tools are things employed in the exercise of manual (tech-

    nical) abilities.

    Unfortunately, it is far from clear what kind of tool concepts

    might be. Worse still, the analogy is misleading to begin with.

    The idea that concepts are akin to tools in that they are objects

    (concrete, mental or abstract) with which we operate in conceptu-

    al thought amounts to a reication. There is a dierence between

    the possession of a tool and the possession of the ability to em-

    ploy the tool as I keep discovering to my cost when trying to

    operate our electric drill. This distinction cannot be drawn in the

    case of concepts. To possess a concept is ipso facto to possess the

    ability to use the concept.

    5

    I now turn to two proposals that avoid the pitfall of treating

    objects as if they were bona de objects.

    7 Ways of thinking

    First, the Neo-Fregean proposal that concepts are senses or `mo-

    des of presentation' (Peacocke 1992; Knne 2005). Unfortunately,

    the latter is merely a catch-phrase, and one Frege himself never

    explained adequately, least of all with respect to concepts, which

    5

    In this respect, concepts resemble skills. To possess a skill is ipso

    facto to possess the ability to apply the skill.

  • 26 Hans-Johann Glock

    he regarded as referents rather than senses of predicates. But we

    can put some esh on it by treating concepts as ways of thin-

    king about objects, though not in the adverbial sense of thinking

    about them hard or longingly. More specically, concepts are ways

    of thinking about or conceiving of objects as possessing certain

    properties, without themselves being properties. To render that

    suggestion viable, we need to avoid literal interpretations of the

    Fregean idea that a sense is a `mode of presenting a referent'.

    Strictly speaking, there can be no way of presenting a referent

    unless there is a referent or extension. In the case of concepts,

    this would rule out uninstantiated concepts, which is absurd. On

    my construal, therefore, ways of thinking about objects are direc-

    ted not just at those objects which possess the relevant properties,

    but at all objects of which the relevant properties can be predi-

    cated either truly or falsely. To put it dierently, a concept is a

    way of thinking of objects from a suitable range as possessing or

    lacking certain properties. This reintroduces the idea of classica-

    tion. Finally, we can operationalize the idea of ways of thinking,

    thereby further spelling out its cognitive dimension. The concept

    expressed by a predicate is determined by the features to which

    the subject refers in deciding whether a given object falls under

    the concept, or would decide, if the question arose.

    6

    Neo-Fregeanism does justice to the cognitive dimension in several

    respects. First, its answer to the possession question runs:

    A subject S possesses the concept F i S is capable of

    thinking of an object as being an F.

    Secondly, the Neo-Fregean answer to the denition question has

    it that concepts are `representational abstract entities' (Knne

    2007: 346-7). Qua modes of presentation they are not linguistic

    symbols predicates of a language of thought but things ex-

    pressed by symbols. Yet they in turn are ways of thinking about

    objects or of objects as having properties. Concepts are at the

    same time representanda of the predicates of public languages

    and representantia of properties. And they are subjective not in

    6

    For a more elaborate discussion of Neo-Fregeanism, see Glock 2011.

  • What are Concepts? 27

    the sense of being inside the minds or brains of individuals, but

    only in a sense related to the function question: it is essential to

    concepts that they play a role in cognitive acts and operations.

    Hurdles remain nonetheless when it comes to expatiating upon

    the idea of thinking of an object as possessing certain properties.

    For one thing, to accommodate even all employments of predica-

    tive concepts Neo-Fregeans are driven to statements like

    one thinks of something as F if one judges, that it is F,

    when one hopes that it is F, when one wonders, whether it

    is F, etc. for all propositional attitudes and acts. (Knne

    2007: 343)

    Alas, when I wonder whether Susan is well, I do not, normally,

    think of her as being well. Accordingly, `thinking of something as

    F ' cannot have its normal sense here, and hence cannot be used

    to explain the Neo-Fregean notion of `way of thinking'. One might

    respond that `thinking of something as F ' has a technical sense

    here; it is something one does when one judges that x is F, hopes

    that x is F, wonders whether it is F, etc. But this would once more

    take us back to square one, namely the cognitive phenomena that

    concepts were supposed to explain.

    For another, `thinking of objects as possessing certain properties'

    does not t all types of concept or conceptual thought. It directly

    captures predicative concepts and classication. And perhaps the

    idea can be extended to comparative, quantitative, spatial and

    temporal concepts, and to individual concepts, provided that the

    latter are welcomed as bona de concepts in the rst place. But

    it does not capture logical concepts and inference. To possess

    the concept of negation is not a `mode of presenting' or a `way of

    thinking' about a putative logical object negation, or the property

    of being negated, or even of negated propositions or a proposition

    as negated. Instead, it is a way of operating with negation, e.g.

    in negating propositions and drawing inferences.

  • 28 Hans-Johann Glock

    8 Techniques and rules

    A nal cognitivist approach promises both more specicity and

    greater generality. It also has the advantage of acknowledging

    that a concept is something employed in conceptual thought

    without reifying it. A concept is not an object, properly speaking,

    the story goes, but a technique. Thus Wittgenstein maintained

    that `a concept is a technique of using a word', or `the technique

    of our use of an expression: as it were, the railway network that

    we have built for it' (1988: 50 and 2000: MS 163: 56v). To master

    or possess a technique is to master or possess an ability. Yet

    techniques are not themselves abilities, but something which the

    possessor of an ability uses in exercising the ability. There is a

    dierence, for instance, between the ability to skin a rabbit and

    the various techniques one might employ to this end.

    Wittgenstein regarded concepts as linguistic techniques. But

    his idea can be given a Kantian twist, in order to avoid the

    potentially problematic implication that concepts are the

    prerogative of linguistic creatures. One can tie concepts instead

    to thought or understanding rather than language. Concepts are

    techniques not just for using words, but for mental operations or

    mental acts which may or may not be expressed in language. The

    capacity for such mental operations may presuppose possession

    of language, yet it can denitely be exercised by a subject that

    does not engage in either overt or silent speech at the time (see

    also section 1 above).

    But what kind of mental operation? Here we face the question of

    what function or functions concepts are supposed to full. The

    most popular candidate, and the one that has preoccupied us so

    far, is classication. Often classication is in turn spelled out as

    an operation of discrimination, of sorting things into those that

    do and those that do not fall under the concept. This elaboration

    invites an objection, however. There is at least one concept that

    cannot be used to discriminate between those things that fall

    under it and those that do not, namely the concept of identity

    (Knne 2007: 344). It makes no sense to sort things into those

    that are and those that are not identical with themselves. One

  • What are Concepts? 29

    way of avoiding this problem is to gloss classication not as

    sorting, but as recognizing. In so far as identity is a bona de

    relation at all, it makes sense to recognize that it is one in which

    each thing stands to itself.

    A second response is to cast our net more widely. There is

    a second basic function standardly and plausibly ascribed to

    concepts, namely inference. This obviously accommodates the

    concept of identity, which has a distinctive role in inference.

    In any event, acknowledging inference as a basic function of

    concepts in addition to classication is imperative in order to

    account for logical concepts. As we have seen, these defy the

    labels `mode of presentation' or `way of thinking about', and by

    the same token they should not be lumbered articially with the

    function of classifying things. At the same time logical concepts

    are obviously at least as amenable to being treated as cognitive

    techniques as predicative concepts.

    Accordingly, the proposal currently under consideration is this:

    a concept is not identical with the capacity to classify or infer,

    but only with the technique employed by someone who exercises

    the ability to classify or infer. Next, the term `technique' needs

    to be made more specic. What matters as far as concepts are

    concerned whether they be predicative or logical are the

    rules or principles that guide conceptual thought. Concepts, the

    proposal now runs, are rules or principles of classication and/or

    inference.

    Even this modied proposal is threatened by category mismat-

    ches. It does not seem that to dene a concept is to dene a

    principle or rule. Rather, the principle or rule features in the

    denition. On the other hand, perhaps this is just a vagary

    of the current use of `denition' in English, without further

    conceptual import. There is no linguistic infelicity in maintaining

    that to explain a concept is to explain a principle or rule for

    performing certain mental or linguistic operations.

    7

    At the same

    7

    One might further remonstrate that, strictly speaking, it is terms

    rather than concepts that are dened. After all, concepts are suppo-

    sed to be located at the level of meaning rather than that of symbols.

  • 30 Hans-Johann Glock

    time one would at the very least feel queasy about violating or

    acting in accordance with a concept. But note that one can do

    violence to a concept, by misapplying it or stretching it beyond

    breaking-point. Finally, while rules apply to subjects or agents

    under their `jurisdiction', concepts apply to objects that satisfy

    their dening criteria.

    Another qualm would be that principles can be true or false,

    whereas concepts cannot. Prima facie, at least, rules escape

    this diculty. Even if they are expressed by sentences in the

    indicative mood, it is arguable that their `truth' amounts to

    nothing other than a particular prescription being actually in

    force.

    The question remains, however, what form these principles

    or rules should take. Here we seem to be facing a dilemma.

    One apparent option is that these rules are standards for the

    employment of concepts. They might, for instance, take the

    form of the rules Bennett extracts from Kant (Bennett 1966: 145):

    (IV) You may apply concept F to x i x is . . .

    But on this proposal, the concept F itself would not be

    identical with the rule after all. It would rather be a predicate

    the use of which is governed by the rule.

    A second option is that the rule species another activity, e.g.

    (V) You may treat x in way W i x is . . . .

    In that case the danger is that we are stuck with two un-

    palatable options. One is that W is a place-holder for practical

    activities which may presuppose concept-possession, but which

    someone who has mastered the concept need not be able to

    But the matter is not straightforward. While one cannot dene the

    meaning of an expression, one can certainly explain it. The crucial

    point is that in all three cases terms, concepts, meanings one

    ultimately species and demonstrates rules or principles for certain

    cognitive or linguistic operations.

  • What are Concepts? 31

    engage in; the other is that W is a place-holder for conceptuali-

    zation, which would render the account unexplanatory.

    Fortunately, this dilemma is more apparent than real. The

    second horn can be avoided by noting that the form which

    a conceptual rule takes depends on the kind of concept or

    conceptual operation at issue. It is at least plausible to hold

    that those cognitive operations which are genuinely conceptual

    revolve around classication on the one hand, inference on the

    other. If one is hard up for a generic label, one can say that

    conceptual capacities are those involved in judgement (see also

    Glock 2010a). Thirdly, the operations governed by rules of

    classication and inference are clearly cognitive rather than

    practical in nature, which avoids the rst horn of the dilemma.

    This leaves one nal question: is there a substantive common

    denominator between classication and inference, one that goes

    beyond both being advanced cognitive operations? The answer

    may well be negative. It is not even clear that classication and

    inference always go together. Admittedly, even formal inference

    depending on logical concepts presuppose judgements involving

    predicative concepts and hence classication. But it is less clear

    that classication requires inference of either the formal or the

    material kind. There is at least a case to be made that the

    behavioural capacities of some non-linguistic creatures amount

    to classication rather than mere discrimination of stimuli, yet

    without crossing the threshold of inference (see Newen and

    Bartels 2007; Carey 2009; Glock 2010a).

    9 The proposition problem

    We now need to attend to a problem facing all cognitivist ac-

    counts. Concepts are treated as the components from which pro-

    positions are built, especially in logic and philosophy. At least

    prima facie, however, neither abilities, nor ways of thinking, nor

    rules of classication and inference occur in normal propositions;

    at best, they occur in those propositions which are, respectively,

    about abilities, ways of thinking or rules, i.e. explicitly mention

  • 32 Hans-Johann Glock

    or refer to them.

    There are two ways of responding to this `proposition problem'.

    I shall argue that in combination, these responses promise to re-

    solve this diculty, which would otherwise seem intractable.

    If Strawson (1959: Part II) is to be trusted, a universal such as a

    property can enter a proposition not just in the direct sense that

    the sentence expressing the proposition contains a word or phrase

    referring to the property of being F, but also in the less direct

    sense that the sentence contains a word or phrase signifying it. By

    a similar token, such a sentence would contain a general term ex-

    pressing the concept F, even though it does not refer to it. What

    is more, one can extend this courtesy to any otherwise plausible

    explanans of `concept'. Sticking to the rule proposal, this would

    mean that the predicate in (3) expresses a rule for classiying

    substances into those that possess the property of being sweet

    and those that don't.

    Crucial to this construal is that standard propositions, and by

    implication our common or garden thoughts, are not about con-

    cepts. That insight goes back at least as far as Aquinas. Ideas

    (species) are `not what is thought of (id quod intelligitur) but

    that by which thinking takes place (id quo intelligitur)' (Kenny

    1980: 71). It is also accepted by Price, who identies concepts

    with capacities:

    The concept is not before the mind as an object of in-

    spection. It is at work in the mind, but not as one in-

    spectable content among others . . . It shows itself not as

    a detectable item of mental furniture, but rather as a gui-

    ding force, determining the direction which the series of

    presented particulars [mental images or words] takes . . . '

    (Price 1953: 342).

    Finally, it is congenial to the Neo-Fregeanism propounded by

    Knne. In the spirit of Strawson, Knne distinguishes between

    application, connotes and expression: the general term `dog' ap-

    plies to all and only dogs, connotes the property of being a dog,

    and expresses the concept of being a dog (2005: 254 and fn. 31,

  • What are Concepts? 33

    263; see also his 2003: 4).

    Some such distinction is prerequisite for capturing the dierent

    semantic properties or dimensions of general terms. Nonetheless

    the StrawsonKnne solution to the proposition problem imme-

    diately faces two challenges.

    First, can't the courtesy of being allowed to enter into a proposi-

    tion indirectly be extended from ways of thinking to all otherwise

    plausible candidates for being concepts, notably abilities or ru-

    les? Secondly, why should one accept that any of these candidates

    feature in all propositions, however indirectly?

    The answer to the rst question is straightforward in so far as we

    stick to the relationship between concepts and general terms. It is

    perfectly commonplace to speak of words as expressing concepts.

    And there is no violent infelicity in speaking of general terms as

    expressing ways of thinking. The same goes for rules of classi-

    cation and/or inference. Perhaps one of these notions `ways of

    thinking' or `rule' comes closer to capturing the ordinary mea-

    ning of `concept', yet it is not on account of the possibility of being

    expressed by general terms. By contrast, it is at best misleading

    to speak of general terms as expressing an ability. Conceptual

    abilities are possessed by cognitive subjects, and they are expres-

    sed by in the sense of being manifested in the mental activities

    notably the judgements and inferences of such subjects. And

    we might say that those activities manifest concepts indirectly,

    keeping this relation apart from the expression of concepts by

    general terms. The notion of a conceptual ability points to the

    subject of conceptual thought and to the activity (in a suitably

    loose sense of the term) of conceptual thinking. By contrast, it is

    out of place when it comes to the content of conceptual thought,

    which is precisely what the idea of concepts as components of

    propositions points to. What we still need is a way of reconciling

    the mental or cognitive dimension of concepts with the objective

    dimension suggested by their occurrence in propositions.

  • 34 Hans-Johann Glock

    10 Propositions and concepts as logical

    constructions

    This takes us straight to the second challenge. The Strawson

    Knne response at best removes an obstacle to claiming that

    concepts can be ways of thinking and yet appear in propositions.

    But what positive reasons do we have for accepting that ways of

    thinking appear in propositions, let alone as components of pro-

    positions? The answer, I submit, is that both propositions and

    their components are logical constructions out of the practices

    and abilities of concept-exercising creatures.

    Elsewhere (2010b; 2011) I have tried to substantiate this answer.

    In the present context I conne myself to indicating some of the

    critical steps that need to be taken. They involve attacking an

    orthodoxy in the philosophy of mind and language epitomized by

    the ubiquitous label `propositional attitude'. According to this or-

    thodoxy, intentional verbs like `believe', `know', `desire', `intend'

    signify relations between a subject and a proposition, which is

    in turn composed of concepts. More specically, this orthodoxy

    involves three distinct elements:

    a relational model: an intentional state is a relation bet-

    ween a subject and a content, something the intentional

    state is directed at;

    propositionalism: these contents are propositions

    a building-block model: propositions are (abstract) who-

    les which have (abstract) parts concepts.

    All three elements must be rejected. First, propositionalism is

    ab initio unsuitable for intentional states like craving x or inten-

    ding to (Glock 2010a: 13-4). Next, even `thatish' intentionalverbs like `believe/know/desire that p' are not standardly direc-

    ted at propositions (see White 1972). Thirdly, the relational mo-

    del which treats believing or desiring that p as a relation to a

    bona de object amounts to a reication. Finally, and related-

    ly, the building block model, according to which propositions are

    complex abstract entities composed of concepts as their proper

  • What are Concepts? 35

    parts, is misguided. It transposes the part/whole relation from

    the spatial and temporal sphere to a sphere that of abstract

    entities to which, ex hypothesis, neither spatial nor temporal

    notions apply. What seems to give sense to talk of parts and

    wholes in the case of propositions or thoughts is the fact that

    the linguistic expressions of thoughts namely sentences have

    components namely words (see Kenny 1989: 1267). What is

    said or thought has genuine components to the extent to which

    its linguistic expression has components (which may, for instance,

    be explained when A is called upon to state and explain what she

    believes).

    My approach is top-down in one respect and bottom-up in an-

    other (for the distinction see Dretske 2000: 80-83). On the one

    hand, in the spirit of a moderate contextualism, it regards the

    components of sentences and intentional contents as abstractions

    from entire sentences or `propositions'. On the other hand, this

    semantic top-down approach is favoured, among other things, by

    a bottom-up perspective on the nature and genesis of thought and

    language. To describe more primitive capacities and communica-

    tive practices, we do not need to identify conceptual components

    but can start, in a holophrastic or holodoxastic mode with whole

    sentences or beliefs, respectively. The imperative for parsing ari-

    ses only when we reach a more complex phenomena, in particular

    those which need to be described in terms of classication and

    inference. Even if these phenomena are not conned to creatures

    with language, in describing them we employ the apparatus of

    fully articulated sentences and their components.

    Although propositions are not themselves linguistic entities, they

    are akin to what Prior (1971: ch. 2) called logical constructi-

    ons from linguistic phenomena, namely from the that-clauses by

    which we report and refer to what subjects say or think. The cri-

    teria of identity for propositions make essential reference to lin-

    guistic acts (sayings or utterances). There are propositions no one

    has ever uttered or thought of. But what distinguishes two such

    propositions is evident from the declarative sentences which ex-

    press them. Although our criteria of identity for propositions are

  • 36 Hans-Johann Glock

    not the same as our criteria of identity for sentences, we can only

    identify the former because we can identify the latter. Although

    there are dierent linguistic expressions for the most important

    truth discovered by Newton and the most important truth disco-

    vered by Einstein, what distinguishes these two truths is evident

    from their expressions `F = ma' and `E = mc

    2'.

    If the relational model, propositionalism and the building-block

    model are jettisoned, cognitivism can oer a satisfactory soluti-

    on to the proposition problem. In what sense, then, can rules of

    classication and inference occur in propositions? The answer is,

    very roughly: in the sense that S can only think that a is F in a

    fully conceptual sense if S has the capacity to classify or recognize

    objects as being F and draw inferences from this fact. Propositi-

    ons are what is or can be said or thought. Concepts are rules or

    principles that enable a subject to say or think such things, ways

    in which subjects do or could conceive of properties.

    To talk of propositions and concepts is not just a faon de parler,

    and propositions and concepts are not just `make-believe entities'

    (to use what is indeed a currently fashionable faon de parler).

    Rather, they are logical constructions in a non-reductive sense. It

    may prove impossible to paraphrase concepts away. We may need

    to refer to them in order to describe the highly evolved cognitive

    and/or linguistic abilities of certain creatures. At the same time,

    the nature, individuation and function of concepts ceases to be

    mysterious once we attend to the abilities that enable and neces-

    sitate the ascription of concepts to a subject. In that respect, at

    least, the possession question does indeed enjoy priority over the

    others (see Glock 2010c: 315-9).

    It is only possible to state what propositions and concepts are in

    terms which implicitly refer to what subjects can say or do; and

    we identify propositions and concepts by grouping or classifying

    actual or potential token-expressions according to what they say

    or mean. On this basis we may at least hope to reconcile two

    apparently incompatible features of the established use of `con-

  • What are Concepts? 37

    cept', the cognitive dimension of concepts and their appearance

    in propositions.

    8

    References

    Bennett, J.: Kant's Analytic. Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press, 1966.

    Bennett, M./ Hacker, P.: Philosophical Foundations of Neuros-

    cience.. Oxford: Blackwell, 2003.

    Carey, S.: The Origin of Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University

    Press, 2009.

    Dretske, F.: Perception, Knowledge and Belief . Cambridge: Cam-

    bridge University Press, 2000.

    Fodor, J.: Concepts: Where Science Went Wrong . Oxford: Cla-

    rendon Press, 1998.

    Hume Variations. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2003.

    Geach, P. T.: Mental Acts. London: Routledge and Keegan Paul,

    1957.

    Glock, H.-J.: Quine and Davidson on Language, Thought, and

    Reality . Cambridge University Press, 2003.

    Concepts: Where Subjectivism Goes Wrong. In: Philosophy ,

    84 1, p. 529, 2009.

    Can Animals Judge? In: Dialectica, 64 1, p. 1133, 2010a.

    8

    I wish to thank David Dolby and Frank Esken for helpful comments.

    This material has also proted from discussions in Bielefeld, Olden-

    burg, Osnabrck and Stuttgart, for which I am grateful. Finally,

    thanks are due to the organisers of the `Predication and the Unity

    of the Proposition' conference at the Vienna University of Econo-

    mics, at which I delivered a keynote lecture under the current title,

    and to the Hanse-Wissenschaftskolleg Delmenhorst for supporting

    this work through a fellowship.

  • 38 Hans-Johann Glock

    Concepts; between the subjective and the objective. In: Ha-

    cker, J./ Hacker, P. (Eds.),Mind, Method and Morality: Essays

    in Honour of Anthony Kenny , Cottingham, Oxford: Oxford

    University Press, 2010b.

    Wittgenstein on Concepts. In: Ahmed, A. (Ed.), Critical Gui-

    de to Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press, 2010c.

    A Cognitivist Approach to Concepts. In: Grazer Philosophi-

    sche Studien, 82, p. 131163, 2011.

    Hyman, J.: The Objective Eye. University of Chicago Press, 2006.

    Kenny, A.: Aquinas. New York: Oxford University Press, 1980a.

    The Metaphysics of Mind . Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980b.

    Knne, W.: Conceptions of Truth. Oxford University Press, 2003.

    Properties in Abundance. In: Strawson, P. F./ Chakrabarti,

    A. (Eds.), Universals, Concepts and Qualities, Aldershot: As-

    hgate, 2005.

    Abstrakte Gegenstnde. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 2007 (1st

    edn, 1983).

    Millikan, R.: On Clear and Confused Ideas. Cambridge: Cam-

    bridge University Press, 2000.

    Newen, A./ Bartels, A.: Animal Minds and the Possession of Con-

    cepts. In: Philosophical Psychology , 20 3, p. 283308, 2007.

    Peacocke, C.: A Study of Concepts. MIT Press, 1992.

    Peirce, C.: The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce Vol.

    II.. Cambridge (Mass): Harvard University Press, 1933.

    Price, H. H.: Thinking and Experience. London: Hutchinson,

    1953.

    Prior, A.: Objects of Thought . Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971.

    Saporiti, K.: In Search of Concepts. In: Grazer Philosophische

    Studien, 81, p. 153172, 2010.

    Searle, J.: The Explanation of Cognition. In: Preston, J. (Ed.),

    Thought and Language, p. 103126, Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press, 1997.

    Strawson, P. F.: Individuals: an Essay in Descriptive Metaphy-

    sics. London: Methuen, 1959.

    Entity and Identity . Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.

  • What are Concepts? 39

    Travis, C. S.: Unshadowed Thought: Representation in Thought

    and Language. Harvard University Press, 2000.

    White, A.: What we believe. In: Rescher, N. (Ed.), Studies in the

    Philosophy of Mind: American Philosophical Quarterly Mono-

    graph Series, vol. 6, p. 6984, Oxford: Blackwell, 1972.

    Wittgenstein, L.: The Blue and Brown Books. Oxford: Blackwell,

    1958.

    Wittgenstein's Lectures on Philosophical Psychology 1946-47 .

    Hassocks: Harvester Press, 1988.

    Wittgenstein's Nachlass. The Bergen Electronic Edition. Ox-

    ford: Oxford University Press, 2000 (references according to

    Manuscript number and page number).

    Chair of Theoretical Philosophy II

    Institute of Philosophy

    University of Zurich

    Zrichbergstrasse 43

    CH-8044 Zrich

    Switzerland

    [email protected]