Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    1/25

    "Genocide Denial" Laws as Secular Heresy: A Critical Analysis with Reference to BosniaAuthor(s): Robert M. HaydenSource: Slavic Review, Vol. 67, No. 2 (Summer, 2008), pp. 384-407Published by:Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27652849.

    Accessed: 11/02/2015 09:55

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Association for Slavic, East European, and Eurasian Studiesis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve

    and extend access to Slavic Review.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/stable/27652849?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/27652849?origin=JSTOR-pdf
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    2/25

    DISCUSSION

    "Genocide Denial" Laws as Secular

    Heresy:

    A

    Critical

    Analysis

    with Reference

    to

    Bosnia

    Robert

    M.

    Hayden

    In

    early February

    2007,

    the

    British

    newspaper

    the

    Daily

    Telegraph

    reported

    that

    Germany

    would

    propose

    to

    the

    European

    Parliament

    legislation

    requiring

    that

    "each member

    state

    shall take the

    measures

    necessary

    to

    ensure

    that the

    following

    intentional

    conduct

    is

    punishable:

    'publicly

    condoning,

    denying

    or

    grossly trivialising

    of crimes

    of

    genocide,

    crimes

    against

    humanity

    and

    war

    crimes.'"1 The Ottawa Citizen

    reported

    imme

    diately

    thereafter that

    under such

    legislation,

    Canadian

    retired

    Major

    General

    Lewis MacKenzie

    would

    face

    charges

    for

    questioning

    the

    num

    bers

    killed

    at

    Srebrenica

    in

    1995.

    According

    to

    the

    paper,

    MacKenzie

    ac

    knowledges

    that thousands

    were

    killed but denies that

    the

    acts

    constituted

    genocide.2

    This German proposal for criminalizing speech about historical

    events

    raises

    many

    troubling

    issues,

    and

    no

    less

    a

    genocide

    scholar

    than

    Deborah

    Lipstadt,

    who

    won

    a

    legal

    case

    against

    David

    Irving

    on

    the issue

    of Holo

    caust

    denial,

    came

    out

    firmly against

    it.3

    The

    proposed

    law is

    clearly

    con

    trary

    to

    what

    Amnesty

    International,

    in

    a

    1985 criticism

    of the

    prosecution

    of various

    nationalists

    and other dissidents

    in

    what

    was

    then

    Yugoslavia,

    described

    as

    "the

    non-violent

    exercise of

    internationally recognized

    hu

    man

    rights,

    in

    particular

    the

    right

    to

    freedom

    of

    expression."4

    The

    legisla

    tion has

    been

    criticized

    on

    such

    grounds,

    and

    passage

    delayed.5

    But this

    proposed European

    Union

    (EU)

    legislation

    about

    genocide

    denial is

    only

    one of a number of such laws in Europe, some of which are in force and

    have been used

    to

    convict

    people

    of

    verbal crimes.

    A

    Turkish

    politician,

    for

    example,

    was

    convicted

    in

    Switzerland

    in

    March

    2007

    for

    denying

    that

    the

    mass

    killings

    of

    Armenians

    in

    1915

    constituted

    genocide,

    even

    though

    I

    am

    grateful

    for

    the

    comments

    of

    Jennifer

    Cash,

    Bill

    Chase,

    Noam

    Chomsky, Ilya

    Pri

    zel,

    Mark

    Steinberg,

    and

    especially

    for those of

    several

    anonymous

    reviewers

    for Slavic

    Review.

    1.

    "EU Plans

    Far-Reaching

    'Genocide Denial'

    Law,"

    Daily Telegraph,

    2

    February

    2007.

    2.

    Ottawa

    Citizen,

    2

    February

    2007.

    3.

    Daily

    Telegraph,

    2

    February

    2007.

    4.

    Amnesty

    International,

    Yugoslavia:

    Prisoners

    of

    Conscience

    (London,

    1985),

    9-10.

    5.

    The

    blog

    of

    Deborah

    Lipstadt, "History

    on

    Trial,"

    covered the

    issue:

    see

    entries

    for

    29

    May

    2007

    ("EU

    Legislation

    on

    Genocide

    Denial: Still

    in

    Flux")

    and

    23

    April

    2007

    ("EU

    Law

    to

    Outlaw

    Genocide Denial

    Defeated"),

    though

    the latter

    pronouncement

    was,

    as

    Lipstadt

    admitted

    on

    29

    May

    2007,

    premature.

    See

    lipstadt.blogspot.com

    (last

    consulted

    22

    February

    2008).

    Slavic Review

    67',

    no.

    2

    (Summer

    2008)

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    3/25

    "Genocide Denial" Laws

    as

    Secular

    Heresy

    385

    he had

    acknowledged

    that

    massacres

    took

    place.6

    Others have been

    con

    victed

    in

    Austria and France for

    denying

    the

    reality

    of the Holocaust.

    In

    Europe,

    such cases are

    governed

    overall

    by

    the

    European

    Conven

    tion

    on

    Human

    Rights,

    Article

    10(1)

    of

    which

    provides

    that

    "Everyone

    has

    the

    right

    to

    freedom

    of

    expression.

    This

    right

    shall

    include

    freedom

    to

    hold

    opinions

    and

    to

    receive and

    impart

    information and ideas without

    interference

    by public authority

    and

    regardless

    of frontiers." This

    right,

    however,

    is

    qualified

    by

    Article

    10(2),

    which

    states

    that "The exercise of

    these

    freedoms,

    since it carries with it duties and

    responsibilities,

    may

    be

    subject

    to

    such

    formalities, conditions,

    restrictions

    or

    penalties

    as are

    pre

    scribed

    by

    law

    and

    are

    necessary

    in

    a

    democratic

    society,

    in

    the

    interests

    of national

    security,

    territorial

    integrity

    or

    public safety,

    for the

    preven

    tion of disorder

    or

    crime,

    for the

    protection

    of

    health

    or

    morals."

    Further,

    Article

    17

    provides

    that

    "Nothing

    in

    this Convention

    may

    be

    interpreted

    as

    implying

    for

    any

    State,

    group

    or

    person any

    right

    to

    engage

    in

    any

    ac

    tivity

    or

    perform

    any

    act

    aimed

    at

    the

    destruction

    of

    any

    of the

    rights

    and

    freedoms

    set

    forth herein

    or

    at

    their limitation

    to

    a

    greater

    extent

    than

    is

    provided

    for

    in

    the Convention." Taken

    together,

    Articles

    10(2)

    and

    17

    provide

    mechanisms for

    imposing

    restrictions

    on

    the

    rights

    otherwise

    guaranteed by

    Article

    10(1).

    A

    provision

    in

    the

    proposed

    legislation saying

    that

    "member

    states

    may

    choose

    to

    punish only

    conduct

    which

    is

    either

    carried

    out

    in

    a

    manner

    likely

    to

    disturb

    public

    order

    or

    which is

    threatening,

    abusive

    or

    insult

    ing"

    is

    hardly reassuring,

    since it would

    actually

    increase

    the

    vagueness

    and

    uncertainty

    that

    Amnesty

    International

    complained

    of in

    1985: that

    the "verbal delict" sections of socialist

    Yugoslavia's

    criminal

    law

    rested

    on

    "the

    vague

    formulation

    of

    legal provisions

    which

    enables them

    to

    be

    ap

    plied

    so as

    to

    penalize people

    for the

    non-violent exercise

    of

    their

    human

    rights."7

    By

    the

    language

    of the

    proposed

    EU

    legislation,

    states

    would

    be

    empowered

    to

    criminalize

    nonviolent,

    verbal actions that

    are

    not

    likely

    to

    disturb

    public

    order and

    are

    not

    "threatening,

    abusive,

    or

    insulting";

    in

    deed, they actually are called on to do so, but given the option to be more

    limited

    in

    their

    approach.

    This call

    to

    criminalize verbal

    acts

    that do

    not

    disturb

    public

    order

    and

    are

    not

    threatening,

    abusive,

    or

    insulting

    makes the

    proposed "genocide

    denial"

    legislation

    closely

    resemble

    two

    other

    regimes

    of

    criminalization of

    speech

    in

    modern

    Europe.

    As

    already

    mentioned

    in

    regard

    to

    Yugoslavia,

    the

    states

    of

    what

    was

    then

    "actually existing

    socialism" had similar

    prohi

    bitions

    on

    speech

    critical

    of

    key

    elements

    of

    the socialist

    order,

    and this

    article

    points

    out

    some

    of the

    similarities

    in

    the

    language

    used

    to

    justify

    genocide

    denial laws

    and

    those

    criminalizing

    some

    verbal actions under

    state socialism. Further, both of these efforts to criminalize

    speech

    rest on

    6. "Turkish Politician Fined

    over

    Genocide

    Denial,"

    9 March

    2007,

    at

    www.swissinfo

    .org/eng

    (last

    consulted

    22

    February

    2008).

    7.

    Council

    of the

    European

    Union,

    2794th

    Council

    meeting, Justice

    and Home

    Af

    fairs,

    Luxembourg,

    19-20

    April

    2007,

    "Council Framework

    Decision

    on

    Combating

    Rac

    ism and

    Xenophobia,"

    Council of the

    European

    Union Press Release

    8364/07

    (Presse

    77)

    (EN).

    Emphasis

    added.

    Amnesty

    International,

    Yugoslavia,

    10.

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    4/25

    386

    Slavic

    Review

    justifications

    similar

    to

    those

    used

    to

    justify

    treating

    heresy

    as

    a

    criminal

    offence,

    punishable

    by

    state courts

    rather than

    just religious

    ones,

    in Brit

    ain and the United States from the late

    eighteenth

    until the

    early

    twenti

    eth centuries.

    It is

    due

    to

    these

    similarities

    that

    I

    analyze

    "genocide

    denial"

    laws

    as

    efforts

    to

    punish

    secular

    heresy.

    Though

    the

    concept

    of

    heresy

    is

    derived

    originally

    from

    religious

    dis

    course,

    the

    term

    has

    wider

    meaning,

    as

    "a

    doctrine,

    opinion

    or

    set

    of

    opinions

    at

    variance with established

    or

    generally

    received views

    or

    doc

    trines."8

    I

    see

    criminalization

    of such unorthodox

    views

    as an

    attempt

    to

    protect

    deeply

    held doctrines

    that

    are

    widely regarded

    as so

    important

    that

    challenging

    them

    should be

    a

    punishable

    offense.

    The

    whole

    point

    of

    criminalizing

    the

    presentation

    of

    a

    point

    of

    view

    is

    to

    prevent anyone

    from

    considering

    that

    some

    elements of it

    might

    be

    true,

    and

    so

    defin

    ing

    all

    forms of criticism

    as

    illegitimate

    may

    be the clearest indication

    that the ban

    involves

    heresy.

    Were

    a

    heretical

    challenge

    to

    be

    true,

    the

    impugned

    belief

    system

    would have

    to

    fall,

    and thus the

    possibility

    that

    a

    heresy

    might

    be

    true

    is

    incompatible

    with the

    very

    concept

    itself.

    Reli

    gious

    heresy

    cannot

    logically

    be reduced

    to

    an

    empirical question,

    since

    God's

    truth is

    not

    testable

    empirically.

    Genocide denial claims could

    often

    be

    treated,

    at

    least

    in

    principle,

    as

    empirical questions,

    but

    criminalizing

    the

    denial

    of

    genocide

    is

    aimed

    at

    preventing

    empirical investigation

    that

    would

    counter

    the officialized truth; that is, after all, the very

    essence

    of

    the

    crime.

    A

    striking

    feature of the

    concept

    of

    genocide

    denial

    is that

    it

    is

    being

    invoked

    to

    justify

    infringement

    of

    the fundamental

    right

    to

    freedom

    of

    expression

    in

    societies that

    otherwise claim

    to

    make human

    rights

    cen

    tral

    to

    their

    ideology.

    Since this

    infringement

    can

    be made

    even

    in

    cases

    when there is

    no

    threat

    to

    public

    order,

    it

    is

    not

    comparable

    to

    the classic

    example

    of

    justifiable infringement

    of free

    speech

    in

    the United

    States,

    that freedom of

    speech

    does

    not

    cover

    "falsely

    calling

    fire

    in

    a

    theatre,"

    or

    the

    creation

    of

    a

    "clear

    and

    present

    danger"

    to

    public

    order.9

    The

    same

    capacity to justify violation of what would otherwise be fundamental prin

    ciples

    of

    legitimate

    social

    or

    political

    action

    was,

    until the twentieth

    cen

    tury,

    exhibited

    by

    the

    concept

    of

    heresy,

    since it

    was

    punished

    as a

    secular

    crime,

    not

    a

    religious

    one,

    in

    self-consciously

    secular,

    modern

    states.

    One

    is

    reminded of

    Kenneth

    Burke's "God

    terms,"

    those

    key

    concepts

    that

    can

    be invoked

    as

    ultimate values

    that

    stop

    further

    discussion and

    that need

    not

    be

    deistic:

    money,

    for

    example,

    as a

    God

    term

    for

    economists.10

    If

    God

    terms

    need

    not

    be

    deistic,

    neither

    must

    heresy.

    These

    are

    not

    abstract

    issues,

    but rather

    ones

    that

    can

    have real

    con

    sequences,

    not

    only

    for deniers of the

    reality

    of the

    Holocaust,

    Turkish

    politicians

    who

    deny

    that the 1915 massacres of Armenians constituted

    genocide,

    and Canadian

    generals

    unwise

    enough

    to

    speak

    about their

    experiences

    in

    peacemaking

    missions in

    the

    Balkans,

    but also for

    scholars

    8.

    Webster's

    Twentieth-Century

    Dictionary,

    unabridged,

    2d

    ed.

    9.

    Schenck

    v.

    United

    States,

    249

    U.S.

    47

    (1919).

    10.

    Kenneth

    Burke,

    A

    Grammar

    of

    Motives

    (1945;

    Berkeley,

    1969).

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    5/25

    "Genocide DeniaV Laws

    as

    Secular

    Heresy

    387

    and others

    who

    take

    seriously

    the

    need

    to

    understand

    the

    facts,

    causes,

    and

    meanings

    of

    instances

    of

    mass

    killings

    that

    are,

    arguably,

    genocide,

    because the nature of

    "genocide

    denial" laws is to

    prevent,

    or at least dis

    courage

    strongly,

    the

    argument

    from

    taking place.

    In

    order

    to

    show the

    potentially

    oppressive

    nature

    of

    these

    laws,

    this article

    makes

    a

    sustained

    critical

    analysis

    of the

    findings

    of

    the International Criminal Tribunal

    for

    the

    Former

    Yugoslavia

    (ICTY)

    in

    the

    case

    of

    General

    Radislav

    Krstic that

    the

    mass

    killings

    of

    Bosniaks

    by

    Bosnian Serb forces

    in

    Srebrenica in

    July

    1995 constituted

    genocide.

    Since the

    proposed

    EU

    legislation

    calls for

    criminalizing

    the

    denial

    of

    genocide

    when

    specific

    acts

    have

    been

    recog

    nized

    as

    such

    by

    a

    competent

    international

    court,

    if that

    legislation

    passes,

    denying

    the

    applicability

    of the

    term

    to

    Srebrenica

    seems,

    prima

    facie,

    to

    constitute

    a

    criminal

    act.

    It

    is

    thus with

    some

    discomfort that

    I do

    exactly

    that,

    by

    questioning

    the

    ICTY

    decision.

    It is

    my

    contention

    that the

    finding

    that the Srebren

    ica

    massacre

    constituted

    genocide

    distorts the

    definition of

    the

    term

    by

    making

    it

    so

    broad that

    it

    loses the

    possibility

    of uniform

    application.

    If

    this

    contention

    is

    true,

    however,

    the

    concept

    of

    criminalizing "genocide

    denial"

    not

    only

    becomes

    contrary

    to

    principles

    of free

    speech

    and

    intel

    lectual

    inquiry

    but

    also manifests the

    same

    problem

    that

    Amnesty

    Inter

    national identified

    in

    its

    reports twenty

    years ago

    on

    the

    vagueness

    of the

    "verbal crimes"

    provisions

    of

    the criminal

    laws

    of

    the former

    Yugoslavia,

    which made

    it

    possible

    for

    them

    to

    be

    applied

    for

    politically

    motivated

    reasons

    to

    punish

    the

    legitimate

    exercise

    of

    human

    rights

    and freedoms.

    An

    Inherently

    Provocative

    Case

    Study:

    The

    Issue

    of

    "Genocide"

    in

    Bosnia

    It is

    probably

    unavoidable that

    this

    case

    study

    be

    provocative.

    Bosnia

    was

    unquestionably

    the

    site of

    major

    crimes

    in

    violation of

    international

    hu

    manitarian

    law,

    and

    Srebrenica the site of the

    single

    largest

    mass

    killing

    in Europe since the 1940s. As such, they have become emblematic of the

    need

    felt

    by

    many

    to

    develop

    new means

    of

    punishing

    such crimes.

    To

    question

    whether

    "genocide"

    took

    place

    must

    therefore be

    provocative

    to

    those who

    truly

    believe that that

    supposed

    fact

    cannot

    be

    questioned.

    But

    it is

    precisely

    such

    a

    seemingly

    well-settled situation that is

    needed

    to

    show the

    fallacy

    of

    attempting

    to

    make

    any

    judicial

    decision immune from

    challenge.

    The

    inherently

    provocative

    nature

    of the

    case

    study

    makes discussion

    of

    it

    difficult,

    however.

    Indeed,

    one

    referee

    for

    this

    journal

    bluntly

    as

    serted

    that the

    first

    version

    of

    this

    paper

    constituted

    "genocide

    denial"

    and was "brilliant and vicious," without addressing any of my arguments.

    Not

    exactly

    a

    scholarly critique,

    but indicative of the

    problem

    one

    faces

    in

    even

    discussing

    these issues.

    The

    word

    genocide,

    a

    term

    stemming

    from

    the Holocaust and

    invoking

    its

    unquestionably

    well-documented

    horrors,

    connotes

    exceptional

    evil,

    more

    than

    other

    war

    crimes and

    mass

    killings.

    To

    those

    who

    firmly

    believe that

    genocide

    has

    occurred,

    questioning

    that

    belief

    is

    an

    immoral,

    perhaps

    even

    a

    "vicious,"

    act.

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    6/25

    388

    Slavic

    Review

    It

    is

    necessary

    to

    state

    up

    front that

    my

    challenge

    is

    not

    to

    the

    facts

    of

    the

    mass

    killings

    at

    Srebrenica

    as

    determined

    by

    the

    ICTY,

    or

    to

    the crimi

    nality

    of

    those

    acts,

    but rather

    to

    labeling

    them

    as

    "genocide."

    In

    arguing

    what

    will

    be

    a

    controversial

    case,

    this

    article

    first discusses

    the

    magnitude

    of

    the

    mass

    killing

    at

    Srebrenica,

    accepting

    the

    figures

    put

    forth

    by

    the

    ICTYs

    experts

    in

    scientific

    articles and

    a

    study

    directed

    from

    Sarajevo

    that

    has

    been

    supported

    by

    several

    European

    states.

    There

    is

    no

    question

    that

    the

    killings

    at

    Srebrenica

    were

    criminal and their

    perpetrators

    were

    guilty

    of

    a

    number of serious crimes

    punishable by

    the

    ICTY:

    extermination,

    persecution,

    murder,

    and

    inhumane

    treatment,

    to

    name

    other

    crimes

    of

    which General Krstic

    was

    convicted. The issue

    is

    simply

    the

    applicability

    of

    the

    term

    genocide.

    A

    Necessarily

    Provocative

    Analytical

    Framework:

    Secular

    Heresy

    My

    invocation

    of

    the

    term

    heresy

    to

    cover

    genocide

    denial

    laws,

    equating

    for this

    purpose

    beliefs

    in

    concepts

    such

    as

    human

    rights

    with

    those

    in

    the

    tenets

    of

    deistic

    religions,

    also

    seems

    to

    be

    provocative.

    Yet

    as

    stated

    above

    with reference

    to

    Kenneth Burke's "God

    terms" and

    the

    diction

    ary

    definition of

    heresy

    and

    in

    more

    detail

    below,

    what

    is

    comparable

    between

    religious

    heresy,

    genocide

    denial

    prohibitions,

    and the

    "verbal

    delicts" of criticizing state socialism is that they

    are

    all concerned with

    protecting

    beliefs

    considered

    essential

    to

    the

    just ordering

    of

    society.

    I

    belabor this

    point

    because

    despite

    these

    arguments

    and

    references,

    and

    indeed

    without

    discussing

    or even

    noting

    them,

    one

    reviewer of

    an ear

    lier

    version

    questioned

    the

    applicability

    of

    "arguing

    from

    medieval

    heresy

    and

    dogma," despite

    my

    explicit

    argument

    that

    I

    was

    not

    doing

    that,

    and

    another

    asserted

    that

    by

    invoking

    the

    concept

    of

    heresy

    I

    ignore

    that

    the

    genocide

    denial laws

    had

    "serious

    arguments

    in

    their

    favor and

    serious

    people

    behind

    those

    arguments." Although

    this

    is

    no

    doubt

    true,

    it is

    ir

    relevant:

    many

    of those who

    banned

    religious

    heresy

    and

    criticisms

    of

    the

    premises of state socialism were serious people making serious arguments.

    Or

    at

    least,

    they

    thought

    that

    they

    were.

    The

    point

    is

    that

    those

    who would

    criminalize

    genocide

    denial,

    like

    those

    who criminalized

    criticisms

    of

    state

    socialism and those who

    criminalized the

    promulgation

    of

    religious

    her

    esy,

    used

    very

    similar

    reasoning,

    and

    even

    similar

    wording,

    to

    justify

    their

    actions.

    I

    use

    the

    term

    heresy

    not

    as

    a

    metaphor

    but rather

    as

    an

    analytical

    term:

    this

    is

    the

    larger

    concept

    that

    encompasses

    efforts

    to

    criminalize

    speech

    that

    questions

    basic

    tenets

    of

    an

    ideological

    or

    belief

    system,

    such

    as

    inter

    nal criticisms of

    state

    socialism,

    or

    denial

    of

    the

    applicability

    of the

    term

    genocide

    for some mass crimes, in a

    system

    that

    purports

    to make central

    the

    protection

    of human

    rights.

    If this is

    "provocative,"

    as

    reviewers

    have

    complained,

    the

    provocation

    seems

    necessary

    to

    force

    consideration

    of

    the similarities between these

    efforts

    at

    criminalizing speech

    on

    political

    grounds.

    The

    comparison

    may

    well

    cause

    discomfort

    to

    those who

    think

    that

    efforts

    to

    protect

    secular belief

    systems

    are

    not

    subject

    to

    the

    same

    forms of

    criticism

    as

    deistic

    ones,

    but that

    is

    an

    assumption

    that

    this article

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    7/25

    "Genocide

    Denial"

    Laws

    as

    Secular

    Heresy

    389

    is

    meant

    to

    bring

    into

    question

    with

    the

    concept

    of "secular

    heresy,"

    to

    which

    we now

    turn.

    Heresy

    in

    a

    Secular

    Europe

    As

    a

    category

    of

    criminal

    act,

    heresy

    is

    generally

    linked

    to

    religion,

    espe

    cially

    Christianity.11

    Yet for hundreds

    of

    years,

    in

    English

    and

    American

    law,

    at

    least,

    while

    heresy

    has

    been defined

    in

    terms

    of

    denying

    some

    of

    the essential

    doctrines

    of

    Christianity,

    its

    criminalization

    has

    been

    justi

    fied,

    not

    on

    theological grounds,

    but

    rather

    on

    the

    need

    to

    protect

    public

    order

    and

    the

    bases

    of

    morality.

    Thus

    in

    the classic

    eighteenth-century

    statement

    of

    English

    law,

    Sir

    William

    Blackstone

    made

    it clear

    that

    while

    the

    decision

    to

    punish

    apostasy

    and

    heresy

    as

    denials

    of

    religion

    should

    remain

    exclusively

    in the

    realm

    of

    ecclesiastical

    courts,

    criminal

    penalties

    by

    the

    state

    of

    up

    to

    three

    years

    imprisonment

    were

    justified

    because

    the

    acts

    threaten

    to

    "destroy

    all

    moral

    obligation,"

    those

    principles

    of

    cor

    rect

    action

    upon

    which

    society

    ultimately

    relies,

    because

    almost

    everyone

    believes

    in

    them.12

    American and

    British

    cases

    from the nineteenth

    and

    early

    twentieth

    centuries

    took

    the

    same

    position

    and extended

    it

    by

    say

    ing

    that

    punishment

    for

    verbally

    denying

    Christianity

    was

    justified

    on

    the

    grounds

    that

    it

    offended

    the

    beliefs

    of

    the

    majority

    of

    the

    people

    and

    thus

    threatened the public peace.13 By 1883,

    the law

    in

    England

    was

    that

    verbal

    denials

    of the

    tenets

    of

    Christianity

    could

    only

    be

    punished

    as

    crimes

    if

    there

    was

    malicious intent

    to

    insult others.14

    These

    grounds

    for

    permitting

    heresy

    to

    be

    punished

    are

    secular,

    since

    what

    is

    at

    stake

    is

    not

    the

    truth

    of

    any

    specific

    Christian doctrine but the

    risk that denial

    of

    these truths

    may

    spark

    violence

    since the

    vast

    majority

    of

    the

    population

    believe

    Christianity

    to

    be

    the

    one

    true

    religion.

    Thus

    heresy

    is

    punishable

    because the

    belief

    system

    it

    challenges

    is

    pronounced

    central

    to

    the maintenance

    of

    social

    order.

    We

    may

    recall

    that

    speech

    and

    writings

    that

    "endanger

    the

    social

    or

    der" were prohibited under state socialism in eastern Europe and that

    prosecutions

    on

    such

    grounds

    were

    cited

    by organizations

    such

    as

    Am

    nesty

    International

    as

    violations

    of

    human

    rights.

    In

    the

    specific

    case

    of

    socialist

    Yugoslavia,

    Article

    114 of

    the

    federal criminal

    code

    prohibited

    acts "intended

    to

    curtail

    or

    overthrow

    the

    authority

    of the

    working

    class

    and

    working people

    . . .

    breaking

    up

    the brotherhood

    and

    unity

    or

    de

    stroying

    the

    equality

    of

    the

    nations

    and

    nationalities

    of

    Yugoslavia."15

    A

    large

    part

    of the

    justification

    provided

    by

    the

    Yugoslav

    government

    at

    the

    time

    was

    that

    they

    were

    punishing

    "hate

    speech."

    Amnesty

    International

    noted

    in its

    1985

    report

    that

    repression

    of

    speech

    was most

    severe

    in Bos

    11. See

    generally

    Leonard

    W.

    Levy,

    Blasphemy:

    Verbal

    Offense

    against

    the

    Sacred,

    From

    Moses

    to

    Salman

    Rushdie

    (New

    York,

    1993).

    12.

    William

    Blackstone,

    Commentaries

    on

    the Laws

    of

    England,

    9th ed.

    (London, 1783),

    bk.

    4,

    chap.

    4,

    p.

    44.

    13.

    Levy,

    Blasphemy,

    413.

    14.

    Ibid.,

    486-87.

    15.

    Quoted

    in

    Amnesty

    International,

    Yugoslavia,

    34.

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    8/25

    390

    Slavic

    Review

    nia

    and

    Herzegovina

    and

    also

    that the

    government

    "frequently

    referred

    to

    the

    bloodshed

    of

    that

    period

    [that

    is,

    World

    War

    IPs

    "bitter

    communal

    fighting"]

    as a

    justification

    for

    repressive

    measures."16

    But

    Amnesty

    Inter

    national

    clearly

    did

    not

    accept

    that

    argument,

    since it

    adopted

    fourteen

    "prisoners

    of

    conscience"

    from

    among

    those

    so

    persecuted.

    It

    is,

    however,

    very

    much

    the

    same

    kind of

    reasoning

    that lies behind

    recent

    attempts

    to

    criminalize

    "genocide

    denial." The

    proposed legisla

    tion is

    justified

    as an

    attempt

    to

    prohibit

    racism

    and

    xenophobia.

    A

    similar

    regulation

    on

    "Cybercrimes,"

    providing

    for

    "the

    criminalisation

    of

    acts

    of

    a

    racist and

    xenophobic

    nature

    committed

    through

    computer

    systems,"

    provides

    a

    clear

    statement

    of the

    centrality

    of the

    ideology

    underlying

    the

    rules:

    that

    "acts

    of

    a

    racist

    and

    xenophobic

    nature

    constitute

    a

    violation

    of

    human

    rights

    and

    a

    threat

    to

    the

    rule

    of

    law and

    democratic

    stability."

    Thus,

    even

    though

    this

    regulation

    recognizes

    that "freedom

    of

    expres

    sion

    constitutes

    one

    of

    the

    essential

    foundations of

    a

    democratic

    society,

    and

    is

    one

    of

    the

    basic

    conditions

    for

    its

    progress

    and

    for

    the

    develop

    ment

    of

    every

    human

    being,"

    application

    of

    this

    core

    democratic value

    must

    be

    denied

    when

    communication

    involves

    "racist

    and

    xenophobic

    propaganda."17

    A

    principle

    that

    must

    fall

    upon

    the

    invocation

    of another

    one

    is infe

    rior

    to

    the

    latter,

    so

    this

    phrasing

    means

    that

    achieving

    the

    goal

    of

    fighting

    racism

    and xenophobia is superior to protecting the mechanisms usu

    ally

    regarded

    as

    necessary

    for

    maintaining

    a

    democratic

    society.

    Clearly,

    then,

    criminalization

    of

    genocide

    denial

    sanctifies

    the beliefs

    challenged

    by

    racism

    and

    xenophobia

    as

    the

    true

    core

    values

    ensuring

    the

    stability

    of

    the

    social

    order of

    modern

    Europe.

    I

    say

    "sanctifies"

    because while these

    values

    are

    secular,

    in

    the

    sense

    of

    not

    being grounded

    directly

    in the

    es

    tablished

    religious

    orders

    of

    Europe, they

    function

    as

    core

    moral values

    in

    the

    same

    way

    that the

    religious

    doctrines

    of

    the

    period

    did

    when

    heresy

    was

    criminalized

    on

    nonreligious

    grounds.

    Of

    course,

    it is

    not

    necessary

    to

    define

    "religion"

    solely

    in terms

    of

    belief in

    a

    supernatural

    power,

    and

    Emile Durkheim's view of religion as society celebrating itself seems ap

    plicable

    here.18

    Genocide

    denial

    differs from

    other

    proscribed

    "hate

    speech"

    in

    that

    it

    is

    defined

    as

    a

    criminal

    offense

    in

    all

    contexts,

    while

    other

    verbal hate

    crimes

    are

    defined

    in

    terms

    of

    contexts

    that

    are

    especially dangerous.

    Ac

    tually,

    in

    adopting

    the

    Cybercrimes

    convention the

    Council

    of

    Europe

    had

    earlier

    called

    for

    criminalization

    of

    certain

    forms of

    speech,

    and

    specifi

    cally

    of

    genocide

    denial,

    without

    attracting

    the

    controversy

    of

    the

    EU

    pro

    posal.

    The

    electronic

    speech

    to

    be

    criminalized

    by

    the Council of

    Europe

    includes

    "Dissemination of

    racist

    and

    xenophobic

    material

    through

    com

    puter

    systems"

    (Article

    3)

    with "racist and

    xenophobic

    material" defined

    as

    "any

    written

    material,

    any

    image

    or

    any

    other

    representation

    of

    ideas

    16.

    Ibid.,

    27-28.

    17. Council of

    Europe,

    "Additional

    Protocol

    to

    the

    Convention

    on

    Cybercrime,

    concerning

    the

    Criminalisation of Acts of

    a

    Racist

    and

    Xenophobic

    Nature

    Committed

    through

    Computer Systems,"

    28

    January

    2003

    at

    http://conventions.coe.int/Treaty/

    (last

    consulted

    22

    February

    2008).

    18.

    Ibid.

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    9/25

    "Genocide

    Denial" Laws

    as

    Secular

    Heresy

    391

    or

    theories,

    which

    advocates,

    promotes

    or

    incites

    hatred,

    discrimination

    or

    violence,

    against

    any

    individual

    or

    group

    of

    individuals,

    based

    on

    race,

    colour,

    descent or national or ethnic

    origin,

    as well as

    religion

    if used

    as

    a

    pretext

    for

    any

    of these

    factors"

    (Article

    2).

    Also

    to

    be criminalized

    is the

    making

    of

    a

    "racist

    and

    xenophobic

    motivated

    threat"

    (Article

    4),

    or a

    "racist and

    xenophobic

    motivated insult"

    (Article

    5).

    Prohibiting

    "threats,"

    "insults,"

    and

    "promoting,"

    "advocating,"

    and

    "inciting"

    hatred

    or

    violence

    may

    be

    seen

    as

    a

    rational

    means

    of

    preventing

    violent social

    conflict.

    "Genocide denial"

    (Article

    6),

    though,

    seems

    of

    a

    different

    nature,

    since

    it

    criminalizes

    "distributing

    or

    otherwise

    making

    available,

    through

    a

    computer system

    to

    the

    public,

    material

    which

    denies,

    grossly

    minimises,

    approves

    or

    justifies

    acts

    constituting genocide

    or

    crimes

    against

    human

    ity."

    These

    actions?denying, minimizing,

    approving,

    and

    justifying?are

    not

    linked

    to

    circumstances

    in

    which the

    action

    might

    spark

    an

    immediate

    threat

    to

    social

    peace.

    Instead

    they

    are

    to

    be

    criminalized

    even

    in

    contexts

    in

    which

    there is

    no

    danger

    that

    they

    could

    serve

    to

    advocate,

    incite,

    or

    promote

    violence,

    or

    threaten

    anybody,

    and

    they

    are

    not

    phrased

    in

    terms

    of

    hatred

    or

    racism.

    The

    draft

    EU

    proposal,

    in

    specifying

    that

    states

    "may

    choose

    to

    punish only

    conduct

    which is either

    carried

    out

    in

    a manner

    likely

    to

    disturb

    public

    order

    or

    which

    is

    threatening,

    abusive

    or

    insulting"

    (emphasis

    added),

    is

    instructive:

    they

    may

    also

    choose

    to

    punish

    speech

    that

    is

    not

    threatening, abusive,

    or

    insulting

    or a

    threat

    to

    public

    order.

    Major

    human

    rights organizations

    seem

    caught

    in

    a

    dilemma,

    sup

    porting,

    in

    principle,

    freedom

    of

    speech

    but

    also

    supporting

    prosecution

    of

    "hate

    speech."

    Amnesty

    International

    continues

    to

    express

    concerns

    about

    the

    potential

    of

    some

    kinds

    of

    genocide

    denial

    legislation

    to

    violate

    the

    right

    of

    free

    speech.

    In

    October

    2006,

    Amnesty

    International

    issued

    a

    statement

    criticizing

    the

    adoption

    by

    the

    French National

    Assembly

    of

    a

    bill that

    would

    make it

    a

    crime

    to

    contest

    that

    the

    massacres

    of

    Armenians

    in

    Turkey

    in

    1915

    constituted

    a

    genocide,

    since

    "the

    proposed

    law

    has

    the

    effect

    of

    criminalising

    those who

    question

    whether the Armenian

    mas

    sacres constituted a genocide?a matter of legal opinion?rather than

    whether

    or

    not

    the

    killings

    occurred?a

    matter

    of

    fact."19 On

    the

    other

    hand,

    Amnesty

    International's web

    site

    shows

    no

    expression

    of

    concern

    that Switzerland did

    exactly

    that

    in

    February

    2007,

    convicting

    a

    Turkish

    man

    for

    denying

    that the

    1915

    massacres

    constituted

    "genocide"

    even

    though

    he

    acknowledged

    that

    massacres

    took

    place.20

    A

    month after

    that conviction another

    press

    release

    on

    "Racism

    and Discrimination

    as

    Europe's Key

    Human

    Rights

    Problems"

    called

    for

    EU member

    states to

    "provide

    effective

    protection

    against.

    . .

    hate

    speech

    across

    the

    EU,

    while

    safeguarding

    freedom

    of

    expression."21

    Human Rights Watch, for its part, has expressed some concern about

    19.

    Amnesty

    International,

    Public

    Statement: "France:

    Amnesty

    International

    Urges

    France

    to

    Protect

    Freedom of

    Expression,"

    AI

    Index:

    EUR

    21/009/2006

    (Public),

    18

    Oc

    tober

    2006.

    20.

    "Turkish Politician Fined

    over

    Genocide

    Denial,"

    9

    March

    2007.

    21.

    Amnesty

    International EU

    Office Press

    Release,

    "Racism and

    Discrimination

    ?

    Europe's

    Key

    Human

    Rights

    Problem,"

    AI

    Index: IOR

    61/010/2007

    (Public),

    21

    March

    2007.

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    10/25

    392

    Slavic Review

    the

    dangers

    of

    criminalizing

    "hate

    speech"

    and

    "genocide

    denial,"

    yet

    seems

    to

    be

    willing

    in

    the

    end

    (probably

    unlike

    King

    Solomon

    though

    he

    was

    not,

    ultimately,

    put

    to

    the

    test)

    actually

    to

    split

    the

    baby:

    "Genocide

    deniers should

    be

    marginalized,

    and

    even

    subject

    to

    other

    forms of

    sanc

    tion

    where

    they

    cause

    real

    harm,

    but

    they

    should

    not

    be

    subject

    to

    incar

    ceration

    except

    where their actions

    amount to

    incitement

    to

    violence."22

    The

    mechanisms of

    "marginalization"

    or

    of

    "other

    forms

    of

    sanction"

    re

    main

    unspecified,

    as

    does the

    concept

    of

    "real

    harm,"

    raising

    problems

    of

    vagueness.

    The

    difficulty

    faced

    by

    both

    Amnesty

    International

    and

    Human

    Rights

    Watch

    is

    in

    keeping

    with

    the

    unremarked

    incongruity

    that

    an

    organization

    called

    Amnesty

    International

    is

    running

    a

    "campaign"

    to

    prosecute people

    accused of

    genocide

    and "crimes

    against

    humanity,

    war

    crimes,

    torture,

    extra-judicial

    executions

    and

    disappearances"

    and

    specifically

    to

    support

    international

    tribunals

    such

    as

    the

    ICTY.

    If

    an

    organization

    that

    defines

    itself

    as

    being

    "concerned

    solely

    with

    the

    impartial

    protection

    of human

    rights"

    supports

    prosecutors,

    it

    should

    not

    be

    surprising

    that

    it

    is

    willing

    to

    accept

    a

    ban

    on

    any

    criticism

    of the

    philosophical

    underpinnings

    of the

    prosecutions.23

    Liability

    for

    genocide

    denial makes

    sense

    if

    one

    accepts

    that

    genocide,

    as

    the

    ultimate

    manifestation

    of

    racism and

    xenophobia,

    actually

    is the

    greatest challenge to the moral principles currently said to define Euro

    pean

    civilization.

    By

    this

    reasoning,

    the

    possibility

    of

    genocide

    makes

    rac

    ist and

    xenophobic

    speech

    threatening

    to

    "the

    rule

    of

    law

    and

    democratic

    stability,"

    rather

    than

    being

    of

    purely personal

    concern to

    the

    recipient,

    and

    possibly

    threatening

    to

    the

    peace

    of

    only

    a

    local

    community.

    It

    is,

    af

    ter

    all,

    this threat

    to

    the

    general

    social

    order that

    justifies

    the

    suppression

    of what

    would

    otherwise

    be

    essential

    democratic

    rights.

    But if the

    risk of

    genocide

    occurring

    is

    remote,

    the

    threat

    to

    the democratic

    order

    is

    as

    well,

    and

    so

    the

    justification

    for

    censoring

    hate

    speech

    becomes

    much

    less

    compelling.

    It is

    for this

    reason,

    I

    think,

    that

    the

    occasional

    finding

    that

    "genocide"

    has occurred is

    actually

    a necessary condition for justifying the

    suppression

    of

    "hate

    speech."

    "Genocide

    denial"

    is

    thus

    not

    criminalized

    because

    it

    actually

    threatens

    public

    order,

    but

    because it

    threatens

    the

    presumption

    that

    hate

    speech endangers

    the

    general

    moral

    and

    social

    order.

    This

    is

    not to

    say

    that

    genocide

    has

    not

    taken

    place

    or

    cannot

    take

    place,

    but

    only

    to

    explain

    why

    the

    question

    of

    genocide

    is

    so

    sacred

    that

    not

    only

    is its

    denial

    punishable,

    but,

    as

    with

    other

    forms

    of

    heresy,

    it

    is

    by

    definition

    impossible

    to

    defend

    against

    the

    charge

    by

    referring

    to

    facts

    that

    would

    support

    the

    challenge

    to

    the

    established

    doctrine,

    since the

    very

    attempt

    to do so would itself constitute the crime of

    genocide

    denial.

    Yet this exercise

    in

    thought

    control

    is

    not

    likely

    to

    help

    us

    understand

    the

    22.

    Human

    Rights

    Watch,

    "Genocide

    Denial: Incitement

    or

    Hate

    Speech?"

    World

    Report

    2007

    at

    www.hrw.org/wr2k7/essays/shrinking/4.htm

    (last

    consulted

    22

    February

    2008).

    23.

    web.amnesty.org/en/international-justice

    (last

    consulted

    22

    February

    2008).

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    11/25

    "Genocide

    Denial" Laws

    as

    Secular

    Heresy

    393

    causes

    of

    mass

    killings

    in

    the modern world.

    In

    fact,

    the

    contrary

    is

    true.

    By

    ruling

    out

    forms

    of

    empirical investigation

    of

    some

    of the

    worst

    cases

    of mass

    killing

    in recent

    history,

    the criminalization of

    "genocide

    denial"

    can

    only

    impede

    our

    understanding

    of

    the

    nature

    of the crimes.

    Courts,

    Facts,

    and

    Meaning

    Lest the last

    sentence

    seem

    extreme,

    the

    European

    Court of

    Human

    Rights

    has

    stated,

    with

    specific

    regard

    to

    genocide

    denial,

    that there is

    a

    "category

    of

    clearly

    established

    historical

    facts?such

    as

    the

    Holocaust?

    whose

    negation

    or

    revision would

    be

    removed

    from the

    protection

    of

    Ar

    ticle

    10

    by

    Article

    17."24 The

    question

    would

    then

    become

    how

    a

    "histori

    cal

    fact"

    should become

    "clearly

    established." Genocide denial

    legislation

    proposed by

    the Council

    of

    Europe,

    written

    specifically

    to

    conform

    with

    the

    provisions

    of

    this

    European

    Court

    of Human

    Rights

    decision,

    seems

    to

    answer

    this

    in

    a

    rational

    and

    indeed

    indisputable

    way:

    "acts

    constitut

    ing

    genocide

    or

    crimes

    against

    humanity,

    as

    defined

    by

    international

    law

    and

    recognized

    as

    such

    by

    final

    and

    binding

    decisions

    of

    the

    International

    Military

    Tribunal,

    established

    by

    the

    London

    Agreement

    of

    8

    August

    1945

    [the

    Nuremberg

    Tribunal],

    or

    of

    any

    other

    international

    court

    established

    by

    relevant international

    instruments."25

    Decisions

    of

    the ICTY and

    the

    International Court of Justice (ICJ) would clearly qualify.

    Justice

    Robert

    Jackson

    of the

    U.S.

    Supreme

    Court

    once

    quipped

    that

    he and his

    colleagues

    "are

    not

    final because

    we

    are

    infallible,

    but

    we are

    infallible

    only

    because

    we are

    final."

    And while

    courts

    do indeed

    make

    final

    dispositions

    in

    regard

    to

    the

    matters

    in front of

    them,

    the adversarial

    process

    used

    in

    courts

    is

    notoriously

    unsuited

    for

    making

    reliable determi

    nations of fact. Were it

    otherwise,

    scientific

    progress

    would be

    conducted

    via adversarial

    proceedings

    rather than

    through

    the

    constant

    process

    of

    testing

    ideas. International

    tribunals

    may

    be final because there is

    no

    ap

    peal

    from

    them,

    but this

    does

    not

    mean

    that their

    decisions

    are

    any

    more

    reliable or accurate than those of any other court.

    Differences in evidence

    presented,

    the

    varying

    skills of

    advocates,

    and

    the

    predilections

    of

    judges inevitably

    lead

    to

    differing

    decisions.

    As

    shown

    below,

    different

    courts,

    and

    even

    different benches of the

    same

    court,

    may

    give

    contradictory

    decisions

    on

    whether

    "genocide"

    took

    place,

    so

    that

    a

    single

    authoritative

    opinion

    may

    be hard

    to

    isolate.

    Yet

    even

    if

    there

    is

    a

    single opinion,

    there is

    no

    guarantee

    that it is based

    on

    complete

    or

    reli

    able

    evidence.

    It

    has

    long

    been

    a

    stable

    of the

    literature

    in

    law

    and social

    science that

    the formal

    equality

    between

    parties

    in

    legal proceedings

    is

    often

    a

    fiction,

    and that

    some

    litigants

    enjoy

    substantial

    advantages

    over

    their adversaries.26 In

    particular,

    parties

    involved in a number of cases

    dealing

    with the

    same

    sets

    of issues

    ("repeat

    players")

    have

    substantial,

    sys

    24.

    Case

    ofLehideux

    and

    Isorni

    v.

    France,

    European

    Court of

    Human

    Rights,

    Judgment,

    23

    September

    1998

    (55/1997/839/1045),

    para.

    47.

    25.

    Council

    of

    Europe,

    "Additional

    Protocol."

    26.

    Marc

    Galanter,

    "Why

    the

    'Haves' Come Out

    Ahead:

    Speculations

    on

    the

    Limits of

    Legal Change,"

    Law and

    Society

    Review

    9,

    no.

    1

    (Autumn

    1974):

    95.

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    12/25

    394

    Slavic

    Review

    temic

    advantages

    over

    opponents

    whose sole interest is

    in

    the

    single

    case

    litigated

    between them

    ("one-shotters").

    In

    the

    ICTY,

    the

    prosecutor

    is

    a

    repeat

    player

    par

    excellence,

    having

    command

    over

    far

    greater

    resources

    of

    money,

    personnel,

    and

    political

    connections than

    do

    defense

    attorneys.

    Few of

    the

    latter

    have

    participated

    in

    more

    than

    one

    case,

    and

    defense

    at

    torneys

    are

    in

    any

    event

    less

    likely

    than the

    prosecution

    to

    have

    a

    strategy

    connecting

    the

    disparate

    cases

    and

    in

    fact

    are

    probably

    ethically

    barred

    from

    doing

    so.

    For

    example,

    while

    prosecutors

    can

    and

    do

    negotiate

    with

    "small

    fish"

    to

    get

    their

    testimony

    against "big

    fish,"

    a

    defense

    attorney

    who would sacrifice

    the interests

    of

    one

    client in

    favor of those

    of

    another

    would

    be

    acting

    unethically.

    Prosecutors

    can

    bring strings

    of coordinated

    cases

    all

    aimed

    at

    establishing

    that

    point, against single-shot

    defendants

    and

    their

    lawyers

    who

    may

    have neither

    the

    personal

    interest

    nor

    the

    insti

    tutional

    or

    economic

    capacity

    to counter

    them.

    For

    this

    reason,

    a

    finding

    of

    "genocide"

    in

    a

    particular

    case

    may

    well reflect

    only

    the

    ability

    of

    the

    prosecution

    to

    bring superior

    resources

    to

    bear

    in

    the

    proceedings

    and

    to

    manipulate

    cases

    strategically

    in

    ways

    not

    open

    to

    defense

    attorneys.

    The ultimate flaw

    in

    proclaiming

    a

    court

    decision

    to

    be

    final, however,

    is

    that the

    question

    of

    whether

    "genocide"

    took

    place

    is

    not

    one

    of

    fact but

    of

    the

    meaning assigned

    to

    a

    set

    of

    facts

    taken

    to

    have been

    proved.

    The

    fundamental difference

    between these

    two

    enterprises

    is

    that

    a

    question

    of fact can in principle be determined on the basis of empirical evidence

    (for

    example,

    how

    many

    were

    killed

    at

    Srebrenica?),

    while

    the

    assignment

    of

    meaning

    to

    facts thus

    established

    can

    have

    no

    empirical

    referent

    (for

    example,

    how

    many

    must

    be

    killed,

    under

    what

    circumstances,

    for

    "geno

    cide"

    to

    be

    said

    to

    have

    occurred).

    Tzvetan

    Todorov

    puts

    the

    matter

    well:

    "facts

    can

    be

    right

    or

    wrong,

    but

    meanings

    are

    constructed

    by

    the

    writing

    subject,

    and

    may

    change.

    A

    given interpretation

    may

    be

    untenable,

    that

    is,

    it

    may

    be

    refuted,

    but

    there is

    no

    absolute

    degree

    of

    truthfulness

    at

    the

    other

    end

    of the

    scale."27

    Genocide denial laws

    treat

    questions

    of

    mean

    ing

    as

    questions

    of

    fact,

    a

    logical

    error

    that is

    also

    an

    attempt

    to

    freeze

    history.

    This is an

    impossible

    task, at least without total control over the

    production

    and

    dissemination

    of

    social

    memory.

    A

    critical discussion of

    the

    findings

    of

    genocide

    in

    Bosnia

    provides

    a case

    study

    to

    support

    the

    above

    arguments.

    The

    Factual Context:

    Numbers of

    Dead in

    Bosnia,

    1992-95,

    and

    at

    Srebrenica,

    July

    1995

    Almost

    as

    soon

    as

    the

    war

    began

    in

    Bosnia,

    in

    1992,

    high

    numbers of dead

    were

    reported.

    At

    a

    hearing

    of the

    U.S.

    Commission

    on

    Security

    and

    Co

    operation

    in

    Europe

    (CSCE)

    on "War Crimes and the Humanitarian Crisis

    in

    the former

    Yugoslavia"

    on

    25

    January

    1993,

    Congressman Christopher

    Smith

    noted

    that

    a

    few

    weeks

    earlier,

    Bosnian

    President

    Alija

    Izetbegovic

    27.

    Tzvetan

    Todorov,

    Hope

    and

    Memory:

    Lessons

    from

    the

    Twentieth

    Century,

    trans.

    David

    Bellos

    (Princeton,

    2003),

    123;

    see

    also

    Tzvetan

    Todorov,

    "Fictions

    and

    Truths,"

    Morals

    and

    History

    (Minneapolis,

    1995).

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    13/25

    "Genocide Denial"

    Laws

    as

    Secular

    Heresy

    395

    had stated that

    more

    than

    200,000

    had

    been

    killed

    and

    that

    70,000

    were

    being

    held

    in

    detention

    camps.28

    At

    a

    CSCE

    hearing

    on

    4

    February

    1993,

    Bosnian

    Foreign

    Minister Haris

    Silajdzic repeated

    the

    200,000

    figure,

    and

    that

    figure

    was

    widely accepted

    thereafter.

    At

    a

    hearing

    of

    the

    U.S.

    House

    International Relations Committee

    on

    18 October

    1995,

    Secretary

    of

    De

    fense William

    Perry

    said that

    more

    than

    200,000

    people

    had been

    killed;

    but

    at

    a

    hearing

    before the

    U.S.

    Senate

    Armed

    Services

    Committee

    on

    7

    June

    1995,

    Perry

    had

    stated

    that,

    in

    1992,

    there

    were

    about

    130,000

    ci

    vilian

    casualties in Bosnia.

    Richard

    Holbrooke,

    on

    the

    other

    hand,

    in

    an

    interview

    on

    the tenth

    anniversary

    of the

    Dayton Agreements,

    raised

    the

    figure

    to

    300,000

    dead.29

    News

    accounts

    tended

    to

    keep

    to

    the

    200,000

    figure,

    used

    as

    recently

    as

    18 December

    2005

    in

    the

    New

    York

    Times.30

    Estimates

    of

    casualties

    made

    by

    researchers

    during

    the

    war

    varied

    widely. Figures

    from institutions

    or

    individual

    researchers within Bosnia

    and

    Croatia

    ranged

    from

    a

    low

    of

    156,824

    to

    a

    high

    of

    329,000.

    Those

    from

    outside Bosnia

    were

    somewhat

    lower,

    ranging

    from

    25,000

    to

    60,000

    by

    former

    State

    Department

    officer

    George

    Kenney

    to

    200,000

    by

    Chicago

    law

    professor

    Cherif Bassiouni.31

    After the

    war,

    demographers

    Ewa

    Tabeau

    and

    Jakub

    Bijak,

    working

    as

    experts

    for

    the

    Office

    of the Prosecutor

    in

    the

    ICTY,

    drew

    on

    a

    variety

    of

    sources

    to

    arrive

    at

    an

    estimated

    total

    of

    102,621

    war-related

    casual

    ties in Bosnia-Herzegovina from 1992 to 1995.32 Of known casualties (as

    opposed

    to

    estimates),

    68.6

    percent

    were

    Muslims

    (officially

    called Bos

    niaks after

    1994),

    18.8

    percent

    Serbs,

    and 8.3

    percent

    Croats,

    with

    47,360

    estimated

    to

    be

    military

    casualties,

    and

    55,261

    civilian.

    They

    noted,

    how

    ever,

    that their

    figures

    from

    Republika

    Srpska

    were

    the

    least

    complete

    and

    reliable.

    Mirsad

    Tokaca,

    the director of

    a

    nongovermental

    research

    center

    supported

    by

    a

    number

    of

    western

    governments,

    responded

    to

    the initial

    release

    of

    Tabeau and

    Bijak's findings

    in

    an

    interview

    in

    the main Sara

    jevo daily, Oslobodjenje,

    that

    was

    headlined

    "The

    total number

    of victims

    in

    B&H was less than 150,000

    "33

    The exclamation

    point

    provides

    evidence

    of

    how

    much

    this lowered

    number

    challenged

    accepted

    wisdom.

    In

    a

    Reu

    ters

    interview

    the

    next

    day,

    Tokaca

    said,

    "we

    can

    now

    say

    with

    almost ab

    solute

    certainty

    that the number is

    going

    to

    be

    more

    than

    100,000

    but

    definitely

    less

    than

    150,000."34

    Tokaca

    has continued

    to

    revise

    the

    total

    28.

    Transcripts

    of

    hearings

    of the

    CSCE

    may

    be

    accessed

    at

    www.csce.gov

    (last

    con

    sulted

    22

    February

    2008),

    where

    they

    are

    organized

    by

    issue

    and

    by

    country,

    then listed

    chronologically

    within

    each

    category.

    29.

    On U.S. Public

    Broadcasting System,

    The

    Charlie

    Rose

    Show,

    23

    November

    2005.

    30.

    Bill

    Marsh,

    "The

    Civilian

    Toll of

    War,"

    New York

    Times,

    18

    December

    2005.

    31.

    These

    studies

    are

    summarized and

    evaluated

    by

    Ewa Tabeau and

    Jakub Bijak,

    "War

    Related

    Deaths

    in

    the

    1992-95

    Armed

    Conflicts

    in Bosnia

    and

    Herzegovina:

    A

    Cri

    tique

    of Previous

    Estimates

    and Recent

    Results,"

    European

    Journal of

    Population

    21,

    nos.

    2-3

    (2005):

    187-215.

    32.

    Ibid.

    33.

    Oslobodjenje,

    9

    December

    2004.

    34.

    Report

    carried

    on

    Justwatch

    listserv,

    10

    December

    2004.

    Also available

    at

    www.

    bosnia.org.uk/news/news_body.cfm?newsid=1985

    (last

    consulted

    22

    February

    2008).

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    14/25

    396

    Slavic

    Review

    downwards

    as

    the

    project

    has neared

    completion:

    in

    December

    2005

    the

    BBC

    reported

    that,

    although

    the

    project

    would

    not

    be

    completed

    until

    March

    2006,

    final

    figures

    would be

    about

    102,000

    and that

    using

    the

    data

    processed

    to

    date,

    67.87

    percent

    of

    the casualties

    were

    Bosnian

    Muslims,

    25.81

    percent

    Serbs,

    and

    5.39

    percent

    Croats. Of the

    Muslim

    casualties,

    50

    percent

    were

    military,

    50

    percent

    civilian,

    a

    ratio that

    holds for the

    far

    fewer

    Croat

    casualties

    as

    well.

    Serb

    casualties

    were

    overwhelmingly

    mili

    tary:

    21,399,

    to

    1,978

    Serb

    civilians.35

    Thus the

    two most

    recent

    studies of the

    1992-95

    war

    agree

    that there

    were

    about

    102,000

    casualties.

    They

    differ

    mainly

    in that

    Tokaca's

    study

    shows

    more

    Serb

    military

    casualties

    and

    fewer

    Serb

    civilian

    casualties

    than

    does

    Tabeau

    and

    Bijak's study.

    Rather

    ironically, George Kenney's figure

    of

    60,000

    through

    1994

    was

    thus

    apparently

    closer

    to

    the

    true

    figure

    than

    any

    of the

    more

    widely

    accepted

    numbers,

    an

    ironic

    result because

    Ken

    ney

    was

    called

    a

    "revisionist"

    at

    the

    time.

    It is

    striking

    that the ratio

    of mili

    tary

    to

    civilian

    victims

    was

    actually

    very

    high

    for

    a war

    in

    twentieth-century

    Europe.

    Most modern

    conflicts

    produce

    far

    more

    civilian

    casualties

    than

    military

    ones.

    The

    single

    greatest

    incident

    of

    mass

    killing during

    the

    war

    occurred

    in

    July

    1995

    when the

    Bosnian Serb

    Army

    took control

    of

    the "safe area" of

    Srebrenica

    in

    eastern

    Bosnia. The

    judgment

    of

    the

    Trial Chamber of the

    ICTY in the case of General Krstic states concisely what happened next:

    Within

    a

    few

    days,

    approximately

    25,000

    Bosnian

    Muslims,

    most

    of them

    women,

    children and

    elderly

    people

    who

    were

    living

    in the

    area,

    were

    uprooted

    and,

    in

    an

    atmosphere

    of

    terror,

    loaded

    onto

    overcrowded

    buses

    by

    the Bosnian

    Serb forces and

    transported

    across

    the

    confronta

    tion

    lines into Bosnian

    Muslim-held

    territory.

    The

    military-aged

    Bosnian

    Muslim

    men

    of

    Srebrenica, however,

    were

    consigned

    to

    a

    separate

    fate.

    As

    thousands of

    them

    attempted

    to

    flee the

    area,

    they

    were

    taken

    pris

    oner,

    detained

    in

    brutal

    conditions

    and

    then

    executed.

    More

    than

    7,000

    people

    were never seen

    again.36

    Demographic

    experts

    employed

    by

    the Office of

    the

    Prosecutor of the

    ICTY

    have

    estimated that

    at

    least

    7,475

    persons

    were

    killed

    in

    this

    action,

    including

    one-third

    of

    all

    Muslim

    men

    enumerated in the

    April

    1991

    cen

    sus

    of

    Srebrenica. Less than

    1

    percent

    of

    the

    victims

    were

    women,

    and 89.9

    percent

    were

    men

    between the

    ages

    of sixteen

    and

    sixty.37

    While

    some

    of

    these

    men

    were

    killed

    in

    military

    action,

    thousands

    were

    executed. The

    result

    of the

    operation

    was

    to

    drive almost

    all Muslims

    from

    Srebrenica,

    which

    was

    almost

    73

    percent

    Muslim

    before

    the

    war;

    only

    a

    few

    hundred

    have

    since

    returned.

    35.

    BBC

    Worldwide

    Monitoring,

    17 December

    2005;

    carried

    on

    Justwatch

    listserv,

    17

    December

    2005.

    See also

    Emir

    Suljagic,

    interview

    with Mirsad

    Tokaca,

    "Genocide

    Is

    Not

    a

    Matter of

    Numbers,"

    Bosnian

    Institute

    News

    and

    Analysis,

    19

    January

    2006,

    at

    www

    .bosnia.org.uk/news.news-body.cfm?newsid=2139

    (last

    consulted

    22

    February

    2008).

    36.

    Prosecutor

    v.

    Radislav

    Krstic,

    ICTYTrial

    Chamber I

    Judgment,

    2

    August

    2001

    (here

    after

    Krstic

    trial

    judgment),

    para.

    1.

    37.

    All

    figures

    are

    from

    Helge

    Brunborg,

    Torkild Hovde

    Lyngstad,

    and

    Henrik

    Urdal,

    "Accounting

    for

    Genocide: How

    Many

    Were Killed in

    Srebrenica?"

    European Journal

    of

    Population

    19,

    no.

    3

    (2003):

    229-48.

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    15/25

    "Genocide Denial" Laws

    as

    Secular

    Heresy

    397

    The

    criminality

    of

    many

    of these actions is clear. What

    may

    be

    ques

    tioned, however,

    is whether

    applying

    the

    term

    genocide

    to

    this action is

    ap

    propriate.

    Because the ICTY

    proclaimed

    the mass

    killing

    at Srebrenica a

    genocide

    in

    the trial of

    General

    Krstic,

    a

    discussion of this

    question

    must

    focus,

    first,

    on

    the

    tribunal's

    reasoning, specifically

    on

    the

    judgments

    of

    both the

    Trial Chamber

    and

    the

    Appeals

    Chamber

    in

    this

    case.38

    At the

    time

    those

    crimes

    were

    committed,

    General

    Krstic,

    a

    general-major

    in

    the

    Army

    of the

    Republika

    Srpska,

    was

    chief

    of

    staff/deputy

    commander,

    then

    commander,

    of the

    Drina

    Corps

    of

    that

    army,

    the

    corps

    that committed

    the

    crimes

    at

    Srebrenica.

    The Trial Chamber Decision in the Krstic Case

    Genocide is defined

    as

    specific

    "acts committed with intent

    to

    destroy,

    in

    whole

    or

    in

    part,

    a

    national, ethnical,

    racial

    or

    religious

    group,

    as

    such,"

    including killing

    members of the

    group

    or

    causing

    serious

    bodily

    or men

    tal

    harm

    to

    them;

    the

    goal

    of

    bringing

    about the

    "physical

    destruction

    in

    whole

    or

    in

    part"

    is

    important

    as

    well.39

    It

    was

    undeniable that the Bos

    nian

    Serb

    Army

    had killed members of the

    group

    and caused

    bodily

    and

    mental harm

    to

    those who

    survived.

    The

    only

    question

    was

    that of intent:

    "whether

    the

    offences

    were

    committed with

    the

    intent

    to

    destroy,

    in

    whole

    or

    in part,

    a

    national, ethnical, racial

    or

    religious group,

    as

    such."40

    In

    regard

    to

    Srbrenica,

    this

    definition

    is

    more

    problematical

    than

    non-lawyers might

    realize. The

    original

    1946

    United Nations' General

    As

    sembly

    resolution defined

    genocide

    as

    "a denial of the

    right

    of

    existence

    of entire

    human

    groups,"

    and

    it

    was

    said

    at

    that time

    that

    the

    victim of

    genocide

    was

    not

    the individuals

    killed but the

    group.41

    But

    what

    counts

    as

    "the

    group"

    in

    this case? The

    prosecution

    was

    inconsistent,

    referring

    at

    various

    times

    to

    the

    Bosnian

    Muslims,

    the

    Bosnian

    Muslims of

    Srebrenica,

    and

    the

    Bosnian

    Muslims

    of

    eastern

    Bosnia.

    The Trial Chamber

    agreed

    with

    the defense

    that the

    proper group

    was

    the

    Bosnian

    Muslims,

    leaving

    the question of whether the destruction of a part of that group would

    qualify

    as

    genocide.42

    Having

    made this

    determination, however,

    the Trial Chamber then

    contradicted

    itself

    by saying

    that

    the

    killing

    of all members

    of the

    part

    of

    a

    group

    located

    within

    a

    small

    geographical

    area

    . . .

    would

    qualify

    as

    genocide

    if carried

    out

    with

    the

    intent

    to

    destroy

    the

    part

    of the

    group

    as

    such located

    in this small

    geo

    graphical

    area.

    Indeed,

    the

    physical

    destruction

    may

    target

    only

    a

    part

    of

    the

    geographically

    limited

    part

    of the

    larger

    group

    because the

    perpetra

    38. The ICTY has

    two

    levels,

    or

    chambers. The Trial

    Chamber

    hears

    cases

    and makes

    the

    initial

    decision;

    these

    decisions

    may

    be

    appealed

    to

    the

    Appeals

    Chamber,

    which

    makes

    a

    final

    judgment.

    39.

    Krstic trial

    judgment,

    para.

    540.

    Although

    the Krstic

    court

    uses

    the definition

    found

    in

    the ICTYs

    founding

    statute,

    this is drawn

    directly

    from

    the relevant United Na

    tions

    treaty

    definitions.

    40.

    Ibid.,

    para.

    544.

    41.

    Ibid.,

    para.

    552.

    42.

    Ibid.,

    para.

    560.

    This content downloaded from 143.210.133.25 on Wed, 11 Feb 2015 09:55:35 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 Genocide Denial Laws as Heresy

    16/25

    398 Slavic

    Review

    tors

    of

    the

    genocide

    regard

    the intended

    destruction

    as

    sufficient

    to

    an

    nihilate

    the

    group

    as a

    distinct

    entity

    in

    the

    geographic

    area at

    issue.43

    Yet

    even

    annihilation

    of

    a

    small local

    group

    seems

    unlikely

    to

    threaten

    the

    larger "group

    as

    such,"

    already

    defined

    as

    the Bosnian

    Muslims,

    that

    is,

    the

    group

    itself

    (rather

    than

    the

    individuals

    that

    comprise

    it),

    which

    is

    the

    party

    to

    be

    protected

    from

    genocide.

    Further,

    the

    Bosnian

    Serb

    Army

    did

    not

    try

    to

    kill all

    members of the

    group,

    as

    mentioned

    by

    the

    court

    in

    its

    reasoning,

    but rather

    only

    males between

    the

    ages

    of sixteen

    and

    sixty;

    although

    they

    were

    treated

    appallingly,

    women,

    small

    children,

    and

    old

    people

    were

    transported

    out

    of

    Srebrenica.

    In this

    connection,

    the

    Trial Chamber

    referred

    to

    "the

    catastrophic impact

    that the

    disappear

    ance of two or three generations of men would have on the survival of

    a

    traditionally patriarchal society,"

    thus

    incorporating

    into

    its

    reasoning

    stereotypes

    about Bosnian

    society.44

    Strangely,

    the

    Trial Chamber

    also

    re