21
Bulletin de Ia S odete Americaine de Philosophie de Langue Franfaüe J,7 o lume 14, Number 1, Spril1g2004 Eschatology and Positivism: The Critique of Phenomenology in Derrida and Foucault Leonard Lawlor In his early "What is 1\1etaphysics?," Heidegger claims that the question expressed in the tide of his essay puts the ques- tioner-us-in question. This "putting us in question" then moves forward towards, as Heidegger says, the completion of the transformation of man, understood as subject, into exist- ence (Dasein).l This complete transformation, fot Heidegget, as we know from the Introduction to the essay that he added in 1949, amounts to an overcoming ofmeta- physics understood as Platonism or as the mere reversal of Platonisrn (pM 363/279). At this moment, I think it is still necessary to take seriously Heidegget's attempt to overcome metaphysics. 2 Heidegger had pointed the way towards the ovetcoming of metaphysics by calling us to think what he calls the "Auseinander' of the opening of being itself (pM 369/ 284). How are we to translate ioto English this German word "AuJeinandef'? Perhaps as the "outside of one another" or even

Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    0

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

Bulletin de Ia SodeteAmericaine de Philosophie de Langue FranfaüeJ,7olume 14, Number 1, Spril1g2004

Eschatology and Positivism:The Critique of Phenomenologyin Derrida and Foucault

Leonard Lawlor

In his early "What is 1\1etaphysics?," Heidegger claims thatthe question expressed in the tide of his essay puts the ques­tioner-us-in question. This "putting us in question" thenmoves forward towards, as Heidegger says, the completion ofthe transformation of man, understood as subject, into exist­ence (Dasein).l This complete transformation, fot Heidegget,as we know from the Introduction to the essay that he addedin 1949, amounts to an overcoming ([Jberwindun~ ofmeta­physics understood as Platonism or as the mere reversal ofPlatonisrn (pM 363/279). At this moment, I think it is stillnecessary to take seriously Heidegget's attempt to overcomemetaphysics.2 Heidegger had pointed the way towards theovetcoming of metaphysics by calling us to think what hecalls the "Auseinander' of the opening of being itself (pM 369/284). How are we to translate ioto English this German word"AuJeinandef'? Perhaps as the "outside of one another" or even

Page 2: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

I ESCHATOLOGY AND POSITIVISM

las the "outside itsel[" No matter what, however, "Auseinandef'implies that, in order to overcome metaphysics, we must havea thought of the outside. A thought of the outside would bea thought that comes from the outside which is as weil athought abOl..lt the outside. This outside, it seems to me, how­ever, is not "the opening of being," as Heidegger says, btlt theopening of life. Tb.e outside is a place in which life and deathindefinitely delimit one another. But to move us to this placeof delimitation, we must start with a critique of phenomenology.

We must start here because phenomenology has showna remarkable resilience across the Twentieth Century. But moreimportantly, we n1ust start here because phenomenology hasalready conceived life through its central concept of Erlebnis("lived-experience" in English, "VCft/' in French). Therefore,we can ask whether phenomenology itself has already initi­ated an overcoming of metaphysics. Husserl, oE course,thought so. Yet, certain critiques in France dating from the1960's imply that lived-experience consists in a kind oE inside­ness, which is not interna~ and a kind oE sameness, which isnot identity-but lmxture and ambiguity. IE mixture andambiguity defme lived-experience, then it follows that some­times phenomenology restores Platonism, while other times itmerely reverses Platonism into its opposite. Understood inthis way, as sameness and inside-ness, phenomenology doesnot overcome metaphysics. Phenomenology is not a thoughtof the outside-or, at least, this is what I would like to showhere. IE you heard the allusion in the ph.rase "the thought ofthe outside," you know that I am thinkillg of Foucault, inparticular, the critiqtle of phenomenology found in his 1966vsMots ef fes fhoses. 3 The other critique con1es from Derrida's1967 La Voix ef le phenomene.4 In any case, what I intend to dohere is reconstruct the critique of phenomenology found inFoucault and Derrida.5 I am going to start witl1. Foucault, andin particular, with Chapter Nine of Les Mots et les fhoses, "Mallalld his Doubles."

23

Page 3: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEON.i\RD L\\"'V1..0R

The Analysis of Lived-Experience (vecu) is aDiscourse with a Mixed Nature

Chapter Nine of LeJ MotJ et leJ t'hoJcs, "Man and hisDoubles," contains, of course, Foucault's critique of modernllumanism.6 The chapter therefore focuses on man (and noton the human being). Foucault defines man as a double; he isat once an object of knowledge and a subject that knows (NIC323/312). ~1an (and again not the human being) is what oc­cupies, as Foucault says, this "ambiguous position." The en­tire critique of humanism unfolds, for Foucault, from thisdesignation of man as "ambiguous," adesignation which re­calls, of course, ~lerleau-Ponty and Sartre. I shail turn toMerleau-Ponty in a moment. In any case, for Foucault, theambiguity that defmes man consists in two senses of finitude.In one sense, finitude consists in the empirical positivities, theempirical contents of "work, life, and language," which tellman that he is finite (NIC 326/315). The knowledge of life,for instance, teils man that he is going to die. The other senseis that this finitude is itself fundamental. The forms of knowl­edge in which the very contents that tell Ulan that he is finiteare forms whicl~ are themselves finite. For instance, for man,there is no inteilectual intuition. So, fmitude is ambiguousbetween empirical content and foundational forms. For Fou­cault, this ambiguity of finitude results in an "obligation" toascend "up to an analytic of fmitude." Here it is necessary tohear the word "analytic" in its Kantian sense, as a "theory ofthe subject" (MC 330/310). For Foucault, this would be ananalytic "where the being of man will be able to found, intheir positivity, all the forms that indicate to him that he is notinfmite" (MC 326/315, myemphasis). This analytic would bethe discourse oE phenomenology.

The discourse of phenomenology would aim at, accord­ing to Foucault, a truth that would be neither empirical con-

24

Page 4: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

I ESCHATOLOGY AND POSITIVISM

tent nor transcendental form, while trying to keep the empiri­cal and transcendental separated. This is an important quali­fication-"while trying to keep the empirical and transcen­dental separated"-since what is at issue is here whether pl1-e­nomenology can maintain the separation between the empiri­cal and the transcendental. In any case, according to FOll­cault, phenomenology would be an analytic of man as a sub­ject in this precise sense: man as subject, "that is, as the placeof empirical knowledge but led back as close as possible towhat makes empirical knowledge possible, andas the pure formthat is immediately present to these contents." Man as sub­ject therefore would be the third and intermediary term inwhich empiricity and transcendentality would have their roots.According to Foucault, this third and intermecliary term hasbeen designated by "Je vetu." "Le vecd' responds to the "obli­gation" to analyze finitude, that is, to the obligation to have atheory of the subject. Here is Foucault's definition oE "fe lJeCU':"lived-experience, in fact, is at once the space where all em­pirical content is given to experience; it is also the originaryform that luakes them in gel1eral possible." We can now seethe problem with "Je vel'U," and indeed, with "man." "Le veftl'must be concrete enough in order to he able to apply to it adescriptive language; yet it must he enough removed frompositivity so that it can provide the foundations for empiricalpositivity. The discourse of vel"U tries to make the empiricalhold for the transcendental: the empirical is the transcenden­tal and the transcendental is the empirical, or, the content isthe form and the form is the content. Lived-experience there­fore is a mixture. And thllS FOllcault says that "the al1alysis oflived-experience [lJecu] is a discourse with a mixed nature: it isaddressed to a specific hut ambiguous layer" C1'1C 332/321).This analytic "mixes" the transcendental and the empiricaltogether. Therefore, what we have seen so far is that the con­cept of lived-experience, as Foucault understands it-and this

25

Page 5: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEON.l\RD L\\-X;'LOR

is also how Detrida understands it, as we shall see in a mo­ment-consists not in an identity of empirical content andfoundational form but in a mixture or ambiguity between thesetwo. Here, howevet, one could plausibly wondet whethet sucha defmition can be found in phenomenology. So, let us turnnow to Hllsserl and then to 1-1erleall-Ponty to confltm thisdefinition.

Lived-Experience (das Erlebnis, le vecu) inGeneral

We have been discussing Erlebnis; so, let us turn toHusserl's classical defmition of Erlebnis in ldeas I, in section36, which is entitled "Intentional Lived Experiences. LivedExperiences in General."7 Here, in order to distinguish whathe is doing from psychology, Husserl says, "Rather [than adiscourse of real psychological facts; the word "real" is, ofcourse, important,] the discourse hete and throughout is aboutputely phenomenologicallived-experiences, that is, their es­sences, and on that basis, what is 'a priori' enclosed in [inbeslfJlossen] their essences with unconditional necessity" (HUA111:1, p. 80).R As I just said, that I-Iusserl calls psychologicalfacts "real" is important, because all purely phenomenologi­cal lived-experiences are "reelle." What Husserl calls inten­tional lived experiences, thoughts in the broadest sense, arereelle, which means that thoughts are internal. Yet, intentionallived experience also contains "the fundamental characteristicof intentionality," the property of being consciousness ofsomething. This "of something"-the fundamental charac­teristic of intentionality-means that lived-experience is re­lated to an outside; something comes from the outside intolived-experience. But, Husserl says, "within the concrete unityof an intentionallived experience," there are reelle moments,which do not have the fundamental characteristic of inten-

26

Page 6: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

ESC!-L\:fOLOGY .i'\ND POSI'1TVIS~f

tionality; these reelle moments are the data of sensation. Here,Husserl has discovered something non-intentional and there­fore passive at the very heart of lived-experience, somethingthat comes from the outside, and yet he has designated thesemoments as "reelle," and thereby as "enclosed in" "dasErlebnis iiberhaupt." By means of this "ii.berhallpt" and this"in beschlossen," we can conclude already that Erlebnis, in thisclassical formulation, consists in a sameness, wruch is not iden­tity, and an inside-ness which is not sirnply internal; in a word,ErlebniJ "in general" consists in a mixture.

To demonstrate this sameness and inside-ness again, Iwould also like to look at another Husserl text: the fmal ver­sion of Husserl's 1927 Encyclopedia Britannica entry on "Phe­nomenology." As is well-known, this text introduces phenom­enology through phenomenological psychology. Phenomeno­logical psychology, Husserl says here, has the task of investi­gating the totality of lived experience. But, more irnportandy,phenomenological psychology, according to Husserl, is aneasier way to enter into the transcendental problem that oc­curred historically with Descartes, that is, that all of reality,and finally the whole world, are for us in existence and inexistence in a certain way only as the represel1tational contentof our own representations. Thus everyth.ing real has to berelated back to uso But this "us" cal1not be the psyche, ac­cording to Husserl, because the psyche is defined by the mun­dane sense of being as Vorhandenheit, presence, or, more liter­ally, presence-at-hand. To use a mundane being-whose on­tological sense is Vorhandenheit-to account for the reality ofthe world-whose ontological sense is also Vorhandenheit-iscircular, and this circularity defmes psychologism.9 In con­trast to psychologism, phenomenology claims, according toHusserl, that there is a parallelism between psychological sub­jectivity and transcendental subjectivity and that this parallel­ism involves a deceptive appearance (Schein) of "transcenden-

27

Page 7: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEONj\RD L\\v1..0R

tal duplication." It is important here, it seems to me, that,while Husserl recognizes that there is some sort of differencebetween the transcendental and the psychological or the em­pirical, he does not, we might say, partition off the transcen­dental from the psychological or en~pirical. Instead, he saysthat transcendental sllbjectivity is defined by Vorhandenheit tao,but "not in the same sense" (nitht im selben Sinn vorhanden ist).10Indeed, Husserl thinks that by saying "not in the same sense,"he has eliminated the deceptive appearance and makes theparallelism understandable. This is what he says, "the parallel­ism of the transcendental and the psychological spheres ofexperience has become comprehensible...as a kind of iden­city of the interpenetration [Ineinande~ of ontological senses."11This "kind of identity," he also describes as "ambiguity"(Zweideutigkeit). Here Husserl thinks the "Ineinander," literally,one in the other, but not, we might say, the ''Auseinander,'' liter­ally, one outside of the other. Nevertheless, this "Zweideutigkeit'and "Ineinander' should make us think of Merleau-Ponty. So Iwould like to turn now to Merleau-Ponty, and in particular, tohis Phenomenology of Pert'eption. 12

On the very first page of the ]Jhenomenology of ]Jerception,j\,ferleau-Ponty speaks of IJeCU, and, throughout the ]Jhenom­enology the word modifies the term "monde," "warld." For ex­ample, in the chapter called "The Phenomenal Field," 11erleau­Ponty says that "the fttst philosophical act therefore would bethat of returning to the lived-world on this side of the objec­tive world" (phP 69/57). Yet, he uses the word as a noun-"level'tI'-only twice. The ftrst time occurs in the chapter called"Space"; here he says "lived-experience [fe 1Jet'U] is really livedby me... , but I can live more things that I can think of [plus dechoses queJe m'en representeJ. What is only lived is ambi?Jalent'(phP 343/296; my emphasis). For Merleau-Ponty, ambivalenceis the crucial characteristic of veeu. And this characteristicguides his analysis of intersubjectivity in the Phenomenology oj'

28

Page 8: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

ESCfL'\'l'OLOGY .A.ND POSI'lT\TIS~f

.Perception, which is where he uses "fe vectl' for the second time,in the chapter called "Others and tl1e Human World." Here"fe vel'U"is defmed by self-givenness (phP 411/358); but, thisself-givenness is also given (phP 413/360). In other words,the active is also passive. In this formula we can see the im­portance of the positive affttmation in the "is." This positiveaffttmation is the heart of ambivalence. N ow, these two usesof "Je 1Jectl' in the ])henomenofogy of ])erlr:ption depend of course

on Merleau-Ponty's appropriation of Husserl's concept of.Fundiert/ng. In the chapter called "The Cogito;' Merleau-Pontyspeaks of the relation between founding (fe fondant) andfounded (fe fonde) as one that is "equivocal" (equivoque), since"every truth of fact is a truth of reason, every truth of reasoniJ a truth of fact" (phP 451/394; my emphasis).13 Merleau­

Ponty also says that d1.e relation of matter and form is a rela­tion of J-1undierung. "The form integrates the content to thepoint that it appears to end up being a simple mode of theform ... but reciprocally ... the content remains as a radicalcontingency, as the fltst establishment or the foundation ofknowledge and action.... It is trus clialectic of form and con­tent that we have to restore" (phP 147-48/127). We can nowsummarize what we see in Merleau-Ponty's concept of "Ie vel"U."For Merleau-Ponty, "fe vetil' is ambivalent or equivocal-it is,we could say, a mixture, un mefange-because the content ofexperience, "le sol," as J\Ierleau-Ponty also says, becomes, isintegrated into, the form of expressiol1. Phenomenologicallived experience therefore is not defmed by identity, but bysameness and mixture of form and content, or of empiricaland transcendental.

"Un Ecart intime, mais invincible"

Both Husserl and the early Merleau-Ponty conceiveErfebniJ as mixture and ambiguity because both want to over-

29

Page 9: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEON.A.RD L\\v~OR

come the duality of subject and ohject, or even the duality ofwhat Heidegger calls the ontological difference. In otherwords, phenomenology is an attempt to overcome Platonismor Cartesianism (dualisms) by mixing together content andform. In both Foucault and Derrida, we fmd statements thatassert that the phenomenological concept of ErlebniJmixes inthis way. First we have Foucault's statement in Chapter Sevenof Les Mots et les choses, which is called "The Limits of Repre­sentation." Foucault says:

Undoubtedly, it is not possible to give empiri­cal contents transcendental value, or to movethem onto the side of a constituting subjec­tivity, without giving rise, at least silencly, to ananthropology, that is, to a mode of thought inwhich the in principle limits of knowledge[t'onnazssance] are at the same time [en meme temps]the concrete forms of existence, precisely asthey are given in that san'le empirical knowl­edge [Javoitj. ~1C 261/248, my emphasis)

Evel1. if phenomenology is transcendental, Foucault is saying,it still falls prey to a "silent anthropology." It takes my presentor ourpresent experiences, which are content, as foundationalforms. In other words, on the basis of the empirical contentsgiven to me, or, better, to UJ, phenomenology tries to deter­mine the form of that empirical content. While trying to keepthem separate, phenomenology makes the transcendental andthe empirical the same. It confuses them (MC 352/341). Now,in the Introductiol1 to LLt Voix et lephinomene, Derrida makes avery similar statement, hut he adds something that helps ussee the principle of the critique:

Presence has always been and will always be,to infinity, the form in which-we can say thisapodictically-the infInite diversity of contentwill be produced. The opposition-which

30

Page 10: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

ESCI-L<\:fOLOGY .A.ND POSI'l'I\TIS~f

inaugurates metaphysies-between form andmatter fmds in the eonerete ideality of the liv­ing present its ultimate and radical justifiea­rion. (VP 5/6)

When Derrida says here that the opposition between formand content finds its ultimate and radical jllstification, he meansthat content, the root of empirieal positivity, and form, thefinality of transcendental foundation, are mixed together inthe living present at the same time. Indeed, in both quotes, wesee that the mixture of subject and objeet in lived-experieneedepends on a temporal sameness: "at the same time" or "si­multaneity," "en meme temps" or "a la fois." This dependenceon temporal sameness teils us already that a eritique of theconeept of lived-experienee will eome from a kind of spatialthirlking and from are-institution of dualisms.

Derrida's eritique ean be seen most elearly in chapter sixof La Vozx et le phenomene, entided "The Voiee that Keeps Si­lent." As is weil-known, Derrida's eritique centers on the eOll­eept of presenee. So here is the definitioll of presence thatDerrida provides in Chapter Six:

presence (is] simultaneouslJ [a laibis] . 0 • the being-­b~fore ~fo the obJoett, available for a lookand.. .proximi!J to se!! in interiori!y. The "pre"oE the present objeet now-beEore is an against[tontre] (Gegenwart, Gegenstand) simultaneously[a laftis] in the sense of the whol!J against [tout­tontre] oE proximity and in the sense of theentounter [l'entontre] of the op-posed. (VP 83­84/75; Derrida's italies)

Presenee, as Derrida understands it, is Cl la ibis elose by andproximate, and a la ibis away and distant. In other words, itmust be "at the same time" self-presenee and presence, theobject as repeatable to infinity and the presence of the eonsti­tuting acts to themselves. For Derrida, this ambiguity betweenpresence of an objeet and self-presenee of a subjeet is found

31

Page 11: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEON.i\RD L\\v'LOR

in the voice of interior monologue, in other words, hearingoneself speak. The primary characteristic of this "absolutelyunique type of auto-affection" (VP 88/78) is ten1porality.When I speak to myself silently, the sound is iterated acrossmoments. This temporal iteration is why, as Derrida explains,sOllnd is the most ideal of all signs (VP 86/77). Thlls, inhearing-oneself-speak, one still exteriorizes one's thoughts or"meaning-intention" or acts of repetition in the iterated anditerable phonemes. This exteriorization-expression-seemsto imply that we have now moved from time to space. But,since the sound is heard by the subject during the time he isspeaking, the voice is in absolute proximity to its speaker,"within the absolute proximity of its present" (VP 85/76),"absolutely elose to me" (VP 87/77). The sllbject lets him­self be affected by the phoneme (that is, he hears his ownsounds, ms own voice, "la voix propre") without any detourthrough exteriority or through the world, or, as Derrida says,without any detour through "the non-proper in general" (Vp88/78). Hearing-oneself-speak is "lived [vecue] as absolutelypure auto-affeetion" (VP 89/79). What makes it be a pureauto-affeetion, according to Derrida, is that it is "a self-prox­imity which would be nothing other than the absolute reduc­tion of spaee in general" (VP 89/79). Yet-and this is a cru­cial "yet"-there is a double here between hearing and speak­ing. As Derrida says, this pure auto-affection, which is thevery root of transcendental Erlebnis, supposes that "a puredifference...divides the presence to oneself" (VP 92/82). Tmsdifference divides the "auto." As Derrida says, "It producesthe same as the self-relation within the differenee with one­self, the same as the non-identical" (VP 92/82). Being non­identical, auto-affection is ambiguous. We rnust understandthe non-identity, however, in the following way: when I hearmyself speak, the hearing is arepetition of the speaking thathas already disappeared; re-presentation (Vergegenwärtigun~has

Page 12: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

I ESCI-L;\TOLOGY AND POSITIVISM

Ftervened, and that intervention means, in a word, space. AsIDerrida says, "the 'outside' insinuates itself in the movementIhy which the inside of non-space, what has the name of 'time,'appears to itself, constitutes itself, 'presents' itself" (VP 96/86). Within time, there is a fundamental "spacing" (ejpacemen~

(VP 96/86).14 Derrida also calls this spacing "un ecart' within"Je fJeed' (VP 77/69). On the basis of Derrida's use of theword "el'art," we can rejoin Foucault.

In UJMotJ et leJ t'hoJeJ, Foucault says that all of the doublesin which man consists are based on "un ecart i~fime, maiJ invin­cihle"; the English translation says, a "hiatus, miniscule and yetinvincible" C1'IC 351/340). Here we can dissociate an ambi­guity in the word "in:fime." This "Cl'art' is "infime," that is,miniJcule; insofar as it is miniscule, the "et'arf' closes and relates"in the manner of "a mixed nature." But, this "ecarf' is also"injime," in the sense of infinitesimal, infmitely divisible, andthus a great distance that separates and keeps open. It seemsto me tl~at this ecart i~ftme sets up all the problems that areours. In fact, I think it is impossible to over-estimate the im­portance of chapter nine in Lej' Motj' et lej' thosej', "Man and hisDoubles." Foucault says here, after mel1tioning this minisculehiatus, that:

[In conttast to classical thought, in which timefounds space], in modern thought, what is re­vealed at the foundation oE the history ofthings and of the historicity proper to man isthe distance hollowing out the Same, it is thehiatus [ecar~ that disperses the Same and gath­ers it back at the two edges of itselE It is thisprofound spatiality that allows modernthought still to think time-to know it as suc­cession, to promise it as completion, origin orreturn. (MC 351/340)

3

Page 13: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEON.A.RD L\\v'LOR

It seems to me, if I may extend the analysis a bit, that we mustsee this "profound spatiality" working, as weIl, in Deleuze'scritique of phenomenology found both in his 1968 DiJferen(/cand Repetition15 and in his 1969 Logü' of SenJc. 16 For Deleuze,the phenomenological concept of Urdoxa, wmch one fmds inboth Hllsserl and in Merleau-Ponty, is not originary, since it isalways "copied off"-"decalqul'-the doxa or common sense.1

?

This "copying off" means that the Ufdoxa is mixed with orthe same as the doxa; they resemble one another and are notdifferentiated. The phenomenological concept of Urdoxa hasviolated therefore the most basic principle of Deleuze'sthought, perhaps the most basic principle of thought itself:"The foundation can never resemble the founded." Deleuzecontinues, "It is not enough to say about the foundation thatit is another history-it is also anothergeograp0', without beinganother world."18 For Deleuze, the earth is a profound spati­ality, consisting in "un ecart infime, mais invint'ible."

Conclusion: Memory and Life

The critique of phenomenology found in Foucault andDerrida, as weil as in Deleuze, is based in this miniscule hia­tus. Despite the fact that all three-Derrida, Deleuze, andFoucault-share the same critique, there is a difference be­tween them. To conclude, I am going to outline the differ­ence between Derrida and Foucault. For both, the critique ofphenomenologicallived-experience is a critique of auto-af­fection. The critique depends entirely on one necessary pos­sibility: wherever the.re is sensing, it must be possible for thereto be a surface, and, wherever there is a surface, it must bepossible for there to be space. This necessary possibility im­plies that auto-affectiol1, being alone and therefore close tooneself and unified with oneself, is always already virtuallydouble, distant fron1 oneself and divided. But-and this is an

34

Page 14: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

ESCI-L\'l·OLOGY i\.ND POSrll\TJS1:f

important "but," as we shall see in a moment-what dividesthe "auto," spacing it and makll1g it double in Dem·da is media­tion, Vergegenwärtigung. Derrida always conceives the "ecartinfime" through Vergegenwärtigung, re-presentation. In Derrida,re-presentation contaminates presentation; mediation, in otherwords, contaminates the immediate, hut contamination is stillme­diation. Thus, understood as mediation, contamination prom­ises unity, even tllough it cannot, by necessity, ever keep thispromise. The other is always already close by and coming,without ever arriving. Without ever being able to arrive, theone who is going to keep the promise is to come in person (inthe flesh, Leiblich). Therefore, we must characterize Derrida'scritique of phenomenology (as he himself has done) as aneJchatologülJl critique. It is a critique based in a promised unitythat demands to be done over again and again.19

Like that of Derrida, Foucault's critique too dependsentirely on one necessary possibility: wherever these is sens­ing, it must be possible for there to be a surface, al~d, wher­ever there is a surface, it must be possible for there to be space.This necessary possibility implies that auto-affection, beingalone and therefore close to oneself and unified with oneself,is always already virtually double, distant from oneself anddivided. .But-and this is where we see the difference fromDerrida-what divides the auto, spacing it and making it doublein ~oul'ault is a battle.20 Foucault conceives the "etlJrt injime" asa battle. The opponents il~ the battle are words and things, orhearing and seeing. The battle consists in attacks and cross­ings across the surface (entrecroisements), but these attacks do not.form a unity. No unity is ever promised in the battle. Politics,wluch looks to be peace, as Foucault pointed out in Surveiller etpunir, is war being fought with other means. For Foucault, theaudio-visual battle is an immediate relation. There is no me­diation because the opponents are can never be mixed to­gether, or, we might say, can never contaminate one another.

35

Page 15: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEON-i\RD L\\~'LOR

Instead, the opponents are posited as such; there is always theopposition of resistant'e. Therefore, we must eharaeterizeFoueault's eritique of phenomenology (as he himself has done)as apOJitivistic eritique.21 It is a eritique based in a duality with­out negation and thus it is entirely positive.22

What are we to make of the clifference in their critiques?We must return onee more to Chapter Nine of Les Mots et feschoses, "Man and his Doubles." Here, Foucault had laid out akind of genealogy of phenomenology. At the beginning ofthe nineteenth eentury, he tells us, tl1.ere was a dissoeiation inthe double sense of fmitude, between empirieal eontent andfoundational forms of knowledge. This dissoeiation wasKant's thought. The dissociation, however, led to what Fou­eault calls a transcendental aesthetics (the empirieal eontent)and a transeendental clialeetie (the foundational forms). Thetranseendental aestheties beeame positivism; the transeendentaldialeetic became esehatology. During the nineteenth eenturyand at the beginning of the twentieth century, this dissocia­rion between positivism and esehatology eame to be associ­ated in two ways: Marxism and phenomenology. We can seethe assoeiation in Marxism insofar as 1vfarxism claimed to givethe positive truth of man in eonditions of labor and at thesame time promised a revolutionary utopia. We can see thisassoeiation in phenomenology insofar as phenomenologyspeaks of the eontent of Erlebnis, which can be positively de­scribed as the truth, and at the same time of the fulfillment of ameaning-intention, in other words, the promise of fulfilledtruth. For Foucault, this assoeiation leads to the ambiguitythat defmes both Marxism and phenomenology. N ow it seemsto me that, in their similar but different eritiques of phenom­enology, Foueault and Derrida have onee again dissoeiatedpositivism and eschatology. The association that phenomenol­ogy and Marxism made has become unraveled. The doublesthat eame to be the ambiguity of Husserl's thought, positiv-

36

Page 16: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

ESC!-L\'l'OLOGY.A.ND POSrlTVIS1-f

ism and eschatology, have now themselves become dissoci­ated into the thought of Foucault and Derrida. On the onehand, we have Derrida's messianism, wh.ich leaps back to theeschatology oE the nineteenth century. On the other hand,we have Foucault's "fortunate positivism" (un positiviJmehcurcux),23 which obviollsly leaps back to the positivism of thenineteenth centu.ry. Foucault and Derrida have dissociatedimmanence and transcendence, Eaith and knowledge, and, wemight even say, the heart and the brain. Both the brain andthe heart are complicated spaces; we might even appropriateHeidegger's term ''Auseinander' in order to conceive them. Yet,without the heart, one could not speak oE life; and withoutthe brain one could not speak of memory. Now we can seewhat to make oE the difference between th.e critiques ofphenom-enology that we [md in Foucault and Derrida. Thisis our task. We must continue the overcoming of metaphys­ics by trying to find a new way oE associating the heart and thebrain. In other words, is it possible for us to :find a new distri­bution, a new ''partage,'' as either Derrida or Foucault wouldsay, between the double oE the heart al1d the bram? Perhapsthis new partitioning can be found only under the heading of"memory and life."24

UnilJersity oj' Memphis

37

Page 17: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEONi\RD L\\v'LOR

Notes

1Martin Heidegger, "Was ist Metaphysik?" in Wegmarken(Frankfurt am Main: Victorio Klostermann, 1967), 112. En­glish translation: "What is ~1etaphysics?" in ])athmarks, trans.David Farrell I<rell, ed. William McNeill (New York: Cam­bridge University Press, 1998), 89. Hereafter all essays inPathmarks will be cited as P1-1 with reference first to the Ger­man, then to the English translation.

2 I have written two companion essays to "Eschatologyand Positivism": "Un Ecart Injime: The Critique of the Con­cept of Lived-Experience (IJetu) in Foucault," which is forth­coming in ReJ'ear{,'h in J)henomenology; and Leonard Lawlor,"Verendlichung (Finitization): The Overcoming of 1-1etaphys­ics with Life," which at this moment is unpublished. All threeessays are contributions to two book projects in progress:Towards the Outside: Continentall)hilosop~y before 1960, andMemoryand Lift: an Ar{;heology qf' the Experience qf- Thought. Concerningthe overcomU'lg of metaphysics in Heidegger, I think that whatHeidegger says, late in his career in 1964, in "Time and Be­mg," must not mislead uso Although Heidegger seems to re­pudiate the intention of overcoming metaphysics, he endorsesa thinking that overcomes the obstacles that tend to make asaying of being, without reg~d for metaphysics, inadequate.~1ore importantly, when he speaks of leaving metaphysicsalone, he uses the verb "überlassen," which also suggests a kindof super-engagement with metaphysics. See 1-1~tin Heidegger,Zur Sache des Denkens (Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1969), 25. En­glish translation: On Time andBeing, trans. Joan Stambaugh (NewYork: Harper Colophon, 1972), 24

:; Michel Foucault, Les Mots ef !es choses (P~is: Gallimard,1966). English translation: The Orderqf Things, trans. anony­mous (New York: Random House, 1970). Hereafter referredto as Me, with reference first to the French, then to the En-

38

Page 18: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

ESCI-L\'l'OLOGY .i\ND POSI'l'IVISivf

glish translation. This project would be complete, it seems,only by a reading of ivferleau-Ponty's "L'Homme et l'adversite,"in Sig'nes (paris: Gallimard, 1960), 299 and 306. English trans­lation: SignJ, trans. Richard C. McCleary (Evanston: North­western University Press, 1964), 235 and 241. I intend to pur­sue this question of the melange in Merleall-Ponty in. anotherbook project: Merleau-l~onryand the ]:Jolitü'al.

4Jacques Derrida, La Vozx et le phenomene (paris: PressesUniversitaires de France, 1967). English translation: Speet'h and.Phenomena, trans. David B. Allison (Evanston, IL: Northwest­ern University Press, 1973). Hereafter cited as VP with refer­ence fIrst to the French, then to the English translation. I willuse the French titles oE La Voix et lephenomene and Les Mots etleJ thoJeJ since the English translations are somewhat mis­leading.

50ne finds a similar critique of the concept of Erlebnisin Hans-Georg Gadamer's Wahrheit und Methode (Tübingen:l\10 hr, 1975). English translation: Truth and Method, 2d rev.ed., trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. l\1arshall (NewYork: Continuum, 1989). Gadalner claims that the conceptof Erlebnis consists in the immediacy of self-consciousnessand in an immediacy that yields a content (das Erlebte). Hiscritique is that ErlebniJ is unity and interiority, whereas life it­self is self-diremption.. Here he takes bis inspiration fromHegel, "the speculative import of the concept of life" (WahrheitundMethode, 237; Truth andMethod, 250-51). Thus, because ofthe idea of self-diremption, Gadamer stresses the idea of judg­ment (Urtei~, wbich literally meal1S "original partitioning."Nevertheless, despite Gadamer's emphasis on Ur-teil, we thinkwith Foucault that life is not expressed in a judgment, whichstill relies on unity or synthesis, but in the infmitive of a verbwruch can be infinitely divided without unity. It is the expres­sion of the indefmite, a universal singularity. On this idea ofthe verb, see Gilles Deleuze, LiJgique du sens (paris: I\tfinuit,

39

Page 19: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEON.i\RD L\\~'LOR

1969), 11. English translation: LiJgic ~f' SenJe, trans. Mark Lester,with Charles Stivale, ed. Constantin V Boundas (New York:Columbia University Press, 1990), 3. See also Foucault's re­view of Deleuze's Logique du JenJ and Difference el repetition,"Theatrum Philosophieum," in Dits et icrits I, 1954-1975 (paris:Gallimard, 2001), 950-51. El~glish translation: Michel FOllcalllt,Language, Counter-M"emory, j)ral'lice, trans. and ed. Donald F.Bouchard (New York: Cornell University Press, 1977), 173­75. IE there is a concept in Foucault, it would be an infmitive,like "repnfJenter," "clasJer," "parler," "echanger," or "surveiller etpunir," or finally, ''penser.'' It is important to recal1 that Deleuzesays that a statement (un enonte)-and in Foucault a staten~ent

is the true equivalent to the concept-is a "curve" (un courbe).See Gilles Deleuze, .Foucault (paris: ~1inuit, 1986),87. Englishtranslation: .Foucault, trans. Sean Hand (Minneapolis: Univer­sity of l\1innesota Press, 1988), 80.

GSee l\1ichel Foucault, "Vie: experience et vie," in Dits etecrit, IV, 763-776. English translation: "Life: Experience andScience," trans. Robert Hurley, in ESJential WorkJ of MichelFou­cault: AestheticJ~ Method, and Epistemology, val. 2, ed. James D.Faubion (New York: The New Press, 1998), 465-478.

7Edmund Husserl, Husserliana (hereafter Hua) 111.1: IdeenZu einer reinen Phänomenologie undphanomenologiJchenPhilosophie:ErJteJ .Buch, ed. Karl Schuhmann (The Hague: ~1artinus

Nijhoff, 1976). English translation: Ideas j)ertaining 10 a ])ure])henomenofogy andto a])henomenologüLlI])hilosophy, trans. F.I<'ersten(The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982). See also EdmundHusserl, ldies directricespour unephenominologie, trans. Paul Ricreur(paris: Gallimard, 1950).

8 Here I am relying on a later revision of the passage thatHusserl made: "copy D." See I<.ersten's English translation,p.73.

9 This solution to the transcendental problem, a solutionwhich defmes "psychologism," is circular because it takes some-

40

Page 20: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

ESCI-L'\'l'OLOGY .L'\ND POSI'l'IVIS~f

thing existing in the world, the psyche, which has the onto­logical sense of something existing in the world, Vorhandenheit,and tries to make this something present account for all thingspresent.

10 Edmund Husserl, Hua IX: ]Jhänomenologische ]Jsychologie(The Hague: 1\1artinus Nijhoff, 1962), 292. English transla­tion: in The EJJential.Husserl, trans. Richard E. Palmer, ed. DonnWelton (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999), 331.

11 Hua IX, p. 294; The Essential HusJerl, 332.12 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, ]Jhenomenologie de la perception

(paris: Gallimard, 1945). English translation: l)henomenology ~f'

.Perception, trans. Colin Smith, rev: Forrest Williams (New Jer­sey: The Humanities Press, 1981). Hereafter PhP, with refer­ence first to the French, then to the English.

13 Thomas Busch also cites this passage in his "Maurice1-1erleau-Ponty: Alterity and Dialogue" in Circulating .Being:EssqYJ in LAte ExiJtentialiJm (New York: Fordham UniversityPress, 1999), 83. Busch's interpretation of Ivlerleau-Ponty'sconcept of ambiguity and equivocity is based on the idea ofdialogue, an idea very different from a battle.

14Spacing implies what Derrida calls "archi-writing" andthus vision: "when I see myself writing and when I signify bygestures, the proximity of hearing myself speak is broken"(VP 90;80). Thus here we could speak of a story of the eye,

I which would allow for a further comparison with Foucault.15 Gilles Deleuze, Difference et repetition (paris: Presses

Universitaires de France, 1968), 179. English translation: Dif­ferente and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York: ColumbiaUn.iversity Press, 1994), 137.

16 Gilles Deleuze, Logique du sens (paris: Iv1inuit, 1969),119 and 124; English translation: Logic of Sense, trans. IvlarkLester, with Charles Stivale, ed. Constantin Boundas (NewYork: Columbia University Press, 1990), 97 al1d 102.

41

Page 21: Eschatology andPositivism: The Critique of Phenomenology

LEON.i\RD L\\~'LOR

17 See Deleuze, Difference et repetition, 177; Differen{;e andRepetition, p. 135; also Deleuze, Logique du sens, 54; Logic oj'Sense, 39.

18 Deleuze, Logique du .rens, 120; Logir: qj' Sense, 99, my em­phasis.

19 I have coined a word for this idea of "a promise thatdemands to be done over again and again": "refinition." Seethe Preface to my Derrida and Husserl' The Basit: ])roblem of ])he­nomenology (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002), asweIl as Thinking Through .Frenr:hPhilo.rop~y: The .Being of the(Que.r­tion (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2003).

20 This description is based largely on !v1ichel Foucault,CCl'i n'est pas une pipe (paris: Fata Morgana, 1973). Englishtranslation: Thi.r is l\lot aPipe, trans. James Harnes (Berkeley:University of Califorma Press, 1983). See also Gilles Deleuze,~oul'tlult, 119/112.

21 I am extrapolating from what Foucault has said in hisL'ordre du di.rcourJ (paris: Gallimard, 1971), p. 72; English trans­lation: "The Discourse on Language," appendix to TheArr:he­ofogy oj~ Knowledge, trans. A. M. Sheridan (New York: Pantheon,1972),234.

22 If we were to pursue further this difference betweenFoucault and Derrida, we would have to investigate the con­cept of multiplicity.

23 Foucault, L'Ordre du di.rcourJ, 72; "The Discourse onLanguage," 234.

42